+ All Categories
Home > Documents > A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Date post: 19-Jan-2016
Category:
Upload: ena
View: 49 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend
Description:
A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving. Theoretical Foundations, History and the Resolution Calculus for classical First-order Logic Uwe Keller based on material by B. Beckert, R. Hähnle, A. Voronkov, A. Leitsch and T. Tammet. Content. Intoduction Motivation & History - PowerPoint PPT Presentation
54
A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving Theoretical Foundations, History and the Resolution Calculus for classical First-order Logic Uwe Keller based on material by B. Beckert, R. Hähnle, A. Voronkov, A. Leitsch and T. Tammet
Transcript
Page 1: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Theoretical Foundations, History and the Resolution Calculus for classical First-order Logic

Uwe Keller

based on material by B. Beckert, R. Hähnle, A. Voronkov, A. Leitsch and T. Tammet

Page 2: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Content Intoduction

Motivation & History Theorem Proving, ATP and Calculi

Foundations FOL, Normalforms & Preprocessing, Metaresults

Resolution Basic calculus, Unification Refinements, Redundancy Decision procedures

Chain Resolution A Variant of Resolution for the Semantic Web

Demo

Page 3: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Part I:Introduction

Motivation & History Theorem Proving, ATP and Calculi

Page 4: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Modelling(automated)

Deduction

Logic and Theorem Proving

Real-world descriptionin natural language.Mathematical ProblemsProgram + Specification

Syntax (formal language).First-order Logic, Dynamic Logic, …

Valid Formulae

Provable Formulae

Formalization

Semantics(truth function)

Calculus(derivation / proof)

Correctness

Completeness

Page 5: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

How did it start … Results from first-half of the 20th century in

mathematical logic showed … we can do logical reasoning with a limited set of simple

(computable) rules in restricted formal languages like First-order Logic (FOL)

That means computers can do reasoning!

Implementation of ATP First: Computers where needed :- ) AI as a prominent field: Reasoning as a basic skill! Mid 1950‘s first attempts to implement an ATP

Today (A)TP is no longer only a part of main stream AI Central shared problem: How to represent and search

extremely large search spaces!

Page 6: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

A rough timeline in ATP … before 1950: Proof-theoretic Work by Skolem, Herbrand, Gentzen and Schütte 1954: First machine-generated Proof (Davis) 1955ff: Semantic Tableaus (Beth, Hinitkka) 1957: First machine-generated Proof in Logic Calculus (Newell & Simon) 1957: Lazy substitution by free (dummy) Vars (Kanger, Prawitz) 1958: First prover for Predicate Logic (Prawitz) 1959: More provers (Gilmore, Wang) 1960: Davis-Putnam Procedure (Davis, Putnam, Longman) 1963: Unification (J.A. Robinson) 1963ff: Resolution (J.A. Robinson); Inverse Method (Maslov) 1963ff: Modern Tableau Method (Smullyan, Lis) without Unification 1968: Modelelimination (Loveland), with Unification 1970ff: PROLOG (Colmerauer, Kowalski), Refinements of Resolution 1971: Connection Method (Bibel), Matings (Andrews) with Unification 1985: ATP in non-classical logics, Renaissance of Tableaux Methods 1987: Tableaus with Unification 1993ff: Renewed interest in Instance-based Methods: DPLL, Modelevolution …

Page 7: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Theorem Proving Given

a formal language (or logic) L a calculus C for this language (= set of rules) a conjecture S and a set of assumptions or axioms A in the

language L

Determine Can we construct a proof for S (from A) in calculus C?

Logic = Syntax + Semantics + Calculus TP = Proof-search in C (Huge search problem)

Correctness and completeness of Calculi essential properties

Calculus = Non-deterministic Algorithm Central problem in ATP: How to implement a non-deterministic

algorithm „efficiently“ on a deterministic machine :- )

Page 8: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Theorem Proving (II) Research areas

Interactive / tactic TP vs. Automated TP Classical Logic vs. Non-classical logics

Calculi for … ATP - General principle: Refutation approach

Resolution, Tableau, Inverse Method, Instance-based Methods ITP – General principle: Show Proof situation/context

Sequent Calculi others – General principle: Generation of complex

formulae based on very simple axioms Hilbert-style Calculi

Central difference: What are the elements in a proof & what is a proof?

