+ All Categories
Home > Documents > 03 a Critique of Skinner's Views on the Explanatory Inadequacy of Cognitive Theories

03 a Critique of Skinner's Views on the Explanatory Inadequacy of Cognitive Theories

Date post: 07-Jul-2018
Category:
Upload: jonathan
View: 218 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend

of 19

Transcript
  • 8/18/2019 03 a Critique of Skinner's Views on the Explanatory Inadequacy of Cognitive Theories

    1/19

    A Critique of Skinner's Views on the Explanatory Inadequacy of Cognitive TheoriesAuthor(s): Michael G. WessellsSource: Behaviorism, Vol. 9, No. 2 (Fall, 1981), pp. 153-170Published by: Cambridge Center for Behavioral StudiesStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/27758983 .Accessed: 21/10/2011 14:42

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of 

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    Cambridge Center for Behavioral Studies is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access

    to Behaviorism.

    http://www.jstor.org

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ccbshttp://www.jstor.org/stable/27758983?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/27758983?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ccbs

  • 8/18/2019 03 a Critique of Skinner's Views on the Explanatory Inadequacy of Cognitive Theories

    2/19

    A

    CRITIQUE

    OF

    SKINNER'S

    VIEWS

    ON

    THE

    EXPLANATORY

    INADEQUACY

    OF

    COGNITIVE

    THEORIES

    Michael

    G.

    Wessells1

    Vassar

    College

    Over

    several

    decades,

    B.

    F.

    Skinner

    (1953, 1957,

    1964,

    1968, 1969,

    1974,

    1977a)

    has

    sharply

    criticized

    mentalistic

    theories,

    including

    the

    cognitive

    theo

    ries that

    now

    pervade experimental psychology.

    When

    one as

    influential

    as

    Skin

    ner

    condemns

    cognitive

    theories,

    it is all too

    easy

    for radical behaviorists to

    reject

    cognitive

    theory

    and research

    without

    a

    fair

    hearing.

    This

    is

    unfortunate

    because behavioral

    and

    cognitive

    analyses

    are

    complementary (Catania,

    1973;

    Segal,

    1977).

    As discussed

    below,

    cognitive

    analyses

    can

    specify

    the

    biological

    bases of behavior and

    the

    private

    events that influence

    behavior. Behavioristic

    analyses,

    on

    the other

    hand,

    can

    identify

    the

    environmental

    antecedents of

    public

    and

    private

    events. It is

    unlikely

    that

    the entire

    behavioral

    story

    can

    be

    told

    fully

    either

    from

    the

    inside,

    as

    many

    cognitivists

    have

    attempted

    to

    do,

    or

    from

    the

    outside,

    as

    many

    behaviorists

    have

    attempted

    to

    do. Joint

    inquiry

    among

    behaviorists

    and

    cognitivists

    could lead

    to

    a

    more

    complete

    understand

    ing

    of

    both

    the

    environmental

    and the

    private

    determinants

    of behavior.

    This

    paper

    is

    written

    in

    the

    spirit

    of

    fostering

    cooperation

    among

    behaviorists

    and

    cognitivists.

    Skinner's

    criticisms

    of

    cognitive

    psychology

    may

    be

    divided into

    two

    propo

    sitions

    which

    will be

    examined

    in

    separate

    papers.

    First,

    cognitive

    theories

    lack

    explanatory

    power.

    Second,

    cognitive

    theories obstruct

    the search for

    the

    causes

    of

    behavior.

    The

    aim

    of

    this

    paper

    is

    to

    critically

    evaluate

    the

    first

    proposition

    and

    to

    argue

    that

    Skinner

    has

    not

    identified

    principled

    limitations

    on

    the

    ex

    planatory

    power

    of

    cognitive

    theory.

    It

    is

    important

    to note what

    is

    at stake

    here.

    If all

    cognitive explanations

    were

    logically

    flawed, cognitive

    theories

    and

    the

    research

    they

    guide

    would

    be

    unworthy

    of

    the

    serious

    attention

    of

    radical

    behaviorists,

    and

    attempts

    to

    bridge

    behavioral

    and

    cognitive

    analyses

    would

    be

    ill-advised.

    This

    paper

    also

    examines

    some

    of

    the weaknesses

    of Skinner's

    pro

    gram

    for

    explaining

    behavior,

    particularly

    behavior

    that

    is influenced

    by

    biologi

    cal factors.

    The

    aim

    is

    not to

    disparage

    the radical

    behaviorist

    outlook,

    to

    which

    the author

    is

    highly sympathetic,

    but

    to

    disarm

    ineffective

    criticisms

    that detract

    from

    the

    radical

    behaviorist

    position.

    After

    all,

    if

    behaviorism

    is

    to

    advance,

    it

    must be

    criticized

    by

    behaviorists

    (Sidman,

    1976).

    The

    plan

    of

    this

    paper

    is to

    evaluate

    separately

    each of

    Skinner's

    three

    main

    proposals regarding

    the

    inadequacy

    of

    cognitive

    explanations.

    These

    proposals

    may

    be

    summarized

    as

    follows.

    First,

    cognitive

    explanations

    are

    incomplete

    in

    H

    am

    grateful

    to

    John

    Donahoe,

    J.

    D.

    Keehn,

    Jan

    Krueger,

    Steve

    Sadowsky,

    and

    an

    anonymous

    re

    viewer

    for

    their

    helpful

    comments

    on

    an

    earlier

    version

    of

    this

    paper.

    Requests

    for

    reprints

    should

    be

    sent

    to

    Michael

    G.

    Wessells,

    Department

    of

    Psychology,

    Vassar

    College,

    Poughkeepsie,

    New

    York 12601.

    153

  • 8/18/2019 03 a Critique of Skinner's Views on the Explanatory Inadequacy of Cognitive Theories

    3/19

    Michael

    G.

    Wessells

    that

    they

    fail

    to

    specify

    the

    environmental antecedents

    of

    inner events.

    Second,

    cognitive

    explanations

    are

    fictional

    because

    they

    are

    circular and because

    the

    putative

    inner

    processes

    are

    not

    causes

    of

    behavior

    but

    are

    either

    mediational

    or

    epiphenomenal.

    Third,

    cognitive

    explanations

    are

    unnecessary

    since

    they

    add

    nothing to an exhaustive analysis of the functional relations between the envi

    ronment

    and behavior.

    These

    proposals

    are

    difficult

    to

    evaluate

    for

    several

    reasons.

    For

    one

    thing,

    Skinner's

    position

    is

    dynamic,

    even

    ambivalent

    (Dennett,

    1978),

    and

    he

    some

    times modifies the

    strength

    of

    or

    the

    grounds

    on

    which he

    makes

    a

    particular

    statement

    (cf.

    Scriven,

    1956).

    Further,

    Skinner's

    objections

    intertwine extensive

    ly,

    so an

    evaluation

    of his

    critique

    requires

    an

    analysis

    of

    his

    overall

    approach.

    Although

    this

    paper

    concerns

    his

    criticisms of

    experimental cognitive

    psychol

    ogy,

    particularly

    theories of information

    processing,

    it

    will

    be

    necessary

    in

    some

    instances

    to

    examine his

    broader, and,

    in

    general,

    older views

    on

    mentalism

    and

    on cognitive theories from the nonexperimental areas of psychology. The analy

    sis

    of Skinner's

    older

    views

    may

    seem

    unfair

    because

    cognitive

    theories have

    .changed

    rapidly

    in recent

    years.

    But

    the

    older

    ideas discussed

    below

    have

    occur

    red

    repeatedly

    and have

    appeared

    in

    works

    that Skinner

    published

    after

    the

    mid-1960s,

    following

    the

    rise of

    theories of

    information

    processing.

    Although

    contemporary cognitive

    theories

    will

    be discussed in

    order

    to

    show the

    timeli

    ness

    of

    the

    issues,

    most

    of

    the

    statements

    regarding

    the nature

    of

    cognitive

    analy

    ses

    could

    have been

    made

    in

    reference to

    prominent

    theories

    from

    the

    1960s

    and

    the

    early

    1970s.

    Moreover,

    many

    of the

    theories

    discussed

    in

    this

    paper

    and in its

    sequel

    had

    appeared

    well

    before

    1977,

    the

    year

    in

    which

    Skinner

    published

    his

    most recent critique of cognitive psychology. Keeing these points inmind, Skin

    ner's

    main

    proposals

    regarding

    the

    explanatory

    inadequacy

    of

    cognitive

    theory

    are

    now

    examined.

    INCOMPLETENESS

    The

    proposal

    that

    cognitive

    theories

    are

    incomplete

    is

    illustrated

    in

    the fol

    lowing

    passages

    concerning

    mental

    way

    stations, thirst,

    and

    feelings,

    respectively.

    .

    .

    .

    We

    may

    object,

    first,

    to

    the

    predilection

    for

    unfinished causal

    se

    quences. ... An action is not explained by attributing it to expectations

    until

    the

    expectations

    have

    in

    turn

    been

    accounted

    for.

    .

    . .

    (Skinner,

    1969,

    p.

    240)

    ...

