+ All Categories
Home > Documents > 09697250120087923

09697250120087923

Date post: 02-Jun-2018
Category:
Upload: laura-leander-wilde
View: 217 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend

of 15

Transcript
  • 8/10/2019 09697250120087923

    1/15

    This article was downloaded by: [University of Sydney]On: 06 January 2015, At: 22:07Publisher: RoutledgeInforma Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954Registered office: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK

    Angelaki: Journal of theTheoretical HumanitiesPublication details, including instructions for authors and

    subscription information:

    http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/cang20

    CAVE PAINTINGS AND WALL

    WRITINGs: Blanchot's signatureLars IyerPublished online: 09 Jun 2010.

    To cite this article:Lars Iyer (2001) CAVE PAINTINGS AND WALL WRITINGs: Blanchot's

    signature, Angelaki: Journal of the Theoretical Humanities, 6:3, 31-43

    To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/09697250120087923

    PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

    Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all the information(the Content) contained in the publications on our platform. However, Taylor& Francis, our agents, and our licensors make no representations or warranties

    whatsoever as to the accuracy, completeness, or suitability for any purposeof the Content. Any opinions and views expressed in this publication are theopinions and views of the authors, and are not the views of or endorsed byTaylor & Francis. The accuracy of the Content should not be relied upon andshould be independently verified with primary sources of information. Taylor andFrancis shall not be liable for any losses, actions, claims, proceedings, demands,costs, expenses, damages, and other liabilities whatsoever or howsoever causedarising directly or indirectly in connection with, in relation to or arising out of theuse of the Content.

    This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes.Any substantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly

    http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/cang20http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/09697250120087923http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/cang20
  • 8/10/2019 09697250120087923

    2/15

    forbidden. Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditions

    Dow

    nloadedby[UniversityofS

    ydney]at22:0706January2015

    http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditionshttp://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditions
  • 8/10/2019 09697250120087923

    3/15

    General culture, Blanchot observes,would like to make to know a verb with-out an object: it is a matter of knowing in a waythat is absolute and substantial, not of learning

    what one does not yet know (Friendship 55;

    67). The notion of the work of art allows us to

    draw the old and the new into the horizon of

    culture: we know what it is and we know, for this

    reason, what any work of art can be. Our capac-

    ity to know outpaces everything; the avant-garde

    is, for us, only the outward edge of a movement

    whose origins and inner dynamic are alreadyfamiliar. Likewise, no artwork is too old, too

    obscure or too unfamiliar to be recognised as

    what it is and thereafter restored to its place

    within culture. What matters above all else is

    culture as a whole, the totality or the continuity

    of the knowable as it is known by those of us

    who live in the West. We recognise the artwork,

    we know in advance what it is and how it binds

    itself to a particular history, a particular institu-

    tionalisation. We know but we do so in a manner

    that is docile; we acquiesce to the substantiality

    of the gallery, to the absoluteness of the

    museum.

    But is it not because art is already deadthat

    the individual work of art seems to offer itself so

    completely to a certain history, a certain monu-

    mentalisation? This is why, perhaps, the crushed

    face of Saint Elizabeth of Baberg and the adoles-

    cent smiles of Praxiteles statues seem strangelycomplete, for they regard and smile at us from

    an eternal immobility. Perhaps Hegel is right:

    art belongs to the past (Aesthetics 11) since it

    is no longer the absolute mode of expression and

    self-understanding for European people.

    Everything is ours artworks have been freed

    from their subjection to religious, mythic or

    civic purposes. The columns of the Greek temple

    are no longer an integral component of a place

    of worship, but realise and exemplify a style that

    would come to influence Byzantine and Western

    church architecture. Everything is ours the

    tourists who admire the spectacle of the Japanese

    Shinto temple are right to understand this expe-

    rience in the same way as they might the Auriga

    of Delphi, the Royal Portal of Chartres,

    Khmerian heads, Wei and Tang Bodhisattvas

    i.e., as the distant forerunners of contemporary

    art. Everything is known but the object of

    knowledge is already dead; the word artbelongs, in its modern usage, to a time it has

    already outlived. To think the artwork as the

    artwork to think the notion of art in its

    historicity is to think what has already been

    killed. Art cannot be resurrected, but we could

    pronounce the words Lazarus, venture forth

    that would have it approach us in its death not

    in order to restore it to life nor indeed to mourn

    art, to restore its purity by freezing it in immo-

    bility, but in order to understand the extent of

    its death and its distance from us. If art is dead,

    3 1

    lars iyer

    CAVE PAINTINGS AND

    WALL WRITINGS

    blanchots signature

    AN GELAKIjour na l of th e th eo re tica l hu man it ies

    volume 6 number 3 december 2001

    ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/01/030031-13 2001 Taylor & Francis Ltd and the Editors ofAngelaki

    DOI: 10.1080/09697250120087923

    Dow

    nloadedby[UniversityofS

    ydney]at22:0706January2015

  • 8/10/2019 09697250120087923

    4/15

    blanchots signature

    then this death cannot be made authentic,

    personal, proper; it refuses itself to mourning.

    The stench of death surprises us, for the corpse

    of art is not like that of certain saints whose flesh

    has not rotted from their bones: the saints who,

    we could imagine, would rise again and walk one

    day among us.

    It might seem as if Saint Elizabeth of Baberg

    craved for her face to be crushed or that the

    caves of Lascaux waited only to be discovered in

    order to fade: that the work of art was always as

    it appears to us in the museum. But what we call

    art, Blanchot would remind us, is real and it is

    fragile; it belongs to history and is marked by its

    adventures. The crushed face and the fading

    cave walls are figures for a certain event thatdoes not befall the artwork from without as a

    kind of empirical accident that is easily erased.

    Rather, this event would attest to a worklessness

    that can be said to unwork history, one that

    implicates the history of art and, as I will argue,

    disturbs historiographical and evolutionary

    accounts of the origin of the human being.

    Blanchot would confront us anew with the

    artwork in its materiality, its ineradicable

    historicity. In wresting art from historiography

    and, thereby, from discourses on the history of

    art and art criticism, he also invites a reconcep-

    tion of the step into humanity the step into

    history.

    In his discussion of Batailles book on the

    cave paintings at Lascaux, Blanchot focuses on

    what he calls the signature a fragmentary

    rcit or narrative that the painter of the cave

    walls leaves in order to indicate his own masteryover the work of art: the fact that he and he

    alone was responsible for it. But this signature is

    a figure for a certain non-human worklessness

    that divides any project, any attempt to accom-

    plish a task, from itself.

