+ All Categories
Home > Documents > AGAINST MORAL CHARACTER EVALUATIONS: The undetectability of virtue and vice Peter B. M. Vranas Iowa...

AGAINST MORAL CHARACTER EVALUATIONS: The undetectability of virtue and vice Peter B. M. Vranas Iowa...

Date post: 01-Jan-2016
Category:
Upload: karen-gilmore
View: 218 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend
Popular Tags:
26
AGAINST MORAL CHARACTER EVALUATIONS: The undetectability of virtue and vice Peter B. M. Vranas Iowa State University Conference on Virtue Ethics and Moral Psychology, 7 October 2005
Transcript

AGAINST MORAL CHARACTER EVALUATIONS:The undetectability of virtue and vice

Peter B. M. Vranas

Iowa State University

Conference on Virtue Ethics and Moral Psychology, 7 October 2005

THE EPISTEMIC THESIS

Epistemic thesis: Moral character evaluations are almost always epistemically unwarranted.

Definitions: Moral character evaluations: evaluations of

people as good, bad, or intermediate. A person is indeterminate iff the person is

neither good nor bad nor intermediate. A person is fragmented iff the person would

behave deplorably in an open list of situations and admirably in another such open list.

THE ARGUMENT FORTHE EPISTEMIC THESIS

(P1) Most people are fragmented.___________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________

(L1) The prior probability that a person is fragmented should be high.(P2) The posterior probability that a person is fragmented shouldn’t differ much from the prior.___________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________

(L2) The posterior probability that a person is fragmented should be high.(P3) Fragmentation entails indeterminacy.___________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________

(C1) The posterior probability that a person is indeterminate should be high.

OVERVIEW

Part 1: Review of previous results Most people are fragmented (P1) Fragmentation entails indeterminacy (P3)Part 2: Posterior probability of fragmentation Approximate IndependencePosterior Prior Approximate Independence holdsPart 3: Objections to the epistemic thesis The triviality objection The objection from ought-implies-can The objection from comparative evaluations

(P1) MOST PEOPLE ARE FRAGMENTED

(1) There is an open list of situations in which most people would behave deplorably: Obedience experiments (Milgram) Stanford Prison Experiment (Zimbardo) Seizure experiments (Latané & Darley)

(2) There is an open list of situations in which most people would behave admirably: Electrocution experiments (Clark & Word) Theft experiments (Moriarty) Rape experiments (Harari et al.)

(P3) FRAGMENTATION ENTAILS INDETERMINACY

(P0) If A behaves much better than B in an open list of situations and much worse in another list, then A is neither better nor worse than B.

__________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________

(1) Every fragmented person is neither better nor worse than some intermediate person (who never behaves deplorably or admirably).

(2) Every good person is better, and every bad person is worse, than any intermediate person.

__________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________

(3) No fragmented person is good or bad.Similarly, no fragmented person is intermediate.

PART 2

Part 1: Review of previous results Most people are fragmented (P1) Fragmentation entails indeterminacy (P3)Part 2: Posterior probability of fragmentation Approx. IndependencePosteriorPrior Approx. Independence holdsPart 3: Objections to the epistemic thesis The triviality objection The objection from ought-implies-can The objection from comparative evaluations

THE POSTERIOR PROBABILITY OF FRAGMENTATION

Notation:F: person p is fragmented.Ds: p behaves deplorably in situation s.Approximate Independence Condition: P(Ds|Ds) P(Ds)...

The argument:(P4) If Approximate Independence holds, then P(F|Ds) shouldn’t differ much from P(F).(P5) Approximate Independence holds.

________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________

(P2) P(F|Ds) shouldn’t differ much from P(F).