    In

    each

    case

    we

    have

    a

    causal

    chain

    consisting

    of

    three

    links:

    (1)

    an

    operation

    performed

    on

    the

    organism

    from

    without

    ?

    for

    example,

    water

    deprivation;

    (2)

    an

    inner

    condition

    -

    for

    example,

    physiological

    or

    psychic

    thirst;

    and

    (3)

    a

    kind of

    behavior

    -

    for

    example,

    drinking.

    .

    . .

    The

    most

    objectionable

    practice

    is to

    follow

    the

    causal

    sequence

    back

    only

    as

    far

    as

    the

    hypothetical

    second link.

    .

    . .

    ...

    We

    cannot

    account

    for the

    behavior

    of

    any

    system

    while

    staying

    wholly inside it; eventually we must turn to forces operating upon the

    organism

    from

    without.

    (Skinner,

    1953,

    pp.

    34-35)

    154

  • 8/18/2019 03 a Critique of Skinner's Views on the Explanatory Inadequacy of Cognitive Theories

    4/19

  • 8/18/2019 03 a Critique of Skinner's Views on the Explanatory Inadequacy of Cognitive Theories

    5/19

    Michael

    G.

    Wessells

    computer

    programs

    To

    be

    sure,

    a

    cognitive

    theory

    does

    not

    explain

    the

    occurrence

    of

    a

    particular

    response

    by specifying

    the

    environmental

    antecedents

    of

    the

    response.

    Yet

    an

    explanatory

    cognitive

    account

    does accommodate

    the

    effects

    of

    the

    environ

    ment. In a complete cognitive account, the effects of exposure to particular

    stimuli

    would be

    deducible

    from

    a

    set

    of

    universal

    principles

    that

    specify

    the

    internal

    mechanisms

    that allow

    the

    environment

    to

    influence

    behavior.

    Using

    the

    familiar

    computer

    metaphor,

    a

    cognitive

    explanation

    would

    specify

    the

    princi

    ples

    governing

    the hardware

    of

    the

    human

    information

    processing

    system.

    In

    turn,

    these

    principles

    constrain

    the

    kinds

    of

    programs

    the

    system

    can

    use,

    the

    kinds

    of functions

    the

    system

    can

    perform

    and

    the

    mechanisms

    whereby

    the

    environment influences

    the

    system.

    Because such

    an

    account must

    accommodate

    the

    functional relations

    between environment

    and

    behavior,

    it is

    not

    incomplete

    in

    the

    sense

    Skinner

    contends.

    Indeed,

    if this

    type

    of

    explanation

    is

    incomplete,

    then behavioristic accounts must also be incomplete, for the functional relations

    determined

    by

    behaviorists

    are

    a

    subset of the data that

    a

    cognitive explanation

    must

    eventually

    accommodate.

    Because

    Skinner

    has not

    demonstrated

    that

    cog

    nitive

    explanations

    are

    logically incapable

    of

    accounting

    for the effects

    of

    the

    environment,

    his

    criticism

    is

    uncompelling.

    One

    might

    argue

    that

    a

    cognitive

    explanation

    is

    incomplete

    because it

    does

    not

    indicate

    which

    aspects

    of

    the

    phylogenetic

    environment

    determined

    the

    uni

    versal

    processing

    mechanisms

    of

    the

    organism

    and,

    indirectly,

    the

    effects

    of

    the

    ontogenetic

    environment. But this criticism

    applies

    to

    all

    analyses

    of

    behavior,

    Skinner's

    included.

    As

    will

    be

    argued

    in

    detail

    later,

    it

    may

    be

    neither

    necessary

    nor practical to demand that a theory identify the phylogenetic antecedents of

    behavior.

    The

    conclusion

    that

    cognitive explanations

    are

    not

    necessarily

    incomplete

    does

    not

    imply

    that current

    cognitive

    theories

    are

    explanatorily

    adequate.

    In

    fact,

    contemporary

    cognitive

    theories

    are

    descriptive,

    not

    explanatory

    (for

    dis

    cussions

    of

    descriptive

    and

    explanatory cognitive

    theories,

    see

    Honig,

    1978;

    Pylyshyn,

    1973).

    Extant

    theories have

    not

    identified

    universal

    properties

    or

    mechanisms that

    underlie

    and

    constrain

    learning. Rather,

    current

    theories

    postu

    late constucts

    and

    processes

    ?

    for

    example,

    the

    depth

    and

    the

    elaborateness

    of

    processing

    (Craik

    and

    Tulving, 1975),

    reconstructive

    retrieval

    processes

    (Spiro,

    1980), and schemata (Thorndyke, 1977)

    -

    that serve to order observations, to

    identify

    possible

    mechanisms

    underlying

    behavior and to

    generate

    predictions.

    These

    descriptive

    theories

    are

    incomplete,

    as

    both

    cognitivists

    and

    behaviorists

    would

    agree.

    Yet

    these

    theories

    constitute

    a

    transitional

    step

    along

    the

    arduous

    path

    toward

    explanation.

    Viewed

    in

    this

    manner,

    these

    theories

    are

    invulnerable

    to

    the

    criticism

    of

    incompleteness. They

    become

    vulnerable

    only

    if

    they

    are

    mistakenly

    regarded

    as

    explanatory.

    Nothing

    inherent in

    the

    cognitive

    approach

    necessitates

    such

    an

    error.

    Of

    course,

    this

    rejection

    of Skinner's

    incompleteness

    criticism

    does

    not

    entail

    the

    acceptance

    of the

    strategies

    that

    many

    cognitivists

    use

    in

    constructing

    an

    explanatory

    theory.

    These

    strategies

    and

    the

    problems

    associated with them will be discussed in the second paper.

    If

    cognitive

    theories

    are

    not

    inherently

    incomplete, why

    do

    they

    appear

    to

    be

    incomplete

    from

    the

    radical

    behaviorist

    outlook?

    Primary

    among

    the

    many

    possible

    reasons

    are

    the

    following. First,

    many

    of

    the

    cognitive

    accounts

    pro

    posed

    by

    laypeople

    (and

    by

    misguided

    psychologists)

    are

    incurably

    vague

    and

    in

    156

  • 8/18/2019 03 a Critique of Skinner's Views on the Explanatory Inadequacy of Cognitive Theories

    6/19

  • 8/18/2019 03 a Critique of Skinner's Views on the Explanatory Inadequacy of Cognitive Theories

    7/19

  • 8/18/2019 03 a Critique of Skinner's Views on the Explanatory Inadequacy of Cognitive Theories

    8/19

    A

    Critique

    Of

    Skinner's

    View

    Of

    The

    Explanatory Inadequacy

    Of

    Cognitive

    Theories

    (Skinner,

    1974,

    p.

    17;

    italics

    added)

    Here Skinner

    asserts

    that

    some

    private

    events,

    particularly

    those

    upon

    which

    we

    can

    introspect,

    are

    collateral

    products

    of

    conditioning

    histories

    and do not

    con

    trol behavior.

    For

    example,

    in

    memorizing

    a

    set

    of

    objects,

    one

    might

    construct

    an

    image of the objects and consciously inspect the image. The introspected

    image

    might

    appear

    to influence

    one's

    recall

    of

    the

    objects.

    From

    Skinner's

    perspective,

    however,

    the

    introspected

    image

    is

    a

    product

    of

    a

    history

    of

    rein

    forcement of

    op?rant seeing

    responses

    (Skinner,

    1953,

    pp.

    270-275; 1974,

    pp.

    82-86).

    Further,

    the

    introspected

    events

    are

    not

    causal,

    for

    the

    physiological

    processes

    involved

    in

    the

    shaping

    and the maintenance

    of behavior

    by

    contin

    gencies

    of

    reinforcement

    are

    beyond

    the

    scope

    of

    introspection

    (Skinner,

    1974,

    pp.

    216ff.;

    1977a,

    pp.

    9-10).

    For

    the sake of

    clarity,

    Skinner's views

    concerning circularity,

    the

    non

    causal status

    of

    private

    events,

    and

    epiphenomenalism

    will

    be

    examined

    sepa

    rately.

    Circularity

    The

    proposal

    that

    cognitive

    theories

    are

    logically

    circular is

    cogent

    in

    many

    instances.

    Indeed, cognitivists

    have

    recognized

    the

    circularity

    of influential

    theories such

    as

    the

    levels-of-processing

    analysis

    of

    memory

    (Baddeley,

    1978;

    Eysenck,

    1978;

    Postman,

    1975).

    The

    problem

    of

    circularity

    has

    hampered

    at

    tempts

    to

    define

    the

    units

    and the

    capacity

    of

    short-term

    memory

    (Glanzer

    and

    Razel,

    1974;

    Simon,

    1974),

    to

    distinguish empirically

    between short-term

    mem

    ory

    and

    long-term

    memory

    (Waugh

    and

    Norman,

    1965),

    and to

    determine

    the ef

    fects of

    semantic

    structure

    upon

    the retrieval of

    information

    from

    semantic

    memory

    (Smith,

    1978),

    among

    others.

    In

    pointing

    out

    this

    problem,

    Skinnerhas

    performed

    an

    important

    service.

