+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

Date post: 08-Dec-2016
Category:
Upload: alexia
View: 216 times
Download: 1 times
Share this document with a friend
167
2. Elementary Integration Theory NOTATION FOR CHAPTER 2: X denotes a set. 2.1 Riesz Lattices This section begins with the definitions and elementary properties of real and extended-real functions. Definition 2.1.1 An extended-real-valued function on X, or simply, an extended-real function on X , is a mapping f : X -t lR. A real-valued function on X, or simply, a real function on X is a mapping f : X -t lR. Thus lR x and lR x denote, respectively, the set of all extended-real functions on X and the set of all real functions on X . Algebraic operations and an order relation on lR x are -x - defined as follows. Let f, 9 E lR and let a E lR. a) The sum f + 9 is defined iff f(x) + g(x) is defined for every x in X, and in that case f + 9 : X ----+ lR, X f---t f(x) + g(x) . b) fg: X -t lR, x H f(x)g(x). c) of:X-tlR,xHOf(x). We set -f:=(-l)f. d) f g:- f(x) g(x) for every x in x. o Thus, operating with functions is simply operating pointwise with extended- real numbers. With few exceptions, the rules and properties of lR carryover to lRx. We also want to adopt the 00-00 convention. Convention 2.1.2 -x (The 00-00 convention for lR ). If P is an assertion about extended-real-valued junctions, then lip holds" is understood to mean: C. Constantinescu et al., Advanced Integration Theory © Springer Science+Business Media New York 1998
Transcript
Page 1: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2. Elementary Integration Theory

NOTATION FOR CHAPTER 2:

X denotes a set.

2.1 Riesz Lattices

This section begins with the definitions and elementary properties of real and

extended-real functions.

Definition 2.1.1

An extended-real-valued function on X, or simply, an extended-real

function on X , is a mapping f : X -t lR. A real-valued function on X, or

simply, a real function on X is a mapping f : X -t lR. Thus lR x and lR x

denote, respectively, the set of all extended-real functions on X and the set of

all real functions on X . Algebraic operations and an order relation on lRx are -x -

defined as follows. Let f, 9 E lR and let a E lR.

a) The sum f + 9 is defined iff f(x) + g(x) is defined for every x in X,

and in that case

f + 9 : X ----+ lR, X f---t f(x) + g(x) .

b) fg: X -t lR, x H f(x)g(x).

c) of:X-tlR,xHOf(x). We set -f:=(-l)f.

d) f ~ g:- f(x) ~ g(x) for every x in x.

o

Thus, operating with functions is simply operating pointwise with extended­

real numbers. With few exceptions, the rules and properties of lR carryover to lRx.

We also want to adopt the 00-00 convention.

Convention 2.1.2 -x (The 00-00 convention for lR ). If P is an assertion

about extended-real-valued junctions, then lip holds" is understood to mean:

C. Constantinescu et al., Advanced Integration Theory© Springer Science+Business Media New York 1998

Page 2: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

280 2. Elementary Integration Theory

"P is true provided that every sum appearing in P, whether of extended­

real numbers or of extended-real-valued junctions, is defined. " 0

Definition 2.1.3 For every finite family (f.)tEI from IRx , define the sum

L ft : X -+ IR, x 1---+ L ft(x) . o tEl tEl

Although we could define the sum of finitely many extended-real functions

provided that 00-00 does not appear, such generality introduces additional

complications and is not needed for integration theory. In fact, a completely

general definition is more easily obtained as a consequence of integration theory.

We also follow notational convention from the arithmetic of numbers and

write f - g for f + (-g) .

Definition 2.1.4 A junction f E IRx is said to be positive (negative) iff

f ;::: 0 (f:::; 0). Given a set Fe IRx , we write F+ for the set of all positive

functions in F.

For each function f in IR x we define

f+: X -+ IR, x 1---+ { f(x) if f(x) ;::: 0

0 if f(x) :::; 0

f-: X -+ IR, x 1---+ { 0 if f(x) ;::: 0

- f(x) if f(x) :::; 0

If I : X -+ IR, x 1---+ If(x)l.

The functions f+, f- , and If I are called, respectively, the positive part of f,

the negative part of f and the absolute value of f . 0

The next theorem describes the elementary order properties of IRx. We

omit its easy proof as well as the proofs of the subsequent observations which

can all be carried out operating pointwise.

Theorem 2.1.5 IRx is a complete lattice with order relation:::;. The constant

functions 00 and -00 are, respectively, the largest and smallest element of

IRx . The supremum {infimum} of a family from IRx is the pointwise supremum

{infimum}. In other words, given any set Fe IRx and any x EX,

(V) (x) = sup(f(x)) and (1\) (x) = i~~(f(x)). 0 JE:F JE:F JE:F J

Page 3: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.1 Riesz Lattices 281

Note, however, that lRx is not a vector lattice since addition cannot be

completely defined. Nevertheless, all the rules of computation listed in Theorem

1.2.6 hold in lRx as well (with, of course, the 00-00 convention in force). In particular, we have r = f V 0, f- = (-I) V 0 and III = f V (-I) for

every f E lRx . The formulae governing sup and inf for nonempty families

(Proposition 1.1.17) are also valid in lRx, as well as the distributivity laws

(Proposition 1.2.8). Since lRx is a complete lattice, it is no longer necessary

to hypothesize the existence of suprema and infima in these rules, but the

assumption of the existence for sums that is embodied in the 00-00 convention

is required. We state explicitly the rules for order convergent sequences in lRx. As a

-x -x complete lattice, lR is also a-complete, and every sequence from lR has a

limes superior and a limes inferior. Since operations in lRx are defined point­

wise, order convergence in lRx is just pointwise convergence.

Proposition 2.1.6 the following hold.

-x If (fn)nEIN and (gn)nEIN are sequences from lR , then

a) For every x EX,

( lim sup fn) (x) = lim sup fn(x) , n-+oo n-+oo

( lim inf fn) (x) = lim inf fn(x) . n-+oo n-+oo

-x b) The sequence (fn)nEIN order-converges to f E lR iff, for each x in X, the sequence (fn(X))nEIN converges to f(x). In this case

( lim fn) (x) = lim fn(x) = f(x) n-+oo n-+oo

for every x EX.

-x Let (fn)nEIN and (gn)nEIN be order-convergent sequences from lR ,and let Q

be a real number. Then

c) (fn V gn)nEIN is order-convergent and

lim (fn V gn) = (lim fn) V ( lim 9n) n-+oo n-+oo n-+oo

d) (fn /\ gn)nEIN is order-convergent and

lim (fn /\ 9n) = ( lim fn) /\ ( lim 9n) n-+oo n-+oo n--+oo

Page 4: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

282 2. Elementary Integration Theory

e) (afn)nEIN is order-convergent and

lim (afn) = a lim fn. n-+oo n-+oo

f) (fn + gn)nEIN is order-convergent and

lim (fn + gn) = (lim fn) + ( lim gn) n-+oo n-+oo n-+oo

(Remember Convention 2.1.2.} o

Note that if (fn)nEIN and (gn)nEIN are both increasing (decreasing), then

in f) lim can be replaced by V (by 1\); see Proposition 1.8.19.

Having summarized the properties of real and extended-real functions, we

turn to the definition of a Riesz lattice. Essentially, the spaces we want to

describe are sublattices of lRx that are closed under addition and real scalar

multiplication. However, the fact that addition of two functions on X is only

defined when their sum is defined pointwise at every point of X creates a minor

inconvenience. We introduce some useful notations to overcome this.

Definition 2.1.7 -x -x Take f, 9 E lR and F, (} C lR . Then

(f -+ g) := {h E lRx I If x E X and f(x) + g(x) is defined, } then h(x) = f(x) + g(x).

(f ~ g) := (J -+ (-g»

If -+ 91 := {Ihl I h E (J -+ g)}

If ~ gl := {Ihl I hE (J ~ g)}

F -+ (}:= U (J -+ g) /E:F,9EQ

F ~ (}:= U (J ~ g) 0 /E:F,gEQ

Proposition 2.1.8 Let f, g, and h be extended-real functions on X. Then

a) (J -+ g) = (g -+ J) .

b) hE (J -+ g) iff 9 E (h ~ J) .

Proof. The truth of a) is evident. To prove b), suppose that h E (J -+ g) and

fix x in X. We distinguish three cases.

Case 1: If f(x) is real, then both f(x) + g(x) and h(x) - f(x) are defined,

h(x) = f(x) + g(x) , and g(x) = h(x) - f(x) .

Page 5: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.1 Riesz Lattices 283

Case 2: Suppose that f(x) = 00. If h(x) = 00 also, then h(x) - f(x) is

undefined. If, on the other hand, h(x) < 00, then because h E (J -i- g) it must

be that f(x) + g(x) is not defined. In other words, g(x) = -00, and we have

g(x) = h(x) - f(x).

Case 3: Suppose finally that f(x) = -00. If h(x) = -00, then h(x) - f(x)

is not defined. If h(x) > -00, then hE (J -i- g) implies that f(x) + g(x) is

undefined, g(x) = 00, and g(x) = h(x) - f(x).

Thus in each case either h(x)- f(x) is undefined or else g(x) = h(x)- f(x).

Since x is arbitrary, it follows that 9 E (h -.:... 1) . The fact that 9 E (h -.:... 1) implies h E (J -i- g) can be proved by a similar

argument. 0

-x x Definition 2.1.9 A nonempty set .c c IR is called a Riesz lattice (in IR ,

or on X ) iff it satisfies the following three conditions. (RL 1) If f,g E.c, then (J -i- g) c.c. (RL 2) If f E.c and 0: E IR, then o:f E .c . (RL 3) If f, 9 E .c, then f 1\ 9 E.c and f V 9 E .c.

A Riesz lattice contained in IRx is called a real Riesz lattice. 0

IRX is trivially a Riesz lattice, as is the set {J E IRx I {J I- O} is finite}.

Every vector sublatticc of IRx is an example of a real Riesz lattice. For every

Riesz lattice .c in IRx , the set .c n IRx is a real Riesz lattice.

Why do we use this particular definition for function classes'? Any construc­

tion of an integral starts with some convenient class of functions whose integrals

are known. The linearity properties of integrals only make sense if this class is

closed under addition and scalar multiplication. The class of functions whose

integrals have been defined is then expanded, possibly more than once. In this

book, one of the extensions is achieved via monotone approximation, and Axiom

(RL3) is used in the rnonotone--approximation process.

The easy proof of the next proposition is left to the reader.

Proposition 2.1.10 The following assertions hold for every Riesz lattice .c in IRx .

a) The zero function, 0, belongs to .c.

b) For every f in .c, - f belongs to .c.

c) For every f in .c, If I, rand f- belong to .c+.

d) If f and 9 belong to .c, then (J -.:... g) c .c .

Page 6: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

284 2. Elementary Integration Theory

e) Given a finite family (f.).EI in £, n IRx , the sum E f. belongs to £' . • EI

f) Given a nonempty finite family (f.).EI in £', both V f. and "f. belong 'EI .EI

to £'. o

Many Riesz lattices have special order properties relative to the full space

IRx. We discuss these properties briefly.

Definition 2.1.11 A set :F c IRx is said to be:

a) conditionally a-completely embedded in IRx iff, given any nonempty

countable family (f.).EI in :F which is bounded in :F, both V f. and .EI

"f. belong to :F; .EI

b) a-completely embedded in IRx iff, given any nonempty countable family

(f.).EI in :F, both V f. and "f. belong to :F. 0 .EI .EI

Every (conditionally) a-completely embedded lattice in IRx is itself a (con­

ditionally) a-complete lattice, with order relation induced by the order relation

on IRx , but the converse is ~ot true. Obviously every set that is a-completely

embedded in IRx is also conditionally a-completely embedded.

When the set in question is a Riesz lattice, the test for a-complete em­

bedding or conditionally a-complete embedding is easier. One need not test

all countable families. It is enough, for instance, to test positive increasing se­

quences. More precisely, we have the following two propositions.

Proposition 2.1.12 Let £, be a Riesz lattice in IRx . Then the following are

equivalent.

a) £, is conditionally a-completely embedded in IRx.

b) Given any sequence (fn)nEIN in £, which is bounded in £', both V fn nEIN

and " f n belong to £'. nEIN

c) Given any sequence (fn)nEIN in £, which is decreasing and bounded below

in £', the function " fn belongs to £'. nEIN

d) Given any sequence (fn)nEIN in £,+ which is increasing and bounded above

in £', the function V fn belongs to £'. nEIN

Page 7: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.1 Riesz Lattices 285

Proof. a) - b) and b) =:} c) are trivial (and hold for arbitrary subsets .c of

IRx ).

c) =:} d). If (fn)nEIN is a sequence in .c+ which is increasing and bounded

above in .c, then (- in)nEIN is a sequence in .c which is decreasing and bounded

below in .c. Since

nEIN

it follows that V in belongs to .c. nEIN

nEIN

d) =:} b). Let (fn)nEIN be a sequence in .c which is bounded in .c. For

each n E IN , define

if defined

otherwise.

The sequence (hn)nEIN increases and each hn is positive. Since

we see that every hn is in .c and therefore in .c+. To verify that the sequence

(hn)nEIN is bounded above in .c, note that if g' and g" are elements of .c which

bound the original sequence (fn)nEIN from above and below, respectively, then

the function 19'1 + 19"1 is defined, belongs to .c and bounds (hn)nEIN from

above. Hypothesis d) implies that V hn belongs to .c. Now nEIN

V hn E / V ~ il) , nEIN \ nEIN

so

V in E / V hn -+- it), nEIN \ nEIN

by Proposition 8 b). We conclude that V in must belong to .c. nEIN

To conclude that V in belongs to .c, we argue as follows. Since (fn)nEIN nEIN

is bounded in .c, so is (- in)nEIN. The last argument shows that V (-in) nEIN

belongs to .c. Now recall that 1\ in = - V (-in). o nEIN nEIN

Page 8: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

286 2. Elementary Integration Theory

Proposition 2.1.13 The following conditions on a Riesz lattice .c in lRx

are equivalent.

a} .c is a-completely embedded in lRx .

b} Given any sequence (fn)nEJN in .c, both V fn and 1\ fn belong to .c. nEJN nEJN

c) Given any decreasing sequence (fn)nEJN in .c, the function 1\ fn belongs nEJN

to .c.

d) Given any increasing sequence (fn)nEJN in .c+, the function V fn be-nEJN

longs to .c.

Proof. a) - b) and b) ::::} c) are trivial.

c) ::::} d). For every increasing sequence (fn)nEJN in .c+, the sequence

(- fn)nEJN is a decreasing sequence in .c and V fn = - 1\ (- fn) . nEJN nEJN

d) ::::} b). From d) and the preceding proposition it follows that .c is con-

ditionally a-completely embedded in lRx. It therefore suffices to show that

every sequence in .c is bounded in .c. Let (fn)nEJN be a sequence in .c. Then

is an increasing sequence in .c+, and d) ensures that its supremum, V Ifni, nEJN

belongs to .c. Since

-V Ifni::; fm ::; V Ifni nEJN nEJN

for every m in 1N the proof is complete. o

It is useful to single out those subsets of X on which some element of the

Riesz lattice takes infinite values.

Definition 2.1.14 Let.c be a Riesz lattice in lRx. A set A C X is called

.c-ezceptional iff there is a function f belonging to .c such that

f(x) = 00 for every x in A.

-x A function f E lR is called .c-ezceptional iff {J =f. O} is an .c-exceptional

set.

lJ1(.c) shall denote the collection of all .c-exceptional subsets of X, and

N(C) the collection of all .c-exceptional functions on X. 0

Page 9: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.1 Riesz Lattices 287

Thus

1)1(£) = {A c X I A C {g = oo} for some 9 E £}

and

-x N(£) = {f E IR I {f =f. O} C {g = oo} for some 9 E£}.

If f belongs to £, then each of the sets {f = oo}, {f = -oo}, and {If I = oo}

is £-exceptional.

If £ = IRx , then 1)1(£) = I.l3(X) and N(£) = £. If £ is a real Riesz

lattice, then 1)1(£) = {0} and N(£) = {O} . There are many ways of characterizing £-exceptional sets and functions,

several of which are presented in the next two propositions.

Proposition 2.1.15 For every Riesz lattice £ in IRx, the following condi­

tions on a subset A of X are equivalent.

a) A E 1)1(£) .

b) ooeA E £.

c) A C B for some B E 1)1(£) .

d) A C {f =f. O} for some f E N(£) .

Proof. a) => b). By hypothesis, there is an f in £ such that f(x) = 00 for

every x in A. For this f,

so ooe A must belong to £.

b) => a). This is obvious.

a) => c). Take B := A. c) => d). Take f := eB.

ooeA E (J ...:.. J)

d) => a). By hypothesis, A C {f =f. O} c {g = oo} for some f in IRx and

some 9 in £.. Thus A belongs to 1)1(£). 0

Proposition 2.1.16 For every Riesz lattice £ in IRx, the following condi­

tions on a function f E IRx are equivalent.

a) f E N(£).

Page 10: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

288 2. Elementary Integration Theory

b) If I E N(£) .

c) oof E £.

d) {J 1= O} C {g 1= O} for some 9 E N(£) .

e) {J 1= O} C A for some A E 91(£) .

Proof. a) =} b). After all, {If I 1= O} = {J 1= O}.

b) =} c). Put A := {If I 1= O}. By the previous proposition, the function

ooe A belongs to £. Since

oof must also belong to £. c) =} a). If oof E £, then loofl E £ and so f E N(£) .

a) =} d). Put 9 := f· d) =} e). Put A:= {g 1= O} and use Proposition 15 d) =} a).

e) =} a). By hypothesis, {f 1= O} cAe {g = oo} for some 9 in £. Thus

{J 1= O} is in 91(£); that is, f belongs to N(£). 0

The characterizations

N(£) = {J E ffi.x I oof E .c} and 91(£) = {A c X I ooeA E £}

are especially useful.

Proposition 2.1.17 Let £ be a Riesz lattice in ffi.x. Then I.P(A) C 91(£)

for each A E 91(£), and the union of every finite family in 91(£) belongs to

91(£) .

Proof. The first claim merely restates Proposition 15 c) =} a) . Let (A'),El be

a finite family from 91(£). Since

ooe U A, = V ooe A, ,

'EJ 'El

we conclude that ooe U A, belongs to £ and that U A, belongs to 91(£). 0 ,EJ 'EI

Corollary 2.1.18 If f and 9 are arbitrary elements of a Riesz lattice £ in -x ffi. ,then the set

{x E X I f(x) + g(x) is not defined}

is £-exceptional.

Page 11: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.1 Riesz Lattices 289

Proof. The set in question is a subset of the set

{J = oo} U {g = oo} . o

Definition 2.1.19 Let C be a Riesz lattice in IRx. A property P depending

on elements of X is said to hold C-almost everywhere (or simply C-a.e.) iff

the set

{x E X I P(x) is false or P(x) is not defined}

is an C-exceptional set.

If P holds C-almost everywhere, then we write

P C-a.e.

provided that P(x) is defined for every x in X, and we write

P(x) C-a.e.

in case P(x) is not necessarily defined for every x in X. o

Example 2.1.20 Operations and relations on the set IRX were defined point­

wise. Thus properties offunctions in IRx are properties which refer to points of X , and it is meaningful to assert that such a property holds £-almost every­

where. Let f and 9 be extended-real functions on the set X, let (fn)nEIN be a sequence from IRx , and let £ be a Riesz lattice in IRx. Then

f = 9 £-a.e. {::=} {J =F g} E 1)1(£) ,

f ~ 9 £-a.e. {::=} {J > g} E 1)1(£) ,

f(x) = lim fn(x) C-a.e. {::=} n-+oo

{ (fn(X))nEIN does not converge

{::=} x EX or lim fn(x) =F f(x)

n-+oo

} E 'It(C).

Moreover, every function in £ is C-a.e. finite, and f(x) + g(x) is defined £­

a.e. for all functions f and 9 in £. Every C-exceptional function equals zero

C-a.e., and conversely. If h is a function in (f + g) , where f and 9 belong

to £, then h(x) = f(x) + g(x) £-a.e. 0

Page 12: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

290 2. Elementary Integration Theory

Proposition 2.1.21 Let C be a Riesz lattice in IRx .

a) Every C-exceptional function belongs to C. In other words, N{C) c C.

b) If A is an C-exceptional subset of X, then feA belongs to N{C) for

every extended-real function f on X, and feX\A belongs to C if f

belongs to C.

c) Every function which is C-almost everywhere equal to a function belonging

to C must itself belong to C.

d) If f and g belong to C and if

h{x) = f{x) + g{x) C-a.e.

then h belongs to C.

Proof a) If f belongs to N{C) , then oof belongs to C by Proposition 16

a) => c) . Since

f E (oof ~ oof)

f must also belong to C. -x

b) Take A E I)'1{C) and f E IR . Since

{feA =f. O} c A,

feA belongs to N{C) by Proposition 16 e) => a). By a), feA belongs to C.

The last claim now follows, since

-x c) Suppose that f = g C-a.e., for some f E C, g E IR . Put

A:={f=f.g}.

By a) and b), the functions feX\A and geA belong to C. Moreover, their sum

is defined and equals g. Hence g belongs to C.

d) Let

A := {x E X I f{x) + g{x) is not defined}

and let

h' := feX\A + geX\A .

Then A is C-exceptional by Corollary 18, so h' = h C-a.e. In view of b), h'

belongs to C. By c), h belongs to C. 0

Page 13: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.1 Riesz Lattices 291

Proposition 2.1.22 If.c is a Riesz lattice in IRx , then .c-a.e. equality of

functions is an equivalence relation on the set IRx .

Proof. Reflexivity and symmetry are trivial. To prove transitivity, take f, 9, hE -x IR such that f = 9 .c-a.e. and 9 = h .c-a.e. The inclusion

{J :;': h} c {J :;': 9} U {9 :;': h}

then implies that {J:;': h} is .c-exceptional (Proposition 17). o

The proof of the next observation is left to the reader as an exercise.

Proposition 2.1.23 Let.c be a Riesz lattice in IRx and take f, 9, hE IRx .

a) If f ::5 9, then f ::5 9 .c-a.e.

b) f = 9 .c-a.e. iff f ::5 9 .c-a.e. and 9::5 f .c-a.e.

c) If f ::5 9 .c-a.e. and 9::5 h .c-a.e., then f ::5 h .c-a.e.

-x In other words, ::5 .c-a.e. is a preorder on IR . o

Proposition 2.1.24 Let.c be a Riesz lattice in IRx . Suppose that fl> hand

91, 92 are functions in 1R x such that

fi = 9i .c-a.e.

for i = 1, 2, and let h be an extended-real function on X. Then

a) O'.fl = 0'.91 .c-a. e. for every 0'. E IR.

b) f1l2 = 9192 .c-a.e.

c) If h(x) = fl(x) + h(x) .c-a.e., then

h(x) = gl(x) + 92(X) .c-a.e.

Now suppose that (f')'EI and (g')'EI are finite families in IRx such that

f, = gL .c-a.e.

for every £ in I. Then

d) V fL = V 9, .c-a.e. LEI LEI

Page 14: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

292 2. Elementary Integration Theory

e) A It = A gt £-a.e. tEl tEl

Proof The key here is once again the closure of 91(£) under subsets and finite

unions. Thus the proposition is a consequence of the following five inclusions,

one for each assertion in the proposition:

a) {all =f. agd C UI =f. gd

b) {1I12 =f. glg2} C {II =f. gd U U2 =f. g2}

c) {x E X I gl(X) + g2(X) is undefined or =f. h(x)}

C {x E X I II (x) + l2(x) is undefined or =f. h(x)} U UI =f. gd U {h =f. g2}

d) {V/t=f.Vgt}cUUt=f.gJ tEl tEl tEl

e) {A It =f. A gt} C UUt =f. gJ. o tEl tEl tEl

Page 15: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.2 Daniell Spaces 293

2.2 Daniell Spaces

Daniel spaces are the basis for the construction of an integral. This section

presents the necessary definitions and elementary properties of such spaces.

Definition 2.2.1 Take Fe IRx . A junctional on F is a real-valued func­

tion with domain F. A functional £ on F is said to be:

a) additive if given f, g, hE F,

£(h) = £(f) + £(g)

whenever h E (f -+- g) ;

b) homogeneous if given f E F and a E IR,

£(af) = a£(f)

whenever af E F;

c) linear if it is both additive and homogeneous;

d) positive if £(f) 2: 0 for every f in F+;

e) increasing if it increases relative to the order relations on F and IR. o

Notice that if F is a real Riesz lattice, then the preceding definitions are

consistent with Definition 1.5.1.

Although no occasion for confusion should arise, a word of caution is proba­

bly in order. Take Fe IRx . If £ : F ~ IR is viewed as an element of IRF , that

is, as a real-valued function on F, then £ is positive iff £(f) 2: 0 for every

f E F, according to Definitions 2.1.4 and 2.1.1. However, with £ : F -t IR

viewed as a real functional on F, £ is positive iff £(f) 2: 0 for every f E F+ ,

by Definition 1 d).

Proposition 2.2.2 Let £ be a functional on a Riesz lattice C. in IRx .

a) Suppose that £ is additive. Then £(0) = 0 and £( - f) = -£(f) for every

f E c.. If f, 9 E C. and hE (f .:.- g) , then

£(h) = £(f) -£(g) .

Page 16: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

294 2. Elementary Integration Theory

b) If £ is additive and (f')'EI is a finite family in £. n IRx , then

£ ( 2: f,) = 2: £(f,) . 'EI ,EI

If £ is also homogeneous and (a')'EI E IR I , then

£ ( 2: ad,) = 2: a/(f.) . ,EI ,EI

c) If £ is additive, then £ is positive iff £ is increasing.

d) If £ is increasing, then for every nonempty family (f')'EI in £. for which

1\ f, E £. ,EI

£ (/\ fL) :S inf £(fL) , ,EI LEI

and for every nonempty family (fL),El in £. for which V f, E £. LEI

£ (v f,) ~ sup £(f,). LEI LEI

e) If £ is homogeneous and increasing, then

1£(f)1 :S £(Ifl)

for every f in £..

Proof. The proofs of assertions a), b), and d) are left to the reader.

c) In view of a), £ additive and £ increasing certainly imply £ positive.

Conversely, assume that £ is additive and positive. Given f and 9 in £. with

f :S g, define

{ g(x) - f(x)

h : X ---+ IR, X t-----+ o

if defined

otherwise.

Evidently, h is a positive function belonging to (g"':" f) . It follows by a) that

O:S f(h) = £(g) - f(f).

Thus £(f) :S f(g) and £ increases.

e) From -If I :S f :S If I we conclude that

-£(Ifl) :S £(f) :S £(Ifl) . o

Page 17: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.2 Daniell Spaces 295

Proposition 2.2.3 Let £ be a positive linear functional on a Riesz lattice C -x -x in IR . Take f, 9 E C and hEIR . Let A be an C-exceptional set.

a) If f belongs to N(C) , then £(J) = £(Ifl) = o.

b) £(JeA) = 0, £(JeX\A) = £(J) .

c) If f :::; g C-a.e., then £(J) :::; £(g) .

d) If h = f C-a.e., then h belongs to C and £(h) = £(J).

e) If h(x) = f(x) + g(x) C-a.e., then h belongs to C and

£(h) = £(J) + £(g) .

Proof. a) If f belongs to N(C) , then the functions f, If I , oof, and loofl all belong to C (Propositions 2.1.16, 2.1.21). Now

loofl + loofl = loofl ,

so

£(Ioofl) + £(Ioofl) = £(joofD .

Since £ takes only real values, we conclude that £(Ioofl) = o. The inequality

o ::; If I ::; loofl

yields

o ::; £(Ifl) ::; £(Ioofl) = 0

(Proposition 2 c)) and therefore £(Ifl) = o. By Proposition 2 e), £(J) = o. b) follows from a) and Proposition 2.1.21 b).

c) Put B := {J > g}. By hypothesis, B is C-exceptional, and

By Proposition 2 c), £ is increasing. Using b), we have

d) is a consequence of c) and Propositions 2.1.21 c) and 2.1.23 b).

e) That h belongs to C was established in Proposition 2.1.21 d). Put

Page 18: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

296 2. Elementary Integration Theory

B := {x E X I f(x) + g(x) is not defined}

and note that B is .c-exceptional. Using b) and d), we have

f(h) = f(feX\B + geX\B) =

= f(feX\B) + f(geX\B) =

= f(f) + f(g) . o

It is now clear why the function values ±oo do not disturb the real­

valuedness of positive linear functionals on Riesz lattices. For a Riesz lattice

.c only admits positive linear functionals which ignore the sets on which func­

tions from .c take infinite values.

The preceding considerations enable us to make the following definition.

Definition 2.2.4 Let f be a positive linear functional on the Riesz lattice .c,

and take f, 9 E .c. Then

f(f ± g) := f((I ± g}) := f(h) ,

f(lf ± gl) := f(l(I ± g}1) := f(lhl) ,

where h is an arbitrary element of (I ± g) . o

Note, however, that the expression f(f + g) need not have meaning.

Our construction of integrals starts with positive linear functionals satisfy­

ing a rather weak continuity or convergence condition. The condition in question

is described in the next definition.

Definition 2.2.5 A functional f on a set :F c IRx is said to be nullcontin­

uous iff

lim f(fn) = 0 n ..... oo

for every decreasing sequence (fn)nEIN in :F for which

/\ fn = o. nEIN

A Daniell space is a triple (X,.c, f), where .c is a Riesz lattice in IRx

and f is a positive, linear, nullcontinuous functional on .c. o

Page 19: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.2 Daniell Spaces 297

The name "Daniell space" is chosen in recognition of the work of P.J.

Daniell, who in 1918 constructed an integral starting with a positive linear

nullcontinuous functional on a real Riesz lattice.

It is important that in Definition 5 1\ is taken in IRx and not in F. Therefore, if ( is a positive linear functional on a real Riesz lattice £', null­

continuity and O'-continuity of ( (see Definition 1.7.1) do not coincide! It is

immediate that O'-continuity of ( implies nullcontinuity, but the converse need

not hold as the following example shows. (The converse is true, however, if £,

is conditionally 0'- completely embedded in IRx .)

Example 2.2.6 Put £, := C([O, 1]) and define ( by ((f) := f(O) for every

f E£'. Then ( is a positive linear functional on £, which is trivially nullcon­

tinuous. Now consider the sequence (fn)nEIN from £,+, defined by

fn(x) := 1/\ nx (x E [0,1]) .

Then V fn = e[O,!] where V is taken in C([O, 1]). But ((fn) = 0 for every nEIN

n E IN while (e[O,Ij) = 1. Thus ( is not O'-continuous (see Proposition 1.7.3.

a) => c)). 0

Proposition 2.2.7 Let ( be a positive linear functional on a Riesz lattice £,

in IRx. Then the following are equivalent.

a) ( is nullcontinuous.

b) inf ((fn) = 0 for every decreasing sequence (fn)nEIN from £, which sat­nEIN

isfies 1\ fn = O. nEIN

c) For every increasing sequence (fn)nEIN from £', if V fn belongs to £', nEIN

then

( (V fn) = sup ((fn) . nEIN nEIN

d) For every decreasing sequence (gn)nEIN from £', if 1\ gn belongs to £', nEIN

then

( (1\ gn) = inf (gn) . nEIN

nEIN

Page 20: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

298 2. Elementary Integration Theory

Proof. a) - b) follows easily from the fact that f is increasing (Proposition

2 c)).

b) ::::} c). Let (In)nEIN be an increasing sequence from £, for which

1:= V In nEIN

belongs to £'. Given n E 1N , define

and

hn : X --; lR , ..----r - X' ----'- { 10 (x) - In(x) if defined

otherwise

h~ : X --; lR, if hn(x) < 00

if hn(x) = 00.