    In the second part of my discussion, I argue

    that those who wrote on the walls in the events

    in Paris in May 1968 can be said to append their

    signature in a way that re-echoes the signatureBlanchot discovers on the cave walls. Discussing

    Blanchots account of the events alongside his

    discussion of Batailles book, I explore the ethi-

    cal and political repercussions of Blanchots

    account of worklessness.

    the cave paintings

    Blanchot writes:

    it is certainly true that Lascaux fills us with a

    feeling of wonder [la merveille; the translator

    provides us with a word linked happily to the

    experience in which philosophy has been saidto be sourced]: this subterranean beauty; the

    chance that preserved and revealed it; the

    breadth and scope of the paintings, which are

    there not in the form of vestiges or furtive

    adornment but as a commanding presence; a

    space almost intentionally devoted to the bril-

    liance and marvel of painted things, whose first

    spectators must have experienced, as we do,

    and with as much naive astonishment, the

    marvellous revelation; the place from which artshines forth and whose radiance is that of a

    first ray first and yet complete. (Friendship

    1; 9)

    The chance that let us witness the huge aurochs,

    the unicorn, the red deer, oxen, horses and stags

    is no doubt remarkable. Our curiosity is piqued

    about the techniques that allowed our ancestors

    to exaggerate the contours of the cave walls and

    augment them with pigment. What, we might ask

    ourselves, about the function of the Lascaux

    paintings were the caves the focus of rituals, of

    secret ceremonies? We turn to the commentaries

    in the books in which we read about what we call

    prehistoric art; we read learned articles about the

    caves or turn the pages of reproductions. But

    what incites our wonder, according to Blanchot,

    is the self-affirming presence of a great work of

    art. Ours would be the simple, awe-struck

    response that captivated the first spectators ofthe paintings. What we confront is already a great

    work; at Lascaux, we discover that the cave paint-

    ings that are the birth of art reveal a profound

    truth about art and its historicity: at its birth,

    Blanchot writes, art is revealed to be such that

    it can change infinitely and can ceaselessly renew

    itself, but cannot improve (Friendship 1; 9).

    The cave paintings would be both ancient and

    contemporaneous, since they appear to awakenthe same wonder in us as they would in any spec-

    tator.

    This account of Blanchots evocation of the

    cave paintings might seem persuasive. For who

    now would insist that ancient art is cruder or less

    3 2

    Dow

    nloadedby[UniversityofS

    ydney]at22:0706January2015

  • 8/10/2019 09697250120087923

    5/15

    iyer

    refinedthan newer art? Is it not a tribute to our

    universal humanism that we can place the caves

    of Lascaux alongside the primitivist sculptures of

    Picasso in our imaginary museum?1

    Furthermore, we might agree with Blanchots

    claim that art can be said to happen as the expe-

    rience of wonder it incites in its viewers. Art is

    what satisfies us because it offers an unequivocal

    experience: one that affects us when we catch

    sight of a reproduction of a Van Gogh in the

    boardroom. The work of art offers itself to us as

    unbreached experience, a primal non-contradic-

    tion, a unity that preserves itself despite the

    commercialisation of art. We are reassured: art

    remains art because the origin is not a discreet

    point in the past, but continues to hold sway, togovern, measuring out the fate of what is to

    come.

    But Blanchot does not confirm us in this view

    of art. Granted, he makes the claim that art can

    always and already be said to be complete, since

    alterations and refinements of artistic technique

    do not alter what is marvellous about it. He

    seems to affirm that art can be said to happen or

    indeed be reborn as the wondrous, re-originating

    for the first spectators at Lascaux just as it will

    be born again for all subsequent spectators. But

    in claiming that allorigination is but a re-origi-

    nation that there is no absolute beginning of art

    to which all its other re-beginnings could be

    related Blanchot points to an experience on the

    part of those who view the artwork that disturbs

    the usual conception of wonder. At Lascaux,

    according to Blanchot, we encounter the force,

    brilliance and mastery of a power that is essen-tially the power of a beginning, which is always

    to say, of a beginning-again that is always prior

    (Friendship 10; 19).

    Lascaux names a site where something has

    recommenced that disturbs the inherited concept

    of art. What recommences there can only be

    understood if the notion of art along with atten-

    dant notions of authorship, artistry, and creativ-

    ity are rethought from an experience oftransgression. What sets Batailles account of

    Lascaux apart from those by specialists in art and

    prehistory, Stephen Ungar comments, is his

    view that the work of art is distinguished from

    the products of other work by a destructive force

    associated with transgression and the sacred

    (Phantom Lascaux 258). Batailles Lascaux

    links the creation of the cave paintings with the

    emergence of the human being as it is bound up

    with murder and eroticism. It is this aspect of

    Batailles work that Blanchot draws upon in his

    account of the birth of the work of art. Blanchot

    argues that the experience of the work of art

    permits the step from pre-human into human

    existence; it is only in the context of a discussion

    of humanity and a certain inhumanity that the

    question concerning the happening of the work

    of art can be broached.

    Bataille, according to Blanchot,

    shows that the paintings of Lascaux are

    probably linked to the movement of effer-

    vescence, to the explosive generosity of cele-bration when man, interrupting the time of

    effort and work thus for the first time

    truly man returns to the sources of natural

    overabundance [la surabondance] in the

    jubilation of a brief interlude [la jubilation

    dun bref intermde] to what he was when he

    was not yet (Friendship 4; 12; translationamended)

    In Lascaux, Bataille sketches the initial alien-

    ation of the human being from the immanent

    realm of animality that opens when the human

    being becomes a creature who works. He explains

    how tools, since they have no value in themselves

    but only in an anticipated result, allow the posit-

    ing of objects. The distinction between ends and

    means introduced by the tool permits the defini-tion of what, Bataille writes in the Theory of

    Religion, is a sphere of objects, a world, a

    plane (30). This positing always uncertain,

    precarious and unevenly realised (Theory of

    Religion 30) counterposes a subject to these

    objects. The tool thus changes nature and so does

    the human being at the same time; as Bataille

    writes, the tool subjugates nature to man, who

    makes it and uses it, but it ties man to a subju-gated nature (Theory of Religion 41). Nature

    becomes, in principle, the property of the human

    being, but only in so far as it is available as an

    object for a subject. As Bataille writes, the grain

    of wheat is a unit of agricultural production; the

    3 3

    Dow

    nloadedby[UniversityofS

    ydney]at22:0706January2015

  • 8/10/2019 09697250120087923

    6/15

    blanchots signature

    cow is a head of livestock, and the one who culti-

    vates the wheat is a farmer; the one who raises

    the steer is a stock raiser (Theory of Religion

    41). But even as the pre-humans who made tools

    and were thereby posited as subjects over against

    a dimension that would be henceforward closed

    to them, they became aware of an essential lack

    or a weakness (Friendship 5; 12) that stemmed

    from their finitude. There remain certain insecu-

    rities in the transcendent plane upon which

    subjects and objects stand opposed to one

    another since the human being is never just a

    subject and nature cannot be objectivised. How

    should we think these insecurities?