Page 9: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Main TP Applications Main Applications

Software & Hardware Verification Theorem proving in Mathematics Query answering in rich knowledge bases (Ontologies) Verification of cryptographic protocols Retrieval of Software Components Reasoning in non-classical Logics Program synthesis …

… many systems implemented ATP: Vampire, Otter, Spass, E-SETHEO, Darwin, Epilog,

SNARK, Gandalf … ITP: Isabelle/HOL, Coq, Theorema, KeY-Prover …

Page 10: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Why is FOL of special interest in the ATP community ? There are less & more expressive logics than FOL

Classical Propositional Logic, Modal Propositional Logic, Description Logics, Temporal Propositional Logic

Higher-order Predicate Logics, Dynamic Predicate Logics, Type Theory

Research in ATP mainly focused on FOL FOL is very expressive, many real-world problems can be

formalized in FOL FOL turned out to be the most expressive logic that one can

adequately approach with ATP techniques

Page 11: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Example … Theorem in (elementary) Calculus

Nullstellensatz: Every function which is continous over a closed interval I=[a,b] must take the value 0 somewhere in I if f(a) <= 0 and f(b) >= 0

Proof idea: Consider the Supremum l of set M = {x : f(x) <= 0, a<=x<=b} and show that f(l) = 0

Page 12: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Example (II) … Formalization

Compact (only LEQ) Redundancy-free Specific definitions

Continous functions Main idea of proof

is already encoded Use Supremum

Can be done by anATP system

… but without properFormalization ?!?

ATP better than humanprover? Robbins Problem in Algebra

Intelligent Proving vs.Combinatorical proving

Page 13: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Part II:Foundations

FOL, Normalforms & Preprocessing, Metaresults

Page 14: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Classical First-order Logic (FOL) Syntax

Signature § Function Symbols, Predicate Symbols, Arity, logical

Connectives, Quantors Terms (over §), Atomic Formulae (over §), Formluae (over §) Definition relative to the signature § of the predicate logic

Semantics First-order structure / interpretation S = (U,I)

Universe U + Signature-Interpretation I Constants I(c) = element of U Functionsymbols I(f) = total functions on U Relationsymbols I(R) = relation on U Logical connectives and quantors in the usual way

Definition relative to the signature § of the predicate logic

Page 15: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Classical FOL (II) Model of a statement

An interpretation S = (U,I) is called a model of a statement s iff valS(s) = t

What does it mean to infer a statement from given premisses? Informally: Whenever our premisses P hold it is the case that the

statement holds as well Formally: Logical Entailment

For every interpretation S which is a model of P it holds that S is a model of S as well

Special case: Validity – Set of premisses is empty Logical entailment in a logic L is the (semantic) relation that a

calculus C aims at formalizing syntactically (by means of a derivability relation)!

Logical entailment considers semantics (Interpretations) relative to a set of premisses or axioms!

Page 16: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Normal Forms What is a normal form? Why are they interesting?

Relation to ATP? Conversion of input to a specifc NF my be required by a calculus (e.g.

Resolution) ) Preprocessing step ATP in a sense can be seen as a conversion in a NF itself, borderline is

fuzzy in a sense

Normalforms in FOL Negation Normal Form Standard Form Prenex Normal Form Clause Normal Form (in a sense a „logic free“ form)

There are logics where certain NF do not exist, like CNF in a Dynamic First-order Logic Certain calculi then can not be applied in these logics!

Page 17: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Negation Normal Form A formula is in Negation NF (NNF) iff. it contains no implication and no

bi-implication symbols and all negation symbols occur only as part of a literal (directly in front of atomic formulae)

How to achieve this NF ? Replace implication and bi-implication by their definition (in terms of Æ and

Ç) Move negation symbols inside to atomic formulae

De Morgan laws Dualize quantifiers when moving negation symbols over a quantor Eliminate multiple negations

All these syntactical transformations generate semantically equivalent formulae

Example

Page 18: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Standard Form A formula A is in Standard Form if no variable x in A occurs

both bound and free and no bound variable is used as a quantor variable for multiple subformulae

How to generate this NF? Bounded renaming of quantor variables and the respective

occurrences Transformed formulae is semantically equivalent to original one

Example (8 x P(x) Æ Q(z)) ! (9 x R(x) Ç 9 z (P(z) Æ Q(z)))

Page 19: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Prenex Normal Form A formula A is in Prenex NF iff. it is of the form

A = Q1x1 … Qnxn B where Qk is a universal or existential quantor and B contains no quantors. B is called the Matrix of A

How to construct this NF? Transform A in NNF and Standard Form Move iteratively outermost quantor to the outside until it reaches

another quantor. Quantors may not cross quantors of different sort (in-scope relation between quantor occurrences may not be changed)

This transformation generates a formulae which is logically equivalent to the original one.