Then hn E (f ...:.. in) . Hence every hn belongs to £'. Thus for each n,

h~ = hn £'-a.e. ,

h~ belongs to £', and f(h~) = f(hn) . The sequences (hn)nEIN and (h~)nEIN are both decreasing and

1\ h~ = O. nEIN

Using b), we have

o = inf f(h~) = inf f(hn) = inf (f(J) - f(Jn)) = nEIN nEIN nEIN

= f(J) + inf (-f(Jn)) = f(J) - sup f(Jn) nEIN nEIN

and so

sup f(Jn) = f(J) . nEIN

c) ::::} d). Use the formula 1\ gn = - V (-gn). nEIN nEIN

d) ::::} b) is trivial. o

We now investigate a stronger form of functional convergence, suitable when

topological compatibility is desired.

Page 21: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.2 Daniell Spaces 299

Definition 2.2.8 Let £ be an increasing functional on a subset :F of lRx .

A sequence (fn)nEIN from :F is called an i-sequence if (fn)nEIN is monotone

and (£(fn))nEIN is bounded in lR. The triple (X,:F, £) is said to be closed iff,

for every i-sequence (fn)nEIN from :F, the function lim fn belongs to :F and n-+oo

£ ( lim fn) = lim £(fn) . n--+oo n--+oo

o

-x Notice that for each monotone sequence (fn)nEIN from lR , lim fn exists.

n-+oo

Moreover, if £ is an increasing functional on some subset :F of lRx , then for

every i-sequence (fn)nEIN from :F, the sequence (£(fn))nEIN converges in lR.

For then (£(fn))nEIN is a monotone sequence of real numbers bounded in lR.

The closure property just defined is an axiomatization of the theorem from

classical integration theory known as the Beppo Levi Theorem (1906). Daniell

spaces that are also closed are the primary objects, from an abstract point of

view, to be studied in this part of the book.

Given a Riesz lattice C in lRx and a positive linear functional £ on C,

if the triple (X, C, £) happens to be closed, then it is immediate from the

definitions that the functional f is nullcontinuous. Thus to show that a given

triple is a closed Daniell space, it is redundant to verify the nullcontinuity.

Proposition 2.2.9 Let f be a positive linear functional on a Riesz lattice C

in lR x . Then the following are equivalent:

a) The triple (X, C, f) is closed: that is, (X, C, £) is a closed Daniell space.

b) For every increasing i-sequence (fn)nEIN from C, the function V fn nEIN

belongs to C and

£ (V fn) = sup £(fn) . nEIN nEIN

c) For every increasing i-sequence (fn)nEIN of positive functions from C,

the function V fn belongs to C and nEIN

£ (V fn) = sup f(fn) . nEIN nEIN

d) For every decreasing i-sequence (fn)nEIN from C, the function 1\ fn nEIN

belongs to C and

Page 22: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

300 2. Elementary Integration Theory

£ (1\ In) = inf £(fn) . nEIN

nEIN

Proof a) '* b) '* c) is evident.

c) '* d). Let (fn)nEIN be a decreasing £-sequence from 1:-. For each n E IN ,

define

Now apply c) to the sequence (hn)nEIN, noting that

if defined

otherwise.

d) '* a). We have to show that lim In E I:- and that £ (lim In) = lim £(fn) n-+oo n-+oo n--+oo

whenever (fn)nEIN is an increasing £-sequence from 1:-. This follows easily using

the formula V In = - /\ (-In). 0 nEIN nEIN

Example 2.2.10 Let L: denote the positive linear functional

£1(X) ---+lR, II----t LI(x). xEX

We show that (X, £1 (X), L:) is a closed Daniell space.

Let (fn)nEIN be an increasing sequence from £1 (X)+ such that

a:= sup Lln(X) < 00. nEIN xEX

Put 1:= V In. Then, using Proposition 1.1.17 g), nEIN

L I(x) = L (sup In(X)) = sup (L In(x)) :::; a xEA xEA nEIN nEIN xEA

for every finite subset A of X. It follows that IE £1(X) and L: I(x) :::; a. xEX

Since I ~ In for every n E IN, L: I(x) ~ a. Hence xEX

LI(x)=a, xEX

and by Proposition 9 c) '* a), (X, £1(X), L:) is a closed Daniell space (which

merely formulates the fact that the normed vector lattice £1(X) is strongly

complete). 0

Page 23: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.2 Daniell Spaces 301

The exceptional sets and functions of closed Daniell spaces have special

properties, as does the behaviour of the functional relative to a.e.-conditions.

The next propositions describe these special properties.

Proposition 2.2.11 If (X, C, l) is a closed Daniell space, then the following

conditions on a function f in lRx are equivalent.

a) f E N(C) .

b) If I E C and l(lfl) = o.

Proof. a) => b) for any positive linear functional i on any Riesz lattice C

(Proposition 3 a)).

b) => a). By Proposition 2.1.16 c) => a) , b) => a), it suffices to show that

oolfl belongs to C. Indeed, the sequence (nlfl)nEIN is an increasing i-sequence from C with supremum oolfl. Since the triple (X, C, l) is closed, we conclude

that oolfl belongs to C. 0

Corollary 2.2.12 If (X, c, i) is a closed Daniell space, then the following

conditions on a subset A of X are equivalent.

a) A E ')1(C) .

o

Proposition 2.2.13 Let (X, C, l) be a closed Daniell space, and let f and

9 be functions in C such that

f $ 9 and i(f) = i(g) .

Then

f = 9 C-a.e.

-x Moreover, if h E lR with f $ h $ g, then hE C and

Proof. Define

f': X ---t JR,

l(h) = i(f) = £(g) .

{ g(x) - f(x)

X t---+ o if defined

otherwise.

Page 24: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

302 2. Elementary Integration Theory

Evidently, f' E (g -.:. f) . Hence h' is in £+, and

£(f') = £(g) - £(f) = o.

It follows (by Proposition 11) that f' is an £-exceptional function, and so

U # h} C U' # O} E 1)1(£).

In other words, f = 9 £-a.e.

If hE IRx with f ::; h ::; g, then the inclusion

U#h}CU#g}

shows that f = h £-a.e. An appeal to Proposition 3 d) now completes the

~~ 0

Finite unions of £-exceptional sets are still £-exceptional. In the case of

a closed Daniell space, "finite" can be replaced by "countable".

Proposition 2.2.14 If (X, £, £) is a closed Daniell space and (A,),E/ is a

countable family from 1)1(£), then U A, also belongs to 1)1(£). ,EI

Proof. If suffices to treat the case I = IN. So let (An)nEIN be a sequence from

1)1(£) . The sequence (fn)nEIN, where

for all n E IN, is an i-sequence from £: it is increasing and £(fn) = 0 for

every n (Proposition 2.1.17 and Corollary 12). Because the triple (X, £, £) is

closed, we conclude that the function V fn belongs to £ and nEIN

£ (V fn) = sup £(fn) = O. nEIN nEIN

But V fn is just the characteristic function of the set U An. In view of nEIN nEIN

Corollary 12 b) =} a), U An belongs to 1)1(£). 0 nEIN

Corollary 2.2.15 If (X, £, £) is a closed Daniell space, then N(£) is a­

completely embedded in IRx . In other words, the supremum and the infimum of

a nonempty countable family of £-exceptional functions are also £-exceptional.

Page 25: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.2 Daniell Spaces 303

Proof. It suffices to show that the supremum of every increasing sequence of

positive £-exceptional functions is itself £-exceptional (Proposition 2.1.13 d)

=> a)). If (fn)nEJN is such a sequence, then

{V fn -# o} = U {In -# o} nEJN nEJN

and V fn' in view of Proposition 14 and Proposition 2.1.16 e) => a), must nEJN

belong to N(£). 0

Corollary 2.2.16 Suppose that (X, £, C) is a closed Daniell space and that

(f')'EI and (g,),o are countable families from lRx such that

f, ::; g, £ -a. e.

for every ~ in I. Then

1\ f, ::; 1\ g, £ -a. e. ,EI 'EI

and

V f, ::; V g, £-a.e. o 'EI 'EI

Having discussed the properties of the exceptional sets and exceptional func­

tions associated with closed Daniell spaces, we turn to the more significant ques­

tion of the compatibility of closed Daniell spaces and their functionals with the

topology of lRx . The remainder of this section describes both how the Riesz

lattice £ is embedded in lR x and the accompanying convergence behaviour of

the functional £.

Theorem 2.2.17 Let (X, £, £) be a closed Daniell space and (f')'EI a non­

empty, countable family from £.

a) If the family (f,) ,E I is directed up relative to the relation ::; £ -a. e., then

the two conditions

sup£(f,) < 00

'EI and

are equivalent and each implies that

Page 26: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

304 2. Elementary Integration Theory

b) If the family (fL)LEl is directed down relative to the relation < .c-a. e.,

then the two conditions

inf £(ft) > -00 tEl

and

A. ft E .c LEI

are equivalent and each implies that

£ (A. fL) = inf £(ft) . LEI

LEI

Proof a) Let cp : IN -+ I be surjective. Construct an increasing sequence

(gn)nEIN in .c by setting

Clearly,

gn:= V f<p(m).

m~n

V gn = V fL. nEIN tEl

Moreover, as we see by complete induction, for each n III N there is an index

(n in I such that

and thus, by Proposition 3 c), such that

If

sup £(f.) < 00 LEI

then

In this case (gn)nEIN is an increasing £-sequence from .c. Since the triple

(X,.c, £) is closed, we conclude that V gn belongs to .c and thus V fL nEIN LEI

Page 27: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.2 Daniell Spaces 305

belongs to C. Conversely, if we assume that V f, belongs to C, then the .el

monotonicity of f yields

sup f(J,) ::; f (V f,) < 00 . ,el ,el

Finally, if either of the two conditions holds, then so does the other and

f (V f,) = f (V gn) = sup f(gn) ::; sup f(J,J ::; ,el nelN ,el ,el

::; sup f(J,) ::; f (V f,) , ,el ,el

from which it follows that

f (~f,) = ~~ff(J,). b) can be proved analogously. o

Proposition 2.2.18 Let (X, C, f) be a closed Daniell space and let (J,),el

be a nonempty, countable family from C.

a) If there is a function 9 in C such that f, ::; 9 C-a.e. for every L in I,

then V f, belongs to C. ,el

b) If there is a function Y in C such that f, ~ 9 C-a.e. for every L in I,

then /\ f, belongs to C. ,el

Proof. a) Let t.p : IN -+ I be surjective. As in the proof of the preceding

theorem we construct an increasing sequence (Yn)nelN in C by putting

gn:= V fcp(m)'

m:Sn

The hypothesis ensures, that for each n E IN ,

gn::; 9 C-a.e.

Hence

Once again, (Yn)nelN is an increasing f-sequence from C. We conclude that

V f, = V Yn E C. ,el nelN

b) can be proved analogously. 0

Page 28: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

306 2. Elementary Integration Theory

Corollary 2.2.19 For every closed Daniell space (X,.c, €), the Riesz lattice

.c is conditionally a-completely embedded in lRx . 0

Corollary 2.2.20 Let (X,.c, €) a closed Daniell space and Un)nEJN a se­

quence from .c. If there is a function 9 in .c with

ifni :S 9 .c-a.e.

for every n, then we have the following.

a) lim sup fn belongs to .c and €(lim sup fn) 2: lim sup €( Un) . n-->oo n-->oo n-->oo

b) lim inf fn belongs to .c and €(lim inf fn) :S lim inf fUn) . n-+oo n-+oo n-+oo

Proof. a) Given n in IN, we put

gn:= V 1m. m2::n

Proposition 18 a) ensures that each gn belongs to .c. Moreover, in view of

Proposition 2 d),

€(gn) 2: sup fUm) . m2::n

Since

lim supfn = A gn n-->oo nEJN

and

lim sup€Un) = inf sup fUm) :S inf €(gn) , n-->oo nEJN m2:n nEJN

the proof will be complete if we can show that /\ gn belongs to .c and that nEJN

€ ( A gn) = inf €(gn) . nEJN

nEJN

Actually, both of the desired results follow from the closed ness of (X,.c, €) and

the fact that (gn)nEJN is a decreasing €-sequence in .c. Note that €(gn) 2: €( -g) for every n E IN .

b) can be proved analogously. o

From this embedding theorem, we obtain the following fundamental theo­

rem, named after H. Lebesgue, the founder of modern integration theory.

Page 29: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.2 Daniell Spaces 307

Theorem 2.2.21 (Lebesgue Dominated Convergence Theorem, 1902) Let

(X, C, f) be a closed Daniell space, and let (fn)nEIN be a sequence from C.

Suppose that f is a function in IRx such that

lim fn(x) = f(x) C-a.e. n---+oo

Suppose also that

Ifni :5 9 C-a.e.

for some function 9 in C and for every n in IN. Then the limit function f

belongs to C and

f(f) = lim f(fn) . n-+oo

Proof At every point x in X where lim fn(x) exists, n---+oo

lim fn(x) = lim sup fn(x) = lim inf fn(x) . n"""'i'OO n-too n---+oo

Thus the hypothesis on f says that

f = lim sup fn = lim inf fn C-a.e. n---+oo n---+oo

Corollary 20 implies, for one thing, that both lim sup fn and lim inf fn belong n-+oo n-+oo

to C. Any function C-a.e. equal to a function in C is itself in .c and must be

assigned the same value by the functional f. Thus f is in C and we conclude

from the inequalities resulting from Corollary 20 that

lim sup f(fn) :5 f (lim sup fn) = f(f) = f (lim inf fn) :5 lim inf f(fn) . n-+oo n-+oo n-+oo n-+oo

Since the reverse inequality

lim inf f(fn) :5 lim sup f(fn) n---+oo n---+oo

always holds, it follows that

f(f) = lim supf(fn) = lim inf f(fn) = lim f(fn). n---+oo n---+oo n---+oo

o

Page 30: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

308 2. Elementary Integration Theory

2.3 The Closure of a Daniell Space

We are now in a position to construct an extension of a Daniell space (X, £., £) , which we call the closure of (X, £., £) .

The construction is in two stages. First, one forms the collections £.t and

£.4. of what one might call the upper and lower functions for the given Daniell

space: functions that are suprema of increasing real sequences from £. and

functions that are infima of decreasing real sequences from £.. One extends

the functional £ so that it assigns values (but possibly infinite values!) to the

upper and lower functions. At the second stage one singles out those functions

that can be arbitrarily approximated by either upper or lower functions. In this

context, two functions are close if their functional values are close. Thus one

singles out those functions for which there is a "bigger" upper function and a

"smaller" lower function such that the upper function and the lower function

are arbitrarily close to each other. It is these functions that will appear in the

closure (X, C(£), l) of the given Daniell space. This way to extend the integral

was used for the first time by W.H. Young in 1905.

Definition 2.3.1 Let (X, £., £) be a Daniell space. Put

£.t := {V fn I (fn)nEIN is an increasing sequence from £. n lRX} nEIN

and, for each f E £.t , put

tt(f) := sup{£(g) I 9 E £. n lRx , g:::; J}.

Obviously f(x) > -00 for every f E £.t and every x EX, and

tt(f) E]- 00,00]

for every f E ct .

o

Proposition 2.3.2 Let (X, £., £) be a Daniell space. Then the following hold.

a) £. n lRx c £.t and tt(f) = £(f) for every f E £. n lRx .

b) The conditions f, 9 E £.t and f :::; 9 imply that ft (f) :::; tt (g) .

c) If f and 9 belong to £.t, then f + 9 is defined and belongs to £.t.

Moreover,

Page 31: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.3 The Closure of a Daniell Space 309

d) If f belongs to £,t, then for every 0: E IR+, oJ belongs to Ct and

et(oJ) = o:et(f) .

e) If f and g belong to Ct , then so do f V g and f /\ g .

f) If (fn)nEIN is an increasing sequence from Ct , then V fn belongs to Ct nEIN

and

Proof. a) follows from Proposition 2.2.2 c).

b) is trivial.

f) Define f:= V fn. Given n E IN, let (fnk)kEIN be an increasing se­nEIN

quence from en IRx such that fn = V fnk. For k E IN, define kEIN

hk := V fnk. n$k

(hk)kEIN is an increasing sequence in en IRx and if n ~ k then

We conclude that

and, letting n -+ 00 ,

Thus

Take gEe n IR x , g ~ f . Then

Using the nullcontinuity of f and a),b), we see that

Page 32: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

310 2. Elementary Integration Theory

f(g) = sup f(g 1\ hk ) ~ sup f(h k ) = kElN kElN

= supf1'(hk) ~ supft(fk) ~ ft(f). kElN kElN

Since 9 is arbitrary,

f1'(f) = sup{f(g) I 9 E C n R X , 9 ~ J} ~ supft(fk) ~ ft(f), kElN

completing the proof of f).

c),d),e). Take f, 9 E Ct and let (fn)nElN and (gn)nElN be increasing se­

quences from C n R X whose suprema are f and g, respectively. Since f and

9 cannot take the value -00, the sum f + 9 is defined. We obtain

f + 9 = (V fn) + (V gn) = V (fn + gn) E ct, nElN nElN nElN

oJ = a (V fn) = V (afn) E ct (a E R+), nElN nElN

f V 9 = (V fn) V (V gn) = V (fn V gn) E ct , nElN nElN nElN

f 1\ 9 = (V fn) 1\ (V gn) = V (fn 1\ gn) E ct . nElN nElN nElN

Furthermore, using f),

ft(f + g) = sup f(fn + gn) = sup(f(fn) + f(gn)) = nElN nElN

= sup f(fn) + sup f(gn) = f1'(f) + ft(g) , nElN nElN

ft(a!) = sup f(afn) = sup af(fn) = nElN nElN

= a sup f(fn) = af1'(f) (a E R+) . o nElN

We introduce CJ.. and fJ.. in complete analogy with Ct and ft.

Definition 2.3.3 Let (X, C, f) be a Daniell space. Then

CJ.. := { 1\ fn I (fn)nElN is a decreasing sequence from C n RX} nElN

and, for f E cJ.. ,

fJ..(!):= inf{f(g) I 9 E CnRx, g;::: J}. o

Page 33: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.3 The Closure of a Daniell Space 311

The properties of (.CJ., fJ.) can easily be derived from those of (.ct, if) by

means of the following proposition.

Proposition 2.3.4 Let (X,.c, f) be a Daniell space and take f E lRx . Then

f belongs to .cJ. iff - f belongs to .ct and in this case

fJ.(f) = -ft( - f).

Proof The sequence (fn)nEIN from lRx is decreasing, after all, iff the sequence

(- fn)nEIN is increasing. Moreover /\ fn = - V (- fn) . nEIN nEIN

If f belongs to .cJ., then

fJ.(f) = inf{f(g) I 9 E .cnlRx , 9 ~ J} =

= - sup{ -f(g) I 9 E .c n lRx , 9 ~ J} =

= -sup{f(-g) I-g E .cnlRx , -g:::; -J} =

o

Corollary 2.3.5 Let (X,.c, e) be a Daniell space. Then the following hold.

a) .c n lRx c.cJ. and eJ.(f) = e(f) for every f E .c n IRX •

b) For every f E .cJ., eJ.(f) < 00.

c) The conditions f,g E.cJ. and f :::; 9 imply that eJ.(f) :::; eJ.(g).

d) If f and 9 belong to .cJ., then f + 9 is defined and belongs to .cJ., and

e) If f belongs to .cJ., then for every a E lR+, af belongs to .cJ. and

f) If f and 9 belong to .cJ., then so do f V g and f 1\ g.

g) If (fn)nEIN is a decreasing sequence from .cJ., then /\ fn belongs to .cJ. nEIN

and

o

Page 34: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

312 2. Elementary Integration Theory

Proposition 2.3.6 Let (X, £, £) be a Daniell space. Take f E £i and 9 E

£t . If f ~ g, then

Proof. We have - f E £t , 9 + (-f) E £t and 9 + (-f) ~ O. Thus

o

Definition 2.3.7 Let (X, £, £) be a Daniell space. Suppose that f E lRx and

take c> O. Then an c-bracket for f relative to £ is a pair (f', f") E £i x £t

such that:

a) f' ~ f ~ I" ;

b) £i(f') , £f(f") E lR;

We put

_ { -xl For each c > 0 there is an } £(£):= f E lR

c -bracket for f relative to £ o

Proposition 2.3.8 Let (X, £, £) be a Daniell space. Then, given f E £(€) ,

SUp{£i(g) I 9 E £i, 9 ~ f} = inf{€t(g) I 9 E £t, 9 ~ f} E lR.

Proof. Let c > 0 be given. There is an c-bracket (f',I") for f relative to €.

Using Proposition 6, we have

-00 < €i(f') ~ sup{€i(g) I 9 E £i, 9 ~ f}

~ inf { £f (g) I 9 E £t , 9 ~ f}

~ £t(f") < 00.

But €t(f") - €i(f') ~ c and c > 0 is arbitrary, so

SUp{£i(g) I 9 E £i, 9 ~ f} = inf{€t(g) I 9 E £t, 9 ~ f} E lR. 0

Page 35: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.3 The Closure of a Daniell Space 313

Definition 2.3.9 Given a Daniell space (X,.c, €) , put

f : C( €) ---+ IR ,

f t----+ sup{€.J.(g) I 9 E.c.J., 9 ~ J} = inf{et(g) I 9 E.ct , 9 ~ J}.

The triple (X,C(€),f) is called the closure of (X,.c,€). o

We justify the terminology chosen by showing that (X, C(€),'l) is the small­

est closed Daniell space extending (X,.c, €) .

Theorem 2.3.10 Let (X,.c, €) be a Daniell space. Then (X, C(€), f) is a

closed Daniell space extending (X,.c, €) .

Proof. We first show that C(€) is a Riesz lattice and that f is a positive linear

functional on C(€).

Take f, 9 E C(€) , h E (J -i- g) and c > O. Let (J',1") and (g', gil) be

~~brackets for f and g, respectively. Then

J'(x) + g'(x) ~ h(x) ~ 1"(x) + g"(X) (1)

for every x for which f(x) + g(x) is defined. Suppose now that f(x) + g(x) is

not defined. Since f'(x) f:- 00, g'(x) f:- 00 and 1"(x) f:- -00, g"(X) f:- -00, we

conclude that

J'(x) + g'(x) = -00, J"(x) + g"(X) = 00,

and thus (1) holds in this case too. Moreover

and

Thus (J' + g', 1" + gil) is an c~bracket for h relative to €. It follows that

h E C( €) , and since

€.J.(J' + g') ~ f(J) + f(g) ~ €t(J" + gil) ,

it also follows that

Page 36: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

314 2. Elementary Integration Theory

£(h) = £(1) + £(g) .

Similarly, one can prove that given a E ffi, al belongs to C(£) and £(aJ) =

a£(I) . Furthermore,

£t(l" V g") + £t(l" 1\ g") = £t(l" + g") E ffi

and therefore the individual terms on the left-hand sides must be real. Subtract

the first equation from the second one to obtain

(£t(l" V g") - £.1.(1' V g')) + (£t(l" 1\ g") - £.1.(1' 1\ g'))

Since both of the first bracketed expressions are positive (Proposition 6), we

conclude that (I' V g' , 1" V g") is an c-bracket for I V 9 , and (1'1\ g' , 1" 1\ g") is an c-bracket for 11\ g. Hence I V 9 E C(£) and 11\ 9 E C(£) .

The positivity of e follows from the relation £(1) 2': £-1-(0) = 0, which holds

for every IE C(£)+. To prove that (X, C(£), £) is a closed Daniell space, it suffices to show that

for any increasing e-sequence (In)nEIN from C(£)+, 1:= V In belongs to nEIN

C(£) and

£(1) = sup £(In) (2) nEIN

(Proposition 2.2.9 c) => a)). So take c > O. For n E IN, let (I~,I~) be an

(c/2n +1)-bracket for In, relative to £. Then ( V lIt, V if) is a ( E ~)-k<n k<n k<n

bracket for V Ik, that is, for In. This follows easily by complete i~duction, k<n

adapting the -arguments used above to show that (I' V g' , 1" V g") is an c-

bracket for I V g. In particular, for n E IN we have

Put

1":= V I:. nEIN

Using Proposition 2 f), we obtain

Page 37: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.3 The Closure of a Daniell Space 315

Since the sequence (Z(Jn))nEIN is bounded in IR, £t(J") is real. The function

I" will serve as one of the two functions in the desired E-bracket for f. To

obtain the other function, first choose m in 1N with

(4)

Now choose l' from £.). so that l' :::; fm, £.).(J') is real and

(5)

The function f' will do. From (4) and (5) it follows that

(6)

Now (3) and (6) imply that

£.).(J'):::; sup£(Jn):::; £t(J") nEIN

and

Clearly l' :::; f :::; I" , so (J',I") is in fact an E-bracket for f, relative to £.

Since E was arbitrary, we conclude that f belongs to £(£) and (2) holds.

It remains to show that (X, £ (£), £) extends the original Daniell space

(X, £, £) . So take f E £. The set

A:= {If I = oo}

is £ exceptional and so e A belongs to £ n IR x . Hence e A belongs to both £t

and £.)., and £t(eA) = £.).(eA) = £(eA) = O. We conclude that eA belongs to

£(£) and that

Thus A is £(£)-exceptional (Corollary 2.2.12 b) => a)). We now use Propo­

sitions 2.1.21 a),b), and 2.2.3 b). The function feA belongs to N(£(£)) and

therefore to £(£). The function feX\A belongs to £ n IRx and therefore to

£(£) . Moreover,

Page 38: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

316 2. Elementary Integration Theory

Since f is the sum of feX\A and feA, f belongs to C(f) and

We have shown that £ C C(f) and flc = f, completing the proof. 0

Proposition 2.3.11 Let (X, £,f) be a Daniell space and (X, C',l') an ar­

bitrary closed triple extending (X, £, f). Then the following implications hold.

a) If f E £t and tt(J) < 00, then f E £' and l'(J) = tt(J) .

b) If f E £i and fi(J) > -00, then f E £' and f'(J) = fi(J) .

Proof. In view of Proposition 4, it suffices to prove a). Take f E £t with

ft(J) < 00. There is an increasing sequence (In)nEIN from £ n lRx having f as its supremum. Then

sup ['(In) = sup f(Jn) = ft(J) < 00. nEIN nEIN

Hence (fn)nEIN is an increasing £I-sequence, and since (X, C',l') is closed, a)

follows. 0

The following theorem implies in particular that the closure of a closed

Daniell space is the given Daniell space itself.

Theorem 2.3.12 For every Daniell space (X, £,l) , (X, C(f),7!) is the small­

est closed Daniell space extending (X, £,f) .

Proof. Let (X, C',l') be a closed Daniell space such that (X, £,f) ~ (X, C',l')

and take f E C(f) . There is an increasing sequence (f~)nEIN from £i and a

decreasing sequence (f~)nEIN from £t such that the sequences (fi(f~»nEIN and

(tt (f~»nEIN both lie in lR,

V f~ 5, f 5, 1\ f~ nEIN nEIN

and

sup fi(f~) = inf £f(J~) = 7!(J) . nEIN nEIN

Using Proposition 11, we conclude that the sequences (J~)nEIN and (J~)nEIN

are l'-sequences. If we put

Page 39: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.3 The Closure of a Daniell Space 317

f':= V f~, 1":= 1\ f~ , nE~ nE~

then f' ::; f ::; 1" , and the functions 1',1" both belong to .12', since (X,.c', £') is closed. Moreover, by Proposition 11,

£,U') = sup£~(J~) = £(J) = inf £t(J~) = £'(J"). nE~ nE~

In view of Proposition 2.2.13, f E £' and £(J) = £'(J). It follows that

(X, £(£), £) ~ (X,.c', £') . D

The essential step toward the construction of the integral is completed with

the introduction of the closure. In fact, many authors stop at this stage and call

(X, £(£),£) the integral of (X,.c, £). We shall, however, make a final extension

in the next section, incorporating the concept of "locally null" functions.

We illustrate the constructions in this section with a simple example.

Example 2.3.13 Let X = {a, b, c, d, e} and

.12 = {J E IR x I f ( a) = V ( b) E IR , f ( c) = 0 , f (d) E IR}

€ : .12 --+ IR, f>---t f(a) .

The reader can easily verify the following statements .

.12 is a (non-real) Riesz lattice in IRx , and (X,.c, £) is a non-closed Daniell

space. Moreover,

.ct = {J E IRx I f(a) = U(b) E]- 00,00], f(c) = 0, f(d) E] - 00, oo]},

€t(J) = f(a) E] - 00,00] for every f E .ct ,

.c~ = {J E IRx I f(a) = U(b) E [-00, 00[, f(c) = 0, f(d) E [-00, oo[},

€~(J) = f(a) E [-oo,oo[ for every f E .c~ ,

£(€) = {J E IRx I f(a) = V(b) E IR, f(c) = O} ,

£(J) = f(a) for every f E £( €) .

In particular, .12 C £(£) .

'" D

We now introduce the upper closure £* and the lower closure €* for a

Daniell space (X,.c, €) .

Page 40: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

318 2. Elementary Integration Theory

Definition 2.3.14

define

-x Let (X,.c, £) be a Daniell space. Then, for f E lR ,

£*(1) := inf{£t(g) I 9 E .ct , 9 ~ J},

£*(1) := sup{£.l.(g) I 9 E.c.l., g::; J}. o

Proposition 2.3.15 Let (X,.c, £) be a closed Daniell space. Take f, g, h E

lRx.

a) If f E .c, then £*(1) = £(1) .

b) If f E .ct , then £*(1) = £t(l).

c) If £* (I) is real, then £* (I) = £(g) for some 9 E .c with 9 ~ f·

d) £*(1) = inf{£t(g) I 9 E.ct , 9 ~ f .c-a.e.}.

e) If f ::; 9 .c-a. e., then £* (I) ::; £* (g) .

f) If f = 9 .c-a.e., then £*(1) = £*(g) .

g) If h(x) = f(x) + g(x) .c -a. e. and if £* (I) + £* (g) is defined, then

£* (h) ::; £* (I) + £* (g) .

h) If 00 E lR+, then £*(001) = 00£*(1). If f ~ 0, then £*(001) = 00£*(1) .

Proof. a) and b) are trivial.

c) By hypothesis, there is in .ct a sequence (gn)nEIN such that gn ~ f for

every nand

Moreover, the sequence (gn)nEIN can be chosen so that £t(gn) is real for every

n and that (gn)nEIN decreases. In view of Proposition 11 a), (gn)nEIN is an £­

sequence from .c. Taking g:= /\ gn we have 9 E .c , 9 ~ f and £(g) = £* (I) . nEIN

d) It suffices to show that £* (I) ::; £t (g) whenever 9 E .ct and 9 ~ f .c-

a.e. Given such a function g, let A := {g < J}. By hypothesis, A E 1)1(.c).

Since ooeA = V neA, the function ooeA belongs to .ct and £t(ooeA) = O. nEIN

Thus 9 + ooeA belongs to .ct. Since f ::; 9 + ooeA , we have

Page 41: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.3 The Closure of a Daniell Space 319

e),f) are left for the reader to prove.

g) If 1, 9 E [) and 1 ~ f , 9 ~ g, then 1 + 9 is defined and belongs to

[), f}(1+g) = £t(1)+£t(g), and h S 1+g £-a.e. By d), £*(h) s £t(J)+£t(g).

It follows that £* (h) S £* (f) + £* (g) .

h) The first assertion is left for the reader to prove. Assume that f ~ O. If

£*(f) > 0, then

£*(00J) ~ £*(nJ) = n£*(f)

for every n in IN, and so £* (00 J) = 00 = ooe* (f) . Suppose that £* (f) = O.

By c), there is a function 9 in £ such that 9 ~ f and £*(f) = £(g) = O. We

conclude successively that g, f and also oof belong to N(£) . Hence

£* (00J) = £( 00J) = 0 = 00£* (f) . D

Next we describe the important convergence properties of £* in the case

where (X, £, £) is closed. The Fatou Lemma (Theorem 16 b)), played a decisive

role in earlier treatments of integration theory.

