+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Assertion.stanford

Assertion.stanford

Date post: 26-Dec-2015
Category:
Upload: volker-wald
View: 37 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend
Description:
a famous essay on assertions by PG
Popular Tags:
52
Assertion Peter Pagin March 4, 2005 An assertion is a speech act in which something is claimed to hold, e.g. that there are infinitely many prime numbers, or, with respect to some time t, that there is a traffic congestion on Brooklyn Bridge at t, or, of some person x with respect to some time t, that x has a tooth ache at t. The concept of assertion has often occupied a central place in the philosophy of language, since it is often thought that making assertions is the use of language most crucial to linguistic meaning, and since assertions are the natural expressions of cognitive attitudes, and hence of importance for theories of knowledge and belief. The nature of assertion and its relation to other categories and phenomena have been subject to much controversy. Some of the ideas of assertion will be presented below. The article is organized as follows: 1. Speech acts 2. Pragmatics 3. Convention 4. Truth 5. Belief and knowledge 6. Social character 7. Logic 1 Speech acts Gottlob Frege characterized the assertoric quality of an utterance as an asser- toric force (‘Behauptende Kraft’; Frege 1918:22) of the utterance. This idea was later taken over by J L Austin (1962:99-100), the founding father of the general theory of speech acts. Austin distinguished between several levels of speech act, including these: the locutionary act, the illocutionary act and the perlocutionary act. The locutionary act is the act of “ ‘saying something’ in the full normal sense” (1962:94), which is the utterance of certain words with certain meanings in a certain grammatical construction, such as uttering ‘I like ice’ as a sentence of English. The notion of an illocutionary act was introduced by Austin by means of examples (1962:98-102), and that is the normal procedure. Illocutionary acts are such acts as asserting, asking a question, warning, threatening, announcing 1
Transcript
Page 1: Assertion.stanford

Assertion

Peter Pagin

March 4, 2005

An assertion is a speech act in which something is claimed to hold, e.g. thatthere are infinitely many prime numbers, or, with respect to some time t, thatthere is a traffic congestion on Brooklyn Bridge at t, or, of some person x withrespect to some time t, that x has a tooth ache at t. The concept of assertionhas often occupied a central place in the philosophy of language, since it is oftenthought that making assertions is the use of language most crucial to linguisticmeaning, and since assertions are the natural expressions of cognitive attitudes,and hence of importance for theories of knowledge and belief.

The nature of assertion and its relation to other categories and phenomenahave been subject to much controversy. Some of the ideas of assertion will bepresented below. The article is organized as follows:

1. Speech acts2. Pragmatics3. Convention4. Truth5. Belief and knowledge6. Social character7. Logic

1 Speech acts

Gottlob Frege characterized the assertoric quality of an utterance as an asser-toric force (‘Behauptende Kraft’; Frege 1918:22) of the utterance. This ideawas later taken over by J L Austin (1962:99-100), the founding father of thegeneral theory of speech acts. Austin distinguished between several levels ofspeech act, including these: the locutionary act, the illocutionary act and theperlocutionary act. The locutionary act is the act of “ ‘saying something’ inthe full normal sense” (1962:94), which is the utterance of certain words withcertain meanings in a certain grammatical construction, such as uttering ‘I likeice’ as a sentence of English.

The notion of an illocutionary act was introduced by Austin by means ofexamples (1962:98-102), and that is the normal procedure. Illocutionary actsare such acts as asserting, asking a question, warning, threatening, announcing

1

Page 2: Assertion.stanford

a verdict or intention, making an appointment, giving an order, expressing awish, making a request. An utterance of a sentence, i.e. a locutionary act, bymeans of which a question is asked is thus an utterance with interrogative force,and when an assertion is made the utterance has assertoric force. Each type ofillocutionary act is a type of act with the corresponding illocutionary force.

The perlocutionary act is made by means of an illocutionary act, and de-pends entirely on the hearer’s reaction. For instance, by means of arguing thespeaker may convince the hearer, and by means of warning the speaker mayfrighten the hearer. In these examples, convincing and frightening are perlocu-tionary acts.

The illocutionary act does not depend on the hearer’s reaction to what hasbeen said. Still, according to Austin (1962:116-17) it does depend on the hearer’sbeing aware of the utterance and understanding it in a certain way: I haven’twarned someone unless he heard what I said. In this sense the performance of anillocutionary act depends on the ‘securing of uptake’ (Austin 1962:117). How-ever, Austin’s view is intuitively plausible for speech acts verbs with speaker-hearer argument structure (like x congratulates y) or speaker-hearer-contentargument structure (x requests of y that p) but less plausible when the struc-ture is speaker-content (x asks whether p). ‘Assert’ is of the latter kind, asopposed to e.g. ‘tell’. It may be said that I failed to tell him that the stationwas closed, since he had already left the room when I said so, but that I stillasserted that it was closed, since I believed he was still there. As we shall see,several theories of assertion focus on hearer-directed beliefs and intentions of thespeaker, without requiring that those beliefs are true or the intentions fulfilled.

Austin had earlier (Austin 1956) initiated the development of speech acttaxonomy by means of the distinction between constative and performative ut-terances. Roughly, whereas in a constative utterance you report an alreadyobtaining state of affairs—you say something—in a performative utterance youcreate something new: you do something (Austin 1956:235). Paradigm exam-ples of performatives were utterances by means of which actions such as bap-tizing, congratulating and greeting are performed. Assertion, by contrast, isthe paradigm of a constative utterance. However, when developing his generaltheory of speech acts, Austin abandonded the constative/performative distinc-tion, the reason being that it is not so clear in what sense something is donee.g. by means of an optative utterance, whereas nothing is done by means of anassertoric one. Austin noted e.g. that assertions are subject both to infelicitiesand to various kinds of appraisal, just like performatives (Austin 1962:133-47).