Example

Page 20: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Clause Normal Form A formula A is in Clause NF iff. it is in PNF, closed, the prefix only

contains universal quantors and the Matrix is on conjunctive normal form.

In other words: A = 8 x1 … 8 xn ( (L1,1 Ç … Ç L1,m1) Æ … Æ (Lk,1 Ç … Ç

Lk,mk)) where Li,j is a literal (negated or positive atomic formula)

How to construct this NF? Transform A in NNF and Standard Form Transform result in PNF Remove existential quantors by Skolemization (Function terms) Apply Distributivity laws to convert Matrix of the result in conjuntive normal

form (conjunction of discjunction of literals) This transformation results in a formula which is not logically equivalent, but

it is satisfiability-preserving (which is enough for the ATP methods later)

Example

Page 21: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Clause Normal Form (II) A formula A is in Clause NF can be written as A = 8 x1 … 8 xn ( (L1,1 Ç … Ç L1,m1

) Æ

… Æ (Lk,1 Ç … Ç Lk,mk)) where Li,j is a literal (negated or positive atomic formula)

Since every formula can be transformed into CNF, the CNF can be seen as „logic free“ representation of a formulae All quantors are universal, no free variables are allowed -> drop quantors Matrix is in CNF = Conjunction of Disjunction of Literals -> Model as a Set of Sets of

Literals Example

The sketched transformation to CNF is not optimal Exponential blowup possible (already for NNF) Syntactical structure of the original formula gets lost Skolemsymbols have unnecessarily many parameters Unnecessarily many new skolem systems are introduced

One can improve all these aspects of a transformation to CNF! Skolemization before PNF transformation, Definitorial CNF for Matrix, Reuse of Skolem

functions

Page 22: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Metaresults Metaresult = Property of a Logic L

Most famous example: Gödels Incompleteness Theorems! Here some metaresults for FOL which form the

theoretical foundation of ATP carry over to many other logics as well

Deduction Theorem If M [ s ² s‘ then M ² s‘ ! s Logical entailment can be reduced to validity

Proof by contradiction If M is a set of closed formulae then

M ² s iff. M [ {¬s} is unsatisfiable (i.e. has no model) Logical entailment can be reduced to unsatisfiability checking Refutation can be used as a universal principle for inference in FOL

Page 23: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Metaresults (II) Complexity of logical entailment, validity and

satisfiability

Propositional Logic Logical entailment (²-relation) is decidable, Satisfiability too Set of valid formulae is co-NP-complete Set of satisfiable formulae is NP-complete

First-order Predicate Logic Logical entailment / validity / satisfiability is undecidable Set of valid formulae is semi-decidable (recursively enumerable) Set of satisfiable formulae is not recursively enumerable

Page 24: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Metaresults (III) Term Interpretations and Herbrand Theorem

S = (U,I) is term-interpretation if U = Term0

Let Term0 be non-empty. An interpretation S = (U,I) is called

Herbrand-Interpretation if S is term-interpretation and I(f)(t1,…,t

) = f(t

,…,t

) for all n-ary function symbols f 2 and

ground terms t,…,t

Herbrand-Modell of s is Herbrand-Intp. I with I ² s

Herbrand-Interpretations are special because they have a simple universe (syntactical) and Terms are basically uninterpreted. Quantifiers then have ground terms as their range!

Computers can deal with such special (syntactical) interpretations, but not with interpretations in general!

Page 25: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Metaresults (IV) Term Interpretations and Herbrand Theorem

Let M be a set of closed formulae s in Prenex-Normalform that contain no existential quantors (for instance s in CNF)

Let T be a set of terms (over signature T(M) := set of T-instances of M, i.e. replace every occurence of a

(universal) variable in any formulae in M with any term in T

Herbrand Theorem Let Term0

be non-empty and M a set of formulae in Prenex-NF without existential quantors.