Theorem 2.3.16 Let (X, £, £) be a closed Daniell space.

a) For every nonempty, countable, upward directed family (f,),o from IRx ,

if £* (f,o) > - 00 for at least one ~o E I , then

£* (V f,) = sup £* (f,) . 'EI 'EI

-x b) Fatou's Lemma (1906). For every sequence (fn)nElN from IR+ '

e* (lim inf fn) Slim inf £* (In) . n-too n-+oo

Proof. a) By Proposition 15 e),

£* (V f,) 'EI

~ sup£*(fJ. 'EI

If sup £* (f,) = 00, equality must hold. So we assume that sup e* (f,) < 00. 'EI 'EI

Fix ~o E I with £*(f,o) > -00, and let J := {~ E I I f, ~ f,o}' According to

Proposition 15 c), for each ~ in J there is a function g, E £ such that

Page 42: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

320 2. Elementary Integration Theory

g. ~ f. and f(g.) = f* (J.) .

We claim that the family (g.).EI is directed up relative to the preorder ~ £-a.e.

Indeed, let £', £" belong to J. There is an £ in I such that f., ~ f., f." ~ f •. Now f., ::; g.' 1\ g., so that

Thus g.' = g.,l\g. £-a.e. (Proposition 2.2.13), that is, g.' ~ g. £-a.e. Similarly

g." ::; g. £-a.e. Note that

by the hypothesis that (J.).El is directed up. Note also that sup f(g.) < 00 . • EJ

Since V f. ~ V g., we use Proposition 15 e) and Theorem 2.2.17 a) to conclude .EJ .EJ

that V g. belongs to £ and .EJ

f* (V f.) = f* (V f.) ~ f (V g,) = sup f(g.) = ~I ~J ~J ~J

= supf*(J,) ::; supf*(J,). ,EJ 'EI

b) Using a) and the monotonicity of f* , we have that

f* (lim inf fn) = supf* (A fm) ::; sup inf f*(Jm) = lim inU*(fn). 0 n->oo nEIN m~n nEIN m~n n->oo

We leave the proofs of the next two propositions to the reader.

Proposition 2.3.17 Let (X, £, f) be a Daniell space. Then for every f E -x rn.,

Proposition 2.3.18 Let (X, £, f) be a closed Daniell space and take -x

f,g,h Ern..

a) If f E £, then f*(f) = f(f) .

b) If f E £J., then f*(f) = fJ.(f).

c) If f ::; g £-a.e., then f*(J) ~ f*(g) .

o

Page 43: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.3 The Closure of a Daniell Space 321

d) If f = 9 .c-a.e., then £*(f) = £*(g).

e) If h(x) = f(x) + g(x) .c-a.e. and if £*(f) + £*(g) is defined, then

£*(h) ~ £*(f) + £*(g).

o

Closed Daniell spaces (X,.c, £) can be characterized in terms of the map­

pings £* and £* .

Proposition 2.3.19 Let (X,.c, £) be a closed Daniell space.

a) .c = {f E IRx I £*(f) = £*(f) E IR}.

b) N(.c) = {f E IRx I £*(Ifl) = O}.

Proof. a) follows from Propositions 15 a) and 18 a) and the fact that (X,.c, £) is its own closure.

b) By Proposition 2.2.11,

N(.c) = {f E IRx I If I E .c and £(Ifl) = O} .

Moreover,

-x for every f E IR . Accordingly, b) follows from a). o

Proposition 2.3.20 For every Daniell space (X,.c, £) ,

Proof. In view of Proposition 17, it suffices to establish the first equality. That

£* ~ t follows immediately from the inclusion

which holds for every f E IRx. Given f E IRx , it follows that £*(f) = -* -* -* £ (f) whenever £ (f) = 00. Suppose that £ (f) is real. By Proposition 15 c), -* - -£ (f) = £(g) for some 9 E .c(£) with 9 ~ f. Then

£*(f) :::; £*(g) = £(g) = t(f).

Page 44: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

322 2. Elementary Integration Theory

Finally, suppose that t (I) = -00. If 9 belongs to £(£)t and 9 2:: f, then -* -t £ (g) = £ (g) > -00. Then, using what has already been shown, we have

£*(1) ::; £*(g) = t(g) = i(g).

Taking the infimum over all such 9 yields £* (I) = -00. o

Combining Propositions 19 and 20, we obtain a new characterization of the

closure (X, £(£), £) of a Daniell space in terms of the mappings £* and £* .

Theorem 2.3.21 Let (X, £, f) be a Daniell space.

a) If f E £(£) 1 then £(1) = £*(1) = £*(1).

b) £(£) = U E lRx 1£*(1) = £*(1) E lR}.

c) N(£(£)) = U E lRx I £*(Ifl) = O}. o

We now describe several aspects of summability which will be useful later.

Example 2.3.22 Take

F(X) := U E lRx I U f= O} is finite},

p.)( : F(X) ---+ lR, f I--t L f(x). xE{NO}

(X, F(X), £)() is a Daniell space. We claim that (X, £l(X), L:) is its closure.

By Example 2.2.10, (X,£l(X), L:) is a closed Daniell space. It obviously

extends (X, F(X), £)() . Take f E £l(X)+. By Example 1.1.11 d), U f= O} is

countable. Let (An)nEIN be an increasing sequence of finite subsets of X with

U An = U f= O}. For n E IN, put fn := feA n • (In)nEiN is an increasing nEIN sequence from F(X)+ with supremum f. Hence f E F(X)t and

£t(l) = sup £)((In) = sup L f(x) = L f(x) < 00. nEIN nEIN xEAn xEX

Proposition 11 a) implies that f E £(£)(). It follows easily that P(X) c £(£)().

The claim is now a consequence of Theorem 12. 0

The summability naturally extends to infinite families of real numbers the

notion of sum. Recall that a family of real numbers and a real-valued function

are two descriptions of the same object (see the section on preliminaries).

Page 45: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.3 The Closure of a Daniell Space 323

Definition 2.3.23 As before, we denote by 2:: the functional

C1 (X) -tIR, ff-'t 2)1):= Lf(x). xEX

A function f E IRx is said to be summable iff it belongs to Cl(X). -x

For f E lR ,we write

2:* f(x) := L* (J). xEX

Equivalently, a family (aX)XEX from lR is said to be summable iff it belongs

to Cl(X). For every summable family (ax)xEX from lR, we write

LaX := L((ax)xEX) XEX

and we call 2:: ax the sum of the family (aX)XEX. In a similar way, given a xEX

family (ax)xEX from lR, we write

and we call 2::* ax the upper sum of the family. xEX

o

Definition 2.3.24 A family (JJ'EI from lRx is said to be summable iff for

each x EX, the family (J,(X))'EI is summable. If (J,)'EI is a summablefamily -x

from lR ,then 2:: f" defined by 'EI

Lf,: X -t lR, x f-'t Lf,(x) ~l ~l

is called the sum of the family (j,),o. If (J,),o is an arbitrary family from -x * lR ,then 2:: f" defined by

'EI

L* f, : X -t lR, x f-'t 2:* f,(x) 'EI 'EI

is called the upper sum of the family (J')'EI. o

Corollary 2.3.25 If (ax)xEX is a summable family from lR, then

xEX xEX

Similarly, if (J')'EI is a summable family from lRx , then

2:* f, = Lf,. o 'EI 'EI

Page 46: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

324 2. Elementary Integration Theory

Proposition 2.3.26 Take f E m.x . Then the following are equivalent.

a) ~* f(x) Em.. xEX

Proof Only a) ::::} b) requires a proof. Let a := ~* f(x) Em.. There is a xEX

decreasing sequence (gn)nEIN in £1(X)t such that gn ~ f and ~t(gn) is real

for every n E:IN and

By Proposition 11 a), (gn)nEIN is a ~-sequence in £1(X), and

Et (gn) = E gn(x) xEX

for every n E :IN. Putting g:= /\ gn, we conclude that 9 E £1 (X) and f ~ g. nEIN

We claim that f = g. Suppose that f(x) < g(x) for some x EX. Put

c5:= (g(x) - f(x)) /\ 1

and choose n E :IN such that

Then h:= gn - c5e{x} E £1(X) and h ~ f, but

contradicting the monotonicity of the mapping ~ . o

Corollary 2.3.27 For every family (ax)xEX from m.+,

Proof. If (aX)XEx is summable, the assertion follows from the definitions.

Otherwise it follows from Proposition 26. 0

The next proposition collects some special properties of summable se­

quences.

Page 47: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.3 The Closure of a Daniell Space 325

Proposition 2.3.28 Let (an)nEIN be a summable sequence of real numbers.

m

a) E an = lim E ak· nEIN m--+oo k= 1

b) inf (E lam I) = 0 . nEIN m>n

c) lim an = O. n--+oo

Proof. a) Apply the Lebesgue Dominated Convergence Theorem to the se­

quence (In)nEIN from fl(IN) defined by

n

fn := L ake{k} (n E IN), k=l

using the fact that (lanl)nEIN is summable. b) follows from a) , and c) follows from b). o

Corollary 2.3.29 A sequence (an)nEIN of real numbers is summable iff

n

lim '" lakl < 00. n-t-oo L....J o

k=l

Corollary 2.3.30 For every sequence (an)nEIN from IR+,

o

We continue with some applications of the preceding considerations.

Theorem 2.3.31 Let (X, C, f) be a closed Daniell space and (J.}.El a count­

able family from C. Then the following are equivalent.

a) The family (f(lf.I)'EI is summable.

b) ~lf.1 belongs to C . • EI

If these assertions hold, then so do the following.

c) f (~lf.l) = Ef(lf.l)· .EI .EI

d) The family (f.).EI is summable C-a. e.

e) The family (f(J'»'E/ is summable.

Page 48: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

326 2. Elementary Integration Theory

f) For f E lRx , if f = L* f, .c-a.e., then f belongs to .c and £(J) = 'EI

~ £(J,). 'EI

Proof We may suppose that I is infinite. Let <p: IN -+ I be bijective. Put

A:= U{II,I = oo}. 'EI

Note that A is .c-exceptional.

a) ::::} b), c). The sequence ( ~ * If cp(k) I)nElN , whose terms belong to .c, is kElNn

increasing and

o :::; £ ( L* Ifcp(kl I) = t £(Ifcp(k) I) :::; L £(11,1) < 00.

kElN n k=! 'EI

Thus (~*lfcp(k)l) is an £-sequence from .c. Therefore Llfcp(k)1 be-kElN n nElN kElN

longs to .c and, using Corollary 30,

£ (Llfcp(kll) = L £(lfcp(k) I) = L £(If,I)· kElN kElN 'EI

Since L*lf,1 is equal to Llfcp(d, both b) and c) follow. 'EI kElN

b) ::::} a). For every n in IN, ~*Ifcp(d belongs to .c and kElN n

It follows that (£(lfcp(k)l)hElN is sum mabIe (Corollary 29). So, therefore, is

(£(11,1)),0,

b) ::::} d). Since the function L* If,1 belongs to .c, it is real .c-a.e. Thus 'EI

d) follows from Proposition 26 a) ::::} b).

a) ::::} e). Since I£(J,) I :::; £(If,1) for every ~, e) follows easily from a)

(Example 1.3.15).

a),b),d) ::::} f). In view of Proposition 2.2.3 d), it suffices to show that ~* f, 'EI

belongs to .c and

£ (2:: I,) = L £(J.) . 'EI 'EI

Set

Page 49: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.3 The Closure of a Daniell Space 327

B := {x E X I {lft{x)J)tEI is not summable}

and note that B is C-exceptional. We have

For n E IN,

n

~ ft = lim '" f<p(k)eX\B C-a.e. L n-+ooL.-t tEl k=l

Itf<p(k)eX\B1 ~ Llftex\BI ~ L*lftl. k=l tEl tEl

Thus E* ft is the C-a.e. limit of a sequence from C bounded in C. Using the tEl

Dominated Convergence Theorem, we conclude that ~ ft belongs to C and tEl

Corollary 2.3.32 Let (X, C, f) be a closed Daniell space. Suppose, for some

sequence (fn)nEIN from C and for some function f belonging to C, that the

sequence (f(lf ~ fnl))nEIN is summable. Then the sequence (fn)nEIN is bounded

in C, and

f{x) = lim fn(x) C-a.e. n-->oo

Proof. Define

hn : X ----+ lR , .-----r - X' ----' { oof{X) - fn(x) if defined

otherwise,

(7)

Then (flhnJ))nEIN is summable. By Theorem 31 a) => b) & d), (hn)nEIN is

summable C-a.e. and h belongs to C. At each x for which (hn(X))nEIN is

summable we have

lim (fn{X) - f(x)) = 0 n-->oo

so (7) holds. Evidently,

-(h + If I) ~ fn ~ h + If I

for every n E IN. Since h + If I belongs to C, the sequence (fn)nEIN is bounded

in C. 0

Page 50: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

328 2. Elementary Integration Theory

Corollary 2.3.33 Let (X, C, f) be a Daniell space. Then every function in

"l(f) is the "l(f)-a.e. limit of a sequence from C that is bounded in "l(f).

Proof. Let f E "l(f). For each n in N there is a function gn belonging to "l(f) net such that f ::; gn and

f(gn) - f(j) = ft(gn) - f(j) < 2 \n (Proposition 11 a)), and there is a function fn belonging to en IRX such that

fn ::; gn and

For each n in N,

- -. - 1 f(lf - fn!} ::; f(lf - gn!} + f(lgn - fn!} < 2n •

Since the sequence (1/2n)nEIN is summable, the sequence mil - fn!})nEIN is summable. Now apply Corollary 32 to conclude that the sequence (jn)nEIN is

bounded in "l(f) and

f(x) = lim fn(x) "l(f)-a.e. n-+oo

Proposition 2.3.34 Let (X, C, f) be a closed Daniell space. Then

-x for every family (j')'EI from IR+ , and

-x for every countable family (j')'EI from IR+ .

o

(8)

(9)

Proof For (j')'EI a finite family from IR~ , inequalities (8) and (9) follow by

complete induction from Propositions 18 e) and 15 g).

Let (j,),E/ be a count ably infinite family from IR: and cp : N -+ I a bi­jection. Using (9) for finite families, together with Theorem 16 a) and Corollary

30, we have

Page 51: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.3 The Closure of a Daniell Space 329

e (E'I.) = e (2:* Icp(n») = e (sup 2:* ICP(k») = .EI nEIN nEIN kEINn

= SUpe (2:* jCP(k») ::5 sup 2:* e(fcp(k») = nEIN kEINn nEIN kEINn

= L* e(fcp(n») = E' e(f.) . nEIN • EI

Finally, let (J.).EI be an arbitrary family from IR: . According to Corollary 27,

E' 4 (f.) = sup L* 4 (f.) . • EI /fi~[te .EJ

For every finite subset J of I,

Inequality (8) follows. o

Page 52: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

330 2. Elementary Integration Theory

2.4 The Integral for a Daniell Space

The following notation simplifies the statements of many later results.

Definition 2.4.1 Let Fe IRx . Then

9t(F) := {U =J O} I f E F} . o

Proposition 2.4.2 For every Riesz lattice C, the following hold.

a) U < g} E 9t(C) whenever f, 9 E C.

b) Given A E 9t(C) , there is an f E C+ n IRx with A = U > O}.

c) Au B E 9t(C) and An B E 9t(C) whenever A, B E 9t(C) .

d) If (X, c, £) is a Daniell space, then for every A E 9t(C(f)) there is a

sequence (An)nEIN in 9t(C) such that A c U An. nEIN

Now suppose that (X, C, £) is a closed Daniell space. Then

e) U An E &t(C) for every sequence (An)nEIN from 9t(C) . nEIN

f) If f E C and A E 9t(C) , then feA and feX\A belong to C.

g) A\B E 9t(C) whenever A, BE 9t(C) .

Proof. a) Note that U<g}={h/\O=JO} and hEC,whence h/\OEC,

where

_ { f(x) - g(x) h:X--tIR, Xl---t

o

if defined

otherwise.

b) There is agE C with A = {g =J O}. Put B := {Igl = co}. Then

eB E C and Iglex\B E C (Proposition 2.1.21 b)). Define f:= eB + Iglex\B.

c) Take f, 9 E C+ n IRx with A = U > O}, B = {g > O} and note that

Au B = U V 9 > A}, An B = {f /\ 9 > O}.

d) Given A E &t(C(£)), take f E C(£)+ with A = U > O}. There

is an increasing sequence (fn)nEIN in C+ n IRx such that f ~ V fn. Put nEIN

An := Un > O} for every n E IN .

Page 53: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.4 The Integral for a Daniell Space 331

e) Let (An)nEIN be a sequence in ~ (.c) . Given n E IN, there is an fn E .c+

such that An = Un > O} . Multiplying by suitable numbers if necessary, we may

assume that eUn) < 1/2n. By Theorem 2.3.31 a) ::} b), f := L;* fn belongs nEIN

to .c and hence

U An = U # O} E ~ (.c) . nEIN

f) First suppose that f E .c+. Take 9 E.c+ with A = {g > O} . Then

feA = V U Ang) E.c. nEIN

Now if f E .c is arbitrary, then feA = f+eA - f-eA E .c. Moreover,

feX\A E (f ..:.. feA) C .c.

g) Take f E .c+ n IRx with A = U > O}. By f), feB E .c. Hence

A\B = U - feB # O} E 6i (.c). o

We now introduce the functions and sets which will serve as the exceptional

functions and sets for the integral.

Definition 2.4.3 For (X,.c, e) a Daniell space,

N(e):= U E IRx I feA E N(l(e)) for every A E ~(C(e))},

!Jl(e) := {B C X IBn A E !Jl(C(e)) for every A E ~ (C(e))}. 0

Proposition 2.4.4 Let (X,.c, f) be a Daniell space.

a) N(C(e)) c N(e) and !Jl(C(e)) c !Jl(e)).

b) Every subset of a set from !Jl(e) belongs itself to !Jl(e).

c) U An E !Jl(e) for every sequence (An)nEIN from !Jl(e). nEIN

-x - ~ d) N(e) = U E IR I feA E N(.c(e)) for every A E 9t(.c)}.

e) !Jl(e) = {B c X IBn A E !Jl(C(e)) for every A E ~(.c)}.

f) For every f E IRx , f E N(e) iff U # O} E !Jl(e) .

Page 54: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

332 2. Elementary Integration Theory

Proof. We leave the proof to the reader. For d) and e), take Proposition 2 d)

into account. 0

Proposition 2.4.5 Let (X, £, £) be a Daniell space. Take g, hE £(£) with

{g =I h} E 1)1(£). Then £(g) = £(h) .

Proof. We have

{g =I h} c {g =I O} U {h =I O} E 6i (£(£)).

Consequently, {g =I h} E 1)1(£(£)). o

Definition 2.4.6 Let (X, £, £) be a Daniell space. Then

£1(£) := {J E IRX I {J =I g} E 1)1(£) lor some 9 E £(£)}.

For IE £1(£), we put

where 9 E £(£) , {J =I g} E 1)1(£). (1)

(In view 01 the preceding proposition, Id is well-defined.) Functions belonging

to £1(£) are said to be £-integrable. The number Itl is called the £-integral

01 I· The triple

(X, £1(£),1)

is called the integral lor the Daniell space (X, £, f) . o

The sign I was introduced by Leibniz in 1675. The name integral was used

for the first time by Jakob Bernoulli in 1690.

Note that given I E £1 (£) , the function 9 appearing in (1) can be chosen in

£(£) nIRx , because {Igl = Do} is £(£)-exceptional. Moreover, if IE £1(£)+,

then 9 can be chosen in £(£)+, since

{J V 0 =I 9 V O} C {J =I g} E 1)1(£)

and 1= IvO.

Theorem 2.4.7 For every Daniell space (X, £, £), (X, £1(£), It) is a closed

Daniell space extending (X, £, £) . Moreover,

Page 55: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.4 The Integral for a Daniell Space 333

Proof. Let III 12 E .c1(1!) , and take 9I. g2 E £(I!) n JRx such that {II =F gd E

1J1(1!) and {l2 =F g2} E 1J1(1!) . Then

{II V 12 =F gl V g2} C {II =F gd u {h =F g2} E 1J1(1!) .

Consequently, II V 12 E .c1(1!). Similarly, 11/\12 E .c1(1!). Take hE (II -i- h)· Then

and thus hE .c1(1!). Moreover,

Ih = f(gl + g2) = f(gd + f(g2) = 111 + 112.

We leave it to the reader to verify that OIl E .c1(1!) and ftOlI = OIftl whenever

IE .cl (£) and 01 E JR, and that ftl ~ 0 whenever IE .c1(1!)+. Consequently, .c1(1!) is a Riesz lattice in JRx and Ii is a positive linear functional on .cl (£).

Let (fn)nEIN be an increasing Irsequence from .c1(1!)+. Given n E IN' ,

choose g~ E £(I!)+ such that {In =F g~} E 1J1(1!) . Put

gn:= V g;" m~n

for every n E IN' . Then

{In =F gn} C U {1m =F g;"} m$n

for every n E IN' , so {In =F gn} E '.n(I!) (Proposition 4 b),c)). Put

B:= U {In =F gn} . nEil"

By Proposition 4 c), B E '.n(I!). The sequence (gn)nEIN is an increasing f­

sequence in £(I!) , and thus

g:= V gn E £(I!). nEil"

But

{V In =F g} c B E '.n(£) , nEil"

and so V In E .c1(1!). Moreover, nEil"

Page 56: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

334 2. Elementary Integration Theory

1 (V fn) = £(g) = sup £(gn) = sup lfn-f nEIN nEIN nEIN f

In view of Proposition 2.2.9 c) =} a), (X, £1(£), fe) is a closed Daniell space.

It clearly extends (X, £(£),£) and hence also (X, £, e).

Let us now prove that SJ1(£I(£)) = SJ1(£). Take A E SJ1(£I(£)). Then feeA =

o and there is agE £(e)+ such that {g =f. eA} E SJ1(e). Since £(g) = 0, we

have 9 E N(£(e)) (Proposition 2.2.11 b) =} a)). Hence {g =f. O} E SJ1(£(£)), and since

it follows that A E SJ1( £) . Conversely, if A E SJ1( e) , then {ooe A =f. O} E SJ1( £) , and since 0 E £(e) , ooeA E £I(e). In other words, A E SJ1(£I(e)).

Finally, use Proposition 4 f) to prove the last statement of the theorem. 0

Definition 2.4.8 Functions belonging to N(e) , that is, to N(£l(e)) , are

called £-exceptional functions. Sets belonging to SJ1(e) , that is, to SJ1(£l(e)) , are called e --exceptional sets. In other words, we call the £1 (e) -exceptional

sets and functions simply £ -exceptional.

A property P that refers to elements of X is said to hold e-almost every­

where (or simply, £-a.e.) iff it holds £I(£)-almost everywhere. Rather than

write P £l(e)-a.e. and P(x) £l(e)-a.e., we write, respectively, P e-a.e. and

P(x) e-a.e. 0

In view of Theorem 4.1.12 (b) of "Integration Theory, Vol. I" by C. Con­

stantinescu and K. Weber (in collaboration wit A. Sontag), the definition of

integral given there (Definition 4.2.12) coincides with the present definition

(Definition 6). It was shown in that book that the integral defined there is, in

fact, the largest (not only a maximal!) element in a natural set of extensions

of the given Daniell space. We shall neither use this result nor repeat its proof

here. What we do prove is that applying the integral construction to the Daniell

space (X, £1 (e), Ie) , we do not obtain a further extension.

Theorem 2.4.9 For every Daniell space (X, £, £), the Daniell space

(X,£I(£),If) is its own integral.

Proof. It clearly suffices to show that £1(Je) is contained in £1(£). We prove

first that SJ1(Je) C SJ1(e). Take BE SJ1(Jf) and A E 9l (£(e)). Then, taking into

account that

Page 57: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.4 The Integral for a Daniell Space 335

we have

and thus

B n A = (B n A) n A E 1J1(£(£)).

Since A is arbitrary, we conclude that B E 1J1(l') .

Now take f E £.1(ft). In view of (2), there is agE £1(£) such that

It follows that f = 9 £-a.e., and Proposition 2.1.21 c) implies that f E £1(l'). o

We provide a simple example for the integral construction.

Example 2.4.10 Consider the Daniell space (X, £, £) from Example 2.3.13.

The reader will readily verify the following statements.

N(£(£))

1J1(£(l'))

N(£)

-x {f E IR I f(a) = f(b) = f(c) = O} ,

{A c X I A c {d, e} } ,

{f E IRx I fex\{c} E NCC(l'))}

{f E IRx I f(a) = f(b) = O} ,

1J1(£) = {A c X I A c {c,d,e}} ,

£1(l') {f E IRx I f(a) = V(b) E IR},

ftf f(a) for every f E £1(£) .

Note that (X, £1(£), ft) is a proper extension of (X, £(£), 1). o

In numerous important cases, the integral and the closure of a Daniell space

are identical. We present a sufficient condition for this to be true.

Proposition 2.4.11 Let (X, £, £) be a Daniell space such that

Page 58: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

336 2. Elementary Integration Theory

i) X = U Ai AE!){(.c)

ii) U B c U An for some sequence (An)nElN from 6i (.c) . BEIJI(C(£» nElN

Then

(X, £(f), f) = (X,.c 1 (f), [) .

Proof. It suffices to show that .c 1(f) c £(f), and this is an easy consequence

of the inclusion lJl( f) c lJl(£( f)) which we now prove. Take C E lJl( f). For

every A E 6i (.c) ,

An (C\ U An) E lJl(£(f)), nElN

and thus, in view of ii),

A n (C\ U An) = 0. nElN

Hence, by i), C\ U An = 0, that is, C c U An. Since C n An E lJl(£(f)) nElN nElN

for every n E IN, it follows that

C = U (C nAn) E lJl(£(f)). o nElN

Corollary 2.4.12 (X, f1 (X), L) is its own integral. o

Definition 2.4.13 Let:F c lRx . Then :F is said to be a-finite iff there is

a countable family (fL)LEI from :F such that

X =UUL :;fO}. o LEI

Corollary 2.4.14 Let (X,.c, f) be a Daniell space. If .c is a-finite, then

(X,£(f),f) = (X,.c 1(f), [) . o

The following properties of f-integrable functions will be useful later.

Proposition 2.4.15 Let (X,.c, f) be a Daniell space, and take f E .c 1(f) .

Page 59: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.4 The Integral for a Daniell Space 337

a) There is an A E 6i (£(£)) such that

A c {f #- O}, feA E £(£) , fex\A E N(£) .

b) There are an increasing sequence (An)nEIN in 6i (.c) and a set C E 1)1(£)

such that

{f #- O} c (U An) U C . nEIN

c) feB E £(£) whenever B E 6t (£(£)) .

d) If {j #- O} c {g #- O} for some 9 E £(£) , then f E £(£) .

Proof. a) There is agE £(£) with {f #- g} E 1)1(£). Putting B := {g #- O},

we have

Since geB = 9 E £(£) , we conclude that feB E £(£). Moreover,

{jeX\B #- O} C {f #- g} E 1)1(£).

By Proposition 4 f), fex\B E N(£) . Now put A := {feB #- O} and note that

A C B and that

B\A c B n {f #- g} E 1)1(£(£)).

b) follows from a) and Proposition 2 d).

c) Choose A as in a). Then feB\A E N(£) and therefore

Moreover, in view of Proposition 2 f),

Accordingly,

feB = feB\A + feBnA E £(£).

d) follows from c) . o

Page 60: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

338 2. Elementary Integration Theory

Proposition 2.4.16

Then Let (X,.c, f) be a Daniell space and take I E .c1 (f) .

i l = s~'p ileA + i!!.f ileA. t AE!Jt (.c) l AE!Jt (.c) I.

(3)

In particular, il I E .c1(f)+, then

(4)

Proof By Proposition 2 f), leA E .c1(f) whenever A E 9t(.c).

First suppose that IE .c1(f)+. Apply Proposition 15 b) to find an increas­

ing sequence (An)nEIN in 9t (.c) such that

We have

and (4) follows.

I = V leAn f-a.e. nEIN

i l = sup ileAn::; sup ileA::; il l nEIN I. AE!Jt(C) l l

Now let IE .c1(f) be arbitrary. Put B:= {J > O}. Then

and hence An B E 9t (.c) whenever A E 9t (.c) . Thus

i r = s~ ireA ~ s~ ileA ~ s~ ileAnB = s~ il+eA. t AE!Jt (.c) t AE!Jt (.c) l AE!Jt (.c) t AE!Jt (C) t

It follows that

i l+ = sup ileA. l AE!Jt(.c) l

Accordingly,

and (3) follows. o

Note that Daniell spaces with identical closures have also the same inte­

gral. In particular, the integrals for a Daniell space (X,.c, f) and its closure

Page 61: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.4 The Integral for a Daniell Space 339

(X, £(£), £) coincide. As a consequence, (3) and (4) remain true if 6l (£) is

replaced by 6l (£( £)) .

The next result is often used when proving that every £-integrable function

has a certain property P. In fact, one can apply the theorem, putting

F : = {J E £ 1 (£) I f satisfies property P}.

Theorem 2.4.17 (Induction Principle) Let (X, £, £) be a Daniell space

and suppose that F is a subset of £1(£) satisfying the following conditions.

i) £ c F.

ii) If (fn)nEIN is an h-sequence from F, and if f E £1(£) satisfies

f(x) = lim fn(x) £-a.e., n-->oo

then f E F.

Proof. By i), and ii),

{J E £t I £t(f) < oo} c F,

{J E £~ I £~(f) > -oo} c F.

Take f E £(£). For each n E IN, there is a lin-bracket (f~, f~) for f

relative to £, and we may choose these brackets in such a way that (f~)nEIN is

increasing and (f~)nEIN is decreasing. By ii),

f' := V f~ E F, f":= 1\ f~ E F, nEIN nEIN

and since f = f' £--a.e. (Proposition 2.2.13), f E F. Hence £(£) C F. Now take f E £1(£). Then f is £-a.e. equal to some g E £(£). Use ii)

for the constant sequence (g)nEIN to conclude that f E F. It follows that

£1(£) c F. 0

Page 62: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

340 2. Elementary Integration Theory

2.5 Systems of Sets, Step Functions, and Stone Lattices

We begin by studying the domains on which measures will be defined.

Definition 2.5.1 A set !Jt of sets is called a ring of sets or a set-ring iff

the following two conditions hold.

a) The empty set belongs to !Jt.

b) Both Au Band A\B belong to !Jt whenever A and B do.

A set-ring !Jt is called a c5 -ring iff

c) n An belongs to !Jt for every sequence (An)nEIN from !Jt nEIN

and it is called a a-ring iff

d) U An belongs to !Jt for every sequence (An)nEIN from !Jt. nEIN

For <5 an arbitrary set of sets, define

X(<5):= UA. AE6

If !Jt is a set-ring (c5 -ring, a-ring) and X is any set containing X (!Jt) ,

then we say that !Jt is a set-ring (c5-ring, a-ring) on X.

A set-ring on X is said to be a-finite iff X can be written as the union

of countably many elements of the set~ring. If!Jt is a a ~finite set~ring on X ,

we shall also say that the pair (X,!Jt) is a-finite. 0

Observe that if !Jt is a a-finite set-ring on X, then X = X (!Jt) .

Proposition 2.5.2 Let!Jt be a set-ring.

a) The union of every finite family from !Jt belongs to !Jt.

b) The intersection of every nonempty finite family from !Jt belongs to !Jt.

c) If A and B belong to !Jt, then so does their symmetric difference ALoB.

d) If!Jt is a c5-ring, then the intersection of every nonempty countable family

from !Jt belongs to !Jt.

e) If!Jt is a c5-ring and if (A')'EI is a countable family from !Jt such that

U A, c A for some A E !Jt, then U A, E !Jt . 'EI ,EI

Page 63: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.5 Systems of Sets, Step Functions, and Stone Lattices 341

f) If ~ is a a-ring, then the union of every countable family from ~ belongs

to ~.

g) If ~ is a a-ring, then ~ is nlso a o-ring.