As an alternative, Austin suggested five classes of illocutionary types (orillocutionary verbs): verdictives, exercitives, commissives, behabitives and ex-positives (Austin 1962:151-64). You exemplify a verdictive e.g. when as a judgeyou pronounce a verdict; an exercitive by appointing, voting or advising; a com-missive by promising, undertaking or declaring that you will do something; abehabitive by apologizing, criticizing, cursing or congratulating; an expositiveby acts appropriately prefixed by phrases like ‘I reply’, ‘I argue’, ‘I concede’ etc.,of a general expository nature.

In this classification, assertion would best be placed under expositives, since

2

Page 3: Assertion.stanford

the prefix ‘I assert’ is or may be of an expository nature. However, an assertionneed not in itself be expository. As a classification of illocutionary types Austin’staxonomy is thus not completely adequate.

Other taxonomies have been proposed, e.g. by Stephen Schiffer (1972), JohnSearle (1975b), Kent Bach and Robert M. Harnich (1979), and Francois Reca-nati (1987). In Bach and Harnich’s scheme, similar to Searle’s, there are fourtop categories: constatives, directives (including questions and prohibitives),commissives (promises, offers) and acknowledgements (apologize, condole, con-gratulate) (1979:41). The category of constatives includes the subtypes, in Bachand Harnich’s terms, of assertives, predictives, retrodictives, descriptives, as-criptives, informatives, confirmatives, concessives, retractives, assentives, dis-sentives, disputatives, responsives, suggestives and suppositives (1979:41).

In this list predictives are distinguished by concerning the future and retro-dictives by concerning the past, dissentives by the fact that the speaker is dis-agreeing with what was earlier said by the hearer, and so on. Assertives, ac-cording to this taxonomy, is not distinguished from other constatives by anysuch feature. As Bach and Harnich point out (1979:46) most of the specializedtypes of constatives satisfy their definition of assertives (see section 6). Thistype then stands out as a higher category, including most but not all of the con-statives; not for instance suggestives (suggesting, conjecturing) and suppositives(assuming, stipulating).

A leading idea in the taxonomies of Searle and Recanati is to distinguishbetween between types according to direction of fit. Constative utterances havea word-world direction of fit (what is said is supposed to conform to what theworld is like), while performative utterances have world-word direction of fit(the world is supposed to be changed to fit what is said). Again, assertion isthe paradigmatic constative type, if not the constative type itself.

2 Pragmatics

Assertion is generally thought of being open, explicit and direct, as opposed e.g.to implying something without explicitly saying it. In this respect assertion iscontrasted with presupposition and implicature. The contrast is, however, notaltogheter sharp, partly because of the idea of indirect speech acts, includingindirect assertions.

2.1 Presupposition

A sentence such as

(1) Kepler died in misery

is not true unless the singular term ‘Kepler’ has reference. Still, Frege arguedthat a speaker asserting that Kepler died in misery, by means of (1) does not alsoassert that ‘Kepler’ has reference (Frege 1892:574). That Kepler had reference

3

Page 4: Assertion.stanford

is not part of the sense of the sentence. Frege’s reason was that if it had been,the sense of its negation,

(2) Kepler did not die in misery

would have been that Kepler did not die in misery or ‘Kepler’ does not havereference, which is absurd. According to Frege, that ‘Kepler’ has reference israther presupposed, both in an assertion of (1) and in an assertion of its negation.

The modern treatment of presupposition has followed Frege in treating sur-vival under negation as the most important test for presupposition. That is,if it is implied that p, both in an assertion of a sentence s and in an assertionof the negation of s, then it is presupposed that p in those assertions. Othertypical examples of presuppostion (cf Levinson 1983:178-81) include

(3) John managed [didn’t manage] to stop in time

implying that John tried to stop in time, and

(4) Martha regrets [doesn’t regret] drinking John’s home brew

implying that Martha drank John’s home brew.In the case of 1, the presupposition is clearly of a semantic nature, since the

sentence ‘Someone is identical with Kepler’, which is true just if ‘Kepler’ hasreference, is a logical consequence both of (1) and of (2). By contrast, in thenegated forms of (3) and (4) the presupposition can be cancelled by context,e.g. as in

(5) John didn’t manage to stop in time. He didn’t even try.

This indicates that in this case the presupposition is a pragmatic phenomenon.It is the speaker or speech act rather than the sentence or the propositionexpressed that presupposes something. The presupposing should still be keptdistinct from asserting. One further reason is that the presuppostion occurs inother illocutionary types as well. For instance, in asking

(6) Did John [didn’t John] manage to stop in time?

the speaker normally assumes that John tried and is only asking about thesuccess.

2.2 Implicature

Frege noted (1879:20) that there is no difference in truth evaluable content,between sentences such as

(7) John works with real estate and likes fishing

(8) John works with real estate but likes fishing.

4

Page 5: Assertion.stanford

‘And’ and ‘but’ contribute the same way to truth and falsity. However, whenusing (8), but not when using (7), the speaker indicates that there is a contrastof some kind between working with real estate and liking fishing. The speaker isnot asserting that there is a contrast. For instance, forming a conditional with(8) in the antecedent preserves the contrast rather than make it hypothetical:

(9) If John works with real estate but likes fishing, I think we can bring himalong

It is usually said that the speaker in cases like (8) and (9), implies that there isa contrast. These are then examples of implicature. H Paul Grice (1975, 1989)developed a general theory of implicature. Grice called implicatures of the kindexemplified conventional, since it is a standing feature of the word ‘but’ to giverise to them. Most of Grice’s theory is concerned with the complementing kind,the conversational implicatures. These rely on general conversational maxims,not on features of expressions. These maxims are thought to be in force inordinary conversation. For instance, the maxim Be orderly ! requires of thespeaker to recount events in the order they took place. This is meant to accountfor the intuitive difference in content between

(10) John took off his shoes and sat down

(11) John sat down and took off his shoes

According to Grice’s account, the speaker doesn’t assert, only implicates thatthe events took place in the order recounted. What is asserted is just that bothevents did take place.