    But

    logical

    circularity

    is

    no

    more a

    necessary

    problem

    of

    cognitive

    theories

    than of b?havioral theories. For example, constructs such as feature detectors

    (see

    Eimas

    and

    Miller,

    1978)

    and

    prototypes

    (see Posner,

    1969;

    Rosch,

    1977)

    have

    been defined

    independently

    of

    the data

    they

    were

    intended

    to

    explain.

    As

    physiological

    inquiry

    advances,

    the

    ability

    to

    define

    inner

    processes

    independent

    ly

    of

    the behavior

    to be

    explained

    will

    undoubtedly improve.

    Further,

    cognitiv

    ists

    can

    avoid

    the

    problem

    of

    circularity

    by anchoring

    constructs

    to

    logically

    independent

    operations

    (Garner,

    Hake and

    Eriksen,

    1956).

    Skinner's

    criticism also

    overlooks

    the

    point

    that

    logically

    circular

    theories

    can

    contribute

    to

    scientific

    inquiry,

    particularly

    in

    the

    initial

    stages

    of

    research

    (Audi,

    1976).

    Specifically,

    they

    help

    to

    organize

    observations

    and

    to

    make

    test

    able

    predictions

    that

    guide

    research.

    Indeed,

    the

    concepts

    of reinforcement

    and

    the

    op?rant organized

    and

    guided

    useful

    research

    before

    attempts

    were

    made

    (for example,Meehl, 1950; Schick, 1971) to define theconcepts independently

    of

    the

    phenomena

    they

    had

    been

    intended

    to

    explain.

    Along

    similar

    lines,

    Skinner's

    treatise

    on

    verbal

    behavior,

    an

    insightful

    interpretation

    that

    many,

    the

    author

    included,

    believe

    will

    guide

    useful

    research,

    proposed

    many

    circular

    ac

    counts.

    Consider

    the

    following

    statements

    concerning

    descriptive

    autoclitics,

    verbal

    responses

    that

    are

    controlled

    by

    other

    covert

    or

    overt

    verbal

    responses

    and

    that

    modify

    the

    reaction

    of

    the

    listener.

    The

    speaker

    may

    acquire

    verbal

    behavior

    descriptive

    of

    his

    own

    be

    havior.

    . .

    .

    The

    behavior

    so

    described

    may

    be

    verbal:

    the

    speaker

    may

    159

  • 8/18/2019 03 a Critique of Skinner's Views on the Explanatory Inadequacy of Cognitive Theories

    9/19

    Michael

    G.

    Wessells

    talk about

    himself

    talking.

    He

    may

    describe

    the

    responses

    he

    has

    made,

    is

    making,

    or

    will

    make.

    For

    example,

    he

    may

    say

    /

    said

    "Heads"

    or

    /

    now

    say

    "Heads"

    or

    /

    will

    say

    "Heads.

    "

    . . .

    The

    events

    available

    to

    him

    as

    stimuli

    consist

    of the

    products

    of

    his

    own

    behavior

    as

    speaker.

    He

    may

    hear himself or react to private stimuli associated with vocal behavior,

    possibly

    of

    a

    covert

    or

    even

    incipient

    form.

    . .

    .

    Such

    stimulation

    may

    also

    assume

    control

    of

    the verbal

    op?rant

    called the

    tact.

    (Skinner, 1957,

    pp.

    313-314)

    Here the

    private

    stimuli,

    particularly

    those

    associated

    with the

    covert

    responses,

    are

    inferred

    directly

    from

    the

    responses

    to be

    accounted for. This

    type

    of

    ac

    count,

    indisputably

    circular,

    occurs

    frequently

    throughout

    Verbal

    Behavior.

    The

    point

    is

    not

    that Skinner's

    analysis

    of

    verbal behavior

    is

    hopelessly

    circular

    (it

    is

    not)

    but

    that

    circularity

    per

    se

    does

    not

    rob

    an

    account of its

    value.

    Circularity

    is

    a

    grave

    problem

    when it

    is

    inherent

    in

    an

    account,

    as

    it is in

    many

    mentalistic

    accounts

    proposed

    by

    laypeople,

    and

    when it

    brings

    inquiry

    to

    an

    end. But

    as

    indicated

    above,

    cognitive

    theories

    are

    not

    inherently

    circular.

    Equally

    important,

    circular

    cognitive

    theories have not

    ended

    inquiry

    but have

    stimulated research aimed

    at

    defining

    independently

    constructs

    such

    as

    the

    level

    of

    processing

    (for

    example,

    Craik and

    Tulving,

    1975; Eysenck

    and

    Eysenck,

    1979).

    These

    considerations weaken

    Skinner's criticism

    substantially.

    Noncausal

    Status

    of

    Inner

    Events

    Skinner's second

    argumeht,

    that

    inner

    processes

    are

    not

    causes

    of behavior

    and that the ultimate causes of behavior are in the environment, leads to a logi

    cal

    regress

    (Audi,

    1976).

    For

    example,

    the

    effects

    of

    the

    ontogenetic

    environment

    at

    a

    particular

    moment

    depend

    in

    part

    on

    the

    effects

    of

    previous

    exposures

    to

    the

    environment,

    as

    witnessed

    in

    the

    phenomena

    of

    blocking

    and

    selective

    atten

    tion

    (Mackintosh, 1974). How,

    then,

    can

    the

    effects

    of

    the

    ontogenetic

    environ

    ment

    that

    occur

    at

    one

    particular

    moment be

    singled

    out

    as

    causal?

    Skinner's

    attempted

    resolution

    of

    this

    problem

    is

    characteristically

    prag

    matic.

    ...

    It

    is

    true

    that

    we

    could

    trace

    human

    behavior

    not

    only

    to

    the

    physical

    conditions

    which

    shape

    and

    maintain

    it but

    also

    to

    the

    causes

    of

    those conditions and the causes of those

    causes,

    almost ad

    infinitum,

    but

    there

    is

    no

    point

    in

    going

    back

    beyond

    the

    point

    at

    which

    effective

    action

    can

    be

    taken.

    That

    point

    is

    not

    to be

    found

    in

    the

    psyche,

    and the

    explanatory

    force

    of

    mental

    life has

    steadily

    declined

    as

    the

    promise

    of

    the

    environment

    has

    come

    to

    be

    more

    clearly

    understood.

    (Skinner,

    1974,

    p.

    210;

    italics

    added)

    . . .

    the

    real

    causes

    lay

    in

    the

    environment,

    because if

    we

    want to

    do

    anything

    about

    genocide,

    it

    is to

    the

    environment

    we

    must turn.

    . .

    .

    (Skinner

    and

    Blanshard,

    1967,

    p.

    331)

    On this

    view, explanation and the ability to control behavior are intimately re

    lated.

    Skinner

    regards

    the

    environment

    as

    the

    cause

    of

    behavior because

    it

    is

    the

    environment

    that is

    directly

    accessible

    and

    that

    can

    be

    used to

    predict

    and

    con

    trol

    behavior.

    For

    Skinner,

    explanation

    is the

    handmaiden

    of

    pragmatism.

    This

    approach

    is

    troublesome because the

    ability

    to

    control

    behavior

    is

    neither

    necessary

    nor

    sufficient

    for

    the

    achievement

    of

    an

    explanatory

    account.

    160

  • 8/18/2019 03 a Critique of Skinner's Views on the Explanatory Inadequacy of Cognitive Theories

    10/19

    A

    Critique

    Of

    Skinner's

    View

    Of

    The

    Explanatory

    Inadequacy

    Of

    Cognitive

    Theories

    Many

    theories

    in

    astronomy

    have

    explanatory

    power

    even

    though

    they

    have not

    enhanced

    our

    ability

    to

    control

    cosmic

    events

    (Martin,

    1978).

    Further,

    environ

    mental

    events

    that

    are

    useful

    in

    predicting

    and

    controlling

    behavior

    may

    not

    be

    causal or explanatory in any intelligible sense. For example, medical physicians

    often

    prescribe

    placebo

    pills,

    the

    ingestion

    of which

    alleviates the

    patients'

    symptoms.

    In these

    cases,

    the

    ingestion

    of the

    placebo

    clearly

    controls

    behavior.

    But

    it

    seems

    odd

    to

    argue

    that the

    ingestion

    of the

    pill

    therefore

    caused

    or

    ex

    plained

    the

    patients'

    behavior.

    For the

    ingestion

    of

    the

    placebo

    may

    have been

    a

    sufficient but

    not

    a

    necessary

    condition for

    the

    modification

    of

    behavior. Behav

    ioral

    control,

    then,

    can

    be achieved

    in

    the

    absence

    of

    explanation

    and

    vice

    versa.

    Environmental

    factors

    cannot be ascribed

    a

    privileged

    explanatory

    status

    simply

    because

    they

    are

    accessible

    and useful in

    controlling

    behavior.

    Another

    problem

    is

    that

    pragmatism

    is

    a

    fickle criterion

    by

    which

    to

    judge

    theories. Contemporary cognitive theories have already advanced the teaching of

    reasoning

    (Collins, 1977),

    the

    measurement

    of

    intelligence

    (Sternberg,

    1977)

    and

    the

    improvement

    of

    memorial

    skills

    (Atkinson,

    1975;

    Morris,

    1977).