Proof a) This is proved by complete induction on the number of elements in

the family. Note that U A. = 0 and 0 is in ~. tE0

b) For arbitrary sets A and B,

An B = A\{A\B) .

Thus An B belongs to ~ whenever A and B do. The full claim now follows

by complete induction.

c),d),f). These are immediate from the definitions.

e) If 1= 0, there is nothing to prove. If not, use the identity

UAt = A\n{A\At). tEl tEl

g) Let (An)nEIN be a sequence from ~. Set

A:= U An nEIN

and observe that

n An=A\ U{A\An ).

nEIN nEIN

Using in turn the definitions of a-ring and set-ring, we conclude in succession

that A belongs to 9l, that each A\An belongs to ~, that U (A\An) belongs nEIN

to ~, and, finally, that n An belongs to 9l. nEIN

D

Example 2.5.3 The set consisting of all finite subsets of a fixed set X is

always a o-ring. It is a a-ring iff X is finite.

If X is an infinite set, then the set consisting of all subsets A of X for

which either A or X\A is finite is a ring of sets but not a o-ring. D

Every ring of sets has a useful decomposition property. Finite unions de­

compose into disjoint finite unions, and the decomposition can be achieved one

set at a time.

Page 64: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

342 2. Elementary Integration Theory

Proposition 2.5.4 Suppose that ~ is a ring of sets and that (A).EI is a

finite family from ~. Then there is in ~ a finite disjoint family (BI<)I<EK of

nonempty sets such that for each L in I there is a subset K. of K with

Proof. (Complete induction on the number n of elements of I) For n = 0 and n = 1, the claim is trivial. Assume that the claim is true

for some n E IN . Let (A.).EI be a family in ~ consisting of n + 1 elements.

Choose La E I and put J:= 1\ {La}. By assumption, there is a finite disjoint

family (CAhEL of nonempty elements of ~ such that for each L E J there is

a subset L. of L with

A.= U CA' AEL,

Then the nonempty elements of the set

{CA n Ao I A E L} U {CA \A. o I A E L} U {Ao \ U CAl AED

constitute the required family (BI<)I<EK.

The proofs of the next two results are easy and left to the reader.

D

Proposition 2.5.5 Let (~.).El be an arbitrary non empty family of set-rings

(of o-rings, or a-rings, respectively). Then

n~· .El

is also a set-ring (a o-ring, or a a-ring, respectively). D

The following corollary establishes the existence of a smallest set-ring (0-

ring, a-ring) containing a given set of sets.

Corollary 2.5.6 Let <5 be an arbitrary set of sets. Then there is exactly one

set-ring that contains <5 and is contained in every set-ring containing <5. The

set-ring in question is

n{~ c ~(X(<5)) I ~ is a set-ring containing 6}.

These assertions remain true if "set-ring" is replaced in all occurrences by "0-

ring" (or by "a-ring"). D

Page 65: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.5 Systems of Sets, Step Functions, and Stone Lattices 343

Definition 2.5.7 Let 6 be a set of sets. The set-ring characterized in Corol­

lary 6 is denoted by 6 r , and is called the set-ring generated by 6. The 8-

ring generated by 6 , denoted 66 , and the a-ring generated by 6, denoted

6"., are defined analogously. 0

Proposition 2.5.8 For every ring of sets v:t,

v:t6 c {A c X(v:t) I A c B for some BE v:t} .

Proof. Let

6 := {A C X(v:t) I A c B for some BE v:t}.

Then 6 is a 8-ring, and 6 contains v:t. Therefore v:t6 C 6 . o

Proposition 2.5.9 If v:t is a 8-ring, then v:tu is the set consisting of all

unions of increasing sequences from v:t.

Proof. Define

6 := {A I A = U An for some increasing sequence (An)nEIN from v:t}. nEIN

Certainly v:t c 6 c v:tu. If we show that 6 is a a-ring, then the proof

will be complete, since v:tu is contained in every a-ring that contains v:t.

Obviously 0 E 6. Let A and B belong to 6. There are in v:t increasing

sequences (An)nEIN and (Bn)nEIN such that A = U An and B = U Bn. nEIN nEIN

Now (An U Bn)nEIN is an increasing sequence from v:t, so its union, AU B, must belong to 6. Next observe that

A\B = (U An) \B = U (An\B). nEIN nEIN

The sequence (An \B)nEIN is increasing and its terms all belong to v:t, since

An \B = n (An \Bm) mEIN

and v:t is a 8-ring. It follows that A \B belongs to 6.

Finally, let (Cn)nEIN be a sequence from 6. For each n in IN, there is in

v:t an increasing sequence (Cn,m)mEIN whose union is Cn . For each m in IN,

put

Page 66: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

344 2. Elementary Integration Theory

Dm:= U Cn,m' n:5m

The sequence (Dm)mEIN is increasing and its terms belong to Vl. Therefore its

union belongs to <5. But

so U Cn belongs to <5. Thus <5 is in fact a a-ring and !RO" = <5 . 0 nEIN

We continue by discussing some important properties of step functions.

Definition 2.5.10 A step function on X is a real function f, defined on

X, such that

(1) .EI

for some finite family (A.).EI of subsets of X and some family (a.).E/ of real

numbers.

Given a subset <5 of I.lJ(X) and a function f in rn.x , the function f is

called an <5 -step function on X iff it has a representation (1) for which every

A. belongs to <5. In this case, (l) is called an <5-representation of f. We

denote by .c~ the set of all <5-step functions on X.

Given a subset <5 of I.lJ(X) and an <5-step function f on X, if

(2)

and (B")"EK is a disjoint family of nonempty sets belonging to <5, then (2) is

called a disjoint <5-representation of the <5-step function f. 0

Proposition 2.5.11 Let!R be a set-ring on X and f an !R-step function

on X.

a) There is a disjoint Vl-representation for f.

b) If f ;::: 0 and if

(3) ,.EK

is an arbitrary disjoint Vl-representation of f , then /3,. ;::: 0 for every K

in K.

c) If f = 0 and if (3) is a disjoint Vl-representation of f, then /3,. = 0 for

every K in K.

Page 67: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.5 Systems of Sets, Step Functions, and Stone Lattices 345

Proof. a) Let

be an 9'\-representation of f. By Proposition 4, there are a finite disjoint family

(B".)"EK of nonempty sets in 9'\ and an associated family (KL)LEl of subsets of

K such that

for every L in I. For", E K, put

(3 .. := L aL' .el

Then

is a disjoint !Jl-representation of f. b),c) are easy to see.

BKCA~

o

Corollary 2.5.12 Let 9'\ be a set-ring on X and f an 9'\-step function on

X.

a) {f > a} E 9'\ for every real number a ~ o.

b) {f ~ a} E 9'\ for every real number a > 0 .

Proof. a) Let

be a disjoint 9'\-representation for f. Then, if a ~ 0 ,

b) can be proved similarly. o

Theorem 2.5.13 Let 9'\ be a set-ring on X.

a) The set of all 9'\-step functions on X is a real Riesz lattice.

Page 68: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

346 2. Elementary Integration Theory

b) If f is an ~-step function on X, then so is the function f /\ ex.

Proof a) It is obvious that .c~ is a real vector space. To prove that .c~ is a

Riesz lattice, it is therefore sufficient, in view of Theorem 1.2.6 n),o), to show

that If I E.c~ whenever f E .c~ . But if

(4)

is a disjoint representation for f, then

Ifl = L 1,BltleB. E .c~ . ItEK

b) Let (4) be a disjoint V't-representation of f. Then, in view of a),

f /\ ex = f /\ e U B. E .c~ . o .EK

Definition 2.5.14 For.c a Riesz lattice in IRx , we say that .c has the

Stone property iff f /\ ex belongs to .c for every f E .c. A Riesz lattice in

IR x that has the Stone property is also called a Stone lattice. A Daniell space

(X,.c, €) is said to have the Stone property iff its Riesz lattice .c has the Stone

property. 0

Thus for any set-ring V't on X, the set of ~-step functions on X forms

a Stone lattice. We shall demonstrate that to every Stone lattice .c whose

elements are step functions on X, there corresponds a set-ring V't(.c) c qJ(X)

such that .c is exactly the collection of all ~(.c)-step functions on X. The set­

ring in question consists of those subsets of X whose characteristic functions

belong to .c.

-x Definition 2.5.15 For:F c 1R ,

V't(F) := {A C X leA E F} .

Proposition 2.5.16 Let .c be a Riesz lattice in IRx.

a) V't(.c) is a ring of sets.

o

-x b) If.c is conditionally a-completely embedded in IR , then ~(.c) is a

8-ring.

Page 69: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.5 Systems of Sets, Step Functions, and Stone Lattices 347

c) If C is a-completely embedded in R X , then ~(C) is a a-ring.

Proof. a) The empty set belongs to ~(C) since C contains the zero function.

Suppose that A and B belong to ~(C). Then eA and eB both belong to C.

Since

it follows that Au Band A\B both belong to ~(C).

b) Let (An)nEIN be a sequence from ~(C). For n E 1N, set Bn := n Am. m:5n

Then /\ eBn belongs to C, by Proposition 2.1.12 a) =} c) . Since nEIN

e n An = /\ e Bn , nEIN nEIN

the set n An belongs to ~(C). nEIN

c) This proof is left to the reader. o

Theorem 2.5.17 If C is a Stone lattice whose elements are step functions

on X, then C is the set consisting of all ~(C) -step functions on X .

Proof. Since C is a Riesz lattice, it is obvious from the definition of ~(C)

that every ~(C)-step function on X belongs to C. We must show that every

element of C is an ~(C)-step function. It suffices to consider only positive

functions from C, since every real function f has the representation f+ - f- .

The zero function is trivially ~(C)-step, so suppose that f E C+ and f i= O.

Then

f(X)\{O} = {15k IkE INn}

for some n E IN and appropriate numbers 15k E R, where we may and do

assume that 15k < 15k+1 for every k in INn-I. Define

Page 70: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

348 2. Elementary Integration Theory

Then

We prove inductively that each Ck belongs to !R(.c). Since

eCI = (~/) A ex

and .c has the Stone property, eCI belongs to .c and C1 is in !R(.c). Suppose

then that Ck belongs to !R(.c) for every k in lNm , m < n. Then

eCm +1 = (_I_g) A ex, 'Ym+l

n m

g:= L 'YkeCk = I - L 'YkeCk . k=m+l k=1

m

The inductive hypothesis ensures that L 'YkeCk belongs to .c. We conclude k=1

successively that g belongs to .c, that eCm +1 belongs to .c and that Cm +!

belongs to !R(.c). Thus C k belongs to !R(.c) for every k in lNn . 0

We now present some general properties of Stone lattices.

Proposition 2.5.18 Let (X,.c, i) be a Daniell space such that .c is a Stone

lattice. Then so are C(i) and .c1(i).

Proof We use the Induction Principle 2.4.17 to prove the second assertion. Let

According to the hypothesis, .c c :F. Let (fn)nEJN be an Jrsequence from :F -x

and I E IR such that

I = lim In i-a.e. n-+oo

If (fn)nEJN is increasing then Ik A ex :::; lim In for every k E IN. If (fn)nEIN is n-+oo

decreasing, then IkAeX ~ (lim In) AO for every k. In either case, (fnAex )nEJN n-+oo

is an It-sequence from .c1 (i) , so

( lim In) A ex = lim (fn A ex) E .c1(i). n--too n--too

Since

I A ex = (lim In) A ex i-a.e., n-+oo

Page 71: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.5 Systems of Sets, Step Functions, and Stone Lattices 349

f 1\ ex E £1(£), and hence f E F. By Theorem 2.4.17, F = £1(£), showing

that £ 1 (£) has the Stone property.

The fact that C(£) is a Stone lattice, follows from the result just proven,

taking Proposition 2.4.15 d) into account. 0

Our next proposition describes the approximation of (arbitrary) positive

functions by positive step functions. We strongly recommend that the reader

sketch the first three or four members of the sequence (fn)nEJN mentioned in

this proposition.

Proposition 2.5.19 -x

Take f E 1R+ . For n in IN, define

Then (fn)nEJN is an increasing sequence of positive step functions on X whose

supremum is f.

Proof. Take x EX. If f(x) = 00, then fn(x) = n for every n E IN. It follows

that (fn(X))nEJN is increasing and has supremum 00.

Now suppose that f(x) < 00. Take n > f(x). There is a unique k E IN

with k/2n ~ f(x) < (k + 1)/2n. Then fn(x) = k/2n and hence 0 ~ f(x) -

fn(x) < 1/2n. It follows that f(x) = lim fn(x). To show that (fn(X))nEJN is n-+oo

an increasing sequence, take n E IN. If f(x) ~ k/2n for some k with 1 ~ k ~

n2n , then f(x) ~ 2k/2n+1 and 1 ~ 2k ~ n2n+l. Thus there are at least twice

as many j's for which f(x) ~ j /2n+1 and 1 ~ j ~ n2n+1 as there are k's for

which f(x) ~ k/2n and 1 ~ k ~ n2n . It follows that

-x Proposition 2.5.20 Let £ be a Stone lattice in 1R . Then f 1\ aex E £ whenever f E £ and a E 1R, a > 0 .

Proof. Simply note that

f 1\ aex = a ( (~f) 1\ ex) o

Page 72: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

350 2. Elementary Integration Theory

Proposition 2.5.21 Let £ be a Stone lattice, conditionally a-completely em­

bedded in IR x .

a) For every 1 E £ and every real number a > 0, the set U ~ a} belongs

to 9\(£).

b) Every positive function belonging to £ is the supremum of an increasing

sequence of positive 9\(£) -step functions on X .

c) Every set belonging to !R(£) can be written as the union of an increasing

sequence from !R(£).

Proof. a) follows from Proposition 20 and the identity

e{f>o} = 1\ n + 1 ((f /\ aex) - (1 /\ ~ex)) - nEIN a n + 1

b) In view of a), b) follows from Proposition 19.

c) Let A E !R(£), and choose 1 E £+ such that A = U i- O}. By b),

there is an increasing sequence (fn)nEIN of positive !R(£)-step functions on X

such that 1 = V In· Set An := Un > O} for every n E IN. Note that each nEIN

An belongs to !R(£) (Corollary 12 a)). Evidently, (An)nEIN is an increasing

sequence whose union is A. o

Corollary 2.5.22 Let (X, £1, l'.) and (X, £2, (2) be closed Daniell spaces

such that £1 and £2 are Stone lattices. Then the following are equivalent.

Proof. The implication a) => b) is trivial.

b) => a). Take f E (£1)+. Then 1 is the supremum of an increasing

sequence (fn)nEIN of positive !R(£I)-step functions on X (Proposition 21 b)).

This same sequence is both an (2-sequence from £2 and an (I-sequence from

£1 . We conclude that f belongs to £2 and

An arbitrary f in £1 can be written as 1+ - f- . Thus a) follows. 0

Page 73: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.5 Systems of Sets, Step Functions, and Stone Lattices 351

Exercises

E 2.5.1 (E)

A monotone set is a set of sets, 6, with the property that if (An)nEIN is a

monotone sequence from 6, then lim An E 6 . n ..... oo

Prove the following.

(a) Let 6 be a set of sets. Then there is a monotone set 6 m such that

6 C 6 m and 6 m C 9'l for every monotone set 9'l with 6 C 9'l. 6 m is

uniquely determined by 6. 6 m is called the monotone set generated by

6.

(f3) Every a-ring is a monotone set.

(-y) If 6 is both a ring of sets and a monotone set, then 6 is a a-ring.

(6) Given the ring of sets, 9'l, 9'lm = 9'l" .

We provide some suggestions for (6) . Clearly 9'lm C 9'l" . Given A C X(9't) ,

define

6 A := {B C X(9'l) I A\B E 9'lm, B\A E 9'lm and Au BE 9'lm}.

Then, given A, B C X(9't), A E 6 8 iff B E 6 A . Given a monotone se­

quence (An)nEIN from 6 A, lim An E 6 A . Hence 6 A is a monotone set. For n-+oo

A E 9't, 9'l C 6 A, and so 9'lm C 6 A . Consequently, if A E 9'l and B E 9'lm , then B E 6 A , and so A E 6 8 . As a result 9'lm C 6 8 whenever B E 9'lm, showing that 9'lm is a ring of sets. Using (-y), 9'l" c 9'lm.

A conditionally monotone set is a set of sets, 6, with the property that

n An E 6 whenever (An)nEIN is a decreasing sequence from 6 and U An E nEIN nEIN

6 whenever (An)nEIN is an increasing bounded sequence from 6. By analogy to (a)-(8) , the following statements hold.

(0:') Let 6 be a set of sets. Then there is a conditionally monotone set 6 mb

such that 6 C 6 mb and 6 mb C 9't for every conditionally monotone set

9'l with 6 C 9't. 6 mb is uniquely determined by 6. 6 mb is called the

conditionally monotone set generated by 6.

(f3') Every 6-ring is a conditionally monotone set.

("(') If 6 is a ring of sets and a conditionally monotone set, then 6 is a

6-ring.

(6') Given a ring of sets, 9't, 9'lmb = 9'l6 .

Page 74: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

352 2. Elementary Integration Theory

2.6 Positive Measures

We begin with the definitions and elementary properties of various kinds of set

mappings, in particular, positive measures.

Definition 2.6.1 Let (5 be a set of sets. A mapping I-" : (5 -+ 1R is said to

be:

a) additive, if given A, B E (5 with Au BE (5 and An B = 0,

I-"(A u B) = I-"(A) + I-"(B) ;

b) positive, if I-"(A) ;::: 0 for every A E (5 ;

c) increasing, if it is increasing as a mapping from the ordered set (5 to the

ordered set 1R;

d) nullcontinuous, if

for every decreasing sequence (An)nEIN from (5 with

If !1t is a ring of sets and I-" : !1t -+ 1R is an additive, positive, nullcontinu­

ous mapping, then I-" is called a positive measure on !1t. A positive measure

space (a positive 8- or a-measure space) is a triple (X, 9t, 1-") where X is

a set, !1t is a set-ring (a 8-ring or a a-ring, respectively) on X, and I-" is a

positive measure on !1t. o

Proposition 2.6.2 Let I-" : !1t -+ 1R be an additive mapping on the ring of

sets !1t. Then:

a) 1-"(0) = o.

b) If (A.).El is a finite disjoint family from !1t, then

c) Given A, B E!1t with A c B,

I-"(B\A) = I-"(B) - I-"(A) .

Page 75: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.6 Positive Measures 353

d) J1- is positive iff it is increasing.

e) For all A, B E 9\,

and if J1- is positive, then

Proof. a) follows from the identity

b) can easily be proved by complete induction on the number of elements

in I. Observe that U A. = 0, so that b) follows from a) in case 1= 0. tE0

c) Note that B is the disjoint union of A and B\A. Since J1- is additive,

and c) follows.

d) If J1- is positive and A c B, then

and the inequality

follows from c) . Conversely, if J1- is increasing, then it follows from a) that

for every A in 9\.

e) Since Au B is the disjoint union of A and B\A, we have

J1-(A U B) = J1-(A) + J1-(B\A) .

Writing B as the disjoint union of B n A and B\A, we have

and e) follows. o

Page 76: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

354 2. Elementary Integration Theory

Proposition 2.6.3 Let p, : 9't --t 1R be a positive, additive mapping on the

ring of sets 9't. Then the following are equivalent.

a) p, is nullcontinuous.

b) inf P,(An) = 0 for every decreasing sequence (An)nEIN from 9't with nEIN

n An = 0. nEIN

c) For every increasing sequence (An)nEIN from 9't, if U An belongs to 9't, nEIN

then

d) For every decreasing sequence (Bn)nEIN from 9't, if n Bn belongs to nEIN

9't, then

Proof. a) - b) follows from the fact that p, is increasing.

b) ~ c). Mimic the proof of Proposition 2.2.7 b) ~ c).

c) ~ d). Let (Bn)nEIN be a decreasing sequence from 9't and assume that

B:= n Bn nEIN

belongs to 9't. The sequence (B1 \Bn)nEIN is increasing, lies in 9't and its union

belongs to 9't:

nEIN nEIN

From c) we conclude that

Hence

from which it follows that

Page 77: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.6 Positive Measures 355

d) ::::} b) is trivial. o

For positive set mappings, nullcontinuity and finite additivity together are

equivalent to countable additivity:

Theorem 2.6.4 Let p, : !Jt -+ IR be a positive mapping on the ring of sets

!Jt. Then the following are equivalent.

a) p, is a positive measure on !Jt.

b) Countable additivity. For every countable disjoint family (A,),El from

!Jt, if U A, belongs to !Jt, then the family (p,(A,) )'ET is summable and ,EI

c) For every disjoint sequence (An)nEIN from !Jt, if U An belongs to !Jt, nEIN

then the sequence (P,(An))nEIN is summable and

Each of these assertions implies that for any countable family (A,)'ET from !Jt,

whenever both sides are defined.

Proof. a)::::} b). Let (A')'EI be a countable disjoint family from !Jt whose

union belongs to !Jt. It suffices to consider the case where I is count ably infinite.

So let cp : IN -+ I be bijective. Construct an increasing sequence from !Jt whose

union is the same as U A, by putting Bn:= U A<p(k) for every n E IN . Since ,ET k<n

p, is nullcontinuous, additive, and positive, we have

00 > p, (UA,) = p, (U Bn) = supP,(Bn) = LET nEIN nEIN

Page 78: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

356 2. Elementary Integration Theory

It follows that the sequence (Jl(Acp(k») kEIN is summable (Corollary 2.3.29) and

hence that the family (Jl(A')tEI is summable. Moreover

b) => c). This implication is evident.

c) => a). First notice that Jl(0) = o. Indeed, hypothesis c) together with

Proposition 2.3.28 a) implies that Jl(0) = lim nJl(0) , which is only possible if n .... oo

Jl(0) = o. The additivity of Jl then follows by hypothesis. We must verify that

Jl is nullcontinuous, for which we use the characterization in Proposition 3 c)

=> a). Let (An)nEIN be an increasing sequence from 9t whose union belongs

to !J't. Construct a disjoint sequence (Bn)nEIN in !J't with the same union as

the given sequence by putting Bl := Al and Bn := An \An- l for n E IN\{l}. Then

Jl (U An) = L Jl(Bn) = J~~ t Jl(Bk) = sup t Jl(Bk) = sup Jl(An) nEIN nEIN k=l nEIN k=l nEIN

as required. The reader can readily verify the final claim, observing that given a sequence

(An)nEIN in 9t,

is a disjoint sequence in 9t having the same union as (An)nEIN. o

Countable additivity appeared for the first time in the thesis of E. Borel

(1894). Next we turn to the notion of boundedness.

Definition 2.6.5 Let 9t be a ring of sets and Jl : 9t -t lR a positive additive

mapping. Then Jl is said to be

a) bounded if there is a real number a such that Jl(A) $ a for every A in

9t;

b) a-bounded if there is a countable family (A.)tEl from 9t with

inf Jl(A\A.) = 0 tEl

for every A in 9t.

Page 79: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.6 Positive Measures 357

A positive measure space (X, 9l, Il) is called bounded or a -bounded iff the

measure Il is bounded or a-bounded, respectively. 0

Our first observation is an obvious consequence of the definitions.

Proposition 2.6.6 Every positive measure space (X, 9l, Il) for which the pair

(X,9l) is a-finite, is a-bounded. 0

We want to show that bounded positive measures are always a-bounded

and that positive measures on a-rings are always bounded. The proofs make

no use of nullcontinuity, so we formulate somewhat more general results first.

Proposition 2.6.7 Let 9l be a ring of sets, and Il : 9l -+ 1R a positive,

additive mapping.

a) If Il is bounded, then Il is a-bounded.

b) If 9l is a a-ring, then Il assumes a maximum on 9l; i.e., there is a set

B E 9l such that

sup Il(A) = Il(B) . (1) AE!)l

c) If 9l is a a-ring and B is any element of 9l for which (1) holds, then

Il(A \B) = 0 for every A E 9l.

Proof. a) Put

a := sup Il(A) AE!)l

and let (An)nEIN be a sequence from the set-ring 9l such that

Take A E 9l. Then A\An = (AUAn)\An and hence

for every n. Thus

Equality must hold throughout, so

Page 80: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

358 2. Elementary Integration Theory

b) With Q and (An)nEIN as in the proof of a), put

Since BE 9t,

B:= U An. nEIN

Q = sup J.L(An) S; J.L(B) S; Q.

nEIN

It follows that Q = J.L(B) .

c) Using Proposition 2 c) and with Q as in the proof of a), we have

Q = J.L(B) S; J.L(B) + J.L(A\B) = J.L(A U B) S; Q

so J.L(A\B) = O. o

Corollary 2.6.8 Every bounded positive measure is a-bounded. Every positive

measure on a a-ring is bounded. 0

Example 2.6.9 Let 9t be a ring of sets and take x E X(9t). Define

Then IS~ is a bounded positive measure on 9t, called the Dirac measure

(1926) on 9t concentrated in x. 0

Example 2.6.10 Let;J' be the set of all finite subsets of X. Define

X:;J'--tlR, At---t LeA(x). xEA

Then (X,;J', X) is a positive IS-measure space and for A E ;J', X(A) is the

number of elements of A. For this reason, X is called the counting measure

on X. The measure X is bounded iff X is finite, and X is a-bounded iff X

is countable. o

Given a positive measure space (X, 9t, J.L) , we want to define a functional

e,.. on .c~ which is naturally associated with the positive measure J.L, where by

"naturally associated" we mean that

for every A in 9t. If

Page 81: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.6 Positive Measures 359

is an 9\-step function on X , linearity requires that

f}J(J) = L Q.JL(A.) . (2) .EI

But if (2) is to be used as a definition for f}J' we need to know that the value of f}J (J) does not depend on the particular representation used for f.

Proposition 2.6.11 Let (X, 9\, JL) be a positive measure space. Suppose that

(A.).E1 and (BK.)K.EK are finite families from 9\ and that (Q.).EI and ((3K.)K.EK are families from 1R such that

L Q.eA, = L (3K.eB •. • EI K.EK

Then

Proof. First suppose that

We show that

By Proposition 2.5.4, there are a finite disjoint family (CAhEL of nonempty

sets in 9\ and an associated family (L.).EI of subsets of L such that for every

LEI,

AEL, AEL,

Take A ELand choose a fixed x E CA • Then

Thus

Page 82: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

360 2. Elementary Integration Theory

.EI .EI AEL,

The general case follows from our special case by considering the 9t-step

function

2: a.eA, - 2: /3"eB •. o .EI "EK

Theorem 2.6.12 Given a positive measure space (X, 9t, J-t), there is exactly

one functional C; on £~ for which (X, £~, C;) is a Daniell space and

(3)

for every A E 9t. This functional is given by

.EI .EI

Proof By Proposition 11, C; (J) does not depend on the representation of f.

The functional C; is evidently linear and satisfies (3). Moreover, the positivity

of C; follows from that of J-t, taking Proposition 2.5.11 a),b) into account. The

uniqueness of the functional is trivial.

It remains to be verified that C; is nullcontinuous. Let (In)nEIN be a de­

creasing sequence from £~ with

/\ fn = O. nEIN

Take € > O. For each n E IN, put An := {fn > €} and A := {II > O}. By

Corollary 2.5.12 a), A and all the An's are in 9t. Since (An)nEIN is decreasing

and n An = 0 , we conclude that nEIN

Put

Then

a:=supfl(x). xEX

Page 83: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.6 Positive Measures 361

for every n E IN . Choose m E IN such that JL(Am) < c. Then

for each n ~ m. Since c is arbitrary,

o

Definition 2.6.13 For (X, 9l, JL) a positive measure space, the functional e;

and the Daniell space (X, £~, e;) described in Theorem 12 are called the func­

tional associated with the measure JL and the Daniell space assocciated with

the measure space (X,!>l, JL) , respectively. 0

The following easily verified proposition describes the reverse situation.

Proposition 2.6.14 Let (X, £, £) be a Daniell space, and define

Then (X, !>l(£) , JLt ) is a positive measure space. o

-x Definition 2.6.15 For:F c IR. and e : :F ~ IR., the mapping

is called the set mapping induced (on 9l(:F)) bye. If (X, £, f) is a Daniell

space and JL is the set mapping induced on 9l(£) bye, then we call (X, 9l(£) , JL) the positive measure space induced by (X, £, e) and JL the positive meaBure

induced bye. 0

The Daniell spaces associated with positive measure spaces always have the

Stone property and their Riesz lattices always consist of step functions. Thus

there is no hope of recovering a Daniell space from its induced positive mea­

sure space unless these two conditions hold. No other conditions are required,

however, as we see from the following theorem.

Theorem 2.6.16 Suppose that (X, £, e) is a Daniell space and £ is a Stone

lattice whose elements are step functions. Then there is a uniquely determined

positive measure space whose associated Daniell space is (X, £, e), namely the

positive measure space induced by (X, £, £) .

Page 84: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

362 2. Elementary Integration Theory

Proof Denote by ,l the set mapping induced on !R(.c) by I. According to

Theorem 2.5.17, !R(.c) is the uniquely determined set-ring !R for which .c

is the set of !R-step functions. By Proposition 14, (X, !R(.c) , Ji) is a positive

measure space. The definition ,i(A) = l(eA) shows that (X, !R(.c) , ,i) is a positive measure space with which the Daniell space (X,.c, I) is associated. 0

Example 2.6.17 Consider counting measure X on the set X (Example 10).

Then f E 1Rx is an ~-step function iff {f "I O} is finite. For such a function

f, we have

Ix(f) = Ix ( L f(x)e{x}) = L f(x)lx(e{x}) = XE{f#O} XE{!#O}

= L f(x)x({x})= L f(x)=Lf(x). xE{!#O} XE{f#O} xEX

Note that we already know the closure of the Daniell space (X, .c~, Ix) as­

sociated with (X,~, X): We showed in Example 2.3.22 that the closure is

(X, e1 (X), E). 0

Definition 2.6.18 The positive measure space (X,!R, p,) is called closed iff

i) U An E!R for every increasing sequence (An)nEIN from !R with nEIN

sup P,(An) < 00; nEIN

ii) I.l3(A) C !R for every A E !R with p,(A) = O. o

Proposition 2.6.19 If (X,!R, p,) is a closed positive measure space, then !R is a 6-ring.

Proof It suffices to show that the intersection of every decreasing sequence

from !R belongs to !R. This follows easily from the formula

o

Theorem 2.6.20 Let (X,!R, /-l) be a positive measure space. Then the follow­

ing are equivalent.

a) (X,!R, p,) is closed.

Page 85: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.6 Positive Measures 363

b) (X, v:t, Jl) is induced by a closed Daniell space (X,.c, f) for which .c is a

Stone lattice.

Moreover, if these equivalent conditions are satisfied, then there is only one

closed Daniell space with the Stone property which induces (X, v:t, Jl), namely

the closure (X, C(f;), f:) of the Daniell space (X, .c~, f;) associated with

(X, v:t, Jl) .

Proof. a)::::} b). Denote by (X, l, f) the closure of (X, .c~, f;) . By Theorem

2.5.13 b) and Proposition 2.5.18, l is a Stone lattice. We show that (X, l, i) induces (X, v:t, Jl) , that is, we must show that

v:t = v:t(l) (4)

and

(A E v:t) . (5)

The inclusion C in (4) and the equality (5) are trivial. To prove the reverse

inclusion in (4), take A E !Jt(l). There is a decreasing sequence (fn)nEIN in

(.c~)t such that fn ~ eA and (f;)t(fn) < 00 for every n E IN and such that

Given n E IN, fn = V hk for some increasing sequence (hk)kEIN from (.c~)+. kEIN

Put

(k E IN , m E IN\ { 1 } ) .