Real or apparent violations of the maxims generate implicatures, on theassumption that the participants obey the over-arching Co-operative Principle.For instance, in the following conversation

(12) A: Where does John spend the summer?B: Somewhere in Canada.

B implies that he doesn’t know where in Canada John spends the summer. Thereasoning is as follows. B violates the Quantity principle to be as informativeas required. Since B is assumed to be co-operative, one can infer that he cannotsatisfy the Quantity principle without violating the Quality principle not tosay anything for which one lacks sufficient evidence. Hence, one can infer thathe doesn’t know. Again, B has not asserted that he doesn’t know, but stillmanaged to convey it in an indirect manner.

2.3 Indirect speech acts

This clear distinction between assertion and implicature is to some extent un-dermined by acknowledging indirect assertion as a kind of assertion proper. Astandard example of an indirect speech act is given by

(13) Can you pass the salt?

5

Page 6: Assertion.stanford

By means of uttering an interrogative sentence the speaker requests the ad-dressee to pass the salt. The request is indirect. The question, concerningthe addressee’s ability, is direct. As defined by John Searle (1975a:59-60), andalso Bach and Harnich (1979:70), an indirect illocutionary act is subordinate toanother, more primary act and depends on the success of the first. An alter-native definition given by Sadock (1974:73) is that an act is indirect just if ithas a different illocutionary force from the one standardly correlated with thesentence-type used. Examples of indirect assertions by means of questions andcommands/requests are given by

(14) May I tell you that, obviously, the square root of a quarter is a half?

(15) Let me tell you that, obviously, the square root of a quarter is a half

(Levinson 1983:266). Rhetorical questions also have the force of assertions:

(16) Is not Switzerland a peace-loving nation?

Another candidate type is irony:

(17) Switzerland is known for its aggressive foreign policy

assuming the speaker does mean the negation of what is literally said. However,although in a sense the act is indirect, since the speaker asserts somethingdifferent from what she would do on a normal direct use of the sentence, andrelies on the hearer to realize this, it is not an indirect assertion by eitherdefinition. It isn’t on the first, since the primary act (the literal assertion) isn’teven made, and it isn’t on the second, since there is no discrepancy betweenforce and sentence type.

Irony does, however, qualify as indirect assertion on the definition given byRecanati (1987:125). According to Recanati, an indirect speech act is a specialkind of conversational implicature, where the speaker not only implicates someproposition p, but also that she intends to convey that p. In the case of (17),there is an apparent flagrant violation of the Quality principle to say only whatis true. On the assumption that the speaker is co-operative, together withbackground knowledge of her political awareness, the hearer can infer that shedoes not mean what she literally says, but rather the opposite, i.e. that whatshe wants to communicate is the negation of what she says. For Recanati, thecommunicative intention is what brings this act under the category of assertionproper (see section (6)).

Although Searle’s definition of indirect speech acts is different, Searle toothinks that they work by means of an inferential mechanism, including thatof conventional implicature. The hearer is supposed to understand that thespeaker cannot merely be performing the primary act, since that would violateconversational principles, and then again conclude by conversational reasoningwhat other act has been performed.

The very idea of indirect speech acts is, however, controversial. It is notuniversally agreed that an ordinary utterance of (13) is indirect, since it has

6

Page 7: Assertion.stanford

been denied e.g. by Levinson (1983:273-76) that a question has really beenasked, over and above the request. Similarly, Levinson have questioned the ideaof a standard correlation between force and sentence form, by which a requestwould count as indirect on Sadock’s criterion. This brings us to the topic ofconventionality.

3 Convention

Austin held that illocutionary acts as opposed to perlocutionary acts are conven-tional, in the sense that they can be made explicit by the so-called performativeformula (Austin 1962:103). According to Austin one can say ‘I argue that’ or ‘Iwarn you that’ but not ‘I convince you that’ or ‘I alarm you that’. Presumably,the idea was that a speech act type is conventional just if there exists a conven-tion by which an utterance of a sentence of a certain kind ensures (if uptake issecured) that a speech act of that type is performed. Austin probably thoughtthat in virtue of the performative formulae this condition is met by illocutionarybut not by perlocutionary act types.

The more general claim that illocutionary force is correlated by conventionwith sentence type has been advocated by Michael Dummett (1973:302, 311).On this view, it is a convention that declarative sentences are used for assertion,interrogative for questions and imperative for commands and requests. Similarviews have been put forward by Searle (1969) and Petr Kotatko (1998). Accord-ing to Searle (1969:38, 40), illocutionary acts are conventional, and the conven-tions in question govern the use of so-called force-indicating devices (1969:64)specific to each language. Searle does not claim that the standard sentence typesare force indicating devices but speculates that a representation of illocutionarytype would be part of the syntactic deep structure.

However, the view that illocutionary acts types are conventional in this sensehas met with much opposition. Peter Strawson (1964:153-54) objected early onthat ordinary illocutionary acts can be performed without relying on any con-vention to identify the force, e.g. when using a declarative sentence like ‘The iceover there is very thin’ for a warning. This kind of criticism, now directed againstDummett, has later been reinforced by Robert J Stainton (1997), stressing thatin appropriate contexts sub-sentential phrases like ‘John’s father’ (pointing at aman) or ‘very fast’ (looking at a car) can be used to make assertions, and giveslinguistic arguments why not all such uses can be treated as cases of ellipsis,i.e. as cases of leaving out parts of a well-formed sentence that speaker andhearer tacitly aware of (Stainton 1995, 1997). It seems that conventions are notnecessary.

Moreover, Donald Davidson (1979, 1982) stressed that no conventional signcould work as a force indicator in this sense, since any conventional sign couldbe used (and would be used) in insincere utterances, where the correspondingforce was missing, including cases of deception, jokes, impersonation and othertheatrical performances. Basically the same point is made by Bach and Harnich(1979:122-27). It seems that conventions are also not sufficient.