    Conceiv

    ably,

    cognitive

    theories

    might

    eventually identify

    methods

    for

    controlling

    behav

    ior

    that

    surpass

    those

    generated

    by

    behavioral

    theories.

    If that

    were

    to

    occur,

    would

    one,

    following

    Skinner's

    approach,

    conclude that

    cognitive

    theories

    pro

    vide

    better

    explanations

    than

    behavioral

    theories

    provide?

    The

    absurdity

    of such

    a

    conclusion

    indicates that

    it

    is

    unjustifiable

    to

    ele

    vate,

    as

    Skinner

    has

    done,

    pragmatic

    and

    methodological

    concerns

    to

    the status

    of

    explanatory

    prerequisites.

    An

    explanatory

    theory

    may

    advance

    one's

    ability

    to control a phenomenon, but the ability to control the phenomenon is not the

    sine

    qua

    non

    of

    the

    explanatory

    power

    of

    the

    theory.

    The

    explanatory

    adequacy

    of

    a

    theory

    should

    be decided

    by

    the

    extent to

    which the

    theory

    agrees

    with

    existing

    observations,

    exhibits

    generality

    and internal

    consistency,

    makes

    novel,

    non

    trivial

    predictions,

    converges

    with

    other

    theories,

    achieves

    parsimony,

    and

    so

    on.

    The control of

    behavior

    is

    relevant

    to

    the

    task

    of

    explaining

    behavior

    only

    insofar

    as

    the

    predictions

    of

    the

    theory

    are

    assessed

    through

    attempts

    to

    control

    behavior.

    But

    the

    kinds of

    predictions

    one

    aims

    to

    make need

    not

    be

    dictated

    by

    the

    pragmatic

    desire

    to

    change

    behavior for

    the better.

    Ironically,

    the

    attempt

    to

    use

    the

    ability

    to

    control

    behavior

    as

    the

    criterion

    for deciding what is explanatory works against Skinner's environmentalist

    approach

    in

    some

    instances.

    According

    to

    a

    strict

    interpretation

    of

    Skinner's

    position,

    genes

    lack

    causal

    status since

    they

    are

    inner structures and

    are

    products

    of the

    phylogenetic

    environment

    (Skinner,

    1953,

    p.

    26;

    1969,

    p.

    87;

    1974,

    pp. 33-45).

    But

    the

    phylogenetic

    environment

    is

    largely

    inaccessible

    and,

    apart

    from

    the

    time-consuming

    method of

    selective

    breeding,

    it cannot be

    used

    to

    con

    trol

    behavior.

    In

    contrast,

    genetic

    structure

    is

    relatively

    discoverable

    and

    acces

    sible,

    and

    the

    ability

    to

    control characteristics

    by

    manipulating

    genetic

    structure

    is

    advancing

    rapidly.

    Using

    the criterion

    of

    control,

    genes

    seem

    to have

    a

    stronger

    claim

    to

    causal

    status

    than the

    phylogenetic

    environment

    has.

    On

    Skinner's

    own

    grounds, then, the argument that it is the phylogenetic environment, not the

    genes,

    that

    causes

    behavior

    must

    be

    rejected.

    With

    regard

    to

    discovering

    the

    bio

    logical

    determinants

    of

    behavior,

    the

    strategy

    of

    environmentalizing

    the

    causes

    of

    behavior

    (Schnaitter,

    1978)

    may

    not

    pay.

    One

    might

    object

    that

    Skinner

    would

    probably

    be

    willing

    to attribute

    causal

    161

  • 8/18/2019 03 a Critique of Skinner's Views on the Explanatory Inadequacy of Cognitive Theories

    11/19

    Michael

    G.

    Wessells

    status

    to

    genes

    so

    long

    as

    particular

    genetic

    antecedents

    of

    behavior

    had

    become

    isolable

    and

    manipulable

    via

    physiological procedures

    (see

    Skinner,

    1972,

    p.

    422;

    1974,

    p. 215).

    But

    here

    again,

    methodological

    considerations

    are

    dictating

    what

    counts

    as an

    explanation;

    the

    positions

    of

    the

    horse

    and the

    cart

    have been

    re

    versed. Also note that in the history of biology, genetic explanations became

    useful

    well before

    genes

    had

    been

    defined

    and

    made

    manipulable

    on a

    physio

    logical

    level

    (Carlson,

    1966; Dunn,

    1965).

    One

    may

    agree

    with Skinner that

    ex

    planatory

    concepts

    must,

    in

    principle,

    refer

    to

    physical

    events.

    But it

    does

    not

    follow

    that

    a

    concept

    lacks

    explanatory

    power

    unless

    its

    physical

    referents have

    been

    identified.

    Like

    investigators

    in the

    biological

    and

    the

    physical

    sciences,

    psychologists

    may

    use

    explanatory

    concepts

    even

    when

    the

    physical

    referents

    of

    the

    concepts

    are

    unknown.

    It

    is

    worth

    mentioning

    here

    why

    many

    cognitivists

    do not

    view

    physiological

    analysis

    as

    their chief

    method.5

    As

    pointed

    out

    earlier, cognitivists

    hold

    that

    the

    functional properties of information processors can be specified on a conceptual

    level.

    Many

    of

    the

    most

    complex

    aspects

    of

    the

    operation

    of

    a

    system

    can

    be

    an

    alyzed

    most

    naturally

    at

    a

    molar,

    nonphysiological

    level

    (Fodor, 1981).

    More

    over,

    attempts

    to

    explain

    and

    to control

    inner

    processes

    need

    not

    await

    the

    de

    velopment

    of

    a

    highly

    advanced

    physiological technology

    that

    could be used

    to

    identify

    the

    physical

    bases

    of inner

    processes.

    This

    approach

    has

    a

    pragmatic

    ring

    to

    it,

    and it

    is

    consistent with

    Skinner's

    (1938)

    view that

    explanatory

    (func

    tional)

    relations

    can

    be discerned

    even

    though

    the

    physiological

    bases

    of

    these

    relations

    are

    unknown.

    In

    conclusion,

    Skinner'.s

    argument

    that

    only

    the

    environment

    causes

    behav

    ior fails because it entails the enslavement of explanation to pragmatic and

    methodological

    concerns.

    A

    more

    reasonable

    position

    for radical behaviorists

    is

    that

    both

    environmental and inner

    events

    are causes

    of

    behavior

    (see

    Schnaitter,

    1978).

    Cognitive

    accounts

    may

    seem

    to

    depart

    from

    this

    view since

    they explain

    behavior

    in

    terms

    of

    universal

    inner

    processes.

    Recall,

    however,

    that

    a

    cognitive

    explanation

    must

    accommodate

    the

    functional

    relations

    between

    the

    environ

    ment

    and behavior that

    are

    formed

    in

    the

    lifetime of the

    organism.

    In

    this

    sense,

    cognitive

    explanations

    do not

    ignore

    environmental

    causes.

    Further,

    cognitive

    explanations

    do

    not

    attribute

    causal

    status

    to all

    inner

    events,

    and

    the

    door

    leading

    to

    epiphenomenalism

    is thus

    kept

    open.

    Epiphenomenalism

    Skinner

    (1974,

    p.

    17; 1977a,

    pp.

    9-10)

    has

    stated

    that

    what

    we

    introspect

    upon

    are

    collateral

    products,

    not

    causes

    of

    behavior,

    and

    that the

    physiological

    processes

    that

    mediate the

    control

    of

    behavior

    by

    the

    environment

    are

    beyond

    the

    reach

    of

    introspection.

    He

    also

    asserts

    that

    cognitive

    psychologists

    say

    they

    know

    cognitive

    processes

    through

    introspection.

    Cognitive psychologists

    have

    two

    answers

    to

    the

    charge

    that

    the

    men

    tal

    apparatus

    is

    a

    metaphor

    or

    construct.

    One

    is

    that

    cognitive

    processes

    are

    known through introspection. Do not all thinking persons know that

    they

    think?

    .

    .

    .

    No

    one

    doubts

    that

    behavior

    involves internal

    processes;

    the

    question

    is

    how

    well

    they

    can

    be

    known

    through

    introspection.

    .

    .

    .

    ^Of

    course, many

    cognitive

    psychologists

    are

    searching

    for

    the

    pysiological

    bases

    of

    cognitive

    processes.

    See Posner

    (1978)

    and

    Thatcher

    and John

    (1977).

    162

  • 8/18/2019 03 a Critique of Skinner's Views on the Explanatory Inadequacy of Cognitive Theories

    12/19

    A

    Critique

    Of

    Skinner's View

    Of

    The

    Explanatory

    Inadequacy

    Of

    Cognitive

    Theories

    (Skinner,

    1977a,

    pp.

    9-10)

    This

    passage

    reveals

    a

    serious

    misunderstanding

    of

    contemporary

    cognitive

    psychology.

    Most

    cognitivists

    now

    believe that

    many

    inner,

    causal

    processes

    cannot be introspected upon. Indeed, Neisser expressed this view in 1967 in his

    discussion of visual

    images:

    . . .