(P4) INDEPENDENCE POSTERIOR PRIOR

Theorem. Consider S independent and identic-ally distributed random variables, each of which can take the values -1, 1, and 0 with probabil-ities pD ,pA , and 1-pD-pA respectively. Let ND and NA be the numbers of these variables which take the values -1 and 1 respectively, and ND and NA the corresponding numbers for (any) S-1 of the S variables. Let F = ND > D & NA > A and let Ds = the s-th variable takes the value -1. Then:P(F|Ds)-P(F) = (1-pD)P(ND = D & NA > A)

-pAP(ND > D & NA = A).

(P5) APPROXIMATEINDEPENDENCE HOLDS

Argument 1: Average correlation coefficients low. E.g., Hartshorne & May (1928, 1930).

Objection: We can predict our friends’ actions.Reply: Behavior may be temporally stable (in

recurring situations) but not cross-situationally consistent. In everyday life we observe our friends in recurring situations.

Argument 2: Personality characteristics like reli-giosity, authoritarianism, introversion don’t predict who obeys in Milgram’s experiments.

PART 3

Part 1: Review of previous results Most people are fragmented (P1) Fragmentation entails indeterminacy (P3)Part 2: Posterior probability of fragmentation Approximate IndependencePosterior Prior Approximate Independence holdsPart 3: Objections to the epistemic thesis The triviality objection The objection from ought-implies-can The objection from comparative evaluations

OBJECTION 1:TRIVIALITY

The objection: (1) We seldom make MCEs, so (2) the epistemic thesis is uninteresting.

Reply 1: (1) is false. Empirical evidence: Never Almost Rarely Somewhat Somewhat Frequ- Very Almost

never rarely frequently ently frequently always_______________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________

#1: 3 20 30 46 54 26 5 5#2: 0 5 10 25 53 53 34 8Reply 2: (2) does not follow from (1). MCEs

sometimes have important functions: they underlie esteem and contempt, praise and blame, explanations of behavior, and advice.

OBJECTION 2:OUGHT-IMPLIES-CAN

The objection: (1) We cannot avoid making MCEs (cf. Spontaneous Trait Inferences, STIs). (2) We have no epistemic obligation to avoid believing what we cannot avoid believing. (3) The epistemic thesis implies that we have an epistemic obligation to avoid making MCEs.

Reply 1: (1) is false. STIs may be controllable. Reply 2: (2) is false. We have an epistemic obligation to avoid believing P iff our evidence makes P unlikely, but this can happen even if we cannot avoid believing P.

OBJECTION 3:COMPARATIVE EVALUATIONS

The objection: (1) If p is better than at least one good person, then p is good. (2) P(p is better than at least one good person|p is better than most people) high. Thus: (3) P(p is good|p is better than most people) should be high. So MCEs are justified if comparative MCEs are.

Against (2): We don’t know what percentage of people are good, so even if p is better than (e.g.) 80% of people we can’t be confident that p is better than at least one good person.

CONCLUSION:THE PRAGMATIC THESIS

Local evaluations: referring to behavior in a relatively narrow range of situations.

The pragmatic thesis: there is good pragmatic reason to prefer local to global evaluations.

The argument:(1) Local evaluations avoid costs of global ones: tempting one’s luck, testing people.(2) Local evaluations preserve benefits of global ones: decisions about association, regulation of emotions.

EPSTEIN AND AGGREGATION

Epstein: Not surprising that correlations low. If you measure once, large error. You need to average many measurements. Correlations between aggregated measures will be high.

Reply 1: Epstein’s argument presupposes constant true score, as when measuring length. But this presupposes cross-situational consist-ency. The issue is empirical, not a priori.

Reply 2: Empirical evidence against Epstein; e.g., Hartshorne, May, & Shuttleworth 1930.

THE VALIDITY OF THE ARGUMENT FOR P1

Theorem 1. Consider P people, SD situations in each of which at least D people behave deplor-ably, and SA different situations in each of which at least A people behave admirably. Let F be the number of people each of whom behaves deplor-ably in more than D of the former SD situations and behaves admirably in more than A of the latter SA situations. Then:FP

P SS

P SS

D D D

D D

A A A

A A

/ /

// /

/.