7

Page 8: Assertion.stanford

Conventionalism has, however, been defended by Kotatko (1998). Kotatkoclaimed that convention and social circumstances together determine what kindof act has been made. Speaker intention plays a role, but what determines theact is what intention the speaker count as having in the Koenraad de Smedt, notwhat intention she actually has. Kotatko argues, with Dummett and againstcommunication-intention theorists, that the public nature of language use wouldbe lost if the force of an utterance were determined by the mental states of thespeaker. A problem with such a position is that an account of the social realityof convention is needed that does not itself make an appeal to mental states.

It is fairly clear that some illocutionary act types are conventional, likepronouncements in court proceedings or in wedding ceremonies, by which insti-tutional facts, such as two persons being married, are created. In the taxonomyof Bach and Harnich, these are the verdictives and effectives, and accordingto Bach and Harnich these types are conventional but not essentially commu-nicative (1979:113-19). Austin focused on such types in his early examples ofperformatives and he was criticized by G J Warnock (1973) for not distinguish-ing the conventionality of those types from the non-conventionality of the otherperformatives (such as ‘I advise you to go west’) generated by the performativeprefix.

Nevertheless, Recanati (1987:81-86) has given a partial defence of Austin’sview, with the claim that there are conventional force indicators, like the in-terrogative and imperative sentence types. These are according to Recanati as-sociated with the ‘illocutionary force potential’ (1987:81) of sentences of thosetypes, consisting in the range of illocutionary forces with which they can bedirectly and normally used. But that is how far the defence of Austin goes. Forspecific illocutionary types like warning, advising and requesting to be conven-tional, there would have to be conventional indicators of those specific types,and according to Recanati (1987:86-93) there aren’t. The closest we come arethe performative prefixes like ‘I advise you’, ‘I warn you’, ‘I request you to’, butthese aren’t force-indicating devices: they are part of the descriptive content ofsentences. When saying ‘I advise you to go west’, the speaker directly assertsthat he advises the addressee to go west, and thereby indirectly advises theaddressee to go west. The advising arises as an intended implicature from thedescriptive content of the assertion. For assertion in particular, the situation iseven worse, on Recanati’s view (1987:163-69). This is because the declarativesentence type is not associated with any uniform illocutionary force potential:declaratives can be used directly for assertoric (constative) as well as for direc-tive and commissive utterances. According to Recanati (1987:165), giving anorder by means of the declarative sentence

(18) When you have finished peeling the potatoes, you’ll scrub the latrine

is giving an order directly, not indirectly. The reason is that the speaker doesnot seem to be reporting anything. However, that (18) cannot be seen as areport depends on the fact that it is in the future tense. There does not, bycontrast, seem to be any obstacle to regarding the act as directly a prediction,

8

Page 9: Assertion.stanford

i.e. a predictive assertion, and indirectly an order (the mechanism would bethat the speaker would lack appropriate evidence for the prediction unless heintended the addressee to understand the utterance as an order and had goodreasons to expect the addressee both to understand and to comply).

Recanati does, however, also back up his claim that declaratives are force-neutral by remarking (1987:166) that the view that promises and other commis-sives, when fully explicit, can only be made indirectly, is suspect. If explicitlymade, a promise is expressed by means of a declarative, since there is no com-missive sentence type, and if such an utterance is directly an assertion, thepromise must be indirect. Maybe that view is in fact suspect, and maybe onlya careful study of a large statistical material can give the answer.

The conventionality claim does not only depend on statistics, however. Ifthe existence of illocutionary force conventions is more than the existence ofregularities of dispositions to speak and interpret in a population, e.g. alongthe lines suggested by David Lewis (1969, 1975), or along any other line, thenthere may well be a statistical form-force correlation without any convention tothe effect. There does not seem to be any good prior reason why the existenceof a correlation must be explained by the existence of a convention.

4 Truth

It has often been noted that there is a close relation between the concepts ofassertion and truth. Connections between assertion and truth have sometimesbeen appealed to for defining the concept of assertion, and sometimes for defin-ing the concept of truth. Four different connections with assertion have beenespecially emphasized: with the use of the truth predicate, with truth as theaim or norm of assertion, with the role of truth in meaning theory, and withtruth as related to correctness of assertions.

4.1 The truth predicate

As often noted in discussion of the truth predicate, there is a close connectionbetween using a sentence like

(19) Kafka wrote many letters to Milena

for making an assertion, and saying of it that it is true, e.g. by means of

(20) ‘Kafka wrote many letters to Milena’ is true

or by means of

(21) That’s true

with reference to (19), or to an utterance of (19)). Strawson (1949) claimedthat using (21) is not to make a new assertion, but to endorse a previous one.Similarly, W.V. Quine (1970:12) said that to call the sentence ‘snow is white’true is to call snow white. In Strawson’s case in particular, the idea was that

9

Page 10: Assertion.stanford

this use of ‘true’ for signalling agreement is basic, and the key to understandingthe truth predicate. This has been called the reassertion theory of truth (Price1987:207).

In Quine’s case it is less clear that the endorsement signalling function isbasic. Rather, Quine emphasized that the truth predicate is a disquotationaldevice (Quine 1970:12). That is, applying the truth predicate to the quotationof a sentence, as in (20), has the same effect as removing the quotes. That is,in general an expression occurring within quotes is mentioned, not used, butwhen the truth predicate is applied to a quoted sentence, what is within quotesis effectively brought from mention to use. This can be seen by consideringsubstitution conditions. In general, a context like

(22) ‘.....’ F

where ‘F’ is some arbitrary predicate, is heavily non-extensional: substituting‘the author of The Castle’ for ‘Kafka’ in the true sentence

(23) ‘Kafka’ has five letters

produces the false sentence

(24) ‘the author of The Castle’ has five letters

despite the fact that ‘Kafka’ and ‘the author of The Castle’ are co-referring, orat least can be interchanged in all extensional contexts without change of truthvalue. But substituting ‘the author of The Castle’ for ‘Kafka’ in (20) produces

(25) ‘the author of The Castle wrote many letters to Milena’ is true

which has the same truth value as (20). In general, the context

(26) ‘.....’ is true

is extensional, and therefore what occurs in this context can be regarded, froma semantic point of view, as used.

