+ All Categories
Home > Documents > 4 Deontological Ethics

4 Deontological Ethics

Date post: 14-Apr-2015
Category:
Upload: anjupoonia
View: 12 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend
42
1 Deontological Approach Dr. Ching Wa Wong City University of Hong Kong [email protected]
Transcript
Page 1: 4 Deontological Ethics

1

Deontological Approach

Dr. Ching Wa Wong

City University of Hong Kong

[email protected]

Page 2: 4 Deontological Ethics

2

Using a person: a preliminary exercise

The trolley problem again. Give a record of you feelings after seeing the

following pictures.

Page 3: 4 Deontological Ethics

3

Page 4: 4 Deontological Ethics

4

Page 5: 4 Deontological Ethics

5

Help!

Ching Wa pushed you!

Page 6: 4 Deontological Ethics

6

Part 1

Kant and deontological ethics

Page 7: 4 Deontological Ethics

7

Deontology

The theory of duty or moral obligation. Duty:

Role-related duty General duty

Obligation: Requirement set on a person because of

his/her identity.

Page 8: 4 Deontological Ethics

8

Basic Kantian themes

1. Personal autonomy: The moral person is a rational self-leglislator.

2. Respect: Persons should always be treated as an end,

not a means. ‘No persons should be used.’

3. Duty: the moral action is one that we must do in

accordance with a certain principle, not because of its good consequence.

Page 9: 4 Deontological Ethics

9

Kant’s philosophy:

What can I know? Critique of Pure Reason

(1781) What ought I do?

Groundwork for the Metaphysic of Morals (1785); Critique of Practical Reason (1788)

What can I hope for? Critique of Judgment (17

90); Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone (1793)

Immanuel Kant (1724-1804)

Page 10: 4 Deontological Ethics

10

Phenomena and Noumena

Phenomena: things as they appear to us; empirical and ther

efore changeable. Noumena:

things-in-themselves, which can’t be known by the use of senses.

Kant argues that if there is such a thing as moral reality, it must be founded on the noumena, and this is because…

Page 11: 4 Deontological Ethics

11

The moral law is in its character absolute, and it can allow no

exception. And empirical knowledge simply cannot

establish such a law.

Page 12: 4 Deontological Ethics

12

Part 2

Kant’s Conception of Moral Values

Page 13: 4 Deontological Ethics

13

The moral worth

On Kant’s view, the moral worth of an action is not determined by its consequences because:

Page 14: 4 Deontological Ethics

14

1. It is possible that someone does something out of evil intention, but ends up bringing good consequences to society.

2. It is also possible that someone does something out of good intention, but ends up bringing about bad consequences.

3. The consequences of an action are not under our control.

4. We can only control our motives when acting as a moral person.

5. Therefore the moral worth of an action is given by our good will.

Page 15: 4 Deontological Ethics

15

Page 16: 4 Deontological Ethics

16

The right motive

‘For example, it is always a matter of duty that a dealer should not over charge an inexperienced purchaser; and wherever there is much commerce the prudent tradesman does not overcharge, but keeps a fixed price for everyone, so that a child buys of him as well as any other. Men are thus honestly served; but this is not enough to make us believe that the tradesman has so acted from duty and from principles of honesty: his own advantage required it;

Page 17: 4 Deontological Ethics

17

it is out of the question in this case to suppose that he might besides have a direct inclination in favour of the buyers, so that, as it were, from love he should give no advantage to one over another. Accordingly the action was done neither from duty nor from direct inclination, but merely with a selfish view.’

(http://eserver.org/philosophy/kant/metaphys-of-morals.txt)

Page 18: 4 Deontological Ethics

18

The right motive can be a motive out of either: self-interest, sympathy (natural inclination), or a sense of duty (the voice of conscience).

Only the final motive will count on Kant’s view.

Page 19: 4 Deontological Ethics

19

Hypothetical Vs categorical imperatives Hypothetical imperative:

What I ought to do if some conditions hold. E.g., Maxim: I ought to attend the lecture if I

want to pass my examination. Categorical imperative:

What I ought to do unconditionally. E.g., Maxim: I ought not to murder no matter

what goal I have.

Page 20: 4 Deontological Ethics

20

Two formulations of the categorical imperative 1. Act only on that maxim that you can will as

a universal law.

2. Always treat humanity, whether your own person or that of another, never simply as a means but always at the same time as an end.

Page 21: 4 Deontological Ethics

21

One Kant’s view, all moral imperatives are categorical imperatives.

They are universally valid and have equal forces to EQUALLY FREE and

RATIONAL AGENTS.

Page 22: 4 Deontological Ethics

22

An example: why lying is wrong

If we use consequences as the basis of moral worth, sometimes lying is right because it makes a lot of people happy.

But the maxim that supports lying cannot pass the ‘universality test’ and the ‘humanity test’.

Page 23: 4 Deontological Ethics

23

Lying is wrong because:

1. If everybody lies, then words lose its function to express truth. The principle of lying therefore cannot be universalized.

2. Lying can be successful only if we use other people’s ignorance. But in this case we are treating them only as a means to our ends.

Page 24: 4 Deontological Ethics

24

Freedom and the kingdom of ends

Given that all rational beings are equal, a kingdom comprising those beings must not favour any party or treat the other as inferior.