    As Kant argues, there is a distinction between

    the intuitus originarius of God, an originalintuition (Anschauung) that creates its own

    objects, and the intuitus derivativus of the

    human being, who does not create objects but

    receives intuitions from them (Critique of Pure

    Reason B72). As Heidegger writes of Kant,

    finite intuition of the being cannot give the

    object from out of itself. It must allow the object

    to be given (Kant and the Problem of

    Metaphysics 18). The finite human being exists

    in the midst of beings that existed before him.

    Clearly, the Bataillean subject who opposes

    objects did not create them. The creation of

    tools, which is the condition of possibility of

    laying out a transcendent plane, does not hold

    back a certain explosive festivity in which nature

    would be revealed in its immanence in its pecu-

    liar proximity to the human being. This jubila-

    tory interlude to which Blanchot refers exposes

    that the humanity of the human being cannot bethought in terms of subjectivity. On this reading,

    the finitude of the human being is to be thought

    in terms of his openness and receptivity to what

    he does not create, i.e., his capacity to be

    affected. The finitude of the human being is

    simply another way of thinking the insecurity of

    the plane of transcendence.

    The insecurity to which the human being is

    condemned in his finitude can be understood interms of the relationship between prohibition and

    transgression as it structures human experience.

    As Blanchot writes, Georges Bataille assumes

    man used to draw a circle around human possi-

    bility from the very beginning (Friendship 5;

    13). Prohibitions about death and murder mili-

    tate against the experience that threatens to

    reveal the inherent instability of the plane of

    transcendence. Everything that has been possible

    for us on this plane civilisation itself was and

    is possible because of these prohibitions. At the

    time, however, as they confirm the strength and

    force of these prohibitions, Blanchot and Bataille

    would point towards certain experiences that fall

    outside merely human possibility.

    Our ancestors, the ones who are not yet

    human, were already enclosed by such prohibi-

    tions. However, Blanchot argues with Bataille

    that whilst these incipient human beings may be

    hard workers, the masters of tools and weapons,

    they have yet to step into fully human existencesince they are bound by the prohibitions that

    debar their societies from that which cannot be

    put to work. They are not yet human, since, as

    Blanchot will explain, they are not capable of

    knowing the law by sovereign infraction, and it

    is only by deliberately defying the prohibitions

    they erect around themselves that they can

    become human (Friendship 5; 14). It is not

    enough to exist within the parameters that are

    measured out through prohibitions. There are

    two leaps, two essential moments of transgres-

    sion that allow pre-human beings to become

    human beings (Friendship 6; 14). In the first,

    pre-humans transcend the immanence of the

    natural world; in the second, they re-cross the

    line that demarcates them from the immanence

    of the natural realm and, through this transgres-

    sion, violate the prohibitions that their ancestors

    set against the dimension from which theyemerged, in so doing, revealing these prohibi-

    tions in their prohibitive force. This transgres-

    sion returns the human being to the immanence

    of animality and thence to that from which he

    originated. Human beings become human only

    by plunging back into the milieu from which pre-

    humans emerged. The origination of the human

    being depends upon the violation of the taboos

    that separate us from immanence. The pre-humans transcendence of nature has to be

    transgressed in a return to immanence that

    simultaneously contests and confirms the force

    of the prohibition. In this return, the prohibi-

    tions that guarantee the integrity and closure of

    3 4

    Dow

    nloadedby[UniversityofS

    ydney]at22:0706January2015

  • 8/10/2019 09697250120087923

    7/15

    iyer

    homogeneity are contested. Homogeneity the

    plane of transcendent beings, i.e., subjects and

    objects is never homogeneous enough because

    it cannot be secured once and for all. It is only

    when the impossibility of achieving homogeneity

    as such is forcibly exposed in the moment of

    transgression that essential lack reveals itself to

    be constitutive of human existence.

    In the instant of transgression, the essential

    lack or weakness that seemed to promise a

    homogenisation of nature to pre-humans reveals

    itself to be doubly lacking. The movement of

    transgression confirms the interdictions that

    demarcate the transcendent from the immanent.

    This movement is not one possibility among

    others, i.e., something that can happen as a resultof work of a plan or a project. It does not

    accomplish what the transgressor sets out to

    accomplish. Rather, it interrupts the dimension

    of the possible, i.e., the world that opens to the

    human being as a plane of transcendence. It cuts

    across the conscious intentions of the human

    beings who would make a work or a project of

    transgression. The movement of transgression

    cannot be initiated through an act of will. Rather,

    it disrupts all such willing, belonging to a dynam-

    ics that is dissimulated by the desire to work, in

    the very setting apart of means from ends. It is

    only in giving this desire its head in letting it

    emerge in its difference from what are normally

    construed to be desires that transgression can

    occur. But this affirmation of a pre-voluntary

    desire is not something the human being can be

    said to be capable of as a subject who can will or

    act. Transgression can only be said to occur onlyin so far as it contests the prohibitions that struc-

    ture the subject.

    This is why, Blanchot writes, the awareness

    that a return to what is variously called anterior

    reality, animal reality, and the first immen-

    sity is a return that is always more than a

    return (Friendship 6; 15). Although this move-

    ment may seem to allow the incipient human

    being to enter these primeval, prehistoric realmsonce again, he also becomes tumultuously

    conscious of this impossible return, becomes

    conscious of the limits and the unique force that

    allows him to break these limits (Friendship 6;

    15). The transgressor cannot simply become

    immanent he does not, as Blanchot writes,

    simply lose himself in the dream of total exis-

    tence; rather, he affirms himself as that which

    is added to this existence (Friendship 6; 15). He

    is aware, that is to say, that he is a supplement to

    existence that the emergence from immanence

    has always and already happened and, therefore,

    that he is the minute part [la part infime] that,

    at a distance and through an ambiguous play, can

    become master of everything, can appropriate it

    symbolically or communicate with it by making

    it be (Friendship 6; 15). To transgress, then, is

    only to become aware of what one cannot trans-

    gress i.e., a transcendence that it is not in the

    power of the human being to reconvert into

    immanence. It is in the growing awareness ofthe impossibility of the return to the first immen-

    sity which is also the impossibility of ever

    definitively overcoming the effort and the work

    that is an ineluctable part of human existence

    that pre-humans become, at last, human beings.