    My

    own

    view,

    as

    the

    reader

    has

    already discovered,

    is

    that both

    memory

    images

    and

    percepts

    are

    constructed

    anew on

    every

    occasion

    when

    they

    are

    experienced.

    .

    .

    .

    When

    an

    image

    is

    constructed,

    the

    opera

    tions of

    synthesis

    use

    the

    information,

    which

    otherwise is

    carried

    silently,

    unconsciously,

    in

    ways

    which

    (by definition)

    we can

    hardly

    "visualize."

    (Neisser,

    1967,

    p. 170)

    Similarly,

    Kosslyn

    (1978),

    who

    has

    used

    introspective

    evidence

    extensively

    in

    his research, writes

    To

    some,

    the

    study

    of

    imagery

    seems

    simple.

    All

    one

    needs

    to

    do

    is

    to

    introspect.

    This is

    equivalent

    to

    saying

    that

    in

    order

    to

    study

    visual

    perception,

    all

    one

    needs

    to

    do is look.

    Clearly,

    much

    processing

    goes

    on

    before

    we

    become

    conscious

    of

    an

    object,

    either when

    we are

    perceiving

    it

    or

    imaging

    it. An

    understanding

    of

    either

    phenomenon

    entails

    uncover

    ing

    the

    mechanisms

    responsible

    for

    representing

    and

    processing

    the rele

    vant

    information.

    . . .

    (Kosslyn, 1978,

    p.

    217)

    Past

    generations

    of

    cognitive

    psychologists

    may

    have based

    explanatory

    accounts

    primarily upon introspective knowledge. But most contemporary cognitivists

    believe that

    introspection

    cannot

    possibly

    reveal the universal

    processing

    mech

    anisms that would constitute

    an

    explanatory

    account.

    Further,

    many

    cognitivists

    believe

    that

    what

    is known

    through

    introspection

    is

    epiphenomenal

    and

    is

    unrevealing

    of

    inner

    pausai

    processes (Anderson

    and

    Bower,

    .1973;

    Anderson,

    1976,

    1978; Kieras,

    1978;

    Pylyshyn,

    1973,

    1978;

    Simon,

    1972).

    Consider,

    for

    example,

    these

    passages

    from

    an

    influential

    paper

    written

    by

    Pylyshyn.

    .

    .

    .

    Just

    because

    we know that

    we

    use

    certain

    mnemonic

    strategies,

    or

    that

    we

    say

    certain

    things

    to

    ourselves,

    or

    that

    we

    "see"

    certain

    ob

    jects

    in our "mind's

    eye"

    or "hear" ourselves

    rehearsing

    a series of num

    bers,

    etc.,

    we

    cannot

    assume

    that

    the

    contents

    of

    such

    subjective

    knowl

    edge

    can

    be

    identified

    with

    the kind

    of

    information-processing

    proce

    dures

    which

    will

    go

    into

    an

    explanatory

    theory.

    (Pylyshyn,

    1973,

    p.

    3)

    . . .

    The

    role

    of

    experienced

    images

    (i.e.,

    appearances)

    in

    thinking

    is

    by

    no

    means

    clear

    since

    even

    if

    we

    make

    the

    assumption

    that

    the

    con

    tents

    of

    our

    experiences

    reveal

    theoretically

    useful

    psychological

    proc

    esses,

    it still

    remains

    true

    that

    very

    little

    (if

    any)

    of

    the

    thinking

    is

    car

    ried

    by

    such

    processes.

    (Pylyshyn,

    1973,

    p.

    6)

    Overall, cognitivists in experimental psychology simply do

    not

    believe

    that

    cognitive

    processes

    are

    known

    through

    introspection.

    For

    the most

    part, they

    use

    introspective

    reports

    as

    data

    to

    be

    explained,

    and

    they

    agree

    with

    Skinner

    (1974,

    p.

    16)

    that

    introspective

    reports

    may

    be useful

    even

    though

    they

    do

    not

    reveal the

    causes

    of

    behavior

    (Kosslyn

    and

    Pomerantz,

    1977). Thus,

    the

    prevalent

    cognitivistic

    position

    on

    introspective knowledge

    agrees remarkably

    well

    with

    163

  • 8/18/2019 03 a Critique of Skinner's Views on the Explanatory Inadequacy of Cognitive Theories

    13/19

    Michael

    G.

    Wessells

    that of

    Skinner.

    It is unfortunate

    that

    behaviorists

    and

    cognitivists

    are

    quick

    to

    point

    out

    their

    differences

    and

    to

    overlook

    their

    convergences.

    Although

    the

    epiphenomenalist

    position

    may

    be

    valid,

    Skinner

    maintains

    the

    position

    on

    contestable

    grounds.

    Skinner's chief

    supporting

    argument

    is

    that the

    construction of our nervous system does not allow us to introspect upon the

    physiological

    events

    that

    mediate

    the effects of

    the

    environment

    on

    behavior

    (Skinner,

    1974,

    p.

    216;

    1977a,

    p.

    10).

    But it

    is

    conceivable

    that

    one

    could

    intro

    spect upon

    causal

    factors without

    introspecting

    upon

    physiological

    events.

    As

    sume,

    for

    example,

    that

    at

    a

    particular

    time,

    there

    occurs

    in

    the

    brain

    of

    person

    P

    a

    set

    of

    neural

    events

    N

    and that

    P

    introspectively

    observes

    a

    visual

    image

    (I)

    of

    a

    set

    of

    objects.

    Also

    assume

    that

    P

    recalls

    the

    names

    of

    the

    objects

    if

    and

    only

    if

    N

    and

    I

    are

    occurring.

    Presumably,

    Skinner's

    position

    would

    be

    that the neural

    events

    (N)

    cause

    both

    the

    image

    and

    the recall

    of

    the

    objects,

    so

    the

    image

    is

    epiphenomenal

    and

    does

    not

    reveal the

    causes

    (N)

    of the

    recall of the

    objects.

    Another possibility, however, is that the image consists of the set of neural

    events

    N

    in

    much the

    same

    way

    that

    an

    overt

    response

    such

    as

    the

    lifting

    of

    an

    arm

    consists

    of

    a

    set

    of

    neural

    and

    muscular

    events.

    On

    this

    view,

    I

    can

    be

    con

    strued

    as

    the

    cause

    of

    the

    recall of the

    objects

    even

    though

    I

    reveals

    nothing

    about

    N.

    This

    hypothetical

    example

    is

    not

    intended

    as

    an

    endorsement

    of

    the

    central-state

    identity

    thesis.

    Rather,

    the

    point

    is that

    physicalism

    does

    not

    re

    quire

    the

    view

    that

    introspective

    knowledge

    is

    necessarily

    limited because

    of

    the

    inability

    to

    introspect

    upon

    physiological

    events

    on

    a

    molecular

    level.

    Whether

    introspected

    events

    are

    epiphenomenal

    is

    an

    empirical

    issue that

    cannot

    be

    decided

    by argument

    or

    by

    apodictic

    decree.6

    Even

    if

    future

    research

    supported the epiphenomenalist position, the cognitive outlook would not there

    by

    be

    undermined.

    NONNECESSITY

    Skinner's

    third criticism of

    cognitive

    explanations

    is

    that

    they

    are unneces

    sary.

    .

    .

    .

    The

    behavior

    generated

    by

    a

    given

    set

    of

    contingencies

    can

    be

    ac

    counted

    for without

    appealing

    to

    hypothetical

    inner

    states

    or

    processes.

    If

    a

    conspicuous

    stimulus

    does

    not

    have

    an

    effect,

    it is

    not

    because

    the

    organism

    has not attended to it or because some central

    gatekeeper

    has

    screened it

    out,

    but

    because the

    stimulus

    plays

    no

    important

    role

    in

    the

    prevailing

    contingencies.

    The

    other

    cognitive

    processes

    invoked

    to

    salvage

    an

    input-output

    formula

    can

    be

    disposed

    of

    in the

    same

    way.

    (Skinner,

    1969,

    p. 8)

    . . .

    There

    is

    a

    familiar

    experiment

    on

    color

    generalization

    in

    which

    a

    pigeon

    pecks

    at

    a

    disk

    of,

    say,

    green

    light,

    the behavior

    being

    reinforced

    on

    a

    variable

    interval

    schedule.

    When

    a

    stable

    rate

    of

    responding develops,

    6Currently,

    extreme

    versions

    of the

    epiphenomenalist

    position

    are

    being challenged

    in

    research

    con

    cerning imagery (Kosslyn

    and

    Pomerantz,

    1977;

    Shepard,

    1978).

    According

    to

    one

    seminal model

    (Kosslyn,

    1980), images

    are

    constructed

    from

    abstract

    conceptual

    knowledge

    that is in

    a

    propositional,

    nonintrospect

    ible format.

    But

    an

    image,

    once

    constructed,

    can

    be

    used in

    further

    processing.

    For

    example,

    the

    image

    can

    be

    scanned

    or

    rotated,

    and

    global

    parts

    of

    the

    image

    can

    be

    compared.

    On this

    view,

    an

    introspectable,

    con

    structed

    product

    of

    nonconscious

    processing

    may

    be

    functional,

    not

    epiphenomenal.