It follows that in the kingdom of ends everybody should be equally free and should not be a means to other people’s end.

The law thus set up is a contract between free and rational agents.

Page 25: 4 Deontological Ethics

25

Morality is thus a matter of social contract made between free and

rational agents.

Page 26: 4 Deontological Ethics

26

Part 3

Questions about Kantian Ethics

Page 27: 4 Deontological Ethics

27

Motivational problems

Why should I obey to the moral law? Answer: Because I want to be a wholly free (a

utonomous) person who acts on the principle that I find most reasonable.

Why should I respect other persons? Answer: This is simply because rational perso

ns are equal.

Page 28: 4 Deontological Ethics

28

Freedom or equality?

Is autonomy or equality the fundamental value in ethics? What if they conflict each other? Answer: In principle they do not conflict each

other, because both are built up in the idea of reason.

But in practice…?

Page 29: 4 Deontological Ethics

29

Conflicts of duties

If duty A conflicts with duty B, how can they be universalized?

Example: I have a universal duty not to kill the Fat man. I also have a universal duty to save the five

workers. What should I do?

Page 30: 4 Deontological Ethics

30

Non-rational beings

The moral law is set up by rational agents who mutually respect each other. Non-rational beings such as animals are not protected by that law because they don’t have this sense of responsibility.

If we have a duty not to be cruel to animals, it cannot be for their sake, but for the reason that we will hurt our own rationality in doing so (that we will develop a bad personality in this practice).

Page 31: 4 Deontological Ethics

31

Some questions to consider

If I am a Kantian, should I support:1. Participatory democracy?

2. Representative (market) democracy?

3. Capitalism?

4. Revolutionary Marxism?

5. Confucian ethics?

6. Anarchism?

Page 32: 4 Deontological Ethics

32

Part 4

Application:

Research ethics

Page 33: 4 Deontological Ethics

33

Using human beings in experiments

Stanley Milgram’s experiment Philip Zimbardo’s Stanford Prison Study Main question:

When will be wrong to use a person in academic research?

Page 34: 4 Deontological Ethics

34

The doctrine of informed consent

The Nuremberg code:

The voluntary consent of the human subject is absolutely essential. This means that the person involved should have the legal capacity to give consent; should be so situated as to be able to exercise free power of choice, without the intervention of any element of force, fraud, deceit, duress, over-reaching, or other ulterior form of constraint or coercion; and should have sufficient knowledge and comprehension of the subject matter involved as to enable him to make an understanding and enlightened decision.

Page 35: 4 Deontological Ethics

35

Autonomy: A Kantian interpretation

By saying that we respect persons as autonomous agents, we imply that they are having equal statuses with us, that we cannot treat them as a means only.

Using somebody implies an imbalanced power structure, meaning that the users are in a higher rank; have more power; have ends in the action plan that the inferior party

cannot share.

Page 36: 4 Deontological Ethics

36

Autonomy thus requires that if I am to be treated as a means, I must also be able to recognize the experimenter’s end as my end. If I can recognize the promoting of collective interests as an

end that I share without contradiction, I can say being deceived is my choice.

Page 37: 4 Deontological Ethics

37

Milgram’s experiment

You are hired by an experimenter to conduct an experiment.In the experiment you play the part of a teacher.

I am a teacher now.

Another participant, after drawing the lot, plays the part of a learner.

I am a learner. And I have to remember the words of the teacher and read them back.

You give the learner some words to remember, and ask him to read out after some time.

If the answer is correct, you say…

Move on to the next

word!

If it is incorrect…

Teacher, give him a punishment. A 15 volt

electric shock.

APPLE--PEACH; LEMON—HONEY; CAR

—TRASH; DEMOCRACY—PLATO;

CHINGWA—TEDDY BEAR…

CHINGWA--

…SNOOPY

Wrong!

Page 38: 4 Deontological Ethics

38

The punishment part

You are in control of a machine generating a voltage ranging from 15 to 450 volts.

Low voltage:

15

Medium voltage:250

High voltage: 450Dangerous

The experimenter keeps instructing you to increase voltage, saying that he takes full responsibility for that.

Do it. I am in charge of all

this.

You do it accordingly.You regret. ‘Why didn’t I stop, man?’The learner screams and shows great pain.

Page 39: 4 Deontological Ethics

39

Milgram’s trick

The lucky thing, or the bad thing is that…

No one in fact got hurt. The learner is a great pretender.

You are cheated, man. There’s no electric

shock at all.

You are angry. You think it is unethical.

You fooled me?

Page 40: 4 Deontological Ethics

40

The Stanford Prison: A case study

Page 41: 4 Deontological Ethics

41

Final questions

Which experiment is more unethical according to Kantian ethics?

Is the respect to autonomy something absolute? Is a lesser degree of autonomy totally unacceptable?

How can we respect people when they are not fully rational?

Page 42: 4 Deontological Ethics

42

References

Driver, Julia, Ethics: the Fundamentals, Blackwell Publishing, ch.5

Mackinnon, Barbara (2007), Ethics: Theory and Contemporary Issues, Thomson Wadsworth, ch.5.

Rachels, James (1995), The Elements of Moral Philosophy, McGraw-Hill, ch.9 & 10.


Recommended