Then B km E v:t and for every m ~ 2 ,

Hence U Bkm E !Jt and, in view of Proposition 19, kEIN

An := Un ~ 1} = n U Bkm E!Jt.

By Proposition 19 again,

m;:::2 kEIN

B:= n An E v:t. nEIN

Page 86: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

364 2. Elementary Integration Theory

Now A C Band

B\A C { A fn =I eA} E ')1(£). nEIN

If A E ')1(£) , then

I-'(B) = f(eB) = f(eA) = O.

Since (X, 9t, 1-') is closed, it follows that A E 9t. If A E 9t(£) is arbitrary,

then by the preceding argument B\A E 9t. Thus

A = B\(B\A) E 9t,

proving (4).

b) ::::} a) is a consequence of the definition of closed Daniell space and of

Corollary 2.2.12. For the final claim, let (X, C, £) be a closed Daniell space with the Stone

property which induces (X, 9t, 1-'). Then

9t(C) = 9t = 9t(£)

and

for every A E 9t. Corollary 2.5.22 b) ::::} a) implies that

(X, C, £) = (X, £, l) . o

Corollary 2.6.21 Let (X, 9t, 1-') be a closed measure space.

a) For every nonempty countable family (A.).EI from 9t which is directed

up, the conditions

sup I-'(A.) < 00 .EI

and

are equivalent and imply that

I-' (u A.) = sup I-'(A.) . • EI .EI

Page 87: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.6 Positive Measures 365

b) For every nonempty countable family (A.).EI from !:R which is directed

down, the set n A. belongs to !:R and .EI

c) For every countable disjoint family (A).EI from !:R, the conditions

and

are equivalent and imply that

d) If (An)nEIN is a sequence from !:R that is bounded above in !:R, then the

sets

'.p(X) lim sup An and '.p(X) lim inf An n-+oo n-+oo

both belong to !:R. If, in addition, there is a set A satisfying

A = '.p(X) lim An, n-+oo

then A belongs to !:R and

Proof Each assertion can be verified by using the map A t-t eA to translate

the assertion in question into a familiar fact about closed Daniell spaces. In par­

ticular, a) and b) follow from Theorem 2.2.17. c) is a consequence of Theorems 4 b) and 2.3.31 a) :::}b). Finally, d) follows from Corollary 2.2.20 and Theorem

2.2.21. 0

Page 88: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

366 2. Elementary Integration Theory

Exercises

E 2.6.1 (E)

A semi-ring is a non empty set of sets, 9t, such that for A, B E 9t there are

finite disjoint families (A.),El and (B),);"EL from 9t with An B = U A, and 'El

A\B= U B).. ).EL

Prove that

(a) given the semi-ring, 9t, A E !)l,. iff there is a finite disjoint family (A')'EI

from 9t with A = U A, . 'El

(Let <5 denote the set of all unions of finite disjoint families from 9t.

Given A, B E <5 , first show that A n B E <5 , next prove that A \B E <5 and finally show that A U B E <5.)

We next describe an important example of a semi-ring. Let A i= 0 be an

interval of IR containing neither 00 nor -00. Let a be the left endpoint of A

and b its right endpoint. Note that -00 ::; a < b ::; 00. Given x, yEA with

x::; y, put

and let

{ [x,y[

[x,y 1:= [x,b]

if y i= b

if y = b,

J:={[x,yl Ix,yEA, x::;y}.

(J3) J is a semi-ring. The elements of Jr (i.e. the finite unions of intervals in

J) are called the interval forms on A.

Let 9t be a semi-ring. By a content on 9t we mean a function, J.L : 9t --+ IR , such that if A E 9t and if (A')'EI is a finite disjoint family from 9t with

A = U A, , then J.L(A) = ~ J.L(A,). J.L is called a-additive if given any disjoint 'El tEl

sequence (An)nEIN from 9t with U An E 9t, J.L( U An) = ~ /l(An). nEIN nEIN nEIN

Prove the following.

(-y) Given a content, J.L, on 9t, there is exactly one additive function ii on

!)l,. with iil!Jt = J.L .

(6) If J.L is a positive content, then ii is positive.

(c:) If J.L is a positive a-additive content, then ii is a positive measure.

Page 89: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.6 Positive Measures 367

(() Given two additive functions on ~,J.l and II, such that J.l1!>t = 1I1!>t, then J.l = II.

(17) If 0 E ~ then each a-additive real function on ~ is a content.

For the proof of (c), we wish to show that jj is a-additive. First take

A E ~ and let (An)nEIN be a disjoint sequence in ~ with A = U An. nEIN

There is a finite disjoint family (B')'EI from ~ such that A = U B,. For ,EI

each LEI then, B, = U (An n B,). Thus for each n E IN and LEI, there nEIN

is a finite disjoint family from ~ whose union is An n B,. Bearing this in

mind, there are, for each LEI, a disjoint sequence (D,k)kEIN from ~ and a kn+l-l

sequence (kn)nEIN from IN such that kl = 1 and AnnB, = U D,k, so that k=kn

B, = U D,k. Use this to conclude that kEIN

J.l(B,) = E jj(An n B.), and finally, nEIN

that jj(A) = E J.l(An). nEIN

The general case is now an easy consequence of what has been proved.

E 2.6.2 (C)

Ulam Sets (S. Ulam, 1930) Let ~ be a ring of sets. A positive measure J.l on

~ is called a two-valued positive measure on ~ iff J.l(~) = {O, a}, a i- O. A set X is called a weak Ulam set (an Ulam set) iff there is no positive two-valued

measure J.l (no strictly positive measure J.l) on I.13(X) such that J.l( {x}) = 0 for every x EX.

Prove the following.

(a) For every set X, the following are equivalent.

(ad X is a weak Ulam set.

(a2) There is no nontrivial 8-stable ultrafilter on X.

(If ~ is a nontrivial 8-stable ultrafilter on X, consider the map

J.l: I.13(X) ---+ 1R, A t--+ { ~ if A E ~

if A ~~.

If J.l is a two-valued positive measure on I.13(X) , consider

~ := {A c X I J.l(A) i- O} .)

({3) If X is a weak Ulam set, then every set with the cardinality of X is also

a weak Ulam set.

Page 90: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

368 2. Elementary Integration Theory

(-y) Every countable set is a weak Ulam set.

(8) Every subset of a weak Ulam set is a weak Ulam set.

(f) If I is a weak Ulam set and if (X,),El is a family of weak Ulam sets, then

U X, is a weak Ulam set. ,E/

(Put Z := {( L, x) I LEI, x E X.}. U X, has the same cardinality as some ,EI

subset of Z. Thus it is sufficient to show that Z is a weak Ulam set and then

to apply (13) and (8). So let p, be a two-valued measure on I.P(Z) with the

property that p,( {z}) = 0 whenever z E Z. For LEI, put Z, := {(L, x) I x E

X,} . Thus, for each L, Z, has the same cardinality as X, and is, consequently,

a weak Ulam set. Thus p,lz, = 0 for LEI. Given J c I, define v( J) := p,( U Z,). Then v is a positive measure on

,EJ

I.P(I) with V({L}) = 0 for every LEI (as has just been shown). But I is, by

hypothesis, a weak Ulam set. Thus p,(Z) = v(I) = 0, showing that Z is a weak

Ulam set.)

() Let X be a set and p, a positive two-valued measure on I.P(X). Let Y be

a weak Ulam set and (AY)YEY a family from I.P(X) such that p,(Ay) = 0

for every y E Y. Then p,( U Ay) = O. yEY

(First assume that (AY)YEY is a disjoint family, and consider the positive

measure

v : I.P(Y) ~ IR, B f---+ p, (U A y ) .

yEB

For the proof of the general case, construct a disjoint family (BY)YEY of

subsets of X such that U By = U Ay.) yEY yEY

('17) The analogous assertions to (13) - (() hold for Ulam sets.

(19) If X is an Ulam set with cardinality Net, then every set with cardinality

Net+! is an Ulam set.

(For every ordinal " define A"f := {f3 I 13 an ordinal, 13 < ,}. A"f and , always have the same cardinality. Denote by , the first ordinal with the

cardinality of Net+! . Then for every 13 < "

A"f = {f3} U AiJ U {a E A"f I 13 < a} .

Page 91: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.6 Positive Measures 369

Let f..t be a positive measure on ~(A"() such that f..t( {,B}) = 0 for each ,B E A"( .

For each ,B E A"( , let ({)(j : A(j --+ X be an injective mapping. For ,B E A"( and

x E X, define A(,B,x) := {a E A"( I ,B < a, ({)o(,B) = x}. Then for each

x EX, (A(,B, X))(jEA"( is a disjoint family of subsets of A"(. Consequently for

each x EX, {A(,B,x) I f..t(A(,B,x)) > O} is countable. Thus

{(,B, x) E A"( x X I f..t(A(,B,x» > O}

has a cardinal strictly smaller than No+l . Hence, for some fj E A,,(, f..t(A(fj, x» =

o for every x EX. Thus f..t( U A (fj, x» = 0 since X is an Ulam set. But A,ij xEX

is also an Ulam set, and we conclude

f..t(A"() = f..t( {fj}) + f..t(A,ij) + f..t( {,B E A"( I fj < ,B}) ::;

::; f..t( {fj}) + f..t(A,ij) + f..t (U A(fj, x») = 0 xEX

showing that f..t(A"() = 0.)

(L) Let X be a weak Ulam set and f..t a strictly positive measure on ~(X)

such that f..t({x}) = 0 for every x EX. Then for each cEnt, c > 0,

there is a subset A of X with 0 < f..t(A) < c.

(Using Zorn's Lemma, there is a filter ~ on X, maximal with respect to

the property that f..t(F) > 0 whenever F E ~. Prove that for every C C X

either C E ~ or X\C E ~. Hence ~ is an ultrafilter. But then there is a

decreasing sequence (Fn)nEIN from ~ such that n Fn = 0.) nEIN

(K) If nt is an Ulam set, then so is every weak Ulam set.

(Let X be a weak Ulam set and f..t a positive measure on ~(X) such that

f..t({x}) = 0 for every x EX. Using (L), construct a sequence (fn)nEIN of

mappings fn : INn --+ ~(X) recursively such that for each n E IN:

i) (fn(k)hElNn is a disjoint family with U fn(k) = X; kElNn

ii) f..t(fn(k)) < 1/2n whenever k E INn;

iii) fn+l(k,j) C fn(k) whenever k E INn and j E IN.

For every 9 E ININ , define

Ag := n fn(g(l), g(2), ... , g(n» . nEIN

Page 92: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

370 2. Elementary Integration Theory

Then Il(Ag) = 0 whenever 9 E 1NIN. But X = U Ag, and (1]) implies our 9EIN IN

assertion. )

(A) If we assume the Continuum Hypothesis (i.e., that 2No = Nd , then weak

Ulam sets and Ulam sets coincide.

Page 93: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.7 Closure, Completion, and Integrals for Positive Measure Spaces 371

2.7 Closure, Completion, and Integrals

for Positive Measure Spaces

Our first goal is to show that every positive measure space has a smallest closed

extension.

Proposition 2.7.1 Let J-L be a positive measure on the set-ring ~ and

let Xl> X 2 be sets containing X(~). For k = 1,2, let (Xk, £k, £k) denote

the Daniell space associated with the positive measure space (Xk'~' J-L) and

(Xk, ~k' J-Lk) the closed positive measure space induced by (Xk, £(£k)' £k)' Then

we have the following.

a) U =I- O} C X(~) whenever f E £(£1) U £(£2) .

b) (~1' J-Ld = (~2' J-L2).

Proof. a) Take k E {1,2} and f E £(£k)' We may assume that f ~ O. There

is an increasing sequence (fn)nEIN in £k with f::; V fn. By Proposition nEIN

2.5.12 a), Un> O} E ~ for every n E IN. Thus

U =I- O} C U Un > O} C X(~) . nEIN

b) Given f E £(£d, define

{ f(x)

x~ 0

if x E X(~)

otherwise.

Note that

for every A E ~. Thus, using a), it is easily verified that the mapping

is an isomorphism of ordered sets such that

for every f E £(£1) . The claim now follows. o

Page 94: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

372 2. Elementary Integration Theory

Proposition 2.7.2 Let p, be a positive measure on the set-ring ~. Let

(X(~), ~(p,), J1) denote the closed positive measure space induced by the closure

of the Daniell space associated with (X(~),~, p,). Then for each X :::) X(~) ,

(X, ~(p,), J1) is the smallest closed positive measure space extending (X,~, p,) .

Proof Let X :::) X(~), and let (X, £, i) be the Daniell space associ­

ated with the positive measure space (X,~, p,). According to Proposition 1,

(X, ~(p,), J1) is the closed positive measure space induced by (X, C(f), f) . Ev­

idently (X,~, p,) ~ (X,~, (p,), J1). Now let (X, !R', p,') be an arbitrary closed

positive measure space for which (~, p,) ~ (~', IL') . By Theorem 2.6.20, there

is a unique closed Daniell space (X, £', i') with the Stone property and such

that (X,~', p,') is the positive measure space induced by (X, C', £') . It follows

that

(X, £, f) ~ (X, £', £')

and therefore

(X,C(f),f) ~ (X,C',f').

Hence

o

We are now ready for the following definition.

Definition 2.7.3 (Measure-space closure) Let p, be a positive measure on

the set-ring !R. Then (X(~), 9l(p,) , J1) denotes the closed positive measure

space induced by the closure of the Daniell space associated with (X(!R),~, p,). We call Ji the closure of p, and (~(p,), J1) the closure of (~, p,). For each

X :::) X(!R) , we call (X, ~(p,), Ji) the closure of (X,!R, p,) . 0

Corollary 2.7.4 For every positive measure space (X,~, p,) , if (X, 6, /I) is a

positive measure space extending (X,~, p,) and if 6 C ~(p,)<T' then 6 C ~(p,)

and

/I = Jile.

In particular, Ji and JiI!Jt6 are the only positive measures on ~(p,) and ~6,

respectively, that extend p,.

Page 95: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.7 Closure, Completion, and Integrals for Positive Measure Spaces 373

Proof We have

(X, 9l, /-l) ~ (X, <5, v) ~ (X, 9l(v), v)

and (X, 9l(v), v) is closed. It follows that

(X, 9l(/-l), p;) ~ (X, 9l(v), v) .

In particular,

Take A E <5. By hypothesis, A belongs to 9l(/-l)u. According to Propositions

2.6.19 and 2.5.9, we may choose an increasing sequence (An)nEIN from 9l(/-l)

whose union is A. Using nullcontinuity, we see that

sup M(An) = sup v(An) = v(A) < 00. nEIN nEIN

Hence A belongs to 9l(/-l) and v(A) = v(A) = M(A) . o

Some authors require the domains for positive measures to be a-rings. But

in view of Corollary 4, allowing arbitrary set-rings as domains does not expand

the collection of closed positive measure spaces. What is gained is greater ease

in defining a particular measure with which one wants to work.

We now turn our attention to extensions of measures induced by integrals.

Definition 2.7.5 (Measure-space integral and completion) Given a posi­

tive measure space (X, 9l, /-l), let (X, £(X, /-l), lx,/J) be the Daniell space asso­

ciated with (X, 9l, /-l). Then

For f E £1 (X, /-l), we define

1 f:= r fd/-l:= r f(x)d/-l(x):= r f x,/J Jx Jx Jtx.~

and call Ixfd/-l the /-l-integral of f. For A E £(X, /-l), we define

Page 96: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

374 2. Elementary Integration Theory

and call J-tx (A) the J-t-measure of A in X.

Functions belonging to £l(X, J-t) are called J-t-integrable junctions on X

and functions belonging to N(X, J-t) are called J-t-null junctions on X. Sim­

ilarly, sets belonging to £(X, J-t) are called J-t-integrable sets in X or J-t­

integrable subsets of X and sets belonging to lJ1(X, J-t) are called J-t-null sets

in X or J-t-null subsets of X .

The integral (X,£l(X,J-t),Jx,/-J is called the integral for (X,~,J-t) or the

integral on X associated with J-t.

The closed positive measure space (X, £(X, J-t), J-tX) is called the comple­

tion of (X,~, J-t) and J-tx is called the completion of J-t on X or simply the

completion of J-t. If (X,~, J-t) = (X, £(X, J-t), J-tX ), then we call the measure

space (X,~, J-t) complete and we say that J-t is a complete measure on X.

We call hi -sequences J-t-sequences, that is, a monotone sequence (fn)nEIN x." from £l(X, J-t) for which Ux fndJ-t)nEIN is bounded in 1R is a J-t-sequence.

Monotone sequences (An)nEIN from £(X,J-t) for which (J-tX(An))nEIN is bounded

in 1R will also be called J-t-sequences.

Finally, a property P that refers to elements of X is said to hold J-t-almost

everywhere (J-t-a.e.) iff it holds £x,/J-a.e. We write P J-t-a.e. and P(x) J-t­

a.e., respectively, for P £x,/J-a.e. and P(x) £x,/J-a.e. 0

Theorem 2.7.6 (Main Theorem on Measure-Space Completion and In­

tegral) Let (X,~, J-t) be a positive measure space and (X, £, £) its associated

Daniell space. Then we have the following.

a) (X, £l(X, J-t), Ix) is a closed Daniell space with the Stone property ex­

tending (X, £, £) .

b) (X, £(X, J-t)' J-tX) is a closed positive measure space extending (X,~, J-t) .

c)

-x -= {j E 1R I feA E N(£(£)), V A E ~}

-x = {j E 1R I feA E N(X,J-t), VA E~}.

Page 97: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.7 Closure, Completion, and Integrals for Positive Measure Spaces 375

d) IJl(X, Jl) = 1Jl(£l(X, Jl))

= {B E £(X,Jl) I JlX(B) = O}

= {B C X IBn A E 1Jl(£(£)), V A E 9l}

= {B C X IBn A E IJl(X, Jl), V A E 9l}

= {B C X I JlX(B n A) = 0, V A E 9l}.

e) If f belongs to £l(X, Jl) , then there are disjoint sets Band C such that

f = feB + fee, BE !R(£(£)), C E IJl(X,Jl).

Moreover, feB belongs to £(£) for every B in !R(£(£)).

f) A set A belongs to £(X, Jl) iff there are disjoint sets Band C such that

If A belongs to £(X, Jl), then An B belongs to 9l(Jl) for every B in

9l(Jl) .

g) If f belongs to £1 (X, Jl), then there are a sequence (An)nEIN from 91

and a set B belonging to IJl(X, Jl) such that

{J # O} C (U An) U B. nEIN

The sequence (An)nEIN can be chosen to be increasing or disjoint.

h) If A belongs to £(X, Jl), then there are a sequence (An)nEIN from 91 and

a set B belonging to IJl(X, Jl) such that

A C (U An) uB. nEIN

The sequence (An)nEIN can be chosen to be increasing or disjoint.

i) For every f belonging to £l(X, Jl) ,

r fdJl = sup r feAdJl + inf r feAdJl. ix AE<Jtix AE<Jtix

For every positive f in £ 1 (X, Jl) ,

r fdJl = sup r feAdJl. i x AE<Jt i X

Page 98: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

376 2. Elementary Integration Theory

j) For every B belonging to £(X, p,) ,

p,X (B) = sup Jlx (A n B) . AE9t

k) For every B eX, B E IJ1(X, p,) n !Jl(p,) iff for every c > 0 there is a

disjoint sequence (An)nEIN from !)l such that

Be U An and LJl(An) < c. nEIN nEIN

f) For every B eX, B E IJ1(X, p,) iff for every A E !Jl and every c > 0

there is a sequence (An)nEIN from !)l such that

An B c U An and L Jl(An) < c. nEIN nEIN

Proof. Note that 6i(C) =!)l in this instance.

a) follows from Theorem 2.4.7 and Proposition 2.5.18.

b) is a consequence of a) and Theorem 2.6.20 b) => a) .

c) ,d) can be deduced from Propositions 2.2.11, 2.4.4 d) and 2.4.15 d).

e) - h) follow from Proposition 2.4.15.

i),j) are consequences of Proposition 2.4.16.

k) Suppose that BE IJ1(X, Jl) n !)l(Jl) and take c > O. There is an f E Ct

with f ;::: eB and ft(f) < 10/3. Moreover, there is an increasing sequence

(fn)nEIN in C+ whose supremum is f. Given n E 1N, put Bn := Un ;::: 1/2} .

Then (Bn)nEIN is an increasing sequence in !Jl such that Be U Bn and since nEIN

eBn ::; 2fn ::; 2f, we see that Jl(Bn) ::; 2 Ix fdJl < ~c for every n E 1N .

Define Al := Bl and An := Bn \Bn- I whenever n > 1. Then U An = nEIN

n U Bn. Moreover, since P,(Bn) = L p,(Ak) for every n E 1N ,

nEIN k=1

For the converse, take c > 0 and let (An)nEIN be a sequence in !)l satisfying

the conditions stated in k). Then (0, e U An) is an c-bracket for eB relative nEIN

to f. Since c is arbitrary, eB E C(f) and p,(B) = f(eB) = O.

1) In view of f), An B E IJ1(X, Jl) n !)l(Jl) whenever B E IJ1(X, Jl) and

A E !)l. Hence 1) follows from d) and k). o

Page 99: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.7 Closure, Completion, and Integrals for Positive Measure Spaces 377

Proposition 2.7.7 Let J-l be a positive measure on the set-ring ryt, and take

sets X, Y with

X J Y J X (ryt) .

Then we have the following.

a) The set X\Y belongs to IJl(X, J-l) .

b) IJl(X, J-l) = {A c X I AnY E IJl(Y, J-l)}.

c) N(X, J-l) = {J E lIr' I fly E N(y, J-l)} .

d) £(X, J-l) = {A c X I AnY E £(Y, J-l)}.

e) .c l (X, J-l) = {J E lRx I fly E .cl(y, J-l)} .

f) For every A E £(X, J-l) , J-lx (A) = J-lY (A n Y) .

g) For every f E .c l (X, J-l) , JxfdJ-l = Jy flydJ-l.

Proof. a) For every A in ryt,(X\Y)nA=0.ByTheorem6d), X\Y belongs

to IJl(X,J-l).

b) We write (X,.c(X),£x) and (Y,.c(Y),£y) for the Daniell spaces asso­

ciated with the positive measure spaces (X, ryt, J-l) and (V, ryt, J-l) , respectively.

Take A E IJl(X, /1) . In other words, suppose that

An BE 1Jl(£(£x))

for each B in ryt. From Proposition 1 and Theorem 6 d), we have

1Jl(£( £ x)) = 1Jl(£( £y)) c '-P(Y) .

It follows that

(A n Y) n BE 1Jl(£(£y)) (1)

for each B in ryt, hence that AnY belongs to IJl(Y, It) . Suppose, conversely,

that A is a subset of X whose intersection with Y belongs to IJl(Y, /1) . Then

(1) holds for each B in ryt, and AnY must belong to IJl(X, It) . Since A\Y

also belongs to IJl(X, It) , by a), we conclude that A belongs to IJl(X, It).

c) Assertion c) follows from b) .

d).f) Take A E '£(X, /1) . According to Theorem 6 f), there are disjoint sets

B E ryt(fl) and C E IJl(X, J-l) such that A = B u C. By b), en Y belongs

Page 100: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

378 2. Elementary Integration Theory

to !J1(Y, f.t) . Invoking Theorem 6 f) again, we conclude that AnY belongs to

£(Y, f.t) . Moreover,

The argument in the other direction is similar.

e),g) Take IE £I(X, f.t)+. By Proposition 2.5.21 b), there is an increasing

sequence (fn)nEIN of positive £(X, f.t)-step functions such that I = V In. In nEIN

view of d), (fnIY)nEIN is an increasing sequence of £(Y, f.t)-step functions with

supremum Ily. In light of f),

sup r Inlydf.t = sup r Indf.t = r fdf.t < 00. nEINiy nEINix ix

Hence

(2)

For an arbitrary I E £1 (X, f.t) , (2) follows by decomposing I as 1= r - 1- . The argument in the other direction is similar. o

Part a) of the preceding proposition shows that £(X, f.t) differs from

£(Y,f.t) , and £l(X,f.t) differs from £l(y,f.t) , unless X = Y. Thus there is

good reason for including X in the denotations for the various objects con­

nected with measures.

We now turn to the problem of finding sufficient conditions for two positive

measure spaces to generate the same integral.

Proposition 2.7.8 Let (X, 9t, f.t) and (X, 6, 1/) be positive measure spaces

with

Suppose that lor every set A in 6 there is a countable lamily (A')'EI from 9t

such that

A\UA, E!J1(X,I/). (3) ,EI

Then

and

Page 101: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.7 Closure, Completion, and Integrals for Positive Measure Spaces 379

Proof. Let (X, £, f) be the Daniell space associated with (X, 9l, /1) . The hy­

potheses imply that

and consequently that

(X,£(f)'£):s (X,£l(X,v),l ) x,v

(4)

Now we use Theorem 6 d) to show that

91(X, /1) C 91(X, v) . (5)

Take B E 91(X, /1) . Given A E 6, let (A.)LEI be a countable family from 9l

for which (3) holds. For every tEl, B n AL belongs to 91(£( t')) and hence, in

view of (4), to 91(X, v). Thus U (B n A L ) E 91(X, v). Since LEI

AnB c (U(B n A.)) U (A\UA) LEI LEI

we conclude that An B E 91(X, v) . By Theorem 6 d), B E 91(X, v) .

Now take f E £l(X, /1). Then f = 9 /1-a.e. for some 9 E £(f). By (5),

f = 9 v-a.e. In view of (4), f E £l(X,V) and

lfdv = 19dV = Z(g) = lfd/1,

proving the first assertion of the proposition. The second assertion follows from

the first. D

Corollary 2.7.9 Let (X, 9l, /1) and (X, 6, v) be positive measure spaces. If

and

then (X, 9l, /1) and (X, 6, v) have the same integral and the same completion:

Page 102: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

380 2. Elementary Integration Theory

Proof. Take A E 6. By hypothesis, A belongs to £(X, p,). Theorem 6 h)

ensures the existence of a countable family (AL)LEI from ~ such that

A\UAL E 91(X,p,). LEI

In order to apply Proposition 8, we show that

A\UAL E 91(X,v). (6) LEI

Since ~ C £(X, v) and £(X, v) is a 6-ring (Proposition 2.6.19), the set

A\ U A L, which can be written as n (A\A) , must belong to £(X, v). Ac-LEI LEI

cording to Theorem 6 f), there are disjoint sets B in ~(v) and C in 91(X, v)

such that

A\UA=BUC. LEI

Corollary 4 implies that

from which we conclude that B belongs to £(X, p,) and ILX (B) = YJ(B) . Since

B is a subset of A \ U A , which is a p,-null subset of X, B must belong to LEI

91(X, v) . Consequently, (6) holds.

Applying Proposition 8, we conclude that

Reyersing the argument, we obtain the opposite inequality and the corollary

follows. 0

Corollary 2.7.10 Let (X,~, p,) and (X, 6, v) be positive measure spaces. If

~ C 6,s C £(X,IL)

and

XI X p, 6,\ = V 16.

then (X,~, p,) and (X, 6, v) have the same integral and the same completion.

Page 103: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.7 Closure, Completion, and Integrals for Positive Measure Spaces 381

and

Using Corollary 9, we conclude that

On the other hand,

(6, /.I) ~ (£(X, v), VX),

Using Corollary 9 again, we have

(X, £(X, /.I), /.IX) = (X, £(X, v), VX) .

The corollary follows. o

A minor consequence is the idem potence of measure-space integrals and

completions.

Corollary 2.7.11 For every positive measure space (X,~,J.l)

Proof. Apply Corollary 10 using (X, 6, /.I) := (X, £(X, J.l)' J.lX) . o

We now investigate consequences arising for measure-space integrals when

the underlying measure space satisfies various boundedness conditions.

Page 104: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

382 2. Elementary Integration Theory

Proposition 2.7.12 Let (X,~,J,t) be a positive measure space and (X,.c,l)

its associated Daniell space. If the pair (X,~) is a-finite, then the following

assertions hold.

a) (X, .cl(X, J,t), Ix) = (X, :e(l), £) .

b) (X, £(X, J,t), J,tX) = (X, ~(J,t), JL) .

Proof By hypothesis, there is a countable family (A')'EI from ~ whose union

is X. The functions eA, belong to .c and

In other words, the Riesz lattice .c is a-finite. We conclude a) from Corollary

2.4.14, and we conclude b) from a) . 0

Proposition 2.7.13 Let (X,~, J,t) be a positive measure space. The following

are equival::nt.

a) (X,~, J,t) is a-bounded.

b) There is a countable family (A),E/ from ~ such that X\ U A E 'EI

IJl(X, J,t) .

c) X belongs to !R(e l (X, J,t)) .

d) The pair (X, £(X, J,t)) is a-finite.

Proof a)::::} b). Given A E ~, there is a countable family (A,),E/ from ~

with

inf J,t(A \A) = O. 'EI

Then

Theorem 6 d) now shows that X\ U A, E IJl(X, J,t). 'EI

b) ::::} d) is trivial.

d) ::::} c) follows from Proposition 2.4.2 e) .

Page 105: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.7 Closure, Completion, and Integrals for Positive Measure Spaces 383

c) =* a) . By Theorem 6 g), there are an increasing sequence (An)nEIN from

~ and a set B belonging to IJt{X, J.t) such that

x = (u A~) UB. nEIN

It follows that A \ U An belongs to IJt{X, J.t) for every A in ~ and that nEIN

o

Bounded measures play a very special role. The completions of such mea­

sures provide a new kind of set system.

Definition 2.7.14 For ~ C ~(X), ~ is said to be a a-algebra on X iff

~ is a a-ring and X belongs to ~. 0

Thus a-algebras are only defined relative to some underlying set X. They

can be characterized in various ways.

Proposition 2.7.15 Let ~ be a set of sets and take X :) X(~). Then the

following are equivalent.

a) ~ is a a-algebra on X.

b) ~ is a 8 -ring and X belongs to ~.

c) The empty set belongs to ~. X\A belongs to ~ for every A in ~ and

U An belongs to ~ for every sequence (An)nEIN from ~. nEIN

Proof. We leave the details to the reader. Observe that

A\B = X\«X\A) U B) . o

Proposition 2.7.16 Let (X,~, J.t) be a positive measure space. Then the fol­

lowing are equivalent.

a) (X,~, J.t) is bounded.

Page 106: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

384 2. Elementary Integration Theory

b) X belongs to £(X, J-t) .

c) £(X, J-t) is a a-algebra on X.

d) (X, £(X, J-t), J-tX) is bounded.

Each of these assertions implies

e) sup J-t(A) = sup J-tx (A) = J-tx (X) . AE!Jl AE£(X,/L)

Proof. a) ~ b). By Corollary 2.6.8 and Proposition 13 a) ~ c), X E

6t(£l(X,J-t)). According to Theorem 6 g), there are an increasing sequence

(An)nEIN from 9t and a set BE 'J1(X, J-t) such that

X = (U An) uB. nEIN

Since

U An belongs to £(X, J-t). Thus X E £(X, J-t). nEIN

The implications b) ~ c) ~ d) ~ a) and b) ~ e) are left to the reader.

o

Example 2.7.17 Let 9t be a set-ring on X and x E X such that {x} E 9t.

The reader can easily verify the following assertions about the Dirac measure

§x := §~ concentrated in x.

-x N(§x) = {J E lR I f(x) = D},

-x £l(§x) = {J E lR I f(x) E lR},

f fd§x = f(x) whenever f E £1 (§x) . o

Given a Daniell space (X, £, £), we finally pursue the question of when

(X,£l(£),it) is generated by a positive measure space.