    Thus, neither Blanchot nor Bataille simply

    retrace the evolutionary process that would allow

    us to designate the origin of the human being.

    Blanchots paradoxical thought of the origin

    conceives it in terms of the desire on the part of

    the incipient human being to enact a transgres-

    sion as a transgression. But this origin involves an

    instant that Blanchot calls the time of differ-

    ence, understood as the point of disjunction

    between the desire to complete a transgression

    and the prohibitive force that defeats this desire,

    rendering the transgression incomplete (that is to

    say, there is no absolute transgression)

    (Friendship 6; 14).2 This origin has the result ofdemarcating humans from pre-humans but it is,

    in itself, always a lacuna it is, Blanchot writes:

    as if the origin, instead of showing itself and

    expressing itself in what emerges from the

    origin, were always veiled and hidden by what

    it produces, and perhaps then destroyed or

    consumed as origin, pushed back and always

    further removed and distant, as originally

    deferred. We never observe the source, nor thespringing forth [jaillissement], but only what

    is outside the source, the source become real-

    ity external to itself and always again without

    source or far from the source. (Friendship 10;

    1819)

    3 5

    Dow

    nloadedby[UniversityofS

    ydney]at22:0706January2015

  • 8/10/2019 09697250120087923

    8/15

    blanchots signature

    The origin whether it is the origin of the human

    being or the origin of the work of art is never

    simply available. Indeed, the withdrawals of both

    these origins are intertwined, for the lack of artis-

    tic ability on the part of pre-humans is emblem-

    atic of their inability to step into a fully human

    existence. If what we call art is deemed to be the

    expression of the humanity of the human being

    as the impossible leap into immanence, then the

    origin of art is as opaque as that of the origin of

    the human being. Blanchot writes that the first

    moments of art, of which Lascaux is an example:

    suggest that man has contact with his own

    beginning is the initial affirmation of

    himself, the expression of his own novelty

    only when, by the means and methods of art,he enters into communication with the force,

    brilliance, and joyful mastery [avec la force,

    lclat et la matrise joyeuse] of a power that

    is essentially the power of a beginning, which

    is always to say, of a beginning-again [de

    recommencement pralable] that is always

    prior. (Friendship 10; 19)

    The cave paintings are indeed wondrous, but

    they are not so because of the ingenuity of their

    creators, whose achievement is hollowed out by a

    fundamental and constitutive non-achievement

    i.e., the impossibility of reclaiming this origin as

    such. It is the experience of the withdrawal of the

    origin that is constitutive of the step into truly

    human existence. In order to become human, to

    step over the threshold, it is not enough merely

    to be in default the retreat of immanence has

    to be experienced in its retreat. But such experi-

    ence is never simply at hand it is not ours toclaim for ourselves. Rather, it is art that permits

    a communication with what Blanchot calls, in

    The Space of Literature, the original experi-

    ence i.e., the experience of the origin in its

    retreat (20947; 31355).3 Communication does

    not refer to the transmission of a message that

    would leave sender and receiver, subject and

    object, intact; it is this experience of the origin

    that pre-dates all beginnings. This experiencecannot be retrospectively appropriated; it cannot

    be said to return and reaffirm itself in the work

    of art.

    The original experience the experience of a

    certain repetition of the origin alters our very

    conception of artistic achievement, along with

    attendant notions of genius, inspiration, creativ-

    ity, etc. But it does more than this since, in

    revealing the interruption of the originating func-

    tion, the work of art shows how any attempt to

    work is interrupted how the dimension of possi-

    bility can never enclose a certain impossibility,

    an experience of the impossible. The artwork

    reveals its uncanny capacity to communicate the

    interruption of any plan, project or work in so far

    as they take place on the plane of transcendence.

    Moreover, it reveals the interruption that must

    have been at play in any human creation that

    appears to be stable and perduring. The

    Blanchovian determination of the artwork reveals

    a worklessness that always inhabits working.As soon as art begins, the original experi-

    ence the experience of the impossible that is, as

    I will explain, also the impossibility of recovering

    an experience as an experience invades and

    contaminates the free mastery of the artist.

    Worklessness always inhabits the work; the pre-

    voluntary desire for worklessness accompanies

    and contests any desire to work. There is never a

    simple, undivided experience of origination,

    understood as a discreet, pristine beginning that

    leads to a work, since there is no stable point

    from which birth whether the birth of art or the

    birth of humanity can begin. There is no

    assignable origin of a process of working that is

    not inhabited, in advance, by a dissension of the

    creative will.

    Preceding the origin, as it were (but only

    because it accompanies and interrupts any osten-

    sible origin as soon as it originates), there is aninterruption of the origin. As Blanchot writes,

    what is first is not beginning, but beginning

    over: beginning itself is the attempt to deter-

    mine a fundamental stability out of which a

    world can emerge (Space of Literature 243; 327).

    Whilst particular determinations of the world

    qua the plane of transcendence emerge partic-

    ular worlds that belong to different societies at

    different times it is also true that such deter-minations are always threatened in their being. It

    is the fact that the dissension of the origin can

    never be left behind once and for all to which

    Blanchot points when he writes: being is

    precisely the impossibility of being for the first

    3 6

    Dow

    nloadedby[UniversityofS

    ydney]at22:0706January2015

  • 8/10/2019 09697250120087923

    9/15

    iyer

    time (Space of Literature 243; 327). Any appeal

    to the origin must negotiate this pre-originary

    dissension, the play of worklessness within work,

    of the inhuman within the human and the imma-

    nent in the transcendent.

    Blanchot would show how the source is always

    redoubled, that the desire for homogeneity and

    work coexists with the uncanny attraction of

    heterogeneity and worklessness. It is the fact that

    we, the spectators, are implicated in this attrac-

    tion, that we are carried, in advance, towards

    what we will not allow ourselves to want, that

    allows us to discern a fear in the experience of

    wonder itself. I have argued that a disjunction of

    time can be said to open between the time of the

    project, the time in which plans are made andtools deployed, and the joyous moment in which

    human beings are returned to the first immensity

    to which they bear an ambiguous relationship. It

    is the possibility of such a disjunction one that

    we can never have done with which makes us

    fear even as we wonder. To wonder is also to be

    afraid: it is to discern the retreat of the origin

    and, along with it, the retreat of those powers

    that are constitutive of fully human existence, the

    threat of the return to a time in which no human

    being had entered history. The beasts on the cave

    wall take us back before the origin to the time

    when the human being did not exist. They

    confront us with the dreadful abyss of the pre-

    historical: of a recurrence of an instant that

    cannot be brought under retrospective control.