Given that Quine characterizes (19) and (20) as being equivalent in thissense, it follows that an assertion by means of (20) in a corresponding sensealso is equivalent with an assertion by means of (19). So Quine need not, andprobably did not, see the endorsement function as basic. This comes out evenclearer in subordinate clauses. For Quine, it is also an immediate consequencethat

(27) If ‘Kafka wrote many letters to Milena’ is true, then Milena probablywrote many letters to Kafka

is equivalent with

(28) If Kafka wrote many letters to Milena, then Milena probably wrote manyletters to Kafka.

10

Page 11: Assertion.stanford

But since ‘true’ is not here used to signal endorsement, the equivalence is notan immediate consequence of Strawson’s view. Rather, the reassertion accountof truth needs to be supplemented with further principles to deliver the result.

Both the reassertion view and the disquotational view of truth belong to thefamily of deflationary theories of truth. The members of this family all explaintruth by appeal to some relation between sentences like (19) and (20)/(21). Itis, however, difficult to spell out such a relation if one is not allowed make useof the concept of truth itself, or something very close. An appeal to assertiondoes remain an option.

4.2 Truth as aim: fact-stating

Another commonly held idea, used for characterizing assertion in terms of truth,is the idea that assertion aims at truth. This is stated e.g. both by BernardWilliams (1966) and by Michael Dummett (1973). It can be understood in tworather different ways, the one intended by Williams and the other by Dummett(for some ways of understanding what it could be for belief to aim at truth, seeEngel 2004).

On Williams’s view, the property of aiming at truth is what characterizesfact-stating discourse, as opposed to e.g. evaluative or directive discourse. It isnatural to think of

(29) The moon is about 384.000 km from the Earth

as stating a fact, and of

(30) Bardot is good

as expressing an evaluation, not corresponding to any fact of the matter. OnWilliams’s view, to regard a sincere utterance of

(31) It is wrong to steal

as a moral assertion, is to take a realistic attitude to moral discourse: thereare moral facts, making moral statements objectively true or false. This viewagain comes in two versions. On the first alternative, the existence of moralfacts renders the discourse fact-stating, whether the speaker thinks so or not,and the non-existence renders it evaluative, again whether the speaker thinksso or not. On the second alternative, (31) is an assertion if the speaker has arealistic attitude towards moral discourse and otherwise not.

On these views, it is assumed that truth is a substantial property (Williams1966:202), not a concept that can be characterized in some deflationary way.As a consequence, the sentence

(32) ‘Bardot is good’ is true

is to be regarded as false, since (30) is objectively neither true nor false; thereis no fact of the matter.

This idea goes against Davidson’s view, according to which the materialbiconditional

11

Page 12: Assertion.stanford

(33) ‘Bardot is good’ is true if and only if Bardot is good

is true, regardless of the status of (30). According to Davidson (1967:31), whowas not a deflationist, any peculiarity of (30), e.g. that of being evaluative asopposed to fact-stating, is shared by (32), and so the equivalence holds anyway.

Conditionals or biconditionals like (33) do present a problem for views likeWilliams’s. As was stressed by Peter Geach (1960, 1965) we can put evaluatingor ‘ascriptive’ sentences in the antecedent of conditionals, like

(34) If Bardot is good, then I want to see all her films.

Since (30) isn’t advanced categorically in either (33) or (34), no evaluation isexpressed by means of it, but since these compound sentences are perfectlymeaningful, (30) must be meaningful as well when occurring as a subsentencein them. In this case, which is Geach’s point (which was also applied to thereassertion theory of truth in the previous subsection), the meaning of (30)cannot consist only in being usable for expressing evaluations.

One way out of this dilemma is to give up the idea that truth is substantialand adopt a deflationary view, or something close to that. On this alternative,saying that assertion aims at truth reduces almost to the claim that assertionsare made (directly) with declarative sentences, those that can be true. It doesn’tfully reduce to this claim, since a speech act of denial (rejection) would also bemade with declarative sentences, but would be opposite to assertion. We couldnot, however, distinguish between them by appeal to the use of ‘true’, for adenial of (30) would again be equivalent with a denial of (32).

A second way out would be to accept a full-blown realism, i.e. to accept theexistence of facts of the matter corresponding to evalauative judgments of anykind. But this is a high metaphysical price to pay.

A third way would be to dissociate assertion from truth. On this alternative,a sincere utterance of (30) does express an evaluation but is an assertion nev-ertheless, and the meaning of (30) does not consist only in being usable for theformer. We would then give up the principle of bivalence, that every sentence iseither true or false, and accept more alternatives, e.g. that (30) is neither truenor false. This will or will not save Davidson’s biconditional (33), dependingthe choice of three-valued semantics. (33) is saved if a biconditional counts astrue when both left hand side and right hand side lack a truth value.

It does not seem that intuitions concerning the everyday use of ‘to assert’are sufficiently uniform and stable for deciding the matter.

4.3 Truth as aim: norms of speakers’ intentions

The other idea of truth as an aim for assertion is that this is what the speakeraims at in making an assertion. The speaker tries to say something true. Sta-tistically, it is no doubt the case that speakers usually believe what they assertto be true, and usually this belief is no doubt part of the reason for making theassertion. However, we cannot go from there to take a speaker’s having this aimas necessary for her utterance to be assertoric, for lies are assertions as much

12

Page 13: Assertion.stanford

as honest utterances. The relation between assertion and the aim of truth hasthen to be indirect.