Page 107: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.7 Closure, Completion, and Integrals for Positive Measure Spaces 385

Theorem 2.7.18 Let (X,C,e) be a Daniell space such that C1 (e) has the

Stone property. Denote by (X, 9't, /.1) the positive measure space induced by

(X, C 1 (e), L). Then (X, 9't, /.1) is complete and

(7)

Proof Let (X, C, e') be the Daniell space associated with (X, 9't, /.1) . By virtue

of Theorem 2.6.20 b) :::} a), (X, 9't, /.1) is closed and

(X,£(t),£i) = (x,c 1 (e), 1) (8)

Thus (7) follows if we can show that I)1(X, /.1) C l)1(e) . So take B E I)1(X, /.1)

and A E iR(£(e)). By (8), A E iR(£(e')). Then, using Theorem 6 e),

B n A E 1)1(£(t)) = l)1(e)

and hence B n A E 1)1(£(e)). It follows that BE l)1(e).

Finally, the completeness of (X, 9't, /.1) is a consequence of (7). 0

Corollary 2.7.19 Let (X, 12, e) be a Daniell space. Then the following are

equivalent.

a) There is a positive measure space (X, 9't, /.1) such that

b) 121 (e) has the Stone properly. o

Observe that the Daniell space (X, C1(e), Ie) from Example 2.4.10 lacks the

Stone property and is therefore not generated by a positive measure space.

Page 108: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

386 2. Elementary Integration Theory

2.8 Measurable Spaces and Measurability

Measurability plays several roles in the theory of integration. First, it yields an

integrability criterion, in fact the most important integrability criterion, which we treat in Section 2.9. It turns out that measurability, when properly defined,

provides a necessary, though not sufficient, condition for integrability. Thus

the set of measurable functions is larger than the set of integrable functions.

Measurable functions, it further turns out, form a class that is large enough

to permit all appropriate limit operations as well as algebraic operations, a

property that makes this class very important in the theory of integration. One

can place in this framework, for instance, the entire theory of .cP-spaces which

will be treated in the next chapter.

Definition 2.8.1 For!Jt a 6-ring on a set X, we define

9Jt(X,!Jt) := {A c X I An BE !Jt, VB E!Jt},

-x M(X,!Jt) := {J E lR I {J < a} E 9Jt(X,!Jt), Va E lR},

and we say that X is a measurable space with 6-ring !Jt or that (X,!Jt)

is a measurable space. Sets belonging to 9Jt(X,!Jt) are called !Jt-measurable

subsets or measurable sets of X . Functions belonging to M(X,!Jt) are called

!Jt-measurable junctions on X. o

Proposition 2.8.2 For every measurable space X with 6-ring !Jt, the set

9Jt(X,!Jt) contains !Jt and is a a-algebra on X. If X belongs to !Jt, then

9Jt(X,!Jt) = !Jt.

Proof. That!Jt c 9Jt(X,!Jt) is evident, as is the reverse inclusion when X

itself belongs to !Jt. Certainly, 0 E 9Jt(X,!Jt) . If A E 9Jt(X,!Jt) , then for every

BE!Jt

(X\A) n B = B\(A n B) E !Jt,

that is, X\A E 9Jt(X,!Jt) . Finally, let (An)nEIN be a sequence from 9Jt(X,!Jt).

Note for B E !Jt that

Using Proposition 2.5.2 e), we conclude that U An belongs to 9Jt(X,!Jt). By nEIN

Proposition 2.7.15 c) ::::} a), 9Jt(X,!Jt) is a a-algebra on X. 0

Page 109: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.8 Measurable Spaces and Measurability 387

Proposition 2.8.3 Let X be a measurable space with 8 ~ring 9t. Then the

following assertions hold.

a) For A eX, A is an 9t~measurable subset of X iff eA zs an 9t~

measurable function on X.

b) Constant extended~real functions on X are 9l.~measurable.

c) For every 9l.~measurable function f on X, the sets

{j=oo}, {j = -oo}, {x E X I f(x) is real}

are 9t~measurable.

d) If (A')'EI is a countable disjoint family of 9t~measurable subsets of X

whose union is X and if (1,),0 is a family of 9l.~measurable functions

on X , then the function

f: X --t IR, X f----t f,(x) (x E A" ~ E 1)

is 9t ~measumble.

e) For every 9l.~measurable function f on X, the function

h : X --t IR, X f----t

is 9t~measurable.

{ f(x)

o if f(x) E IR

if f(x) 1. IR

f) For every real number a and for all 9t~measurable functions f and 9

on X , the sets

{j<g+a}, {j::;g+a}, {j=g+a}, {j#g+a}

are 9t ~measurable.

Proof. a) For a E IR,

if 1 < a

if 0 < a ::; 1

if a ::; O.

In view of Proposition 2, the assertion follows.

Page 110: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

388 2. Elementary Integration Theory

b) is trivial.

c) Since

U = oo} = X\ U U < n}, nElN

U = -oo} = nU < -n}, nElN

{x E X I f(x) is real} = X\(U = oo} U U = -oo})

-x for every f E IR ,c) follows from the fact that 9Jt(X,!R) is a a-algebra on

X. d) For each real number a,

U < a} = U(U. < a} n A.) . • EI

Since 9Jt(X,!R) is a a-algebra, the assertion follows.

e) Assertion e) follows from b),c), and d).

f) To verify that U < 9 + a} is !R-measurable, it suffices to note, in view

of Proposition 2, that

U < 9 + a} = U (U < t3} \ {g < t3 - a} ) . .8EQ

Indeed, given x EX, f(x) < g(x) + a iff there is a rational number t3 such

that f(x) < t3 ::; g(x) + a. The !R-measurability of the other three sets now

follows again in view of Proposition 2, since

U :5 9 + a} = X\ {g < f - a},

U = 9 + a} = U ::; 9 + a}\{f < 9 + a},

U f. 9 + o} = X\U = 9 + o}.

Theorem 2.8.4 Let X be a measurable space with a-ring !R.

o

a) If f is an !R-measurable function on X, then so is of, whenever 0 is

any extended-real number.

b) If f and 9 are !R-measurable functions on X and if f + 9 is defined,

then f + 9 is !R-measurable.

c) For every countable family (j')'EI of !R-measurable functions on X, the

functions

Page 111: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.8 Measurable Spaces and Measurability 389

/\f. and V f • • EI .EI

are both !R-measurable.

-x d) For every f E IR , f is £R-measurable iff both f+ and f- are £R-

measurable.

e) If f is an £R-measurable function on X, then so is If I·

f) If f and 9 are !R -measurable functions on X , then so is f 9 .

g) If f is an £R-measurable function on X and

{ _1 if f(x) E IR\{a}

9 : X --t IR, X t----t al(X)

otherwise,

then 9 is !R-measurable.

h) For every sequence (fn)nEIN of !R-measurable functions on X, the func­

tions

lim sup fn and lim inf fn n-+oo n-+oo

are both !R-measurable.

i) If (fn)nEIN is a sequence of £R-measurable functions on X which is order­

convergent in IRx , then the function lim fn is £R-measurable. n-+oo

j) For every countable family (f')'EI of £R-measurable real functions on X,

if (f.).EI is summable, then E f. is £R-measurable . • EI

k) Every rot(X, !R)-step function on X is !R-measurable.

Proof. a) If Q E IR, distinguish the cases Q = a, Q > a, Q < a. If Q = 00,

note that for each {3 E IR

{oof < {3}= {{J~a} {J < a}

if {3 > a

if (3 ~ a.

In view of Proposition 3 b),f), oof is £R-measurable. Finally,

{-oof < {3} = {-{3 < oo!}

Page 112: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

390 2. Elementary Integration Theory

for every real number f3, so -oof is also 9{-measurable.

b) If f + 9 is defined, then

U+g < a} = U < -g+a}

for every real number a. Thus b) follows from a) by Proposition 3 b),f).

c) For every real number a,

{ /\ ft < a} = UUt < a}. tEl tEl

Since 9J1(X,9{) is a a-algebra on X, we conclude that /\ ft is 9{-measurable. tEl

Since

V ft = -/\(-ft) tEl tEl

it follows from a) that V ft is also 9{-measurable. tEl

d),e) These assertions follow from a) - c).

f) Suppose first that f, 9 ~ 0 and take a E 1R. If a :::; 0, then U 9 < a}

is empty. So suppose that a > O. We claim that

That ~ holds is evident. Suppose that x fails to belong to the set on the right­

hand side. Then f(x) > 0, and for every strictly positive rational number f3

we have

x ~ {g < f3} n {f < ~} .

If g(x) = 00, then f(x)g(x) = 00 and hence x ~ Ug < a}. If g(x) < 00,

then f(x) ~ alf3 whenever f3 E Q, /3 > g(x). Thus

f(x)g(x) = inf{f3f(x) I f3 E Q, /3 > g(x)} ~ a,

and so x ~ U 9 < a} , establishing (1). It follows that f 9 is 9{-measurable.

Now let f and 9 be arbitrary 9{.-measurable functions on X. Set

A:= U ~ a}, B:= U < O},

C:= {g ~ O}, D:= {g < O}.

Page 113: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.8 Measurable Spaces and Measurability 391

The sets A n G, AnD, B n G, B n D are pairwise disjoint, and their

union is X. According to what we have already established, the functions f+ g+ , - f+ g- , - f- g+ , f- g- are all 9\-measurable. Since

rg+ on AnG

-rg- on AnD fg

-f-g+ on BnG

f-g- on BnD

it follows from Proposition 3 d) that fg is 9\-measurable.

g) For a E IR,

{J ~ O}U U < J} if a> 0

{g < a} {J<O}\{J=-oo} ifa=O

{J < O} n U < J}

so g) follows from Proposition 3 b),f) .

h) Assertion h) follows from c).

if a < 0,

i) Assertion i) follows from h) and Proposition 1.8.23 b).

j) If I is empty, the assertion is trivial. If I is finite and nonempty,

the assertion follows from b) by complete induction. Suppose finally that I

is countably infinite. It suffices to prove the assertion for a summable sequence m

(fn)nEIN of 9\-measurable real functions on X. For such a sequence, E fk is k=l

9\-measurable (m E IN) , and

m

~ fn = lim ~ fk L...J m-+oo L.. nEIN k=l

(Proposition 2.3.28 a)). j) is now a consequence of i).

k) follows from a) and j), together with Proposition 3 a). o

We stress that M(X,9\) is not, in general, a Riesz lattice. To wit, the

constant function ooex is always 9\-measurable, so M(X,9\) cannot be a

Riesz lattice unless M(X,9\) = IRx , which is seldom the case.

Proposition 2.8.5 Let X be a measurable space with 8-ring 9\ and take

f in M(X,9\). Then there is a sequence (fn)nEIN of rot(X, 9\)-step functions

on X such that lim fn = f and Ifni ~ If I for every n E IN. If f ~ 0, the n-+oo

sequence (fn)nEIN can be chosen increasing, with fn ~ 0 for every n E IN .

Page 114: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

392 2. Elementary Integration Theory

Proof For I E M(X, 9l)+, the assertion follows from Proposition 2.5.19.

If I is an arbitrary 9l-measurable function on X, then 1+ and 1- belong

to M(X, 9l)+. Choose increasing sequences (9n)nEIN and (hn)nEIN of positive

9Jl(X, 9l)-step functions whose suprema are 1+ and 1- , respectively. Set In :=

9n - hn . Then the sequence (fn)nEIN has the required properties. 0

Page 115: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.9 Measurability versus Integrability 393

2.9 Measurability versus Integrability

In the preceding section, measurability relative to a o-ring was defined and

investigated. It was exactly the defining property of o-rings that implied the

important properties formulated in Theorem 2.8.4: measurability relative to a

ring of sets would have been to weak. Given a positive measure space (X,~, /1-) ,

then, it is not be particularly useful to speak of measurability relative to ~.

Instead, we shall use either the o-ring ~6 generated by ~ or the o-ring

.c(X, /1-) of /1--integrable subsets of X.

The first part of the present section discusses /1--measurable objects and

their relation to /1--integrable objects. Upper and lower /1--integrals, and inner

and outer /1--measures, which are introduced in Definition 4, provide useful tools

for describing the relationship between measurability and integrability.

Definition 2.9.1 Let (X,~, /1-) be a positive measure space. Then

VJl(X, /1-) := VJl(X, .c(X, /1-)) ,

M(X, /1-) := M(X, .c(X, /1-)) .

Sets belonging to VJl(X, /1-) and functions belonging to M(X, /1-) are called /1-­

measurable on X . 0

Proposition 2.9.2 Let (X,~, /1-) be a positive measure space. Then the fol­

lowing assertions hold.

a) 'J1(X, /1-) C .c(X, /1-) C 6t(.c1 (X, /1-)) C VJl(X, /1-) .

b) If A E .c(X, /1-) , BE VJl(X, /1-) and Be A, then B belongs to .c(X, /1-) .

c) If B is a subset of X for which

A~B E 'J1(X, /1-)

for some A E VJl(X, /1-), then B belongs to VJl(X, /1-) .

d) N(X, /1-) C .c1(X, /1-) C M(X, /1-).

e) If g is an extended-real function on X that is /1--a. e. equal to a /1-­

measurable function f on X, then g is /1--measurable.

Page 116: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

394 2. Elementary Integration Theory

I) The conditions I,g E M(X,J-l) , hE m.x,

h(x) = I(x) + g(x) J-l-a.e.

imply that h belongs to M(X, J-l) .

Proof a) The first two inclusions are already known. The third is a consequence

of Propositions 2.5.21 c) and 2.8.2.

b) is evident.

c) The hypothesis implies that both B\A and A\B are J-l-measurable.

S~nce

B = (A\(A\B)) U (B\A) ,

B is also J-l-measurable (Proposition 2.8.2).

d) The first inclusion is already known. For the second, since 1 is J-l­measurable if 1+ and 1- are (Theorem 2.8.4 d)), it suffices to show that

(1)

By Proposition 2.5.21 b), every function in .c1(X, J-l)+ is the supremum of a

sequence of .c(X, J-l)-step functions, which implies that (1) holds (Theorem 2.8.4

c),k)).

e) With 1 and 9 as hypothesized, set

A:={f#g}.

The sets A and X\A both belong to rot(X, J-l) and the function leX\A belongs

to M(X, J-l) (Proposition 2.8.3 a), Theorem 2.8.4 f)). Since geA is J-l-null, it

belongs to .c 1 (X, J-l) and therefore to M (X, J-l) , by d). Then, in view of Theorem

2.8.4 b),

9 = leX\A + geA E M(X, J-l) .

f) follows from e) and Theorem 2.8.4 b).

Corollary 2.9.3 Let (X,!Jl, J-l) be a positive measure space. Then, given 1 E .c1(X,J-l)+ and a E m., a> 0,

{I> a} E .c(X,J-l)' {f ~ a} E .c(X,J-l)

and

o

Page 117: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.9 Measurability versus Integrability 395

Proof. By Proposition 2.5.21 a), {J ~ a} E £(X,J-t). As a J-t-measurable

subset of this set, {J > a} belongs to £(X,J-t) too (Proposition 2 b),d)).

Moreover,

Definition 2.9.4 Let (X, 9l, J-t) be a positive measure space. For f E lRx ,

we define the upper and lower J-t-integral of f by

1* fdJ-t:= (1 ) * (I) , X X,Jl

r fdJ-t:= (r ) (I), J*x JX,Jl *

respectively. For A eX, we define the outer and inner J-t-measure (C.

Caratheodory, 1914) of A to be, respectively,

J-t*(A) := l* eAdJ-t,

J-t*(A):= r eAdJ-t. J*X o

The rules governing upper and lower integrals were already discussed in

Section 2.3. It goes without saying that analogous rules hold for inner and outer

measures. It will prove useful to record the most important of these results.

Proposition 2.9.5 Let (X, 9l, J-t) be a positive measure space.

a) For every subset A of X ,

b) If A c B eX, then

Page 118: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

396 2. Elementary Integration Theory

c) For every nonempty, countable, directed upward family (A.),El from

~(X),

p,* (UA,) = supp,*(A,). ,EI 'EI

d) For every countable family (A')'EI from ~(X),

p,* (UA.) ~ 2:* p,*(A,). ,EI LEI

e) For every disjoint family (A.)LEI from ~(X),

f) A subset A of X belongs to .c(X,p,) iff p,*(A) and p,*(A) are real and

equal. If A belongs to £(X, p,), then

g) m(X,p,) = {A c X I p,*(A) = O}.

Proof. For a),b), and c), use Proposition 2.3.17, Propositions 2.3.18 c) and 2.3.15 e), and Theorem 2.3.16 a), respectively. Assertions d) and e) follow from

Proposition 2.3.34. Assertions f) and g) follow from Propositions 2.3.19, 2.3.15

a), and 2.3.18 a). 0

Example 2.9.6 Consider again the measure space (X, 9t, 6x ) ,with {x} E 9t

(Example 2.7.17). Then

r* fd6x = r fd6x = f(x) ix i*X

-x M(X,6x ) = 1R ,

-x whenever f E 1R . o

Example 2.9.7 Let 3" be the set of finite subsets of X, and let X be

counting measure on 3" (Examples 2.6.10, 2.6.17). In view of Example 2.3.22

and Corollary 2.4.12, we have

Page 119: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.9 Measurability versus Integrability 397

Hence £(X, X) = ~ and therefore

Moreover,

for every A eX.

rot(X, X) = ~(X) , -x

M(X,X) = 1R .

r* * -x JJl fdX = L f(x) for every f E 1R , X xEX

{ X(A)

X*(A) = X*(A) = 00

if A E ~

if A ¢ ~

o

Next we prove the important result that measurable sets have identical inner

and outer measure.

Theorem 2.9.8 For every positive measure space (X,!oR, JJ) , if A belongs to

rot(X, JJ), then

(2)

Proof. Since JJ*(A) $ JJ*(A) , there is nothing to prove if JJ*(A) = 00. Assume therefore that JJ*(A) < 00. In this case we claim that the JJ-measurable set A

must actually be JJ-integrable and therefore satisfy (2). Let

Q := sup{JJx (B') I B' E £(X, JJ), B' c A}

and note that Q is real (Proposition 5 b),f)). Choose an increasing sequence

(Bn)nElN of JJ-integrable subsets of A such that

sup JJx (Bn) = Q.

nElN

Set

B:= U Bn , C:= A\B. nElN

Then B c A, B belongs to £(X, JJ) and JJx (B) = Q. Hence C belongs to

rot(X, JJ). Let D E !oR. Then C n D belongs to £(X, f.l) and

Q = JJX(B) $ f.lX(B) + JJX(Cn D) = JJX(B u (Cn D)) ::; Q,

so JJx (C n D) = 0 and C n D belongs to lJl(X, JJ). Since D was an arbitrary

set in !oR, we conclude that C belongs to lJl(X,JJ) and therefore to £(X,JJ).

As claimed, A belongs to £(X, JJ) and (2) holds. 0

Page 120: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

398 2. Elementary Integration Theory

Corollary 2.9.9 For every positive measure space (X, vt, J.L) , if f E VJ1(X, J.L)+ ,

then

(3)

Proof The validity of (3) follows immediately from Theorem 8 if f is the

characteristic function of a J.L-measurable set.

Suppose next that f is a positive VJ1(X, J.L)-step function, say

for some finite family (A)'EI from VJ1(X, J.L) and some family (a,),El from

lR+ . Using Proposition 2.3.34, we have

Since the reverse inequality always holds, (3) holds.

Finally, let f be an arbitrary positive J.L-measurable function on X. Ac­

cording to Proposition 2.8.5, there is an increasing sequence (fn)nEIN of positive

VJ1(X, J.L)-step functions whose supremum is f. Using Theorem 2.3.16 a) and

Proposition 2.3.18 c), we have

Once again, (3) holds. o

Our next theorem characterizes J.L-integrable objects within the class of

J.L-measurable objects.

Theorem 2.9.10 Let (X, vt, J.L) be a positive measure space. Then for every

set A C X and for every function f E lRx we have the following.

a) A E £'(X, J.L) iff A E VJ1(X, J.L) and J.L* (A) < 00.

b) f E Cl(X, J.L) iff f E M(X, J.L) and f; IfldJ.L < 00.

Proof a) We have already established that J.L-integrability implies J.L-measur­

ability (Proposition 2 a». The rest of a) restates Proposition 5 f) and Theorem

8.

b) If f is J.L-integrable, then so is If I and, by Proposition 2.3.19 a),

Page 121: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.9 Measurability versus Integrability 399

Ix* IfldJ.t < 00. (4)

Moreover, in view of Proposition 2 d), f is J.t-measurable.

Suppose, conversely, that f is J.t-measurable and satisfies (4). Then both

rand f- are J.t-measurable (Theorem 2.8.4 d)) and

(Proposition 2.3.15 e)). Combining Corollary 9 with Proposition 2.3.19 a), we

conclude that rand f- belong to Cl(X,J.t). Hence f belongs to Cl(X,J.t). D

Corollary 2.9.11 Let (X,!Jt, J.t) be a positive measure space and (X, C, f) its

associated Daniell space. Then the following assertions hold.

a) If f E C1(X, J.t), 9 E M(X, J.t) and

Igl $ If I J.t-a.e.,

then 9 belongs to C1(X, J.t).

b) If f E £(f) , 9 E M(X,J.t) and

Igl $Ifl £(f)-a.e.,

then 9 belongs to £( f) .

c) The product of a bounded J.t-measurable function with a J.t-integrable func­

tion is J.t-integrable. In fact, if f belongs to M(X, J.t) and satisfies

oex $ f $ j3ex J.t-a.e.

with o,j3 E JR, then fg belongs to C1(X,J.t) for every 9 E C1(X,J.t) and

satisfies

° Ix gdJ.t $ Ix f gdJ.t $ j3 Ix gdJ.t

for every 9 E Cl(X, J.t)+.

Proof. a) follows from Theorem 10 b).

b) By a), 9 belongs to C1(X,J.t). By Theorem 2.7.6 e), ge{NO} belongs to

£(f) . But Igl $ If I £(f)-a.e. implies that 9 = ge{f;/:O} £ (f)-a.e., so 9 belongs to £(f).

Page 122: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

400 2. Elementary Integration Theory

c) is left to the reader. o

We present some equivalent characterizations of tt-measurable objects.

Proposition 2.9.12 Let (X,!>t, tt) be a positive measure space. Then for each

subset A of X , the following are equivalent.

a) A E VJ!(X, tt) .

b) feA E M(X,tt) for every f E M(X,tt)·

c) An B E '£(X, tt) for every B E !>t.

d) feA E £}(X,tt) for every f E £}(X,tt).

Proof a) ~ b) is a consequence of Theorem 2.8.4 f).

b) ~ c). Let BE!>t. Then eAnB = eAeB E M(X,tt) , by b). Now apply

Proposition 2.8.3 a) and Proposition 2 b) .

c) ~d). We use the Induction Principle (Theorem 2.4.17). Let

The identity eBeA = eBnA shows that eB belongs to F if B belongs to !>t.

Consequently, F contains all !>t-step functions on X. Let (gn)nEIN be a tt­sequence from F and g an extended-real function on X such that

lim gn = g tt-a.e. n-+oo

Note that g must belong to £1 (X, tt) . Since

for every n, (gneA)nEIN is a tt-sequence from £l(X, tt) . Moreover,

We conclude that geA belongs to £1(X,tt). In other words, g belongs to F. By the Induction Principle, F = £1(X, tt) .

d) ~ a) is trivial. o

Proposition 2.9.13 Let (X,!>t, tt) be a positive measure space. Then for each

function f E lR! , the following are equivalent.

Page 123: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.9 Measurability versus Integrability 401

a) f E M(X,Jl).

b) feA E M(X,Jl) for every A E!R.

c) f 1\ aeA E £l(X,Jl) for every A E!R and every a E JR+.

d) . f 1\ neA E £l(X, Jl) for every A E!R and every n E IN .

Proof. a) =} c). Use Theorems 10 b) and 2.8.4 c).

c) =} d) is trivial.

d) =} b). Note that

feA = V (f 1\ neA) nElN

for every A E !R, and apply Theorem 2.8.4 c).

b) =} a). Take a E JR. For each A in !R,

U < a} n A = U e A < a} n A E £( X, Jl) .

A.ccording to Proposition 12 c) =} a), U < a} is Jl-measurable. o

\Ve next pursue the question as to when two positive measure spaces gen­

erate the same measurable objects.

Proposition 2.9.14 Let (X,!R, Jl) and (X, 6, v) be positive measure spaces

such that £(X, Jl) C £(X, v) . If for each C E £(X, v) there is aBE £(X, Jl)

with C6.B E SJ1(X, v), then

9J1(X, Jl) C 9J1(X, v) and M(X, Jl) C M(X, v) .

Proof. Take A E 9J1(X, Jl) and C E £(X, v) . Then, choosing B E £(X, Jl) as

hypothesized, the representation

A. n C = ((A n B)\(A n (B\C))) U (A n (C\B))

shows that An C is v-integrable. Since C was arbitrary, A E 9J1(X, v) . The

second inclusion follows from the first. o

One aim of the discussion commenced in Section 2.8 was to expand the

collections of Jl-integrable sets and functions in order to obtain better proper­

ties. With Jl-measurable objects, upper and lower Il-integrals, and inner and

Page 124: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

402 2. Elementary Integration Theory

outer J.t-measures, that objective is now achieved. Theorems 2.8.4 and 2.9.10

enunciate the desired properties.

But the story continues. Formulating measurability in terms of the mea­

surable space (X, 'c(X, J.t))) is not always satisfactory. Difficulties arise, in par­

ticular, when we work with different meaSUres. Furthermore, one often needs

relationships to the set-ring used to determine measurability, and in this re­

spect 'c(X, J.t) is too large. In these two respects, measurability relative to the

measurable space (X,~) is sometimes very useful. Accordingly, we investigate

9lrmeasurability yet.

Proposition 2.9.15 For every positive measure space (X,!>t, J.t) ,

!JJt(X, !>to) c !JJt(X, J.t) and M(X, !>to) C M(X, J.t) .

Proof. The first inclusion follows from the characterization

!JJt(X, J.t) = {A C X I An BE 'c(X, J.t), VB E !>t}

(Proposition 12 a) - c)), and the second inclusion follows from the first. 0

We investigate the extent to which various kinds of functions from lRx can

be approximated by !>trmeasurable functions.

Theorem 2.9.16 Let (X, 9l, J.t) be a positive measure space and (X, C, £) its associated Daniell space. Then the following assertions hold.

a) For each f E £(l) there are

g, hE M(X, !>to) n £(£)

such that

g~f~h, 9 = h J.t-a.e.

b) For each f E r.l(X,J.t) , there is a

9 E M(X, !>to) n £(£) n IRx

such that

f = 9 J.t-a.e.

Page 125: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.9 Measurability versus Integrability 403

-x c) For each f E lR ,there is agE M(X, 9t6) such that

g:::; f p,-a.e., r f dp, = r gdp, . i*X i*X

If f*X f dp, is real, then 9 can be chosen from

If there is a countable family from 9t whose union contains {J < O}, then 9 can be chosen so that 9 :::; f .

-x d) For each f E lR there is an hE M(X, 9t6 ) such that

f :::; h p,-a.e., [* fdp, = [* hdp,.

If f; fdp, is real, then h can be chosen from

If there is a countable family from 9t whose union contains {J > O} , then h can be chosen so that f ::; h .

Proof. a) Take f E l( £). There are an increasing sequence (gn)nEIN from

C t and a decreasing sequence (hn)nEIN from Ct such that the sequences

(£t(gn))nEIN and (et(hn))nEIN are real,

V gn ::; f::; 1\ hn , nEIN nEIN

and

Then the functions

g:= V gn, h:= 1\ hn nEIN nEIN

meet the requirements (Theorem 2.8.4 k),c), Propositions 2.3.11 and 2.2.13).

b) Take f E C1(X,p,) and choose l' E l(£) with f = l' p,-a.e. By a),

there is a

g' E M(X, 9t6) n l(£)

Page 126: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

404 2. Elementary Integration Theory

with g' = f' p-a.e. Define

{ g'(x) if g'(x) E IR

9 : X --t IR , x f----+

o if g' (x) tf. IR .

Then 9 is as required (Propositions 2.8.3 e), 2.1.21 c)).

c) Take J E IRx. If f*x Jdp = -00, then the function 9 .- -ooex

satisfies the requirements. Assume therefore that

Define

1 Jdp> -00.

*x (5)

By (5), 1i is nonem pty. Choose an increasing sequence (h n ) nEIN from 1i such

that hn :::; J for every nand

sup l hndp = 1 Jdp. nElN *x *x

(Note that fLY hndf.1 = fLJhn) , by Proposition 2.3.18 b)). Assume, without

loss of generality, that f*x hndf.1 is real for every n. Then each hn must be­

long to £1(X, f.1) (Proposition 2.3.11 b)). According to b), there is a sequence

(gn)nElN from M(X, ryts) n £(£) n IRx such that

gn = hn f.1-a .e.

If f*x Jdtl = DC, we can take

g:= V gn nEN

(Theorem 2.8.4 c), Proposition 2.3.18 d)). Otherwise,

sup £(gn) = r Jdf.1 < 00. nElN J*x

In this case, Theorem 2.2.17 a) implies that the function V gn belongs to nElN

£( £) and therefore to £1 (X, f.1) . Applying b) to V gn, we obtain the required nEN

function g.

Now assume that {J < O} c U A" for some countable family (A')'EI ,EI

from ryt. For each n E IN, choose a sequence (Bin) hEr:-; from ryt such that

{hn oF O} \ U Bin) is p-exceptional. Put kEl"

Page 127: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.9 Measurability versus Integrability 405

for each n. By Proposition 2.4.2 e), each en belongs to !'Yt(l(£)). We have

hnecn = hn p,-a.e., hnecn ::::: f and, by Theorem 2.7.6 e), hnecn belongs to

£(£). By a), for each n there is a function g~ belonging to M(X, !)to) n £(£) such that g~ ::::: hnecn and g~ = hnecn p,-a.e. The function g:= V g~

nEIN possesses the required properties.

d) The argument for d) is analogous to that for c). o

Corollary 2.9.17 For every positive measure space (X,!)t, p,) and for every

subset A of X ,

p,*(A) = sup{j1(B) I B E !Ro, B C A}.

Proof. Let (X, £, £) be the Daniell space associated with the positive measure

space (X,!}t, p,). Let A eX. Then

p,*(A) = {.eAdP,=suP { {.J.(9)19E£1(X,p,).J.,g:::::eA} = J*>:. Jx,JJ

= sup {Ix gdp, I 9 E £l(X, p,)+, 9 ::::: eA} =

= sup {£(g) I 9 E £(£)+, 9 ::::: eA} =

= sup {£(g) I 9 E M(X, !}to) n £(£)+, 9 ::::: eA}

(Proposition 2.3.11 b), Proposition 2.3.18 c), Theorem 2.7.6 e), Theorem 16 a)).

By the formula of Theorem 2.7.6 i), if 9 belongs to £(£)+ and satisfies g::::: eA,

then

£(g) = sup £(geB) ::::: sup £(eBn{g#O}) = sup j1(B n {g =f:. O}). BE!)'! BE!)'! BE!)'!

If 9 belongs to M(X, !)to) , then B n {g =f:. O} belongs to !}to for every B in

!}t. We conclude that

o

Corollary 2.9.18 Let (X,!)t, p,) be a positive measure space and (X, £, £) its

associated Daniell space. Then the following assertions hold.

Page 128: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

406 2. Elementary Integration Theory

a) For each A E !1t(J.l) , there are sets

such that

B cAe C, C\B E 'Jl(X, J.l) .

b) For each A E .c(X, J.l) there is a set

such that

Be A, A\B E 'Jl(X,J.l).

c) For each A E '+3(X) there is a set B E VJt(X, !1t6) such that

If J.l* (A) is finite, then B can be chosen from

d) For each A E '+3(X) , there is aCE VJt(X, !1t6) such that

A\C E 'Jl(X, J.l), J.l*(A) = It*(C).

If J.l* (A) is finite, then C can be chosen from

If there is a countable family from !1t whose union contains A, then C can be chosen to contain A.