    Needless

    to

    say,

    the

    evaluation

    of

    this

    view

    requires

    much

    more

    research.

    164

  • 8/18/2019 03 a Critique of Skinner's Views on the Explanatory Inadequacy of Cognitive Theories

    14/19

  • 8/18/2019 03 a Critique of Skinner's Views on the Explanatory Inadequacy of Cognitive Theories

    15/19

    Michael

    G.

    Wessells

    strictly

    behavioral

    analyses.

    One

    of

    these

    gaps

    concerns

    biological

    influences

    on

    learning

    (Seligman,

    1970;

    Shettleworth, 1972;

    Staddon and

    Simmelhag,

    1971).

    Skinner

    (1966,

    1969, 1974,

    1975,

    1977b)

    often

    accounts

    for

    biological

    influ

    ences

    by attributing

    a

    particular

    instance

    of

    stimulus control to

    the effects of the

    phylogenetic environment. But these attributions, though provocative, tend to

    be

    piecemeal

    listings,

    not

    systematic

    accounts.

    Nowhere does

    he

    provide

    an or

    ganized

    account of

    the

    phylogenetic

    contingencies

    that,

    for

    example,

    shaped

    organisms

    in

    ways

    such

    that their behavior

    is

    modified

    by

    some

    contingencies

    of reinforcement but

    not

    by

    others.

    Equally

    important,

    it

    is

    unlikely

    that

    he will

    provide

    such

    an

    account.

    For

    one

    thing,

    the

    phylogenetic

    environment

    is

    mostly

    inaccessible,

    so

    it

    is

    extremely

    difficult

    to

    identify

    the

    environmental factors

    that

    shaped

    behavior

    in

    ancestral

    environments. And

    because

    the

    ontogenetic

    envi

    ronment is

    of

    greatest

    practical

    value

    in

    controlling

    behavior,

    Skinner

    has

    focused

    his research

    almost

    entirely

    on

    the

    ontogenetic

    determinants

    of behavior.

    In the absence of systematic investigations of and accounts of the effects of bio

    logical

    factors

    on

    learning,

    theories of

    stimulus

    control

    are

    incomplete.

    In

    accounting

    for the

    effects of

    biological

    factors, cognitive

    theories

    may

    be

    quite

    useful.

    As discussed

    previously, cognitive

    explanations

    include formalized

    statements

    or

    representations

    concerning

    the

    universal,

    biologically

    based

    prop

    erties

    of

    the

    organism.

    These

    statements,

    provided

    that

    they

    accommodate

    the

    interactions between

    biological

    and

    ontogenetic

    factors that

    occur

    during

    devel

    opment,

    could

    be

    used

    to

    predict

    the

    constraints

    on

    the

    stimuli that will control

    the

    behavior

    of

    organisms.

    Of

    course,

    one

    could

    argue

    that

    cognitive

    explana

    tions,

    even

    if

    attainable,

    are

    not

    necessary

    for

    accounting

    for the effects of

    bio

    logical factors. Skinner (1953, p. 54; 1969, p. 173) believes thatphysiological

    analyses

    will

    eventually

    fill in

    the

    gaps

    in

    our

    understanding

    of the effects of

    the

    phylogenetic

    environment.

    But

    this

    argument

    cuts

    both

    ways.

    If

    cognitive

    theo

    ries

    can

    account

    for observations

    that

    can

    also

    be

    accounted

    for

    via

    behavioral

    and

    physiological

    analyses,

    then the

    latter

    two

    could be viewed

    as

    unnecessary.

    In

    reality,

    our

    present

    knowledge

    is too

    limited

    to

    allow

    definite statements

    about

    the

    necessity

    or

    the

    nonnecessity

    of

    particular

    approaches.

    The

    deeper

    problem

    facing

    Skinner's criticism is that

    an

    account

    that is

    logically

    unnecessary

    is

    not

    therefore

    unimportant

    or

    invalid. For

    example,

    even

    if

    the

    laws

    of

    chemistry

    were

    reducible

    to the

    laws of

    physics,

    it

    would

    not

    fol

    low that the laws of chemistry lack explanatory power and practical utility.

    Moreover,

    a

    physiologist

    could

    argue

    that

    behavioristic

    accounts

    are

    unnecessary

    because

    functional

    relations

    between

    the

    environment

    and

    behavior

    can

    be

    explained

    on a

    physiological

    level.

    Yet this

    does

    not

    imply

    that behavioristic

    accounts

    are

    unimportant

    or

    invalid. The

    laws of

    behavior

    are

    laws

    regardless

    of

    the

    availability

    of

    knowledge

    about

    underlying

    physiological

    processes

    (Skinner,

    1938,

    pp.

    418ff.).

    And the

    behavioral laws have

    obvious

    practical

    value

    (see

    Catania

    and

    Brigham,

    1978).

    Similarly, cognitive analyses

    may

    be

    important

    even

    if

    they

    are

    logically

    unnecessary.

    For

    one

    thing, they

    may

    provide

    system

    atic

    accounts

    of

    the

    effects

    of

    biological

    factors

    on

    behavior.

    Further,

    they

    are

    advantageous in analyzing behavior that has arisen through a complex and un

    known

    history.

    This

    point

    will

    receive additional

    attention in the

    sequel

    to this

    paper.

    In

    conclusion,

    cognitive

    accounts

    are

    not

    added

    theoretical

    baggage

    that

    is

    invented

    whenever

    the

    environmental

    antecedents of

    behavior

    are

    inconspicuous.

    166

  • 8/18/2019 03 a Critique of Skinner's Views on the Explanatory Inadequacy of Cognitive Theories

    16/19

    A

    Critique

    Of

    Skinner's

    View

    Of

    The

    Explanatory

    Inadequacy

    Of

    Cognitive

    Theories

    Even

    if

    an

    individual's

    history

    of

    environmental-behavioral

    relations

    were

    known

    completely, cognitivists

    would view

    the

    explanatory

    task

    as

    incomplete.

    They

    would ask

    what

    were

    the

    biological properties

    that

    permitted

    the

    environment

    to

    have the observed effects on behavior. In light of Skinner's primary goal of con

    trolling behavior,

    it is

    understandable

    that he

    sees

    no

    reason

    to

    look

    beyond

    the

    environmental determinants

    of

    behavior. But in

    light

    of

    cognitivists'

    goal

    of

    explaining

    behavior and

    the

    environmental

    influences

    thereon,

    it

    is

    understand

    able

    that

    they

    look

    beyond

    the

    environmental

    determinants

    of

    behavior.

    Wheth

    er

    cognitivists

    will

    achieve

    an

    explanatory

    theory

    cannot

    now

    be

    determined,

    and it

    is too

    early

    to

    depict cognitive

    accounts

    as

    unnecessary

    diversions from

    the

    path

    toward

    explanation.

    CONCLUSION

    Skinner's

    criticism

    concerning

    explanatory

    incompleteness

    and

    fictionality

    apply

    to

    some

    descriptive

    cognitive

    theories.

    Yet

    many

    descriptive

    theories

    are

    invulnerable

    to

    Skinner's

    proposals

    regarding

    circularity,

    epiphenomenalism

    and

    the

    noncausal

    status

    of

    inner events.

    Further,

    explanatory

    cognitive

    theories

    elude

    the

    incompleteness

    and the

    fictionality

    criticisms

    entirely.

    The

    criticism

    regarding

    nonnecessity

    may

    apply

    to

    cognitive

    explanations,

    though

    this

    has

    never

    been

    demonstrated,

    but

    this

    criticism

    overlooks-the

    potential

    usefulness

    of

    cognitive

    accounts.

    Thus

    none

    of

    Skinner's

    objections

    identify

    principled

    limita

    tions

    on

    cognitive explanations.

    This

    conclusion

    does

    not

    imply

    approbation

    of

    extant

    cognitive theories,

    nor

    does it

    negate

    Skinner's

    poignant criticisms

    con

    cerning

    the

    perils

    of

    cognitive

    theorizing,

    the

    topic

    of

    the

    second

    paper.

    This

    conclusion

    does

    imply,

    however,

    that

    it

    is

    premature

    to

    depict

    cognitive

    ac

    counts

    as

    inherently

    flawed

    and

    unworthy

    of the

    serious, dispassionate

    attention

    of

    radical

    behaviorists.

    The

    paper

    is

    intended to

    be

    propadeutic

    to

    cooperative

    research

    and

    con

    structive

    dialogue

    among

    radical

    behaviorists

    and

    cognitivists.

    Achieving

    the

    latter aims

    requires

    an

    exposition

    of the

    differences

    between

    the

    behavioral

    and

    cognitive

    approaches.

    One of the chief

    points

    made

    above is

    that the two

    approaches diverge sharply

    in

    their

    metatheoretical

    aims

    and

    their

    conceptions

    about explanation. The chief aims of radical behaviorism

    are

    to predict and con

    trol

    behavior.

    Skinner maintains

    that

    the

    greatest

    degree

    of

    behavioral

    control

    is

    accomplished

    by

    manipulating

    environmental

    variables,

    so

    he

    looks

    to

    the

    environment for

    an

    explanation

    of

    behavior.