There are basically two ways of effecting such an indirect connection. One isto complicate speaker intentions. For instance, instead of aiming to say some-thing true, we could say that

(35) the speaker aims at making the hearer believe that the speaker aims atsaying something true.

We might then want to say that if the speaker does not have this primary, heareroriented intention, she is not really making an assertion, and if she does haveit, it is an assertion whether she is honest or not.

The other way is to appeal to the notions of rule, norm or convention. Forinstance, we might try

(36) It is a norm for making an assertion that the speaker aims at sayingsomething true.

On this alternative, an utterance is assertoric just in case it is governed by thisnorm, whatever the speaker in fact aims at in the particular case.

These two ideas have complementary problems. The problem with (35) isthat utterances are made, even if infrequently, that are intuitively assertoric,but where the speaker does not have the required intention. The speaker maybe fully aware that she will be taken as a liar, whether she aims at the truth ornot, and whether or not she tries to make the addressee believe she does aim atthe truth. Being convinced that this hearer oriented aim is unreacheable, shewill not even have it, but is nonetheless making an assertion (for a testimony ofconversations of this kind, se Levi 1958, chapter 8). One may try to overcomethis by complicating the speaker intentions even further, but it hard to see thatany necessary condition of this kind could be immune to couterexamples.

The problem with (36) is that it needs a supplementary criterion for whenthe assertion norm is in force. If we don’t know how to tell whether the normapplies to an utterance, we cannot tell whether it was an assertion or not.

Dummett has combined the two strategies. He has suggested the followingdefinition (Dummett 1973:300):

(MD) A man makes an assertion if he says something in such a manner asdeliberately to convey the impression of saying it with the overriding in-tention of saying something true (Dummett 1973:300).

Dummett’s proposal is presumably intended to give necessary as well as suf-ficient conditions. There are problems of sufficiency with this proposal of thekind that will be discussed in section 6. There are also problems of necessityof exactly the same kind as afflicts (35) above. However, Dummett can over-come these necessity problems by his appeal to convention. That is, it can be aconvention that when uttering a declarative sentence, unless there are explicitindications to the contrary (such as a theatre setting), the speaker counts as

13

Page 14: Assertion.stanford

conveying that he has the overriding intention of speaking truly. Then it is nolonger required that the speaker tries to convey it, as long as the circumstancesmake her count as doing so.

This proposal has the problems that afflict convention theories in general.For instance, indications of non-sincerity can be subtle (it is fairly common tobe unsure whether someone is joking or not), and trying to determine whetherthe convention applies in a particular case does not seem to be any easier thangauging the sincerity of the speaker in the absence of any convention. But thereis a further point. Once the burden of determining assertionhood is shiftedto a convention about means and ways of expressing oneself (setting aside theproblems with this idea), we need to check whether assertion is adequeatelycharacterized in the convention. In Dummett’s case, it is not, because of aproblem with the very idea of appealing to the aim of truth.

For it is not only in assertions that we normally aim at saying somethingtrue. We have that aim also in guesses, presumptions, conjectures and andthe like, all normally aimed at saying something true, but all somehow fallingshort of being assertions. Similarly, if I believe in the truth of, say, Goldbach’sconjecture, I will deliberately convey the impression of pronouncing it with theintention of saying something true, but because of my low degree of certitude,I don’t want to outright assert it. Assertoric force can be said to differ in kindfrom interrogative and imperative force, but only in degree or intensity from e.g.conjectural force. Conventions of the aiming kind don’t discriminate betweenassertion and weaker forms of propounding.

We would therefore need a more demanding norm:

(T) Don’t say what is not true!

The idea is again that an utterance is an assertion just if it is governed by thisnorm. Guesses aren’t, for guesses are, in some sense (in need of clairification),allowed to be wrong. A speaker trying to comply with (T) will not only avoidasserting what she believes to be false, but she will also try to make sure thatwhat she says isn’t false unbeknownst to her. Because of this she will assert onlythat for which she has adequate evidence. She can even be blamed for assertingsomething which was in fact true, if she didn’t have good enough reasons forbelieving it was. This is in accordance with Grice’s supermaxim of Quality: Tryto make your contribution one that is true (Grice 1989:27).

From this standpoint of the norm of (T), assertion is characterized by theway assertions are evaluated. There are several ideas of how to assess assertionsas correct or incorrect. This theme will be pursued in the present section andthe next.

4.4 Truth and correctness

The principle

(EC) An assertion that p is correct if, and only if, the speaker has goodevidence that it is true that p

14

Page 15: Assertion.stanford

is almost universally accepted (for problems concerning conditionals, see section(7)). In the case of mathematics, for instance, an assertion it thought of as cor-rect if the speaker knows a proof of what is asserted (see Prawitz 1998:45, andmany other places). There is room for doubt that there is anything like reason-ably sharp and stable standards of assertoric correctness in ordinary linguisticpractice, and in fact speakers pretty rarely engage in evaluating utterances inthese terms, beyond assessing them for truth or falsity, or blaming the speakerfor breach of confidence and the like. There is therefore not much evidence fromactual practice that the intended notions of correctness play any important role.They can nevertheless belong in the linguistic or philosophical enterprises of re-flecting over that practice.

A second preliminary issue concerns the status of the notion of correctnessinvolved. Is it an inherently normative notion, or is it just descriptive? Ac-cording to e.g. Paul Boghossian (1989:513) the mere fact that we can evaluateassertions as correct or incorrect show that words are governed by norms ofuse. According to Kathrin Gluer (2001:60-65), on the other hand, there is noreason to see in the notions of correctness and incorrectness anything more thana descriptive classification, which may then be coupled with certain a preferencefor correct assertions over incorrect ones, both in making and in taking. Thosepreferences may then be explained e.g. by appeal to social psychology, or thedesire for knowledge.

Setting these questions aside, we can note that the (EC) biconditional hasbeen used in two different ways: as a way of characterizing assertoric correctnessin terms of truth and evidence, or as a way of characterizing truth in termsof correctness and evidence. It is the second alternative that has been mostimportant. We shall return to the first alternative in the next section.