Proof. a) Let A E !1t(J.l). By Theorem 16 a), there are functions g, h such

that

g, hE M(X, !1t6) n £(e) ,

9 ~ eA ~ h, 9 = h J.l-a.e.

Let

Page 129: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.9 Measurability versus Integrability 407

B := {g > a}, C:= {h ?: I}.

The sets Band C belong to VJt(X, ryt6) and B cAe C. Since C\B is

contained in {g -I- h}, C\B is a Ji~null set. By Proposition 2.4.15 d), C\B E

1)1(2:(£)). Thus

eB = eA = ec C(£)~a.e.

and therefore eB and ec belong to C(£) , that is Band C belong to ryt(Ji). b) is a consequence of Theorem 2.7.6 f) and of a).

c) Let A eX. By Corollary 17, there is an increasing sequence (Bn)nEJN from ryt6 such that

Bn C A (n E IN), sup Jl(Bn) = Ji*(A). nEJN

Then B:= U Bn satisfies the stated conditions. nEJN

d) Take A eX. By Theorem 16 d), we can choose an ryt6~measurable

function h such that

eA :s h Ji-a.e., Ji*(A) = i* hdJi.

Moreover, we may assume that h?: 0 (everywhere!), and if Il*(A) is finite, we

may assume that It belongs to C(£). Put

C := {h ?: 1} .

Then C is Ji-measurable (Proposition 15) and

As a subset of {h < eA}, the set A\C is Ji-null and we have

Ji*(A) = Ji*(C).

Finally, if Ji*(A) is finite, it follows from Corollary 11 b) that ec belongs to

C( £) ; that is, C belongs to ryt(Ji) . If there is a countable family from ryt whose

union contains A, then we can choose h so that eA :s h and therefore A c C.

o

Suppose A c X and f E lRx . With part d) of Proposition 12 available,

the obvious definition of fA fdJi makes sense, as long as A is Ji~measurable

and f is Ji~integrable on X. We express the relevant definition in more general

form.

Page 130: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

408 2. Elementary Integration Theory

Definition 2.9.19 Let (X, 9"'t, J.L) be a positive measure space. For f an ar­

bitrary extended-real function on X and A an arbitrary subset of X ,

i* fdJ.L:= L* feAdJ.L,

o

We obtain the following consequence of Theorem 16 d).

Corollary 2.9.20 Let (X, 9"'t, J.L) be a positive measure space. Then for each

f E lR~ , and for every countable disjoint family (A')'EI from !JR(X, J.L) ,

/* *1* fdJ.L= L fdJ.L· U A, 'EI A,

'EJ

(6)

Proof. Put

A:=UA 'EI

and let (X, £, €) be the Daniell space associated with (X, 9"'t, It) . By Proposition

2.3.34,

Assume that f: f dJ.L < 00 , for otherwise there is nothing more to prove. Since

f 2: 0, f: fdfL is real. By Theorem 16 d), there is a function h such that

h E M(X, 9"'t6) n £.(£) n lRx ,

i* fdfL = L hdfL·

We may also assume that h 2: 0 (everywhere). By Corollary 11 b), the function

heA belongs to £.(£) , as do all of the functions heA,. We have

Page 131: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.9 Measurability versus Integrability 409

for every t. It follows that

so that

Using Theorem 2.3.31 b) =>f) , we have

and (6) follows. 0

Corollary 2.9.21 For every positive measure space (X,!>l, f.-l) and every pos­

itive extended-real-valued function f on X ,

r* fdf.-l = sup r* jdf.-l. ix AE'.JtiA

Proof Put

a:= sup r* jdf.-l. AE'.JtiA

We may suppose that a < 00. Choose from !>l an increasing sequence (An)nEIN

such that

sup r* fdf.-l = a nEIN iAn

and set

B :=X\ U An. nEIN

We claim that feB is f.-l-null. Take C E !>l. For each n, Corollary 20 yields

It follows that

Page 132: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

410 2. Elementary Integration Theory

so that

a ~ (* fdIJ+a, icnB

r* fdIJ = o. icnB Since C was an arbitrary element of 9t, Proposition 2.3.19 b) and Theorem

2.7.6 c) show that feB belongs to N(X,IJ) , as claimed. Using Corollary 20

and Theorem 2.3.16 a), we obtain

{* fdIJ = {* fdIJ + J* fdIJ = sup r* fdIJ = a. 0 ix iB U An nEJr..JAn

nEIN

Corollary 2.9.22 For every positive measure space (X, 9t, IJ) and every sub­

set A of X, IJ*(A) = sup IJ*(A n B). o

BE!1l

Definition 2.9.23 Let (X, 9t, IJ) be a positive measure space. Then

o

It has already been noted that M(X, IJ) is not a Riesz lattice. In contrast,

.co (X, IJ) is a Riesz lattice with additional properties. These properties are

described in the next proposition, whose proof is left to the reader.

Proposition 2.9.24 Let (X, 9t, IJ) be a positive measure space.

a) .c°(X, IJ) is a Stone lattice which is conditionally a-completely embedded -x

in IR .

b) The conditions

f E .co(X, IJ) , g E M(X, IJ) , Igl ~ If I IJ-a.e.

imply that g belongs to .cO (X, IJ) .

c) .c1(X,IJ) c .c°(X,IJ).

d) N(.c°(X, IJ)) = N(X, IJ) and 1Jt(.c°(X, IJ)) = IJt(X, IJ) .

e) 9t(.c°(X, IJ)) = 6\(.c°(X, IJ)) = 9Jt(X, IJ)· o

Page 133: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.9 Measurability versus Integrability 411

We need the notion of uniform convergence for our next theorem.

Definition 2.9.25 (Gudermann, 1838) Let A be a subset of X, (fn)nEIN -x -x

a sequence from IR ,and take f E IR . The sequence (fn)nEIN is said to converge uniformly on A to f iff for every c > 0 there is an m E IN such

that for every n ~ m and for every x E A both fn(x) and f(x) are real and

Ifn(x) - f(x)1 < c. o

The following important theorem, then, describes order convergence in

£O(X,J.l) .

Theorem 2.9.26 (Egoroff, 1911) Let (X,!>t, J.l) be a positive measure space.

Take f E £O(X, J.l) and suppose that (fn)nEIN is a sequence from £O(X, J.l)

such that

f(x) = lim fn(x) J.l-a.e. n-+oo

Then for every set A E £(X, J.l) and for every real number c > 0, there is an

!>to -measurable set B C A such that

and the sequence (fn)nEIN converges to f uniformly on B.

Proof. Put

f(x) E JR

fn(x) E JR, 'In E IN

f(x) = lim fn(x) n-+oo

By hypothesis, X\C belongs to IJ1(X, J.l) .

Take A E £(X, J.l) . For all m, n E IN, set

}

Am,n:= An {x E C Ilf(x) - fn(x)1 ~ r!.} ,

Bm,n := U Am,k. k~n

For each m, (Bm,n)nEIN is a decreasing sequence from £(X, J.l) . We claim that

n Bm,n =0 (7) nEIN

Page 134: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

412 2. Elementary Integration Theory

for every m. Suppose that, for some m E IN, x belongs to n Bm,n. Then nEIN

for every n E IN , there is an integer k ~ n such that

1 If(x) - fk(x)1 ~ -.

m

On the other hand, x must belong to C, so

lim fk(x) = f(x). k->oo

This contradition verifies (7). By nullcontinuity, we conclude that

for every m. Now let c; > 0 be given. For each m in IN, choose nm in IN such that

X(B ) < ~ I' m,nm - 2m •

Put

B':= (A n C)\ (U Bm,nm) mEIN

Observe that B' belongs to £(X,J.t). Since

A\B~ = (A\C) U ( U Bm,nm) mEIN

the set A\B' also belongs to £(X,J.t), and

J.tx (A\B') ::; J.tx (A\C) + J.tx ( U Bm,nm) ::; L J.tx (Bm,nm) ::; c; mEIN mEIN

(Theorem 2.6.4). We want to show that (fn)nEIN converges uniformly on B' to

f. Given c;' > 0, choose mE IN such that 11m < c;' . If x belongs to B' , then

x belongs to (A n C)\Bm,nm, so

If(x) - fn(x)1 < ~ < c;' m

whenever n ~ nm • We have established uniform convergence on B'.

Finally, Corollary 18 b) allows us to choose a set B such that

B C B' , B E !m(X, !ReS) , B'\B E IJl(X,J.t) .

This set meets all the requirements of the theorem. o

Page 135: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.9 Measurability versus Integrability 413

Exercises

E 2.9.1 (E)

Let (X, 9\, J.1) be a positive measure space and A an open subset of IR. Suppose

that f: X x A --+ IR has the following properties:

i) f(', y) is J.1-measurable for each YEA.

ii) There is a z E A such that f(', z) E £1(J.1).

iii) There is an N E 1)1(J.1) such that 8f(x, y)/8y exists for each yEA and

each x E X\N.

iv) There is agE £1(J.1) such that for each x E X\N (N as in iii» and

each YEA, 18f(x, y)/8yl :::; g(x).

Now set 8f(x, y)/8y := 0 for each x E Nand yEA. Prove the following

propositions.

(0:) 8f(·,y)/8y E £1(J1) for each YEA.

((3) f(', y) E £1(J.1) for each yEA.

(-y) Define h : A --+ IR, y >-+ ff(x,y)dJ.1(x). Then h is differentiable with

respect to y on A and

dh J 8 dy (y) = 8/(x, y)dJl(X).

E 2.9.2 (E)

Regular Measures. Let (X, 'I) be a Hausdorff space. Denote by ~ be set of

all compact subsets of X and let 9\ C l.P(X) be a set-ring containing ~. A

positive measure J.1 on 9\ is called ~-regular iff

J.1(A) = sup{J.1(K) IKE~, K C A}

for every A E 9\.

Let J.1 be a ~-regular positive measure on ~. Prove the following.

(0:) J.1x is ~-regular.

(Show that

(5:= {A E ~ I /1(A) = sup J.1(K)} KEP. KCA

is a conditionally monotone set, and conclude that (5 = ~6 .)

Page 136: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

414 2. Elementary Integration Theory

({3) For any subset A of X , the following are equivalent.

((31) A is JL-measurable.

(f32) For every c > 0 and for every K E .It, there are sets K' and K" in

.It such that K' c K n A, K" c K\A and JL(K\(K' UK")) < c.

((33) An K E ,C(JL) for every K E.It.

We now formulate the important Theorem of Lusin (Vitali, 1905; Lusin, 1912):

(-y) For every I E IRx , the following are equivalent.

(1'1) I is JL-measurable.

(1'2) For every c > 0 and for every K E .It, there is a set L E .It such

that L C K, JL(K\L) < c and so that IlL is continuous.

(-Y3) For every K E .It, there is a disjoint sequence (Kn)nEIN from .It such that U Kn C K, K\ U Kn is a JL-null set and IIKn is

nEIN nEIN

continuous for every n E IN .

Step 1

Assume that there is A C X such that I = eA. Take K E .It and take

K', K" as in ({32) for an c > o. Then L := K'uK" has the desired properties.

Step 2

Assume that there is a finite family (A.)LEI of JL-measurable subsets of X

such that I = ~ eA, . Apply the result just proved. LEI

Step 3

Assume that 0::; I ::; 1 . For every n E IN , define

By Step 2, there is for every n E IN a set Kn E .It such that Kn C

K, f..L(K\Kn) < c/2n , and InlKn is continuous. Define L:= n Kn. Then nEIN

L has the desired properties. The reader should note that (fn)nEIN converges

uniformly on L to I. Step 4

Let f be an arbitrary function. Define

Page 137: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.9 Measurability versus Integrability 415

g:= ~ (arctan f + i) . Apply Step 3.

("(2) => (,3) . This proof is left to the reader.

("(3) => ("(1). Consider first the case f ~ o. Take A E ~ and a E 1R+ .

There is an increasing sequence (Kn)nElN from it such that U Kn C A and nElN

(A\ U Kn) E 1J1(J.t). Take n E IN. There is a disjoint sequence (Lm)mElN from mElN

it such that U Lm C Kn , (Kn \ U Lm) E 1J1(J.t) , and fiLm is continuous mElN mElN

for every mE IN. For every mE IN, we have f 1\ aeLm E £1(J.t) , and we see

that

It follows from

f 1\ aeKn = E (J 1\ aeLm) J.t-a.e. mElN

E ! (f 1\ aeLm)dJ.t ::; aJ.t(Kn) < 00

mElN

that f 1\ aeKn E £1(J.t). (f 1\ aeKn)nElN is an increasing sequence from £1(J.t)

and V (f 1\ aeKn) = f 1\ aeA J.t-a.e. From nElN

v (f 1\ aeKn) ::; aeA nElN

it follows that f 1\ aeA E £1(J.t). From this and the fact that A and a are

arbitrary, we conclude that f is J.t-measurable. For an arbitrary function f our assertion nOW follows from f = f+ - f- .

Page 138: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

416 2. Elementary Integration Theory

2.10 Stieltjes Functionals and Stieltjes Measures.

Lebesgue Measure

NOTATION AND TERMINOLOGY FOR SECTION 2.10:

A denotes an open, half-open, or closed interval in lR, containing

neither 00 nor -00, and having a nonempty interior.

a is the left endpoint of A.

b is the right endpoint of A.

Note that A C lR and -00 ~ a < b ~ 00 .

A is viewed as an ordered set ordered by the restriction to A of the

order relation on lR, and as a metric space with respect to the

metric

AxA~lR+, (x,Y)r-+[x-y[,

induced by the Euclidean metric

lRxlR~lR+, (x,y)r-+[x-y[

on lR. By convergence of a sequence from A we mean order conver­

gence. Observe, however, that order convergence and convergence

with respect to the metric on A of a sequence from A to an ele­

ment of A are equivalent (Proposition 1.9.13).

We now come to an important example illustrating the abstract theory de­

veloped in the preceding sections, namely Stieltjes functionals and measures.

Here the topological and order structures of the base space come to the fore­

ground. We begin with a review of some topological properties of intervals and

their subsets, and of continuous functions on intervals, including certain prop­

erties that are not needed until Chapter 6.

Proposition 2.10.1 a) A sequence from A converges in A iff it converges

in lR to an element of A.

b) An interval I in A is open (closed) in A iff I = An J for some open

(closed) interval J from lR.

Page 139: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.10 Stieltjes Functionals and Stieltjes Measures. Lebesgue Measure 417

c) A subset B of A. is open (closed) in A iff B = An C for some set

C c JR that is open (closed) in JR. D

Definition 2.10.2 Take x, yEA. Then

{ [x,y[ if y i- b .-

[x,bl if y = b, [x,yl

Ix,yl { lx,yl if x i- a .-

[a,yl if x = a,

lx,y[ if x i- a, yi-b

- { [a,yl if x = a .-

Ix,bl if y = b.

Ix,yl

D

By virtue of Proposition 1 b), the intervals of the form lx, yl, with x, YEA,

are open in A, and the intervals of the form [x, yl are closed in A. Observe

that in any case A is an interval in A which is both open and closed in A.

Proposition 2.10.3 For B C A, the set B is open in A iff it can be written

as the union of a countable, disjoint family of intervals from A that are open

in A.

Proof In light of Proposition 1 c), it suffices to prove the assertion for an open

subset B of JR. For x E B, put

ax := inf{y E JR I ly,xl c B} E JR,

bx := sup{z E JR I [x,z[ c B} E JR,

and Ix := lax, bx[. Then, given x, x' E B, either Ix = Ix' or Ix nIx' = (/), and

B = U Ix. Moreover; there are at most cquntably many distinct intervals Ix xEB

because each of them contains a rational number. D

Definition 2.10.4 For C C A, the set C is said to be:

a) compact in A iff for every family of subsets of A that are open in A

and whose union contains C, there is a finite subfamily whose union also

contains C;

Page 140: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

418 2. Elementary Integration Theory

b) sequentially compact in A iff every sequence from C has a subsequence

that converges in A to an element of C. 0

Proposition 2.10.5 For all x, YEA, the closed interval [x, y] is compact

in A.

Proof. We may assume x ~ y. Let (Bt)tEI be a family of sets that are open

III A and whose union contains [x, y] . Set

C := {Z E [x, y] I :3 a finite set J C I such that [x, z] C U Bt} . tEJ

C is evidently bounded. C is also nonempty, since x is in C. It suffices to

show that sup C belongs to C and sup C = y. Note that sup C E Btl for

some t' E I. There is a z in C such that [z, sup C] C Btl, and there is a finite

set J C I such that [x, z] is contained in U Bt . Since (U Bt) U Btl contains tEJ tEJ

[x, sup C], sup C must belong to C. If sup C were strictly less than y, then

Btl would contain the interval [sup C, z'] for some z' satisfying sup C < z' ~ y.

Hence z' would belong to C. This contradiction shows that sup C = y. 0

Theorem 2.10.6 Take C cA. Then the following are equivalent.

a) C is both closed in A and bounded in A.

b) C is compact in A.

c) C is sequentially compact in A.

Proof. a) =} b). Let (Bt)tEI be a family of sets that are open in A and whose

union contains C. By a), there is a closed interval [x, y] from A that contains

C. The set A\C is open in A and its union with U B t contains [x, y]. By tEl

Proposition 5, I has a finite subset J such that (U Bt ) U (A\C) contains tEJ

[x, y]. Hence U B t contains C. tEJ

b) =} c). Suppose that (Xn)nEIN is a sequence from C, no subsequence of

which converges to an element of C. Then the set

D := {xn I n E IN}

is an infinite subset of C. On the other hand, to each x in C we can associate

a strictly positive real number ex such that the interval lx-ex , X+ex[ contains

Page 141: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.10 Stieltjes Functionals and Stieltjes Measures. Lebesgue Measure 419

only finitely many elements of D. Each of the sets An lx - cx, x + cx[ is open

in A, and their union contains G. By hypothesis, G has a finite subset B

such that

G c U (An lx - Cx , x + cx[) . xEB

D is an infinite subset of G, yet the union on the right contains only finitely

many elements of D. We are forced into a contradiction.

c) '* a). This implication follows easily from the definitions. D

Corollary 2.10.7 Let (Gt)tEI be a nonempty family of sets that are compact

in A. If every nonempty finite subfamily of (Gt)tEl has nonempty intersection,

then the intersection n Gt is also nonempty. tEl

Proof Suppose n Gt is empty, and fix LO E I. For each L in I, the set A\Gt tEl

is open in A, and de Morgan's principle shows that U(A\Gt) contains c. a . tEl

It follows that Gta C U (A\Gt) for some finite subset J of I, hence that the tEJ

intersection Gta n ( n Gt) is empty. D tEJ

Definition 2.10.8 Take f E IRA and Q E IR.

a) For x E la, bl, Q is said to be a left-hand limit of f at x if lim f(xn ) = Q n-+oo

for every sequence (Xn)nEIN from [a, xl nA that converges to x.

b) For x E la, b[, Q is a right-hand limit of f at x if lim f(x n ) = Q for n-+oo

every sequence (Xn)nEIN from lx, bl n A that converges to x. D

-A Proposition 2.10.9 Take f E IR and let Q, f3 be extended-real numbers.

Then the following hold.

a) If Q and f3 are both left-hand limits of f at x for some x in la, bl, or

if Q and f3 are both right-hand limits of f at x for some x in [a, b[ ,

then Q = f3.

b) For x E la, bl, Q is a left-hand limit of f at x iff lim f(xn ) = Q for n-+oo

every increasing sequence (Xn)nEIN from [a, x[ nA that converges to x.

c) For x E [a, b[, Q is a right-hand limit of f at x iff lim f(x n ) = Q for n-+oo

every decreasing sequence (Xn)nEIN from lx, bl n A that converges to x.

Page 142: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

420 2. Element.ary Int.egrat.ion Theory

Proof. a) follows from Proposition 1.8.17.

b) For the non-trivial implication, note that every sequence (:Cn)nEI:\ from

[a, x[ nA. for which (X,,)nEH converges to x but (J(Xn))nEl'i does not conwrge

to n has an increasing subsequence with the same two properties.

c) .\Iodify the argument used for b) . 0

-4. Definition 2.10.10 Take f E ffi . For x E la, bl , let f(x-) denote the left-

hand limit of f at x if that limit exists. For x E [a, b[ , let f(:r+) denote the

right-hand limit of f at x if that limit exists. Moreover, f(a-):= f(a) if a

belongs to A, and f(b+):= f(b) if b belongs to A.

Take f E IRA and x EA. The function f is said to be continuous

from the left at x, or simply left-continuous at x, iff f(x-) is defined

and f(x-) = f(x). Similarly f is continuous from the right, or right­

continuous, at x iff f(x+) is defined and f(x+) = f(x). Finally, f is

continuous at x iffboth f(x+) and f(x-) are defined and f(x+) = f(x-) =

f(x).

A function f E IRA is continuous on A (left-continuous on A, right­

continuous on A) iff f is continuous at x (left-continuous at x, righ(­

continuous at x) for every x in A.

A function f E IRA is uniformly continuous on A iff for every E E

IR, E > 0, there is a 5 E IR, 5 > 0, such that

If(x) - f(y)1 < E

for all x, y in A satisfying Ix - yl < 5. o

In light of the following proposition and of Proposition 1.9.7, the definition

of continuity given here agrees with the one given previously for functions f from the metric space A to the metric space IR.

Proposition 2.10.11

lent.

-A Given x E A and f E IR ,the following are equiva-

a) f is continuous at x.

b) f is both left-continuous at x and right-continuous at x.

c) lim f(xn) = f(x) for every sequence (Xn)nEIN from A that converges to n-+oo X.

d) lim inf f(xn) = lim sup f(xnl = f(x) for every sequence (Xn)nEIN from n--+oo n--+oo

A that converges to x. 0

Page 143: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.10 Stieltjes Functionals and Stieltjes Measures. Lebesgue Measure 421

Proposition 2.10.12 If f E]RA is uniformly continuous on A, then f is

continuous on A. o

Recall that C(A) denotes the set of real-valued continuous functions on

A and K(A) the set of all f E C(A) such that {J =1= O} c [x, y] for some

x, yEA. The elements of K(A) are called continuous functions on A with

compact support in A.

Proposition 2.10.13 The sets C(A) and K(A) are both real Stone lattices.

o

Theorem 2.10.14 a) Every function in K(A) assumes on A a maximum

value and a minimum value.

b) Every function in K(A) is uniformly continuous on A (Dirichlet, 1854).

c) For every nonempty family (fL),EI from K(A)+ that is directed down, if

I\f, = 0 (1) LEI

then

inf (sup f,(X)) = o. LEI xEA

(2)

Proof. a) Given f in K(A) , we must show that there are x, yEA such that

sup f(z) = f(x) , inf f(z) = f(y) . zEA zEA

Let D be a nonempty closed interval in A containing {J =1= O}, and choose

from D a sequence (Xn)nEIN such that the sequence (f(Xn))nEIN is increasing

and

sup f(xn) = sup f(z) . nEIN zEA

By Theorem 6 a) => c), this sequence has a subsequence (Xnk)kEIN converging

to some element x of D. Using the continuity of f, we conclude that

f(x) = lim f(xnk ) = sup f(z). k--+oo zEA

The argument for the existence of the required y is similar.

b) Given f in K(A), let D be as in a). Suppose that f fails to be

uniformly continuous on A. Then there are a real number c > 0 and sequences

(Xn)nEIN , (Yn)nEIN from A such that

Page 144: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

422 2. Elementary Integration Theory

(3)

for every n E IN. We may assume that the sequence (Xn)nEIN comes from D.

The sequence (Xn)nEIN therefore has a subsequence (xnk )kEIN that converges to

an element x of D. The corresponding subsequence (Ynk)kEIN must converge

to the same x. Since f is continuous on A,

contradicting (3).

c) Let (fJ'EI be a non empty family from K(A)+ that is directed down,

and suppose that (1) holds. Let c > 0 be given. Fix LO E I. Let D be a

nonempty closed interval in A such that {fLO =I- O} cD. Choose, for each z in

D, an index Lz such that f" ~ fLo and f" (z) < c, and choose a real number

Oz > 0 such that for every z' E ]z - oz, z + oz[ nA we have

f,,(z') < c.

D is compact, so that D contains a finite subset B such that

DC U]z - oz, z + oz[. zEB

Since (f')'EI is directed down, we may choose TEl so that /;: ~ f" for every

z in B. It follows that

inf supf,(z) ~ sup/;:(z) ~ c ,EI zEA zEA

and finally, since c was arbitrary, that (2) holds. o

Definition 2.10.15 (Baire, 1897) A function f E IRA is said to be:

a) lower semicontinuous at x, for x E A, iff

f(x) ~ lim inf f(xn) n--+oo

for every sequence (Xn)nEIN from A that converges to x;

b) upper semicontinuous at x, for x E A, iff

f(x) ~ lim sup f(xn) n--+oo

for every sequence (Xn)nEIN from A that converges to x;

Page 145: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.10 Stieltjes Functionals and Stieltjes Measures. Lebesgue Measure 423

c) lower semicontinuous on A iff f is lower semicontinuous at x for

every x in A;

d) upper semicontinuous on A iff f is upper semicontinuous at x for

every x in A. 0

-A Proposition 2.10.16 A function f E JR is continuous at x, for x E A,

iff f is both lower semicontinuous at x and upper semicontinuous at x. A

function f E JRA is continuous on A iff it is both lower semicontinuous on A

and upper semicontinuous on A.

Proof. Apply Proposition 11 a) - d) and Proposition 1.8.23 a) . o

-A Proposition 2.10.17 For x E A and f E JR , the function f is upper

semicontinuous at x iff the function - f is lower semicontinuous at x. 0

For real-valued functions, there is the following c-8 characterization of

semicontinuity.

Proposition 2.10.18 For x E A and f E JRA, the function f is:

a) lower semicontinuous at x iff for every c > 0, there is a 8 > 0 such that

f(y) > f(x) - c

for every y E]x - 8, x + b"[ nA;

b) upper semicontinuous at x iff for every c > 0, there is a 8 > 0 such that

f(y) < f(x) + c

for every y E ]x - 8, x + 8[ nA .

Proof. a) Let f be a real-valued function on A that is lower semicontinuous

at x. If the characterization in a) were false, then there would be an c > 0 and

a sequence (Xn)nEIN from A such that

1 Ix - xnl < -, f(x n) ~ f(x) - c

n

for every n. For this sequence we would have lim Xn = x, but n .... oo

lim inf f(x n) ~ f(x) - c, n .... oo

which contradicts the lower semicontinuity. Conversely, the c-8 condition stated

in a) obviously implies that f is lower semicontinuous at x.

b) In view of Proposition 17, b) follows from a). o

Page 146: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

424 2. Elementary Integration Theory

Proposition 2.10.19 -A

Take f E lR and let 0: be a real number.

a) If f is lower semicontinuous on A, then {J ~ o:} is closed in A and

{J > o:} is open in A.

b) If f is upper semicontinuous on A, then {J 2: o:} is closed in A and

{J < o:} is open in A.

Proof. a) It suffices to verify that {J ~ o:} is closed in A. Take x E A, and

let (Xn)nEIN be a sequence from {f ~ o:} that converges to x. Then

f(x) ~ lim inf f(xn) ~ 0:. n-+oo

b) can be proved analogously. o

Having completed our review, we are ready to construct the Stieltjes func­

tionals.

Definition 2.10.20 A partition of the interval A is a family (xkhEINn such

that n 2: 2, each Xk belongs to A, Xk ~ Xk+l for every k E INn-I, Xl = a if

a belongs to A, and Xn = b if b belongs to A.

Given two partitions (Xk)kEIN n and (Yl)lEIN m of the interval A, the partition

(xkhEINn is said to be finer than the partition (Yl)lEINm iff for every £, in INm

there is a k in INn such that Yl = Xk .

The set of all partitions of A is denoted by P(A). Given f E K:(A), we

denote by P(A; J) the set of all partitions (Xk)kEINn of A that satisfy

Given f E K(A) and g E lRA , and given a partition (xkhEINn' which we

call p, belonging to P(A; J), we define, for each k in INn-I,

and we define

n-l

rp*(J,g;p):= Lmk(J)/lk9, k=l

Page 147: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.10 Sticltjes Fllnctionals and Stieltjes Measures. Lebesgue Measure 425

n-I

'P*(J,g;p):= L11h(f)!::,.kg. k=1

The numbers 'P* (J, g; p) and tp* (J, g; p) are called, respectively, the lower and

upper Stieltjes sums for the function f relative to the function 9 and corre­

sponding to the partition p. 0

Although upper and lower Stieltjes sums have been defined for arbitrary

real-valued functions g, it is only when 9 is increasing that these sums are of

interest. The next proposition summarizes important properties of upper and

lower Stieltjes sums for increasing g. These properties all follow easily from the

definitions.

Proposition 2.10.21 Let 9 E ffiA be increasing.

a) For every f in JC(A) and for every partition p in P(A; f) ,

'P*(J,g;p):::; 'P*(J,g;p).

b) For every f in JC(A) and for all partitions PI,P2 in P(A; f), if PI zs

finer than P2, then

c) For every f in JC(A) and for all partitions Pb P2 in P(A; 1) ,

d) For all fl,12 in JC(A) , and for every partition P that belongs to both

P(A; h) and P(A; h) ,

47* (!I +12, g; p) 2:: 47*(Jl, g; p) + 47*(12, g; p),

e) For every f in JC(A) , every positive real number a, and every partition

P in P(A; 1),

Page 148: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

426 2. Elementary Integration Theory

and

<p*(aj,g;p) = a<p*(J,g;p)

<p*(-aj,g;p) = -a<p*(J,g;p),

<p*(-aj,g;p) = -a<p*(J,g;p).

Theorem 2.10.22 (F. Stieltjes, 1894) Let 9 E IRA be increasing.

a) For every f in K(A) ,

inf (<p*(J,g;p)-<p*(J,g;p)) =0. PEP(A;f)

b) For each f in K(A) , there is exactly one real number fg(J) such that

for every partition p in P(A; j) .

c) The mapping

is a nullcontinuous, positive, linear functional.

d) The triple (A,K(A),fg) is a Daniell space.

o

Proof. a) Take f in K(A) and c > o. Fix points c and d in A such that

{J i- O} c [e, d]. By Theorem 14 b), we can choose 6> 0 so that

c If(x) - f(y)1 < 1 + g(d) - g(e)

for all x, y in A satisfying Ix - yl < 6. Now choose from P(A; f) a partition

p = (Xk)kElNn such that IXk+l - xkl < 6 for each k in INn- 1 and such that

e = Xk 1 for some kl in INn, d = Xk2 for some k2 in INn. Then

n-l

o $. <p*(J,g;p) - <p*(J,g;p) = E (Mk(J) - mk(J)) f1 kg $. k=l

c $. 1 + g(d) _ g(e) (g(d) - g(e)) < c.

b) In view of Proposition 21 c), the existence follows from the completeness

of IR. Uniqueness then follows from a).

Page 149: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.10 Stieitjes Functionais and Stieitjes Measures. Lebesgue Measure 427

c) To show that £9 is additive, let 11 and 12 belong to K(A). Let P1 be

an arbitrary partition in P(A; Id and P2 an arbitrary partition in P(A; 12) . It is easy to find a partition P that belongs to each of the sets

P(A; Ii) , P(A; h) , P(A; 11 + 12)

and is finer than both P1 and P2. For such a partition P, we have (using

Proposition 21)

Since

cP*(h,g;P1) + cP*(h,g;P2) :S CP*(J1,g;P) + cp*(h,g;p)

:S CP*(J1 + h,g;p)

:S £9(h + h)

:S cp*(h + h,g;p)

:S cp*(h,g;p) + cp*(h,g;p)

:S cp* (J1, g; pd + cp* (12, g; P2) .

Cp* (f1, g; pd + Cp* (12, g; P2) :S £9(fd + £9(12)

:S CP*(J1,g;P1) + CP*(f2,g;P2)

and since P1 and P2 were arbitrary, it follows from a) that

We leave it to the reader to show that the functional £9 is homogeneous

and positive.