    Our wonder shelters a fear: the fear of what the

    artwork would communicate: the terror of an

    instant without history.

    In the prehistoric cave paintings of this period,

    there are few representations of human beings.

    The painters bring beasts vividly to life, restoring

    them to a joyous and unambiguous presence

    one full of an innocent truth without equivoca-

    tion (Friendship 11; 20). But when human

    beings appear, they are depicted with extremecrudity. In the same cave complex at Lascaux, an

    enigmatic tableau can be found hidden at the

    bottom of a crevasse. It portrays a stretched out

    man with a birds head and an erect penis who

    appears to have speared a wounded bison. For

    Blanchot, as for Bataille, this peculiar addition to

    the cave paintings at Lascaux strangely and

    perfectly corresponds to the fundamental

    enigma, i.e., the question of the coming into

    the world, the advent, of man (Tears of Eros

    5253). As Blanchot comments, it is striking

    that with the figuration of man, an enigmatic

    element enters into this work, a work otherwise

    without secret; a scene also enters it as a narra-

    tive [rcit], an impure historical dramatisation

    (Friendship 11; 20).

    This portrayal introduces a dimension previ-

    ously absent, since the presence of this intriguing

    individual is not of the same unambiguous order

    as that of the great beasts. We do not, Blanchot

    argues, welcome this image with the same spon-taneous pleasure we do not wonder as we do in

    front of the beasts on the cave wall. The naivety

    of this depiction surprises us, as does the place of

    this figure within the tableau of which he is part.

    We may ask whether this individual is asleep or

    dead, or enquire as to the sense of the fragmen-

    tary narrative of which he seems part, but

    Blanchot claims that the meaning of this

    obscure drawing is nonetheless clear; it is, he

    claims: the first signature of the first painting,

    the mark left modestly in a corner, the furtive,

    fearful, indelible [furtive, craintive, ineffaable]

    trace of man who is for the first time born of his

    work, but who also feels seriously threatened

    [gravement menac] by this work and perhaps

    already struck with death [frapp de mort]

    (Friendship 11; 20). Blanchot goes further than

    the Bataille of Lascaux in attributing a meaning

    to what he calls the signature. In Lascaux,Bataille provides a brief survey of some of the

    secondary literature on the enigma of the cave.

    Abb Breuil argues that it commemorates a fatal

    accident that befell a hunting expedition.

    Windels, Brodick, and Lechner follow his inter-

    pretation; but, in so doing, they do not take

    account of what, for Bataille, is the strangest part

    of this scene the birds head. For Kirchner, by

    contrast, the tableau does not present a huntingincident; the prostrate man is not dead, but is a

    shaman in an ecstatic trance, recalling

    Sierozewskis discussion of the sacrifice of a cow

    by the Yakuts. The nudity and erect penis of the

    medicine man would be part of this ritual, but

    3 7

    Dow

    nloadedby[UniversityofS

    ydney]at22:0706January2015

  • 8/10/2019 09697250120087923

    10/15

    blanchots signature

    Bataille complains that this view overlooks the

    bison and his wound. What, then, are we to

    conclude about this scene (Lascaux 140)? Bataille

    draws no conclusion in Lascaux, although in The

    Tears of Eros, published a few years later,

    Bataille follows Blanchot in discovering an

    essential and paradoxical accord between

    death and eroticism that is signed in the

    closed space at the bottom of the crevasse (52).

    For Bataille, as for Blanchot, the fear and tenta-

    tiveness of this first step into humanity is

    revealed in the act that renders Lascaux ambigu-

    ous i.e., the signature of the first artist.

    The signature bears witness to a transgression

    that redoubles the ambiguous origin of the

    human being. As the realisation of affirmation,expression and communication, art remained

    foreign to the pre-humans. It took the arrival of

    the transgressor the one who was no longer

    simply himself, whose being was not, in a certain

    sense, assured to bestow its possibility. The

    first human being is the one who is drawn into a

    transgression that contests the power and the

    authority of the taboo in his experience of the

    work of art. It is by and through the creation of

    this work of art that this individual is in turn

    born as a human being through an act of sover-

    eign infraction.

    This signature is ostensibly a way of allowing

    the artist to stand back from what he has accom-

    plished as the work of art, and proclaim his

    mastery. It is his work; he has exhibited power

    over the materials at hand in order to render

    something beautiful, and he has every right to be

    proud of his virtuosity. But, for Blanchot, thesignature attests to a struggle inherent to

    artistry to a tension between a bold self-affir-

    mation and a certain fearfulness of the painter.

    The work of art does not, he claims, emerge

    out of the creative activity of the artist qua free

    and sovereign human being. In the time of differ-

    ence, there is no agent or subject to carry

    through the creative process; there is no one qua

    I or agent there to realise the work in its realexistence. Instead, there is only the pre-subjecti-

    vated space that opens in the extraordinary

    experience that the original experience names. To

    create an artwork of this kind is to undergo the

    experience in which the author is rendered

    passive beyond the usual notions of passivity. It

    is to be receptive to the original experience to the

    extent that artistic creation always involves a

    moment that passes into forgetting. The time of

    difference, the time of the absence of time, the

    paradoxical happening of an instant to which all

    of Blanchots writings point, always intervenes

    the disjunction between the time of production

    and work and the other time in which there is

    no one there to remember.

    It is this traumatic experience that Blanchot

    writes when he claims to discern evidence in the

    signature of the work that the artist of this first

    painting is seriously threatened by the artwork

    and struck with death. The signature is an

    attempt on the part of the author to reclaim whatis not his to reaffirm authorial sovereignty over

    the happening of the work of art in so far as it

    escapes the usual measure of experience and,

    therefore, the processes of memorisation, of the

    synthesising of the past into a present. The artist

    who laboured at Lascaux gives a sign of his trau-

    matic memory in his depiction of the recumbent

    figure stretched out between a bison and a rhino.

    In this signature, Blanchot discerns the fearful

    mark of the one who struggled with memory in

    his participation in the working of the work. The

    one who signs whose identity as an author is

    granted by an experience he is not there to

    experience does so because he fears an experi-

    ence, an excessiveness over the possibility of

    memorisation that resists his sovereignty and his

    mastery. The artist signs because he is afraid that

    his signature is provisional.4

    In his reading of Bataille, Blanchot is notendorsing or offering another historiographical

    account of the birth of art. The antiquity of

    Lascaux, the marvellous chance that preserved

    the paintings on the cave walls and the miracle of

    its discovery are only figures for the surprise that

    the cave walls present the same enigma as any

    work of art, ancient or modern. The artists of

    Lascaux can be said to be our contemporaries,

    because what we call their work of art attests tothe opening up of what will forever remain out of

    joint.