When using (EC) to account for truth it is crucial how ‘good evidence’ isunderstood. Typically, it is the best possible evidence, i.e. the best evidencethat can be had or could be had (as opposed to something that only could havebeen had but cannot anymore), that is relevant. There is also a question of howto understand ‘has’, as we shall see.

John Dewey (1938) seems to have been the first to characterize truth interms of assertoric correctness, with his notion of warranted assertibility, eventhough this idea had a clear affinity with the verifiability principle of MoritzSchlick (1936). Dewey was later followed by, notably, Michael Dummett (1976)and Hilary Putnam (1981). Common to them is the position that there cannotbe anything more to truth than being supported by the best available evidence.Dewey, following C S Peirce, regarded truth as the ideal limit of scientific inquiry(Dewey 1938:345), and a proposition warrantedly asserted when known in virtueof such an inquiry. Warranted assertibility is the property of a proposition forwhich such knowledge potentially exists (Dewey 1938:9).

Putnam (1981:54-56) operated with an idea of assertibility under ideal epis-temic conditions. Under normal conditions, a speaker can be justified in makingan assertion even though what she asserts is false. The evidence is enough fortruth under normal circumstances, but because of abnormal interference the ev-idence falls short. For instance, improbable changes, say because of a fire, may

15

Page 16: Assertion.stanford

have taken place after the speaker’s observation. However, in ideal epistemicconditions evidence that is sufficient for justifying an assertion also is conclusive.Spelling out what the ideal epistemic conditions are, in a non-circular fashion,has of course been a main problem for this view.

Dummett’s views are more complex. Early on (1973:349-51, 420-23, 1976:48-52) Dummett was concerned with explaining how a concept of truth as distinctfrom a basic concept of correct assertion could emerge at all. He suggested somecontexts where we find we have to make such a distinction, in particular futuretense conditionals. Asserting

(37) It will rain tomorrow

is correct under the same conditions as asserting

(38) It is correctly assertible that it will rain tomorrow.

In this sense (37) and (38) are assertorically equivalent. In Dummett’s terms,they have the same assertoric content (1991:48). But asserting

(39) If it will rain tomorrow, the match will be cancelled

is not equivalent with asserting

(40) If it is correctly assertible that it will rain tomorrow, the match will becancelled

because we think that the best possible evidence available today may well beinconclusive about the weather tomorrow. The antecedent of future tense con-ditionals is in this sense a type of truth inducing context. This context revealsthat (37) and (38) do not have the same ingredient sense (Dummett 1991:48).A further investigation of such contexts was made by Robert Brandom (1976).

Future tense sentences are special because better evidence for them thanany we can have now will (normally) be available later. By contrast, a full-fledged realistic attitude dissiciates truth from evidence completely. Realismabout a certain area is, according to Dummett (1976, 1991), manifested bythe acceptance of the principle of bivalence for sentences about that area. Forinstance, you are in this sense a realist about the past if you take all sentencesabout the past, including

(41) At noon, 12 june 1586, there was an even number of cats in London

to be either true or false, i.e. regardless of whether there is any evidence todecide the matter. Thus, the concept of truth was seen as naturally belongingin positions where one did not equate it with correct assertibility. Dummett hasargued against the legitimacy of such realist notions of truth (e.g. in Dummett1991:343-51).

Dummett has, however, also suggested an anti-realist conception of truthfor logic and mathematics (e.g. in Dummett 1998). Logic and mathematics is

16

Page 17: Assertion.stanford

different from empirical areas, since normally, what is asserted is what is proved.The possession of proof is conclusive evidence, and without a proof a mathe-matical assertion isn’t correct. So availability of proof and correct assertibilitycoincides. But it cannot be correct assertibility in the subjective sense, sincethere may exist a proof of which the speaker isn’t aware. The question is, then,what to count as objective correctness, that is, in what sense a proof shall beavailable. According to Dag Prawitz (1998b) it is enough that there exists aproof in an abstract, timeless sense, even if we don’t know that there is a proof.Our discovery that there is one, by means of constructing a proof representa-tion, gives us knowledge that the statement was true all along, and does notmake it true. For Dummett, this is too realistic. According to Dummett, astatement counts as true just if we have a proof of it, or possess a method thatis guaranteed to generate a proof or a disproof. To the latter category belongse.g. sentence of the form

(42) n is a prime number

for some large n. We may not know whether or not n is prime, but we havea method for deciding the question, and the method will either deliver a proofthat n is prime or a disproof, i.e. a proof that n is not prime. If the methodwould give a proof, then (42) is true even if we don’t know that it is. Fermat’sTheorem, on the other hand, for which no such method existed, was true onPrawitz’s view before the proof by Andrew Wiles was completed, but not onDummett’s (there is, however, a complication in Dummett’s case because of thesemantics of past tense sentences).

4.5 Truth and meaning theory

The idea that the meaning of a declarative sentence is its truth conditions re-ceived a new form with Davidson’s truth theoretic program in semantics (David-son 1967, 1984, Larson and Segal 1995). Several major questions have arisenbecause of this program. At least three of them are directly concerned withassertion.

The first question is whether the truth conditions of a sentence s, as specifiedin a truth theory, coincide with the content of an assertoric utterance of s. JohnMcDowell (1980:120) has claimed this to be the case, and so to Jason Stanley(2000:395). It has been almost categorically denied by Hermann Cappelen andErnie Lepore (1997:294). A first problem for McDowell’s view would be theindexicality of sentences. For instance, the sentence

(43) It is raining

does not have truth conditions simpliciter. Rather, it is true with respect tosome places and times but not others. A solution to problems of this kind was,however, suggested early on by Davidson himself. Instead of the sentence

(44) ‘It is raining’ is true if, and only if, it is raining

17

Page 18: Assertion.stanford

which is itself indexical, and does not capture the general context dependenceof (43), Davidson suggested (1973:135)

(45) ‘It is raining’ is true as uttered by a speaker S at a time t if, and only if,it is raining near S at t.