    In

    this

    approach,

    pragmatism

    and

    explanatory

    conception

    are

    thoroughly

    interwoven.

    In

    contrast,

    the

    principal

    aim of

    cognitive psychology

    is

    to

    explain

    behavior

    by

    specifying

    on a

    concep

    tual level

    the

    universal,

    internal

    structures

    and

    processes

    through

    which

    the

    en

    vironment

    exerts

    its

    effects.

    Some

    unfortunate

    misunderstandings

    have

    probably

    arisen

    from

    the

    failure

    to

    discern

    and

    to

    analyze

    these

    differences

    in

    goals

    and

    in

    conceptions

    about

    explanation.

    From the

    behaviorist outlook, cognitive explanations appear fic

    tional

    in

    that

    they

    do

    not

    refer

    ultimately

    to the

    environment.

    From

    the

    cogni

    tive

    outlook,

    behavioral

    explanations

    appear

    incomplete

    and

    misguided

    because

    they

    describe

    but fail

    to

    explain

    the effects

    of the

    environment.

    In

    order

    to

    achieve

    extensive

    cooperation

    between behaviorists

    and

    cognitivists,

    these

    differ

    167

  • 8/18/2019 03 a Critique of Skinner's Views on the Explanatory Inadequacy of Cognitive Theories

    17/19

    Michael G.

    Wessells

    enees

    in

    conceptions

    of

    explanation

    will

    have

    to

    be

    reconciled.

    Even

    in

    the absence

    of

    a

    reconciliation, however,

    the

    present

    research of

    behaviorists

    and

    cognitivists

    may

    be viewed

    as

    complementary

    (Catania,

    1973;

    Segal,

    1977).

    In

    particular,

    cognitive

    research

    may

    specify important

    private

    events and biological properties that influence behavior, and behavioristic re

    search

    may

    specify

    the environmental

    determinants

    of

    private

    events

    and

    of

    the

    relations between

    private

    events and

    overt

    behavior.

    In

    view

    of the substantial

    gains

    that

    might

    follow

    from

    collaborative

    research,

    it

    seems

    worthwhile

    to

    try

    to

    bridge

    the

    explanatory

    chasm that

    now

    exists.

    REFERENCES

    Anderson,

    J.

    R.

    Language,

    memory

    and

    thought.

    Hillsdale,

    N.

    J.:

    Lawrence

    Erlbaum

    Associates,

    1976.

    Anderson,

    J.

    R.

    Arguments

    concerning representations

    for mental

    imagery.

    Psychological

    Review,

    1978,

    85,

    249-277.

    Anderson,

    J.

    R.

    and

    Bower,

    G.

    H.

    Human

    associative

    memory. Washington,

    D.C.:

    Winston,

    1973.

    Atkinson,

    R. L.

    Mnemotechnics

    in

    second-language learning.

    American

    Psychologist,

    1975, 30,

    821-828.

    Audi,

    R.

    B. F.

    Skinner

    on

    freedom,

    dignity

    and

    the

    explanation

    of behavior.

    Behaviorism,

    1976,4,

    163-186.

    Baddeley,

    A.

    D.

    The trouble with

    levels:

    A

    reexamination

    of

    Craik and Lockhart's framework for

    memory

    research.

    Psychological

    Review,

    1978,55,

    139-152.

    Carlson,

    E. A. The

    gene:

    A critical

    history.

    Philadelphia:

    W. B.

    Saunders,

    1966.

    Catania,

    A. C.

    The

    psychologies

    of

    structure,

    function and

    development.

    American

    Psychologist,

    1973,

    28,

    434-443.

    Catania,

    A.

    C. and

    Brigham,

    T.

    A.

    (Eds.).

    Handbook

    of

    applied

    behavior

    analysis.

    New

    York:

    Irvington,

    1978.

    Chomsky,

    N. A review of B.

    F.

    Skinner's Verbal

    Behavior.

    Language,

    1959, 35,

    26-58.

    Chomsky, N. Reflections on language. New York: Pantheon Books, 1975.

    Chomsky,

    N. On the

    biological

    basis of

    language capacities.

    In R.

    W. Rieber

    (Ed.),

    The

    neuropsychology

    of

    language.

    New York:

    Plenum,

    1976.

    Collins,

    A. Processes in

    acquiring knowledge.

    In

    R. C.

    Anderson,

    R. J.

    Spiro

    and W.

    E.

    Montague

    (Eds.),

    Schooling

    and the

    acquisition

    of

    knowledge.

    Hillsdale,

    N. J.:

    Erlbaum,

    1977.

    Dennett,

    D.

    Brainstorms.

    Montgomery,

    Vermont:

    Bradford,

    1978.

    Deutsch,

    J.

    A.

    The

    structural basis

    of

    behavior.

    Chicago:

    University

    of

    Chicago Press,

    1960.

    Dunn,

    L. CA

    short

    history of

    genetics.

    New York:

    McGraw-Hill,

    1965.

    Eimas,

    P.

    D.

    and

    Miller,

    J. L.

    Effects

    of

    selective

    adaptation

    on

    the

    perception

    of

    speech

    and visual

    patterns:

    Evidence for

    feature

    detectors.

    In

    R.

    D.

    Walk and

    H.

    L.

    Pick,

    Jr.

    (Eds.),

    Perception

    and

    experi

    ence.

    New

    York:

    Plenum,

    1978.

    Eysenck,

    M. W.

    Levels of

    processing:

    A

    critique.

    British

    Journal

    of

    Psychology,

    1978,

    68,

    157-169.

    Eysenck, M. W. and Eysenck, K. C. Processing depth, elaboration of encoding, memory stores, and ex

    pended

    processing

    capacity.

    Journal

    of

    Experimental

    Psychology:

    Human

    Learning

    and

    Memory,

    1979,5,

    472484.

    Fodor,

    J.

    A.

    Psychological

    explanation.

    New York:

    Random

    House,

    1968.

    Fodor,

    J.

    A. The

    mind-body

    problem. Scientific

    American,

    1981,

    244,

    114-123.

    Garner,

    W.

    R.,

    Hake,

    H.

    W. and

    Eriksen,

    C.

    W.

    Operationism

    and the

    concept

    of

    perception.

    Psychological

    Review, 1956,

    63,

    149-159.

    Glanzer,

    M.

    and

    Razel,

    M.

    The size

    of the unit in

    short-term

    storage.

    Journal

    of

    Verbal

    Learning

    and

    Verbal

    Behavior,

    1974,75,

    114-131.

    Honig,

    W. K.

    On the

    conceptual

    nature

    of

    cognitive

    terms:

    An

    initial

    essay.

    In

    S.

    H.

    H?lse,

    H.

    Fowler and

    W.

    K.

    Honig

    (Eds.),

    Cognitive

    processes

    in animal

    behavior.

    Hillsdale,

    N.

    J.:

    Lawrence

    Erlbaum

    Associates.

    Kieras, D. Beyond pictures and words: Alternative information processing models for imagery effects in

    verbal

    memory.

    Psychological

    Bulletin,

    1978,

    85,

    532-554.

    Kintsch,

    W.

    and

    Keenan,

    J.

    Reading

    rate

    and

    retention

    as a

    function

    of

    the number

    of

    propositions

    in the

    base

    structure of

    sentences.

    Cognitive

    Psychology,

    1973,5,

    257-274.

    Kintsch,

    W. and

    van

    Dijk,

    T. A.

    Toward

    a

    model

    of

    text

    comprehension.

    Psychological

    Review,

    1978,55,

    363-394.

    168

  • 8/18/2019 03 a Critique of Skinner's Views on the Explanatory Inadequacy of Cognitive Theories

    18/19

    A

    Critique

    of

    Skinner's

    View

    Of

    The

    Explanatory

    Inadequacy

    Of

    Cognitive

    Theories

    Kosslyn,

    S.

    M.

    Imagery

    and internal

    representation.

    In

    E.

    Rosch and

    B.

    Lloyd (Eds.),

    Cognition

    and

    cate

    gorization. Hillsdale,

    N.

    J.:

    Lawrence

    Erlbaum

    Associates.

    Kosslyn,

    S. M.

    Image

    and mind.

    Cambridge:

    Harvard

    University

    Press,

    1980.

    Kosslyn,

    S. M. and

    Pomerantz,

    J.

    R.

    Imagery, propositions,

    and

    the form

    of internal

    representations. Cog

    nitive Psychology, 1977,5, 52-76.

    Mackintosh,

    N.

    J.

    The

    psychology

    of

    animal

    learning.

    New

    York:

    Academic

    Press,

    1974.

    Martin,

    M.

    Interpreting

    Skinner.

    Behaviorism,

    1978, 6,

    129-138.

    Meehl,

    P. On

    the

    circularity

    of the

    law of

    effect.

    Psychological

    Bulletin,

    1950,47,

    52-75.

    Miller,

    J. R. and

    Kintsch,

    W.

    Readability

    and

    recall

    of

    short

    prose

    passages:

    A

    theoretical

    analysis.

    Journal

    of

    Experimental

    Psychology:

    Human

    Learning

    and

    Memory,

    1980,6,

    335-354.

    Morris,

    P.

    E.