    In this sense, Lascaux is simply the name of

    an inaugural scene that already attests to a

    dissension of the origin to a division that turns

    3 8

    Dow

    nloadedby[UniversityofS

    ydney]at22:0706January2015

  • 8/10/2019 09697250120087923

    11/15

    iyer

    this classical scene of origination against itself.

    This dissension opens in any such origin any

    time, indeed, that an artwork can be said to orig-

    inate dividing the artist from himself and,

    thereby, frustrating the historian of art who

    would tell us a tale about the origin and devel-

    opment of art. This kind of recounting depends

    upon an ascription of authorial agency upon a

    conception of biography that would retrace the

    origin of the work of art to a creator. If my

    presentation of Blanchots arguments is correct,

    then no such ascription is possible. The origin of

    a particular artwork is not the artist; likewise,

    the origin of art as such the origin of what we

    have only recently learned to call art does not

    occur as a conventionally datable occurrence.Despite their significance to a certain historio-

    graphical recounting of the origin of art, the cave

    paintings at Lascaux are merely an example

    an example among other examples.5 But what

    does this example exemplify? If there is no

    origin of art if there is only a pre-originary

    dissension that tears the origin from its originat-

    ing function then no particular artwork,

    including the one canonically defined as the

    first, can be more than an example. By exposing

    the interruption of the origin that always and

    already disturbs the traditional recounting of the

    beginning of art, Blanchot draws attention, in

    the most powerful sense, to the inadequacy of

    the language of origin and inception, history and

    historiography, in so far as it fails to account for

    what happens at the canonically defined birth of

    art. Lascaux is exemplary for Blanchot only in so

    far as the birth of art points towards an experi-ence that outstrips historiographical reckoning.

    the wall writings

    What is remarkable about Blanchots writing is

    that he allows his signature to tremble; he can be

    said to write from the trembling his signature

    bears. He writes out of fear but he does not fear

    his fear; this is why he is able to write of theother of anamnesis, the traumatism that

    precedes, founds, and ruins memory. His signa-

    ture is the condition of his work, but in allowing

    his writing to reveal its trembling, to permit its

    ruination by the very excessiveness of its

    object, Blanchot gives a sign of a happening

    that perturbs all works.

    The signature attached to the particular work

    of art is but an extrinsic sign of the dynamics of

    origination. But its significance and the stakes of

    Blanchots discussion of the work of art are

    greater. The happening of art exposes the prior

    inextrication of working and worklessness and

    hence a certain disjuncture of time that deter-

    mines any kind of production. I have quoted

    Stephen Ungar who explains that, for Bataille,

    the work of art is distinguished from the prod-

    ucts of other work by a destructive force associ-

    ated with transgression and the sacred

    (Phantom Lascaux 258). I am not sure I would

    agree, since what Blanchot calls the signature,along with the aporia of the origin to which it

    attests, is discernible in any work. The artwork

    differs from other products only because the

    signature is visible in a different sense not

    merely obtruding into the space of the artwork

    but opening that space itself. Nevertheless, any

    work that is the outcome of a process of produc-

    tion can be said to exhibit a certain fear and

    trembling.

    Perhaps we must learn how to read the signa-

    tures that are inscribed on the bodies of those

    works that we take to be ours; perhaps, too, we

    will have to understand how the signature signs

    us, each of us that it is written across the

    bodies that we take to be ours. On the most

    solemn monuments of our age on the institu-

    tions of the government and the university, on

    the most imposing works of philosophy, of

    history, the signature is legible. What do we readthere? In a late essay, Blanchot invokes the

    memory of the events: When a number of us

    took part in the May 1968 movement, they

    hoped to be preserved from any ambition in the

    singular (Intellectuals 224; 38). Despite the

    differences between the participants that

    revealed themselves in incessant disputes,

    there was an underlying community between the

    participants (Intellectuals 224; 38). In onesense, it was perfectly possible to distinguish

    between the young and the old, the famous and

    the obscure; in another, all were bound in a rela-

    tionship to one another that allowed each person

    to recognise themselves in the anonymous

    3 9

    Dow

    nloadedby[UniversityofS

    ydney]at22:0706January2015

  • 8/10/2019 09697250120087923

    12/15

    blanchots signature

    words inscribed on the walls and which, in

    the end, even when on occasion they were the

    result of a collective effort, never declared

    themselves the words of an author, being of all

    and for all, in their contradictory formulation

    (Intellectuals 224; 38). The question concern-

    ing the authorship of these words cannot be

    resolved by tracing them back to an individual

    or a group. What is inscribed on the walls is a

    figure for the trembling of signature that signs

    itself in any work.

    Let us read them in From Paris 68:

    Imagination has seized power, Run comrade,

    the old world is behind you! (66), We are reas-

    sured, two and two no longer make four (68),

    The revolution is incredible because it is real(70), Under the paving stones, the beach (72),

    Dream is reality (74), The walls have ears.

    Your ears have walls (76), Poetry is in the

    street (78), Let us ban all applause, the spec-

    tacle is everywhere (80), It is forbidden to

    forbid (86), My desires are reality (88), To

    exaggerate is to begin to invent (90), Speak to

    your neighbours (92), To live for the moment

    (94), A cop sleeps inside every one of us, we

    must kill him (96), Alone, we can do nothing

    (104), We are all undesirables (110), Action

    must not be a reaction but a creation (112),

    Politics is happening in the street, To be free

    in 1968 means to take part, The barricade

    blocks the street but opens the way (114). It is

    not in order to translate such proclamations into

    a substantive political programme that Blanchot

    writes of the wall writings. Indeed, it would be

    better to remember the graffiti that would indi-cate its own provisionality: I have something to

    say but I dont know what or, more simply, I

    have nothing to say, Im playing, Quick!

    (From Paris 6870, 72, 84) slogans that like

    specks of foam splash up from the wave that

    crashed anonymously, impersonally and collec-

    tively through the streets of Paris: specks,

    traces, but nothing more. The participants of the

    events recognised them as signs of the experi-ence that exposes each of them to worklessness:

    a sign of the experience that has no one as its

    subject. Like the signature hidden in the

    crevasse at Lascaux, the wall writings would be

    an extrinsic figure of the movement of trans-

    gression that was affirmed, albeit briefly, on the

    streets of Paris.