Then the following statements are equivalent M has a model M has a Herbrand-model Term0

(M) has a model The last set is a set of formulae in propositional logic

Page 26: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Metaresults (V) Compactness of FOL

A (possibly infinite) set M of formulae has a model iff every finite subset M‘ ½ M has a model (i.e. is satisfiable)

Combining Compactness with Herbrand‘s Theorem Let Term0

be non-empty and M a set of formulae in Prenex-NF without existential quantors.

Then M is unsatisfiable iff. T(M) is unsatisfiable for a finite set of ground terms T ½ Term0

Note that T is a finite set of ground terms over the signature of the formula set M

No „external“ functions symbols have to be considered! Allows for using guided substitutions (Unification!)

Page 27: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Metaresults (VI) That means: logical entailment / validity can be checked

by reduction to unsatisfiabiliy of a set of formulae M‘ which can done by finding suitable finite (counter)-

examples for the quantfied variables such that a contradiction arises

One can only use the Signature of the given set M‘ to find the counterexamples

Basically this is what all ATP procedures do: Find a finite set of counterexamples (objects) such that a respective instance of the orginial formula set is determined as being inconsistent (unsatisfiable)

The theorem immediately gives an algorithm for ATP! Problem: How to construct / find T in the theorem in a clever

way?

Page 28: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Herband‘s Theorem:From Clause Logic to Propositional Logic

Clause Logic

Propositional Logic

(Ground) Substitutions

Clauses

Ground clauses

Incons-istent set

Page 29: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Part III:The Resolution Calculus

Pre-resolution phase: Gilmore‘s Methods, Davis-Putnam Procedure

Unification Basic Resolution Calculus Refinements, Redundancy

Page 30: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Pre-Resolution period: Gilmore‘s Method

First ATP procedure for First-order logic Directly based on Herbrands Theorem

Reduction of FOL entailment to satisfiability in Prop. Logic How to generate candidates C‘ for propositional satisiability checking

from a FOL clause set C Saturation by ground instances from Hn(C) (= set of ground terms of

depth · n) More precisely: Successively generate the sets C‘n of ground clauses :=

{c : c 2 C and rg() µ Hn(C) } Since H_n( C) grow exponentially it is very important to have a good

algorithm for checking satisfiability

Page 31: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Pre-Resolution period: Gilmore‘s Method

„Easy“ test of satisfiability of the generated C‘ set of ground clauses: Transform C‘ into Disjunctive Normal Form D = DNF(C‘) is unsatisfiable iff every consitutent of D contains a

contradiction L Æ ¬L for some literal L Can be done in deterministic time O(n log(n)) Problem: Convertion from CNF into DNF (almost always) exponential

(inherently complex, since otherwise P = NP), (not known at that time!) Pseudocode

begin contr := false while not contr do D‘ := DNF(C‘_n) contr := all constitutents of D‘ contain complementary literals n:=n+1 end whileend

Page 32: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Pre-Resolution period: Gilmore‘s Method

Weak points of Gilmore‘s approach … The generation of the candidate ground clause sets C‘n to be checked the discjunctive normal form transfomation

First weakness is inherent to all procedures directly applying Herbrands theorem

The second problem concerns propositional logic only

Gilmore‘s pioneering implementation did not yield actual proofs for quite simple predicate logic formulas

A possible improvement Avoid transformation to DNF and try to find „good“ decision methods for

satisfiability on CNFs This is basically what was achieved by Davis and Putnam [DP,1960] shortly after

Gilmore‘s implementation

Page 33: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Pre-Resolution period:Davis-Putnam Procedure

Like Gilmore‘s method based on successive production of ground caluse sets C‘N and testing of their unsatisfiability

(Still) very efficient decision method for satisfiability. Requires CNF for ground clauses.

Invented originally for FOL, it became the most powerful SAT decision procedure for Propositional Logic. Many very powerful SAT solvers still are refining DPP today.