    Practical

    strategies

    for

    human

    learning

    and

    remembering.

    In M.

    J.

    A.

    Howe

    (Ed.),

    Adult

    learn

    ing:

    Psychological

    research and

    applications.

    London:

    Wiley,

    1977.

    Neisser,

    U.

    Cognitive

    psychology.

    New York:

    Appleton-Century-Crofts,

    1967.

    Neisser,

    U.

    Cognition

    and

    reality.

    San Francisco:

    W.

    H.

    Freeman,

    1976.

    Newport,

    E. L.

    Motherese:

    The

    speech

    of

    mothers

    to

    young

    children. In

    N.

    J.

    Castellan,

    Jr.,

    D.

    B.

    Pisoni

    and

    G. R.

    Potts

    (Eds.), Cognitive

    theory,

    Vol.

    2.

    Hillsdale,

    N. J.:

    Lawrence

    Erlbaum,

    1977.

    Posner, M. I. Abstraction and the process of recognition. In J. T. Spence and G. H. Bower (Eds.), Advances

    in

    learning

    and

    motivation,

    Vol.

    3. New York:

    Academic

    Press,

    1969.

    Posner,

    M. I.

    Chronometrie

    explorations

    of

    mind.

    Hillsdale,

    N. J.:

    Lawrence

    Erlbaum

    Associates,

    1978.

    Postman,

    L. Verbal

    learning

    and

    memory.

    Annual Re vie

    w

    of

    Psychology,

    1975,

    26,

    241-335.

    Pylyshyn,

    Z. W. What the mind's

    eye

    tells the

    mind's

    brain: A

    critique

    of

    mental

    imagery.

    Psychological

    Bulletin, 1913,80,

    1-24.

    Pylyshyn,

    Z.

    W.

    Images

    and artificial

    intelligence.

    In

    C. W.

    Savage

    (Ed.),

    Minnesota Studies

    in

    the

    Philos

    ophy

    of

    Science,

    Vol. IX.

    Minneapolis:

    University

    of Minnesota

    Press,

    1978.

    Rosch,

    E. Human

    categorization.

    In

    N. Warren

    (Ed.),

    Studies in cross-cultural

    psychology.

    New York:

    Aca

    demic

    Press,

    1977.

    Rosch,

    E.

    Principles

    of

    categorization.

    In E. Rosch

    and

    B.

    Lloyd

    (Eds.),

    Cognition

    and

    categorization.

    Hills

    dale,

    N.

    J.:

    Lawrence

    Erlbaum

    Associates,

    1978.

    Rumelhart, D. E. Understanding and summarizing brief stories. In D. LaBerge and S. J. Samuels (Eds.),

    Basic

    processes

    in

    reading:

    perception

    and

    comprehension.

    Hillsdale,

    N. J.:

    Lawrence

    Erlbaum

    Associates,

    1977.

    Schick,

    K.

    Op?rants.

    Journal

    of

    the

    Experimental

    Analysis of

    Behavior,

    1971,15,

    413-423.

    Schnaitter,

    R.

    Private

    cames.

    Behaviorism,

    1978, 6,

    1-12.

    Scriven,

    M.

    A

    study

    of radical behaviorism.

    In H.

    Feigl

    and

    M.

    Scriven

    (Eds.),

    Minnesota studies

    in

    the

    phi

    losophy of

    science,

    Vol. I.

    Minneapolis:

    University

    of

    Minnesota

    Press,

    1956.

    Segal,

    E. Toward

    a

    coherent

    psychology

    of

    language.

    In W. K.

    Honig

    and

    J. E.

    R. Staddon

    (Eds.),

    Hand

    book

    of op?rant

    behavior.

    Englewood

    Cliffs,

    N.

    J.:

    Prentice-Hall,

    1977.

    Seligman,

    M.

    E. P. On the

    generality

    of the laws

    of

    learning,

    Psychological

    Review,

    1970, 77,

    406-418.

    Shepard,

    R. N. The

    mental

    image.

    American

    Psychologist,

    1978,

    33,

    125-137.

    Shettleworth,

    S.

    Constraints

    on

    learning.

    In

    D.

    S.

    Lehrman,

    R.

    A.

    Hinde

    and

    E.

    Shaw

    (Eds.),

    Advances

    in

    the study of behavior. New York: Academic Press, 1972.

    Sidman,

    M. Remarks.

    Behaviorism, 1976,4,

    279-281.

    Simon,

    H. A. What is visual

    imagery?

    An

    information-processing

    interpretation.

    In

    L.

    W.

    Gregg

    (Ed.),

    Cog

    nition

    in

    learning

    and

    memory.

    New York:

    Wiley,

    1972.

    Simon,

    H.

    A.

    How

    big

    is

    a

    chunk?

    Science,

    1974,183,

    482-488.

    Simon,

    H. A.

    Information-processing

    theory

    of human

    problem

    solving.

    In

    W.

    K.

    Estes

    (Ed.),

    Handbook

    of

    learning

    and

    cognitive

    processes,

    Vol.

    5.

    Hillsdale,

    N.

    J.: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Skinner,

    B.

    F. The behavior

    of

    organisms.

    New

    York:

    Appleton-Century-Crofts,

    1938.

    Skinner,

    B. F. The

    operational

    analysis

    of

    psychological

    terms.

    Psychological

    Review, 1945, 52,

    270-277.

    Skinner,

    B.

    F.

    Science and human behavior.

    New York:

    Macmillan,

    1953.

    Skinner,

    B. F.

    Verbal

    behavior. New

    York:

    Appleton-Century-Crofts,

    1957.

    Skinner,

    B.

    F.

    Behaviorism

    at

    fifty.

    In J.Wann

    (Ed.),

    Behaviorism

    and

    phenomenology.

    Chicago:

    University

    of Chicago Press, 1964.

    Skinner,

    B.

    F. The

    ontogeny

    and

    phylogeny

    of

    behavior.

    Science,

    1966,153,

    1203-1213.

    Skinner,

    B.

    F.

    The

    technology of

    teaching.

    New

    York:

    Appleton-Century-Crofts,

    1968.

    Skinner,

    B.

    F.

    Contingencies

    of

    reinforcement.

    New

    York:

    Appleton-Century-Crofts,

    1969.

    Skinner,

    B.

    F.

    Cumulative

    record,

    third

    edition.

    New

    York:

    Appleton-Century-Crofts,

    1972.

    169

  • 8/18/2019 03 a Critique of Skinner's Views on the Explanatory Inadequacy of Cognitive Theories

    19/19

    Michael

    G.

    Wessells

    Skinner,

    B.

    F.

    About behaviorism. New York:

    Knopf,

    1974.

    Skinner,

    B.

    F.

    The

    shaping

    of

    phylogenetic

    behavior. Journal

    of

    the

    Experimental

    Analysis

    of

    Behavior,

    1915,24,

    117-120.

    Skinner,

    B. F.

    Why

    I

    am

    not

    a

    cognitive

    psychologist.

    Behaviorism,

    1977a,

    5,

    1-10.

    Skinner,

    B. F.

    Herrnstein and the evolution of behaviorism.

    American

    Psychologist,

    1977b, 33,

    1006-1012.

    Skinner, B. F. and Blanshard, B. The problem of consciousness - a debate. Philosophy and Phenomeno

    logical

    Research,

    1967,27,

    317-337.

    Smith.

    E.

    E.

    Theories

    of semantic

    memory.

    In

    W.

    K.

    Estes

    (Ed.),

    Handbook

    of

    learning

    and

    cognitive

    proc

    esses,

    Vol. 5.

    Hillsdale,

    N.

    J.: Lawrence Erlbaum

    Associates,

    1978.

    Spiro,

    R.

    J. Accommodative reconstruction

    in

    prose

    recall.

    Journal

    of

    Verbal

    Learning

    and

    Verbal

    Behavior,

    1980,79,

    84-95.

    Staddon,

    J.

    E.

    R.

    and

    Simmelhag,

    V.

    L.

    The

    "superstition" experiment:

    A

    reexamination

    of its

    implications

    for the

    principles

    of

    adaptive

    behavior.

    Psychological

    Review, 1971,

    78,

    3-43.

    Stern

    berg,

    R. J.

    Intelligence,

    information

    processing,

    and

    analogical

    reasoning:

    The

    componential

    analysis

    of

    human

    abilities.

    Hillsdale,

    N.

    J.:

    Lawrence Erlbaum

    Associates,

    1977.

    Thatcher,

    R.

    W. and

    John,

    E.

    R.

    Functional

    neuroscience,

    Vol.

    1.

    Foundations

    of

    cognitive

    processes.

    Hills

    dale,

    N.

    J.: Lawrence

    Erlbaum

    Associates,

    1977.

    Thorndyke, P. W. Cognitive structures in comprehension and memory of narrative discourse.

    Cognitive

    Psychology,

    1977,

    9,

    77-110.

    Waugh,

    N. C.

    and

    Norman,

    D. A.

    Primary

    memory.

    Psychological

    Review,

    1965,

    72,

    89-104.

    Zuriff,

    G.

    E. Ten

    inner

    causes.

    Behaviorism,

    1979,

    7,

    1-8.

    170


Recommended