Finally, we must verify that £9 is nullcontinuous. Let (fn)nEIN be a se­

quence from K(A) that is decreasing and satisfies 1\ In = O. Each partition nEIN

in P(A; 11) also belongs to P(A; In) for every n. Let P := (Xk)kElN m be such

a partition. Then

Applying Theorem 14 c), we conclude that

d) is a consequence of c) and Proposition 13. o

Page 150: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

428 2. Elementary Integration Theory

Definition 2.10.23 Let g be an increasing rocal-valued function on A. The

functional £g : JC(A) -+ lR described in the preceding theorem is called the

Stieltjes functional on JC(A) associated with g. 0

Incidentally, we have not yet introduced the so--called Riemann- Stieltjes

integrals, integrals that are defined on a wider class of functions, in general,

than the Stieltjes functionals £g. Riemann-Stieltjes integrals are considerably

more difficult to obtain than Stieltjes functionals, and they lost their theoret­

ical usefulness with the appearance of Lebesgue integrals. The extensions that

we develop in the sequel will yield more extensive integrals and with better

properties than Riemann-Stieltjes integrals.

The reader will have noticed that the functional £g corresponding to the

identity function g, defined by g(x) := x for every x, assigns to each I E JC(A)

its Riemann integral.

Theorem 2.10.24 -A

Take IE 1R .

a) f E JC(A)t iff I is lower semicontinuous on A and I > h lor some

hE JC(A) .

b) f E JC(A)~ iff I is upper semicontinuous on A and f < h for some

It E JC(A).

Proof. a) Take f E JC(A)t. There is an increasing sequence (fn)nEIN from

JC(A) whose supremum is I. Given x in A, let (Xn)nEIN be a sequence from

A that converges to x. Since I(Y) 2: fk(Y) for every Y in A and for every

k E IN , we have

for every k. It follows that

lim inf I(xn ) 2: I(x) n-+oo

so f is lower semicontinuous at x.

Conversely, assume that I is lower semicontinuous on A and that I 2: h

for some h in JC(A). For now, we also assume that I is real-valued. First, we

construct an increasing sequence of continuous functions on A whose supremum

is I. For each k in IN define

!k:A~IR., x f-----+ inf(f(z) + klx - zl). zEA

Page 151: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.10 Stieltjes Functionals and Stieltjes Measures. Lebesgue Measure 429

Note that the sequence (Jk)kEIN is increasing and that fk :::; f for every k. We

show that each fk is uniformly continuous on A. Fix k E IN , take c > 0 and

suppose that x, yEA satisfy Ix - yl < c/2k. There is a z E A such that

c fk(X) ~ f(z) + klx - zl- "2.

Since

fk(Y) :::; f(z) + kly - zl :::; f(z) + k(ly - xl + Ix - zl)

we have that

Interchanging x and y, we conclude that

lik(x) - fk(y)1 < c.

Evidently, V fk:::; f . We show that V ik ~ f . Fix x E A, and let c > 0 kEIN kEIN

be given. By Proposition 18 a), there is a 6> 0 such that f(y) > f(x) - c for

every y in ]x - 6, x + 6[ nA. For each k, we therefore have

f(y) + klx - yl > f(x) - c, Y E]x - 6,x + 6[nA.

If y belongs to A \]x - 6, x + 6[ , then for each k we have

f(y) + klx - yl ~ h(y) + k6 ~ inAf h(z) + k6. zE

Hence there is a ko in IN such that for k ~ ko ,

f(y) + klx- yl > f(x) -€, Y E A\]x- 6,x+6[.

It follows for k ~ ko that fk(X) ~ f(x) - c. Thus V fk(X) ~ f(x) - c. Since kEIN

c was arbitrary, we have

V fk(X) ~ f(x) , kEIN

as required.

We still need an increasing sequence from K(A) whose supremum is f. Because f ~ h, we have, for every k, inf fk(Z) > -00, and {ik < O} C [e, d]

zEA for appropriate points e, d belonging to A. For each k in IN construct an

increasing sequence (ik,n)nEIN from K(A) whose supremum is the continuous

function fk: Put !k.n(x) := fk(X) for every x E Uk :::; O} and every n E IN

Page 152: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

430 2. Elementary Integration Theory

and use Proposition 3 for defining the functions fk,n appropriately on the set

{lk > O}. Put

hn := V fk,n (n E IN) . k$n

Then (hn)nEIN is the required sequence from K(A).

Now suppose that f is not necessarily real-valued but does satisfy the

conditions stated in a). Take m E IN. Then f /\ m is real-valued and f /\ m ;:::

h /\ m E K(A). Take x E A, and let (Xn)nEIN be a sequence from A that converges to x. Then

(f /\ m)(x) = f(x) /\ m::; (sup inf f(Xk )) /\ m = nEIN k2;:n

= sup inf(f(xk) /\ m) = lim inf(f /\ m)(xn). nEIN k;:>:n n ..... oo

Thus f /\ m is lower semicontinuous. By what we have already proved, f /\ m E K(A)t. Now Proposition 2.3.2 f) implies that

f = V (f /\ m) E K(A)t. mEIN

b) In view of Proposition 17 and Proposition 2.3.4, b) follows from a). 0

Corollary 2.10.25 Let 9 be an increasing real-valued function on A and

suppose that f belongs to the Riesz lattice £(eg). Then for each c > 0, there

is in £(£g) a function f', upper semicontinuous on A, and a function f", lower semicontinuous on A, such that

f' ::; f ::; f" and £g(f") - £g(f') < c.

The functions f' and f" can be chosen so that for every Q E 1R, Q > 0, the

sets {I';::: Q}, {I" ::; -Q} are bounded in A. 0

The following result applies in particular to the Stieltjes functionals £g.

Theorem 2.10.26 For every positive, linear, nullcontinuous functional i on

K(A) , the following assertions hold.

a) (A, £(£), £) = (A, £1(£), Ii), and £1(£) is a Stone lattice.

b) The positive measure space (A, !J't(£1(i)), J,Jl) induced by (A, £1(£), It) is

closed, and (A, !J't(£1(£))) is a a-finite measurable space.

Page 153: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.10 Stieltjes Functionals and Stieltjes Measures. Lebesgue Measure 431

Proof. a) The Stone lattice K(A) is clearly a-finite. Thus a) follows from

Corollary 2.4.14 and Proposition 2.5.18.

b) is a consequence of a), Theorem 2.6.20 and Proposition 2.6.19. 0

Definition 2.10.27 Let 9 be an increasing real-valued function on A. Then

the integral for the Daniell space (A, K(A), £g), which we denote as usual by

(A, £1(£g), It ), is called the Stieltjes integral associated with g. The positive o

measure induced on !Jt(£I(£g)) by flo shall be denoted by J1-g. The closed posi-

tive measure space (A, !Jt(£1 (£g)), J1-g) induced by the Stieltjes integral associated

with 9 is called the Stieltjes measure space associated with g. The measure

J1-g is called the Stieltjes measure on A associated with g. For f E £1 (J1-g) , we write

lfdg:= If(x)dg(x) := lfdJ1-g.

Quite generally, a positive measure J1- on a ring of subsets of A is said to be

a Stieltjes measure on A iff J1- = J1-g for some increasing real-valued function

9 on A. 0

According to Theorem 2.7.18, the Daniell-space integral called the Stieltjes

integral associated with 9 is the same as the measure-space integral of the

Stieltjes measure space associated with g; that is,

In preparation for describing what kind of sets belong to £(A, J1-g) we define

Borel sets, Ka-sets, and Go-sets, and examine a few of their properties.

Definition 2.10.28 ~(A) denotes the 8-ring generated by the subsets of A

that are closed in A. Sets belonging to ~(A) are called the Borel sets in A.

We use "Borel measurable" as a synonym for ''I.B(A)-measurable'' {provided

A is evident from the context}.

~b(A) denotes the set consisting of all Borel sets in A that are also bounded

in A.

A subset C of A is called a Ka-set in A {Fa-set in A} iff it can be

written as the union of a countable family of sets that are compact {closed}

in A. A subset C of A is called a Grset in A iff it can be written as the

intersection of a countable family of sets that are open in A. 0

Page 154: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

432 2. Elementary Integration Theory

The reader can readily verify the following proposition.

Proposition 2.10.29 a) Intervals from A are Krr-sets in A.

b) The Krr-sets in A, the Frr-sets in A and the Grsets in A are all Borel

sets in A. 0

Proposition 2.10.30 a) The Borel sets in A form a a-algebra on A. A

subset of A is Borel measurable iff it is a Borel set.

b) ~(A) is the a-algebra on A generated by the compact subsets of A.

c) ~(A) is the a-algebra on A generated by the intervals that are closed

and bounded in A.

d) ~(A) is the a-algebra on A generated by

J := {[x, yll x, yEA, x ::; y} .

e) The Borel sets in A that are bounded in A form a 6-ring. In fact, ~b(A)

is the 6 -ring generated by the intervals that are closed and bounded in A.

f) For Be A, B is Borel-measurable iff B is ~b(A)-measurable.

Proof. a) Since A is closed in A, a) follows from Propositions 2.7.15 and

2.8.2.

b) Let <5 denote the a-algebra on A generated by the sets that are com­

pact in A. Since compact sets of A are closed in A, <5 c ~(A), by a). In

view of Propositions 3 and 29 a), every set that is open in A is a Krr-set in A

and therefore belongs to <5. Hence every set that is closed in A belongs to <5, and we conclude that ~(A) C <5.

e) Denote by 9l the 6-ring generated by the intervals that are closed and

bounded in A. Since the set 'I' of all subsets of A that are bounded in A is

obviously a 6-ring, we obtain

9l c ~(A) n'I' = ~b(A) .

For D an interval that is closed and bounded in A, put

<5(D) := {B E ~(A) IBn DE 9l}.

Evidently, <5(D) is a a-algebra on A containing all intervals that are closed in

A. Since every set which is open in A can be written as the union of countably

Page 155: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.10 Stieltjes Functionals and Stieitjes Measures. Lebesgue Measure 433

many closed intervals, 6(D) contains all sets that are open in A and hence

all sets that are closed in A. Thus !B(A) C 6(D) .

Now take B E !Bb(A). Choose an interval D that is closed and bounded

in A and contains B. Then B E 6(D) and hence B = B n D E 9t. Thus

!Bb(A) C 9t.

c) follows from a) and e) .

d) can easily be deduced from c) .

f) The inclusion IDt(A, !B(A)) c IDt(A, !Bb(A)) is evident. So take C in

IDt(A, !Bb(A). Choose an increasing sequence (An)nEIN of compact intervals

from A whose union is A. For each n, C n An E !Bb(A) C !B(A) . Hence

C = U (C nAn) E !B(A) . o nEIN

We can now characterize Ilg-integrable sets.

Theorem 2.10.31 Let Il be a Stieltjes measure on A.

a) Every Borel set in A is Il-measurable.

b) Every Borel set in A that is bounded in A is Il-integrable.

Moreover, given a subset D of A, the following are equivalent.

c) D is Il-integrable.

d) For every real number e > 0 there is an open set B of A and a compact

set C of A, both belonging to '£(A, Il) such that

C cDC Band J-t(B) - Il(C) < e.

e) There are a Grset B and a K,,-set C, both belonging to '£(A, Il) such

that

C cDc Band B\C E I)1(A, Il) .

f) D can be written as the disjoint union of all-integrable K,,-set in A

and a Il-null set in A.

Page 156: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

434 2. Elementary Integration Theory

Proof a) Let C be an interval that is closed and bounded in A. Construct

f E K(A)+ such that C = {f = I}. In view of Propositions 2.9.2 d) and 2.8.3

f), C E oot(A, p,) . It follows that 23(A) c oot(A, p,) (Proposition 30 c)).

b) Take B E 23 b(A) . There is an interval C which is closed and bounded

in A and contains B. Taking f as in the proof of a), we have eB $; f. Then,

according to Corollary 2.9.11 a), eB E .c1(A,p,).

c) ::::} d). Let 9 be an increasing real-valued function on A such that

IJ = lJy and let c > 0 be given. By virtue of Theorem 26 a) and Corollary

25, there is an upper semicontinuous function f' and a lower semi continuous

function f" such that

I' $; e D $; f" ,

V Q: E R, Q: > 0, {I' ~ Q:} is bounded in A,

£g(l") - £g(l') < c/2.

The sequence (e{!'2: 1/ n })nEIN is an increasing IJ-sequence whose supremum lies between f' and e D. Therefore

and there is an m E IN such that

Put

B := {I" > I}, C:= {f' ~ ~} .

By Proposition 19, B is open in A and C is closed in A. Since C is also

bounded in A, it is compact in A (Theorem 6 a) ::::} b)). Thus, using b) ,

C E 'c(A, IJ) . By a), B is IJ-measurable, and eB $; f" . According to Corollary

2.9.11 a), BE 'c(A, IJ) . Moreover, C CDC Band

d) ::::} e) ::::} f) ::::} c). These implications are evident. o

Page 157: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.10 Stieltjes Functionals and Stieltjes Measures. Lebesgue Measure 435

Corollary 2.10.32 Let I-' be a Stieltjes measure on A. Then, for every set

DE 'c(A, 1-'),

I-'(D) = inf{I-'(B) I B E 'c(A, 1-') , DeB, B is open in A}

= sup{I-'(C) ICc D, C is compact in A}.

o

Corollary 2.10.33 Every Lower semicontinuous extended-reaL-valued func­

tion on A is BoreL measurabLe, ~b(A) -measurabLe, and l-'-measurabLe for every

Stieltjes measure I-' on A. The same assertions hoLd for every upper semicon­

tinuous extended-reaL-vaLued function on A.

Proof Note that for each real a, the set {J < a} is open in A if f is upper

semicontinuous and is an FI1 -set in A if f is lower semicontinuous (Proposition

19), and apply Propositions 29, 30 f) and Theorem 31 a) . 0

Proposition 2.10.34 Let I-' be a Stieltjes measure on A. Let 9l be a set­

ring contained in 'c(A,I-') such that 916 contains every intervaL from A that is

bounded in A. Set

v:= I-'I!R

and denote by (A, c" €) the Daniell space associated with the positive measure

space (A, 9l, v). Then

(4)

(5)

Proof By Proposition 2.5.8, every set from 916 is contained in a set from 9l.

Using the hypothesis on intervals from A, we conclude that the pair (A,9l)

is a-finite. The closure and the completion of (A, 9l, v) are therefore identical

(Proposition 2.7.12). Since (A,'c(A,I-'),I-') is a closed positive measure space

extending (A, 9l, v) , it follows that

(Proposition 2.7.2). To complete the proof of (4), we need only show that

'c(A,I-') c 'c(A, v) . Define

Page 158: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

436 2. Elementary Integration Theory

(5 := {B E .c(A, J-L) I B E .c(A, v) and vA(B) = J-L(B) } .

Take B E .c(A, J-L) , and suppose that B is open in A. Then B can be

written as a countable disjoint union of intervals open in A. Each interval

open in A can be written as a countable disjoint union of intervals (half­

open, half-closed) that are bounded in A. These latter intervals belong to (5.

Countable additivity (Theorem 2.6.4) together with Corollary 2.6.21 c) imply

that B E (5. In view of Corollary 32, every J-L-integrable Go-set in A is the

intersection of a decreasing sequence of J-L-integrable sets that are open in A.

Since .c(A, J-L)n.c(A, v) is a a-ring and J-L and vA are nullcontinuous, it follows

that J-L-integrable Go-sets in A must all belong to (5.

Now let B be a compact set of A. Choose an interval C containing B such that C is bounded and open in A. Then C belongs to .c(A, J-L) (Theorem

31 b)), C\B is open in A, and both C and C\B must belong to (5. Writing

B as C\(C\B), we see that B belongs to (5. Using Corollary 2.6.21 a) , we

conclude that J-L-integrable K,,-sets in A belong to (5.

Take B E .c(A, J-L). By Theorem 31 c) => e), there are a J-L-integrable

Go-set D and a J-L-integrable K,,-set C such that C c BcD and D\C is J-L-null. Both C and D belong to (5, so D\C is v-null, so B\C is v­null. As the union of the v-integrable set C and the v-null set B\C, B is

v-integrable. Hence .c(A, J-L) c .c(A, v), proving (4).

Finally, (5) is a consequence of (4), Corollary 2.7.9 and Proposition 2.7.12.

o

Proposition 34 is very useful. It enables us to specify simple set systems for

which the accompanying collection of measures is in one-to-one correspondence

with the set of Stieltjes measures on A. This possibility, which we pursue more

thoroughly in Chapter 6, after real Stieltjes measures have been defined, makes

the rather complicated Stieltjes measures easier to manage.

In preparation for stating the values assigned by Stieltjes measures to the

intervals from A, we make a straightforward observation, which the reader can

readily verify.

Proposition 2.10.35 Let g be an increasing real-valued function on A.

a) For every x E A\{a}, g(x-) exists and

g(x-) = sup{g(y) lyE la, x[} .

b) For every x E A\{b}, g(x+) exists and

Page 159: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.10 Stieltjes Functionals and Stieltjes Measures. Lebesgue Measure 437

g(x+) = inf{g(y) lyE lx, b[} . o

Theorem 2.10.36 Let 9 be an increasing real-valued function on A. If

x, yEA and x :::; y, then

{Lg([x, y]) = g(y+) - g(x-) .

If x, yEA and x < y, then

{Lg( lx, y]) = g(y+) - g(x+) ,

{Lg( [x, y[) = g(y-) - g(x-) ,

{Lg(]x, y[) = g(y-) - g(x+) .

For each x E A, {x} is a {Lg -null set iff 9 is continuous at x.

Proof Let x and Y belong to A with x :::; y. First, choose from A a sequence

(Xn)nEIN that is either strictly increasing (if x =1= a) or constant (if x = a) but

in any case has its supremum equal to x. Next, choose from A a sequence

(Yn)nEIN that is either strictly decreasing (if Y =1= b) or constant (if y = b) but

in any case has its infimum equal to y. For n in 1N, define

1 if Z E [x, y]

0 if Z E A\[xn, Yn]

fn: A --+ JR, Z t---+ Z - Xn X-Xn

if Z E [xn,x[

Yn - Z if Z E ]y, Yn] .

Yn - Y

Note that Un)nEIN is a decreasing sequence from K(A) whose infimum is e[x,y] •

Hence

(6)

Consider the partition

of the interval [xn, Yn]. It is easy to calculate CP* Un, g; Pn) and cp* Un' g; Pn) , and to verify that

Page 160: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

438 2. Elementary Integration Theory

Since

for every n E IN, it follows from (6) that

J-tg([x, yl) = g(y+) - g(x-) .

Now suppose that x, yEA and x < y. Since

[x, yl = lx, yl U [x, xl = [x, y[ U [y, y],

[x, y[ = lx, y[ u [x, xl

and these are all disjoint unions, the remaining formulas follow from the formula

already established.

From what has already been proved, J-tg({x}) = g(x+) - g(x-) for every

x in A. Thus J-tg ( {x}) = 0 iff g is continuous at x. 0

Corollary 2.10.37 Suppose that A = la, b[. Take x E A and let g be an increasing real function on A.

a) la, x[ E £(J-tg) - la, xl E £(J-tg) - g(a+) f= -00, and in this case

J-tg( la, x[) = g(x-) - g(a+) ,

J-tg( la, xl) = g(x+) - g(a+) .

b) lx, b[ E £(J-tg) - [x, b[ E £(J-tg) - g(b-) f= 00, and in this case

J-tg(lx,b[) = g(b-) - g(x+),

J-tg([x, b[) = g(b-) - g(x-) .

c) A E £(J-tg) - g is bounded - J-tg is bounded, and in this case

J-tg(A) = g(b-) - g(a+) .

d) J-tg = 0 - g is constant. o

Page 161: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.10 Stieltjes Functionals and Stieltjes Measures. Lebesgue Measure 439

Corollary 2.10.38 Let g be an increasing real-valued function on A. Then

the following are equivalent.

a) The function g is continuous on A.

b) Every countable subset of A is J.Lg-null.

c) For every x E A, the set {x} is J.Lg -null. o

We now come to the most important example of a StieJtjes measure, namely

Lebesgue measure. This measure distinguishes itself from other StieJtjes mea­

sures by its translation invariance, its special link with the algebraic structure

of IR.

Definition 2.10.39 The Stieltjes measure J.Lg associated with the identity

function

g:A---+A, Xl---+X

is called the Lebesgue measure on A . We denote the Lebesgue measure on A

by AA. The integral associated with AA is called the Lebesgue integral on A.

We use "Lebesgue measurable on or in A", "Lebesgue integrable on or in

A" and "Lebesgue null" as synonyms for "AA-measurable", AA-integrable",

and "AA -null", respectively. -A

For f E IR and x, yEA, if x ~ y and fejx,y[ E £1 (AA), we define

l Y f(t)dt:= lY

fdt:= ! fejx,y[dAA,

luX f(t)dt:= luX fdt := -lY f(t)dt. 0

Corollary 2.10.40 Every countable subset of A is Lebesgue null. The Lebesgue

measure on A is bounded iff the interval A is bounded in IR.

Proof Apply Corollaries 37 c) and 38. o

Theorem 2.10.41 (Translation invariance 0/ Lebesgue measure on IR).

Let A be Lebesgue measure on IR. Let f be an extended-real-valued function

on IR and B a subset of IR. For "I E IR, define

R, := {x + "I I x E B},

Iy : IR ---+ IR, X 1---+ f(x - "I) .

Let "I be a real number.

Page 162: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

440 2. Elementary Integration Theory

a) I is Lebesgue integrable on JR iff 1'"( is Lebesgue integrable on JR, and

in this case

b) B is Lebesgue integrable in JR iff B'"( is Lebesgue integrable in JR, and

in this case

c) I is Lebesgue measurable on JR iff 1'"( is.

d) B is Lebesgue measurable in JR iff B'"( is.

Prool. a) Let J be the set of all bounded intervals from JR. It is easily verified that

6 := {U A. I (A.).EI is a finite family from J} .EI

is a ring of sets. Hence 6 is the set-ring generated by J. Put v:= Ais . Then, by Proposition 34,

(7)

Fix 'Y E JR and put

In view of (7), it suffices to prove that :F = £1(JR, v). We use the Induction

Principle.

By the formulas of Theorem 36, every 6-step function belongs to :F. The

reader can readily verify that lim In E:F for every v-sequence (fn)nEIN from n-+oo

:F. Finally, take I E :F and g E JRIR with g = I v-a.e. If we can show that

B'"( E IJt(JR, v) whenever B E IJt(JR, v) , it will follow that g E :F. But in view

of Proposition 2.7.12 b), this is a consequence of the characterization of null

sets given in Theorem 2.7.6 k) and the formulas from Theorem 36.

It follows from Theorem 2.4.17 that :F = £1 (JR, v) , as claimed.

b) Note that (eB)'"( = e(B~) , and apply a) .

c) Suppose IE M(JR, A)+ and 'Y E JR. By b), C(_'"() belongs to ..c(JR, A) for every Lebesgue integrable set C. Applying Proposition 2.9.13 a) => c) to

Page 163: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.10 Stieltjes Functionals and Stieltjes Measures. Lebesgue Measure 441

the measure space (JR, £(JR, A), A), we conclude that f /\ aec(_,) belongs to

C} (JR, A) for every positive real number a and every Lebesgue integrable set

C. By a), f-y /\ aec belongs to C} (JR, A) for every positive real number a and

every Lebesgue integrable set C. Now Proposition 2.9.13 c) ~ a) shows that

f,y is Lebesgue measurable.

For arbitrary Lebesgue measurable f on JR, note that f = f+ - f- , and

apply what has already been proved to the functions f+ , f- .

d) This assertion follows from c) . o

An analogous theorem obviously holds for Lebesgue measure on an arbitrary

interval A, provided we restrict "I so that AA(B-y) and f f-ydA A are defined.

An interesting question arises: Is every subset of JR Lebesgue measurable?

The following non-trivial example, answering this question, is due to Vitali

(1905).

Theorem 2.10.42 Every Lebesgue integrable set in JR, whose Lebesgue mea­

sure is strictly positive, has a subset that is not Lebesgue measurable in JR.

Proof. Take B E £(lR, AIR) with AIR(B) > O. Without loss of generality

assume, for some m in IN, that

Be [-m,m].

Define an equivalence relation on B as follows:

x - y:- x - y E (Q.

Choose one element (Axiom of Choice!) from each equivalence class, and let C

be the set consisting of the chosen elements of B. We claim that the subset C

is not AIR-measurable.

Let

<p: IN ----+ [-2m, 2m] n(Q

be bijective. For n in IN, define

Cn := {x + <p(n) I x E C}.

Then (Cn)nEIN is a disjoint sequence, and

Be U Cn e [-3m, 3m]. (8) nEIN

Page 164: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

442 2. Elementary Integration Theory

As a subset of a Ant-integrable set, if C were Ant-measurable, it would also

be Ant-integrable. Since Ant is translation invariant, each Cn would also be

Ant-integrable and satisfy

In view of (8), we would have

0< Ant(B) ::; L:* Ant(Cn ) ::; 6m neIN

hence

for every n in IN. This last inequality is not possible. Thus C cannot belong

to VJ1(JR, Ant) . 0

Exercises

E 2.10.1 (E)

We offer a different way to construct Stieltjes measures on A = la, b[ . Let

9 : A -+ JR be increasing and left-continuous, and define

Vg : 3 ---t JR, [x, yl f---t g(y) - g(x) .

(3 denotes the set of all right half-open intervals in A.)

Prove the following propositions.

(a) If B E 3 and if (A.),El is a finite disjoint family from 3 with U A, c B, ,el

then 0 ::; E vg(A,) ::; vg(B) . ,el

({J) If BE 3 and if (A.),El is a finite disjoint family from 3 with B = U A. , ,el

then vg(B) = E vg(A,) . ,el

(-y) If B E 3 and if (A.),el is a finite family from 3 with B c U A., then ,el

vg(B) ::; E vg(A.) . ,el

(6) vg(B) 2:: 0 for any B E 3.

(c) Vg is a u-additive positive content on 3.

Page 165: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.10 Stieltjes Functionals and Stieltjes Measures. Lebesgue Measure 443

(Take [x, y[ E .j and let ([xn' Yn[ )nEIN be a disjoint sequence from .j with

[x, Y[ = U [xn' Yn[ . Take E: > O. By the left-continuity of g, there are a Z E nEIN

lx, y[ and Zn E A, Zn < Xn (for each n E IN) with g(y) - g(z) < E:/2 and

g(xn) - g(zn) < E:/2n +l for each n E IN. [x, zl c U lZn' Yn[ , and so there is a nEIN

finite N c IN with [x, z[ c U ]Zn' Yn[ . Using ('y), g(y) - g(x):s L (g(Yn)-nEN nEIN

g(xn )) + E: . Thus

g(y) - g(x) :S :L)g(Yn) - g(xn)) nEIN

since E: was arbitrary. The converse follows from (a), showing the a-additivity

of IIg .)

(() If 9 E lRA is an increasing left-continuous function, then there is exactly

one positive measure, Jig, on the ring of sets of the interval forms of

A, .jr, with Jig ([x, y[) = g(y) - g(x) for each [x, y[ E .j with x :S y.

(7]) Given a positive measure on .jr, /1, there is an increasing left-continuous

function 9 E lRA with /1 = Jig.

(19) If 9 and h are increasing left-continuous functions on A with Jig = Jih ,

then 9 = h + I for some I E lR.

Of course, we have Jig = /1glJr , where /1g denotes the Stieltjes measure associ­

ated with g.

The reader may wonder why we have carried out the constructions of this

exercise only for left continuous g. The next exercise shows that this is no real

restriction.

E 2.10.2 (E)

Prove the following.

(a) Let 9 E lRA be increasing. For each x E A, define ax := g(x+) - g(x-) .

Then ax 2: 0 for each x E A, and 9 is continuous at x iff ax = 0 .

((3) If [a, (3l c A, then (ax)xE[et,lll is summable, and L ax:S g((3) - g(a) . xE [et,lll

('y) The set of points at which 9 is discontinuous is countable.

(0) If gl and g2 are increasing functions on A with the same points of

continuity such that gl(X) = g2(X) in each point x of continuity, then

/1g1 = /1g2 .

Page 166: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

444 2. Elementary Integration Theory

(c) If g is an increasing function on A, then there is exactly one left­

continuous increasing function 9 on A such that g(x) = g(x) in every

point x of continuity of g.

() J-Lg restricted to the ring of sets of the interval forms of A is identical with

jig in the sense of Exercise 2.10.1.

(77) If g is an increasing function on A, then

E 2.10.3 (C)

Generalized Cantor sets. Let (On)nEIN be a sequence of numbers in 10, 1 [. Denote

by ).,(I) the length of the interval I em.. Take a, b Em., a < b, and set

,:=(a+b)/2. From the interval [a, bl remove an open interval, Ill, of length odb - al

centered on ,. This leaves two disjoint closed intervals, J u and J 12 . Now

remove from J li the open interval I2i of length (2).,(Jli) centered on the

midpoint of J li (i = 1,2). This yields four pairwise disjoint closed intervals,

J 21 , J 22 , J 23 , J 24 . Next remove the open intervals I3i of length (3).,(J2i ) cen­

tered on the midpoint of J2i . This leaves 8 (= 23) pairwise disjoint closed

intervals J3i (i E {I, 2, ... , 8}). Continuing in this way, construct, for each

n E IN, 2n pairwise disjoint closed intervals Jni (i E IN 2n ) . The set

is called the generalized Cantor set determined by (On)nEIN. The set

is the classical Cantor set. (H.I.S. Smith, 1875; Volterra, 1881; Cantor, 1883.)

Denote by Ct (resp. CT ) the set of left (resp. right) endpoints of the inter­

vals Jni (n E IN, i E IN2n). Prove the statements that follow.

(0) Ct and CT are countably infinite disjoint subsets of C .

(/3) Given xEC and c>O, lX-c,xlnct #0 and [x,x+c[nCT #0.

b) Every point of C is a point of accumulation both of Ct and CT'

Page 167: Advanced Integration Theory || Elementary Integration Theory

2.10 Stieltjes Functionals and Stieltjes Measures. Lebesgue Measure 445

(0) C is a perfect set, i.e. C coincides with the set of its points of accumu­

lation.

(c) C has no interior points.

(() C is nowhere dense in JR.

(1]) There is a bijection from C onto the set of all sequences from {O, I}.

Hence C has the same cardinality as JR.

From now on, denote by C the classical Cantor set.

(19) There is exactly one increasing function 9 on [0,1] such that 9 is equal

to (2i - I)/2n on Ini for each n E IN and i E IN2n-l • We call 9 the

Cantor function.

(L) The Cantor function 9 is continuous, and g(O) = 0, g(I) = 1.

(II:) J1-g(C) = 1, but C is a Lebesgue null set.

(..\) Take a E [0,1] and define h(x) := ag(x) + (1- a)x for every x E [0,1].

Then h is an increasing function on [0,1] such that J1-h(C) = a and

h(O) = 0, h(I) = 1.

(J1-) Define

{ 0 for x E C

f : [0,1] --t JR, x ~ n for x E Ini.

Then J f d..\ = 3, where ..\ is the Lebesgue measure on [0, 1], and

J fdJ1-g = 0 where 9 is the Cantor function.

(v) Set 9t:= {[a,,8[ \C I a,,8 E [0, I]} and

v: 9t --t JR, [a,,8[\C ~ g(,8) - g(a).

Then the following are true.

(VI) 9t is a semi-ring.

(V2) v is an additive positive content which is nullcontinuous.

(V3) v is not a-additive.

(0 If J1- is a positive additive real function on the semi-ring {[x, y[ I x, Y E

JR}, then J1- is a-additive iff it is nullcontinuous.


Recommended