Davis-Logemann-Loveland Rules [DLL, 1962] Preliminary step: Reduce all clauses in C

Eliminate multiple occurrences of the same literal (leave only one). Generates a clause set C‘

Then apply the follwing rules non-deterministically to C‘ Tautology-Rule One-Literal-Rule Pure-Literal-Rule Splitting-Rule

Page 34: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Pre-Resolution period:Davis-Putnam Procedure

Davis-Logemann-Loveland Rules [DLL, 1962] Tautology-Rule: Delete all clauses in C‘ containing complementary literals One-Literal-Rule: If there is a clauses c = {l} with only one literal l, remove all

clauses d from C‘ which contain l, and remove the dual literal ld from all other clauses

Pure-Literal-Rule: Let D‘ µ C‘ with the following property: There exists a literal l appearing in all clauses of D‘, but ld does not appear in C‘. Then delete D‘ from C‘

Splitting-Rule: Let C‘ = {A1,…,An,B1,…,Bm} [ R such that R contains l nor ld, all Ai contain l but not ld and all Bj contain ld but not l. Let A‘i = Ai after deletion of l and let B‘j = Bj after deletion of ld.Then split C‘ into C‘1 = {A‘1,…,A‘n} [ R and C‘2={B‘1,…,B‘m} [ R

Properties of the DLL procedure The rules are essentially reductive (atoms are in each step deleted) The rules are correct (rules preserve satisfiability; in case of split only for one of

the new introduced clauses sets The procedure generates sets that contain the empty clause for all cases (of the

applied splits) iff C‘ is unsatisfiable (decision criteria: correctness and completeness, termination)

Example: C = {P Ç Q, R Ç S Ç S, ¬R Ç S, R Ç ¬S, ¬R Ç ¬S, P Ç ¬Q Ç ¬P}

Page 35: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Pre-Resolution period:Davis-Putnam Procedure

Pseudocode of the First-order ATP procedure by Davis & Putnam

begin {C finite set of clauses}

if C does not contain („real“) function symbols

then apply DP1 – DP3 to C‘_0; check the DP decision tree for unsatisfiability

else begin

n:= 0; contr := false

while not contr do

perform DP1 – DP3 on C‘_n

if the DP-decision tree proves unsatisfiability

then contr := true

else contr := false

n:=n+1

end while

end

end

DP1: Reduce all clausesDP2: Delete all tautologiesDP3: Construct a DP decision tree according to the given rules

• Nondeterministic (DP3)• If C does not contain function symbols (with arity > 0) then the procedure always terminates (== decision procedure for FOL clause set)•If C is satisfiable and C contains function symbols then the algorithm does not terminate•Yields a decision procedure for validity of the Bernays-Schönfinkel class in FOL (8* 9*)

Page 36: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Interlude:Inferences & Inference systems An inference I has the form

where n ¸ 0, F1,…,Fn, G are formulae

An inference rule R is a set of inferences more precisely a decidable (usually efficiently computable) n+1-ary relation over

formuale Usually one uses schematic variables for representing formulae in inference rules and

attach some (most often syntactic) conditions to these variables Every instance I 2 R is called an instance of R

An inference system § is a (finite) set of inference rules A proof of G from P in § is a finite sequence of formulae F1, … Fn such that

Fn = F and for all Fi (i · n) it holds that either Fi 2 N or there is an inference I such that Fi is the

conclusion of I and all the premisses P1, … Pj of I are contained in the prefix F1, …, F(i-1)

Here we mainly consider inference systems on clauses, for instance Resolution

F1 F2 … Fn

G

Premisses

Conclusion

Page 37: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

A Revolution in ATP: Robinson‘s Resolution Principle In some sense the simplest possible calculus for FOL (without equality)

In principle only a single inference rule which combines substution and atomic cut

Possible since it requires set of input formulae in CNF (very simple and uniform syntactic form)

Binary substitution rule computing a „minimal“ substitution which makes two atoms equal

A quote from Robinsons landmarking paper [Robinson, 1965] …

Theorem-proving on the computer, using procedures based on the fundamental theorem of Herbrand concerning the FOL Predicate Calculus, is examined with a view towards improving the efficiency and widening the range of practical applicability of these procedures. A close analysis of the process of substitution (of terms for variables) and the process of truth-functional analysis of the results of such substitutions reveals that both processes can be combined into a single new iterating process (called resolution) which is vastly more efficient than the older cylcic procedures consisting of substitution stages alternating with truth-functional analysis stages.