1 11

THREE CONCEPTIONS OF CHARACTER EVALUATIONS

Q6 true(consistencyof bad people)

Q6 false (noconsistencyof bad people)

Q5 true (con-sistency ofgood people)

Consistencyconceptions(middle line)

Impurityconceptions(hard line)

Q5 false (noconsistency ofgood people)

______ Averagingconceptions(soft line)

(P3) FRAGMENTATION ENTAILS INDETERMINACY

(Q5) A person who often behaves deplorably is not good.

(Q6) A person who often behaves admirably is not bad.

(Q7) A person who often behaves deplorably and often behaves admirably is not intermediate (between good and bad).

___________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________

(P3) A person who often behaves deplorably and often behaves admirably is neither good nor bad nor intermediate.

(Q7) FRAGMENTATION PRE-CLUDES “INTERMEDIACY”

(Q10) Every good person is better than any intermediate person.

(Q11) For any fragmented person f there is a good person g who is not better than f.

____________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________

(Q7) No fragmented person is intermediate.In support of Q11: Take f and g who behaves (a)

admirably when f behaves deplorably, and (b) neutrally when f behaves admirably or neutrally. Then g is good but, by the Incom-mensurability Argument, g is not better than f.

OBJECTIONS 1-2 TO Q5

Objection 1: Goodness of character depends on motives, regardless of whether acts deplorable.Reply: (a) I’m not denying that motives matter.(b) If the claim is that only motives matter, I disagree: weakness of will no adequate excuse.

Objection 2: Counterfactual behavior is irrel-evant to character because of “moral luck”.Reply: Counterfactual behavior is irrelevant to responsibility but can be relevant to character.

OBJECTIONS 3-4 TO Q5

Objection 3: Certain counterfactuals irrelevant. You would have committed atrocities had you been raised in Nazi Germany.Reply: Only actual dispositions relevant to Q5.

Objection 4: Even some actual dispositions irrel-evant to character. You would kill if tortured.Reply: Irrelevant only if torture excuses killing; if it does, then killing after being tortured is not deplorable, so counterfactual irrelevant to Q5.

OBJECTIONS 5-6 TO P5

Objection 5: Only extremely deplorable behavior precludes compensation. Crushing ants?Reply: Disagreement about antecedent of P5.

Objection 6: People choose their situations.

Reply: Take p1 and p2, who (know they) would kill if drunk. p1 drinks, p2 does not. Then p1 cp worse than p2, but both cp worse than p3, who would not kill if drunk. Disposition to choose situations does matter, but counterfactual beh-avior even in unchosen situations also matters.

OBJECTION 7 TO P5

Objection 7: There is no fact of the matter about how you would behave in various situations.Reply: Only counterfactuals about whose truth there is a fact of the matter are relevant to P5.

Rejoinder: What if all dispositions probabilistic?Reply: Two extreme cases. (1) For most people high probabilities. Then most people still frag-mented. (2) For most people low probabilities. Then most people not fragmented but still indeterminate.

AN OBJECTION TO Q6: WHAT ABOUT HITLER?

Maybe Hitler was bad; consider Ted Bundy. Being nice to your mother is not admirable. A

few isolated instances are no open list. Bundy was not better than an intermediate

person who never behaves admirably. I’m not saying Bundy was good; only not bad.

So badness cannot be fully compensated. Anchoring bias: good or bad news first? Symmetry argument: why give greater weight

to deplorable than to admirable behavior?

THE INCREDIBILITYOBJECTION

First form: It’s incredible to deny that a brutal serial killer is bad just because in a psycholo-gical experiment he would (e.g.) stop a thief.

Reply: (a) I’m not saying he’s good (or not bad).(b) I’m not relying just on experiments.(c) Anchoring bias: bad or good news first?

Second form: I know my wife is good. It doesn’t matter that she would behave sadistically in an experiment; I don’t even believe she would.

Reply: -You can’t predict. -Experiments matter.


Recommended