    Was it affirmed, then, too, for the society

    from which came the ones who realised the

    paintings at Lascaux? The signature seems to

    attest, in its clandestinity, to an experience that

    was mysterious and difficult of access.

    Nevertheless, in so far as it is always at play at

    every level of production including the work

    of the subject to maintain itself as itself over

    time the worklessness that divides all works

    against themselves can never be preserved as the

    object of an esoteric knowledge. What the partic-

    ipants recognised in the writings on the walls was

    what the incipient human beings witnessed as

    they stepped into humanity.What they saw, then and what the spectator

    of the work of art would see now is the

    evidence of an experience on the part of the

    artist that re-echoes in the experience of the ones

    who stand before the artwork. The words,

    wonder, marvel, amazement, etc. can never

    describe this experience, unless it is thought in

    so far as it shelters an experience of fear. Fearful,

    trembling, the signature is inscribed in the

    artwork attesting to an opening of the world

    the eruption, the transgression of the prohibi-

    tions that permit the laying out of the plane of

    transcendence. The wall writings were there for

    anyone to see. They are the exoteric counterpart

    of the esoteric signature. The enigma of the pit

    is brought into daylight: it is discernible, obvi-

    ous, but recognisable only to those who partici-

    pate in what Blanchot calls the movement of

    May 1968.That is why Blanchot writes of the events as a

    feast; they open a group of human beings to

    an experience that transgresses them in their

    subjectivity (Unavowable Community 29; 54).

    Does this mean that the events would be a blue-

    print for a future revolution: that one would

    have merely to imitate such a programme in

    order to reveal the play of the signature?

    Blanchot reminds us that, although the eventswere exceptional, they provide no solution;

    this happening is sufficient unto itself

    (Intellectuals 224; 38). Perhaps they could be

    said to provide us with an idea of a revolution

    that does not need to succeed or achieve a fixed

    4 0

    Dow

    nloadedby[UniversityofS

    ydney]at22:0706January2015

  • 8/10/2019 09697250120087923

    13/15

    iyer

    goal (Intellectuals 224; 38); but they can do

    no more than this. The feast is spontaneous; the

    explosive generosity of celebration that interrupts

    the time of work re-opens the natural overabun-

    dance, the first immensity that floods over the

    prohibitions that would hold it at bay.

    The festivity of the events echoes the festivity

    of those who first celebrated as they crossed the

    threshold into humanity. But the events are also

    a threshold; what happens there is a transgression

    that permits the step into humanity even as it

    reveals the impossibility of ever completing this

    step once and for all. They repeat what happened

    in the very eruption of the human being into the

    world just because human existence cannot be

    secured once and for all. In the first signature, asin the wall writings of the events of 1968 which

    are themselves a kind of signing we discover

    the trace of the human being who is born

    through the interruption of worklessness onto the

    plane of transcendence. In contradistinction to

    the threat that the work exerts over the one who

    is born of his work and the society of those who

    emerge into history when they view it the

    events give evidence that what was feared once

    need not be an object of fear. It is in an exuber-

    ant joy that the events affirm what was once, and

    for so many times, feared. The mystery is not

    hidden; the enigma is no longer buried in the pit

    or left modestly in a corner. In the daylight,

    affirmed, is the experience that is figured in the

    writings of the wall: the spontaneity of a move-

    ment that is not moved by itself. Who are the

    raggle-taggle, the chienlit the ones who share

    nothing but their festivity, least of all a politicalprogramme recognisable to the men of power

    they oppose only through their absence of reac-

    tion (Unavowable Community 31; 54). There is

    no secret; it is written on the walls, just as it was

    written thousands of years ago by the ones who

    stepped in joy and fearful trembling into human-

    ity. Who were they? who, for that matter, are

    we, the ones who know what art is and what it

    must be? We are the ones who know without theknowing that the absolute and the substantial

    conceal what the wall writings in the events

    affirmed. Blanchot would teach us of what we do

    not yet know and cannot, disclosing a future that

    is also the future of art. Is art dead? Not unless

    we, too, are dead. Not unless the plane of tran-

    scendence covers over what does not fail to affirm

    itself in the explosive generos-

    ity of celebration, when we

    return to the jubilation of the

    interlude when we are once

    again what we were when we

    were not yet.

    notes

    I would like to thankAngelakis reviewers.

    1 I allude to Malrauxs notion of the imaginary

    museum in his Voices of Silence: Man and His Art.

    2 See Derridas Demeure. Fiction and Testimony

    3343, 7071.

    3 As Leslie Hill has argued, The Space of Literature,

    of which The Original Experience is a part,

    should also be read as an oblique response to

    Heideggers recently published essay Der

    Ursprung des Kunstwerks (Blanchot Extreme

    Contemporary 121). There is no question that

    Blanchot is profoundly influenced by Heidegger

    and particularly by The Origin of the Work of

    Art. Blanchot refers to Heidegger only twice in

    The Space of Literature once in a footnote and asa contemporary philosopher who has certain

    views on death. Despite Blanchots expressed

    reservations about Heideggers death analysis in

    Being and Time, Blanchots essay shares several

    important formulations with Heidegger among

    them the distinction between the work of art and

    equipment, and the view that the origin of the

    work of art precedes both the work of art and the

    artist (Blanchot Extreme Contemporary121). This

    is not the place to negotiate the relationshipbetween Blanchot and Heidegger a task that

    would have to draw upon The Sacred Word of

    Hlderlin in The Work of Fire, the long footnote

    appended to The Most Profound Question as

    well as Atheism and Writing and Ren Char

    and the Thought of the Neutral in The Infinite

    Conversation and large sections of The Writing of the

    Disaster. Finally, Do Not Forget and Our

    Clandestine Companion attest, later in

    Blanchots career, to his enduring reservationsabout the German thinker.

    4 The motivations behind his act of signing might

    well be opaque to the artist, but this troubled

    ignorance, the withdrawal of experience from

    itself, means that the anteriority of the original

    4 1

    Dow

    nloadedby[UniversityofS

    ydney]at22:0706January2015

  • 8/10/2019 09697250120087923

    14/15

    blanchots signature

    experience will reaffirm itself as soon as the

    creative process begins again.