Page 38: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

A Revolution in ATP: Robinson‘s Resolution Principle

The basic Resolution Calculus (BRC) Ground case

General case

Fundamental aspects: Iterative grounding of the clause set „Guided“ guessing of interesting instances (Unification) built into the calculus Resolving upon an atom L does not require L to be ground (unnecessary

grounding avoided)

L Ç C ¬L Ç DC Ç D

C Ç L Ç L C Ç L

BinaryResolution Factoring

L Ç C ¬L‘ Ç D(C Ç D)

C Ç L Ç L‘ (C Ç L)

BinaryResolution Factoring

where is the most general unifier of L and L‘

Page 39: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Basic Resolution Calculus:Properties

Properties of the basic Resolution Calculus Given any two clauses, there are only finitely many resolvents using the Resolution

Inference Rule. The Resolution Calculus is sound

If c is provable from C in BRC then C ² c This means in particular: If we can derive the emtpy clause then C is unsatisfiable

The Resolution Calculus is refutationally complete A set C of clauses is unsatisfiable then the empty clause can be proven (derived) from

C Altogether

A set C of clauses is unsatisfiable iff. there is a proof for the empty clause from C in BRC

Remark: Soundness of the inference system can be relaxed to satisfiability- preserving!

How to find a contradiction (empty clause) starting with an initial (unsatisfiable) formula set? Saturation approach (wrt. the inference system BRC)

Page 40: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Resolution:Proof search by Saturation Saturated sets

A set of clauses C is called saturated (wrt. inference system ) if every inference in with premises in C gives a clause in C

Completness reformulated (in terms of saturated sets) A set C of clauses is unsatisfiable iff every saturated set S of clauses with C

µ S also contains the empty clause

That means: Simply construct a(ny) saturated set S of clauses (wrt. BRC) S (saturation algorithm)

Simple algorithm

S:= set of input clauseswhile not finished do(1) Repeatedly apply all inferences to clauses in S, adding to S conclusions of these inferences(2) If the empty clause is proved, terminate with success.

If no inference rule is applicable, terminate with failure

Page 41: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Resolution:Proof search by Saturation

given clausecandidate clause

Conclusions

Search spaceSearch space

Goal clause

Page 42: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Resolution:Proof search by Saturation

Most likely scenario ….

Search space

Page 43: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Resolution:Proof search by Saturation Possible theoretical scenarios

At some moment the empty clause is generated, in this case the input set of clauses is unsatisfiable

Saturation will terminate without ever generating the empty clause, in this case the input set of clauses is satisfiable

Saturation will run forever, but without generating the empty clause. In this case the input set of clauses is satisfiable

Possible practical scenarios At some moment the empty clause is generated, in this case the input set of

clauses is unsatisfiable Saturation will terminate without ever generating the empty clause, in this

case the input set of clauses is satisfiable Saturation will run until we run out of resources, but without generating

the empty clause. In this case it is unknown whether the input set of clauses is (un)satisfiable

Page 44: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Resolution:How to saturate in clever way ? The simple saturation algorithm is highly inefficient Apply inferences not in an arbitrary way, but within some senseful /

useful order. Generate the empty clause as early as possible in the saturation

process

„Prefer“ some inferences over others (in a sense), for instance goal directedness

Actually what we need to ensure then to have completness guaranteed is fairness: A saturation algorithm is fair iff every possible inference is eventually

selected Completness Theorem reformulated (for Saturation Algorithms)

Let A be a fair saturation algorithm. A set C of clauses is unsatisfiable iff A eventually produces the empty clause

Central problem: How to find „good“ saturation algorithms!

Page 45: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

How to guess suitable instances?Unification

Page 46: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Example:Basic Resolution Calculus

Page 47: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Enhancing Efficiency: Refinements of Resolution

Page 48: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Resolution Refinements:Hyperresolution

Page 49: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Resolution Refinements:Ordered Resolution

Page 50: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Enhancing Efficiency: Redundancy Criteria in Resolution

Page 51: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Part IV:Chain Resolution

A Variant of Resolution for the Semantic Web

Page 52: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

Part IV:Demo

assisted by a Resolution-based ATP System: VAMPIRE

Page 53: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

And there is a lot we have not talked about yet … Different Calculi

Tableaux Methods, Instance-based Methods, Inverse Method

Decision Procedures Theory Reasoning, in particular equality ATP in other logics

Modal, temporal logics, description logics Logics for non-monotonic reasoning Paraconsistent logics

Reasoning tasks other than logical entailment / unsatisfiability Query answering

Page 54: A brief Introduction to Automated Theorem Proving

References & further Reading …


Recommended