    5 I will confine myself to one remark on the rela-

    tionship between Blanchot and Heidegger. In The

    Origin of the Work of Art, Heidegger introduces

    a famous example, that of a Greek temple. For

    Heidegger, the temple grants a certain way ofunderstanding the mysteries of birth and death

    and fate the way space and time are experienced

    by a people. Indeed, the temple is, in a certain

    sense, the arbiter of the divine law: the god whose

    figure it contains opens the holy space of the

    temple and allows the people it inaugurates to

    understand life and even afterlife in the context of

    the whole. Heidegger explains that the artwork

    enjoys a quasi-transcendental function, rendering

    a particular understanding of being possible byopening a world. In exploring the figure of the cave

    paintings at Lascaux in Blanchots Friendship, I point

    discreetly towards the possibility of giving an

    account of the stakes of the Greek temple in The

    Origin of the Work of Art in its exemplarity. As

    Heidegger writes, The all-governing expanse of

    this open relational context is the world of this

    historical people. Only from and in this expanse

    does the nation first return to itself for the fulfil-

    ment of its vocation (The Origin of the Work ofArt 167). World is to be understood in terms of

    the way in which beings (including the human being

    itself) come into appearance for a particular

    people (The Essence of Grounds 112).

    Blanchots Lascaux does not perform a similar

    role indeed, no artwork is capable, for Blanchot,

    of disclosing a people to itself. The artwork is

    always the disruption of just such a disclosure. The

    happening of the work of art always leads to the

    disruption of the formation of a historical people;

    it is always transgressive. From a Blanchovian

    perspective, the refusal of the work as it divides

    itself against itself in the course of its origination is

    pacifiedby the emphasis on the world-disclosive

    aspect of Heideggers account of the origin of the

    work of art.

    bibliography

    Bataille, G. Lascaux or the Birth of Art. Trans.

    Austryn Wainhouse. Geneva: Skira, 1955.

    Bataille, G. Theory of Religion. Trans. Robert

    Hurley. New York: Zone, 1988.

    Bataille, G. The Tears of Eros . Trans. Peter Connor.

    San Francisco: City Lights, 1989.

    Blanchot, M. The Space of Literature. Trans. Ann

    Smock. Lincoln and London: U of Nebraska P,

    1982. LEspace littraire. Paris: Gallimard, 1955.

    Blanchot, M. Our Clandestine Companion.

    Trans. David Allison. Face to Face with Levinas. Ed.

    Richard Cohen. Albany: State U of New York P,

    l986.

    Blanchot, M. The Unavowable Community. Trans.

    Pierre Joris. Barrytown: Station Hill, 1988. La

    Communaut inavouable. Paris: Minuit, 1983.

    Blanchot, M. The Writing of the Disaster. Trans. Ann

    Smock. Lincoln: U of Nebraska P, 1986.

    Blanchot, M. Atheism and Writing. Trans. Susan

    Hanson. The Infinite Conversation. By Blanchot.

    Minneapolis and London: U of Minnesota P, 1993.

    Blanchot, M. Ren Char and the Thought of the

    Neutral. Trans. Susan Hanson. The Infinite

    Conversation. By Blanchot. Minneapolis and

    London: U of Minnesota P, 1993.

    Blanchot, M. The Most Profound Question.

    Trans. Susan Hanson. The Infinite Conversation. By

    Blanchot. Minneapolis and London: U of

    Minnesota P, 1993.

    Blanchot, M. Do Not Forget. Trans. Michael

    Holland. The Blanchot Reader. Ed. Michael Holland.

    Oxford: Blackwell, 1995.

    Blanchot, M. The Sacred Word of Hlderlin.

    Trans. Charlotte Mandel. The Work of Fire. By

    Blanchot. Stanford: Stanford UP, 1995.

    Blanchot, M. Hlderlin and the Essence of

    Poetry. Trans. Charlotte Mandell. The Work of

    Fire. By Blanchot. Stanford: Stanford UP, 1995.

    Blanchot, M. Intellectuals in Question. Trans.

    Michael Holland. The Blanchot Reader. Ed. Michael

    Holland. Oxford: Blackwell, 1995. Les intellectuels

    en question: bauche dune rflexion. Paris: Fourbis,

    1996.

    Blanchot, M. Friendship. Trans. Elizabeth

    Rottenberg. Stanford: Stanford UP, 1997. LAmiti.

    Paris: Gallimard, 1971.

    Breuil, H. Lascaux. Le Bulletin de la Socit

    Prhistorique Franaise 6, 7, 8 (1950).

    Brodick, A.H. Lascaux. A Commentary. London:

    Lindsay Drummond, 1949.

    Derrida, J. Demeure. Fiction and Testimony. Trans.

    Elizabeth Rottenberg. Stanford: Stanford UP, 2000.

    4 2

    Dow

    nloadedby[UniversityofS

    ydney]at22:0706January2015

  • 8/10/2019 09697250120087923

    15/15

    iyer

    Hegel, G.W.F. Aesthetics: Lectures on Fine Art.

    Oxford: Oxford UP, 1975.

    Heidegger, M. Der Ursprung des Kunstwerks.

    Holzwege. Frankfurt: Klostermann, 1950.

    Heidegger, M. The Origin of the Work of Art.

    Trans. David Farrell Krell. Basic Writings. 2nd ed.Ed. David Farrell Krell. London: Routledge, 1993.

    Heidegger, M. Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics.

    5th ed. Trans. Richard Taft. Bloomington: Indiana

    UP, 1997.

    Heidegger, M. The Essence of Grounds. Trans.

    William McNeill. Pathmarks. By Heidegger.

    Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1999.

    Hill, L. Blanchot Extreme Contemporary. London

    and New York: Routledge, 1997.

    Kant, I. The Critique of Pure Reason. Trans. Norman

    Kemp-Smith. London: Macmillan, 1929.

    Kirchner, H. Ein archologischer Beitrag zur

    Urgeschichte der Schamanismus. Anthropos 46.1

    (1952).

    Lechner, G. The Interpretation of the Accident

    Scene at Lascaux. Man: A Monthly Record of

    Anthropological Science 51.3 (1951).

    Malraux, Andr. Voices of Silence: Man and His Art .

    Trans. S. Gilbert. New Haven: Princeton UP, 1978.

    Rohan, Marc. From Paris 68. Graffiti, Posters,

    Newspapers and Poems of the Events of May 1968.

    London: Impact, 1988.

    Ungar, Stephen. Phantom Lascaux. Yale French

    Studies 78 (1990).

    Windels, F. Lascaux, Chapelle Sixtine de la prhis-

    toire. Dordogne: Montignac-sur-Vzre, 1948.

    Lars Iyer3 Hartington Road

    Chorlton-cum-Hardy

    Manchester M21 8UZ

    UK

    E-mail: [email protected]

    Dow

    nloadedby[UniversityofS

    ydney]at22:0706January2015