This relativizes truth conditions to speaker and time, and thereby describes theindexicality of (43).

Other potential problems concern implicature, both conventional and con-versational. In uttering his line in

(12) A: Where does John spend the summer?B: Somewhere in Canada.

B may intentionally implicate that he doesn’t know more than he says. In asense, this is part of the content of his utterance, but that more complex contentis not, of course, specified by any systematic semantics as the meaning of

(46) John spends his summer somewhere in Canada.

However, what is implicated does depend on what is directly said by means(46), or by B’s elliptical version of it, which is to be specified by the truththeory. This is the primary assertoric act by the speaker. It may be enough ifthe semantic theory succeeds in specifying the content of primary acts, made bymeans of a sentence, leaving it to pragmatic theory to account for implicatureand indirect speech acts.

There is yet a harder problem. To take a typical example (cf Recanati(1993:263), the sentence

(47) The ham sandwich left without paying

can be used, e.g. when uttered by one waiter to another at a restaurant, toassert that

(48) The guest that had ordered the ham sandwich left the restaurant wihoutpaying.

This is not an indirect speech act or implicature. It is the primary act, but hasa content different from anything that would be specified by a meaning theory,truth theoretic or other. Two pragmatic phenomenona are involved here, bothof which add content to what is literally expressed. First there is the adding of‘the restaurant’, i.g. adding an argument to the verb ‘leave’, without which thesentence isn’t truth evaluable. This is called saturation by Recanati (2001:299)and explicature in Relevance Theory (Sperber and Wilson 1992:182). Secondly,there is the addition of ‘the guest that had ordered’, which isn’t necessary inthat way. This is called free enrichment by Recanati (2001:300), and againexplicature in Relevance Theory.

Although there are different views of the mechanisms involved in success-ful communication of this kind, with pragmatically added content, it is hard to

18

Page 19: Assertion.stanford

deny that the phenomenon is real (but see Stanley 2000). According to scepticalviews, no systematic meaning theory can specify the content of any assertion,because the content will always be different from the meaning of the sentenceused according to such a theory. There is accordingly pessimism about a sys-tematic understanding the pragmatics involved (Cappelen and Lepore 1997),and pessimism about a systematic semantic theory because that (Travis 1985).There is also some optimism about combining systematic semantics theory withgeneral pragmatic principles (e.g. Recanati).

The considerations above concerned the relation between utterance contentand non-linguistic context. There is also, however, a complex of issues concern-ing linguistic context and utterance content. To take a classical example, in thediscourse

(49) A man walks in the park. He whistles.

the second sentence, ‘he whistles’, does not have a proper truth conditionalcontent, not even relative to context. There is no assignment of a value to thepronoun ‘he’ that gives the truth conditions of ‘he whistles’ in this discourse.Rather, the addition of this second sentence has the function of adding infor-mation. More precisely, it has the function of adding information in such a waythat what information is added depends on what information we start out with.The first sentence gives the information (relative to contextual parameters oftime and place) that there is a man that walks in the park, and after the ad-dition we have the more complete information that there is a man that walksin the park and whistles. If truth conditions is a set of possible worlds, thenbecause of the addition the truth conditions of the whole discourse is a propersubset of the truth conditions of the first sentence; the range of possibilities hasbeen narrowed down.

The meaning of the second sentence should then be characterized as a func-tion that maps truth conditions on truth conditions, rather than simply as truthconditions. This can be generalized to all sentences, since simple truth condi-tions correspond to additions that don’t depend on what information one startsout with (the function involved is then just the intersection of the initial set ofworlds with the added set, and if you don’t have any prior information, the ini-tial set is the entire universe of worlds, in which case the intersection is identicalwith the second set). If the utterance that adds the second sentence is an asser-tion in its own right, then these considerations give a reason for denying that ingeneral assertoric content is truth conditions. Theories of discourse semantics,concerned with phenomena of this kind, include Discourse Representation The-ory (Kamp and Reyle 1993) and Dynamic Predicate Logic (Groenendijk andStokhof 1991).

Discourse semantics blends in with context dependence in complicated ways.As has been stressed by Robert Stalnaker (1974, 1978), assertions in a discourseor in a conversation add to recorded information, and thus add to what ispresupposed in the context of utterance. What is presupposed at a given timeaffects the interpretation of utterances made at that time. Thus, as it evolves

19

Page 20: Assertion.stanford

a conversation changes the factors for interpreting new contributions to itself.As was stressed by Lewis (1979), however, there is a mutual influence betweencontext and new conversational contributions. In so-called accommodation, thehearer adds background assumptions that would be required for interpretation.For instance, upon hearing Lewis utter ‘the can has gone upstairs’, the hearerwho didn’t know may accommodate by adding the assumption that there is aunique contextually salient cat.

The second major question concerns the meaning theoretical focus on declar-ative sentences. Truth theoretic or other systematic semantic theories invariablyspecify the meaning of declarative sentences, as opposed to imperative and in-terrogative. There is a corresponding focus on assertion as more central tolinguistic meaning than any other illocutionary type.

This has led to a discussion about whether there could have been a linguis-tic practice with only assertions, or a linguistic practice without assertions (cfDummett 1981:601). An positive answer to the first question and negative tothe second was thought to justify the central meaning theoretical importanceof assertion. Such a discussion is, however, of questionable value. It is part ofnormal human social existence to need and want to share information as wellas to seek information (by questions) and to give directions of various kinds.Only in quite degenerate forms of existence could the need of either kind beabsent, and there is no saying what sort of language, if any, humans would haveor retain under such conditions.

The focus on declaratives in semantics is probably only a matter of conve-nience, due to the fact they will have to be taken account of anyway. For in-stance, a conditional question, of the shorthand form ‘[if p, then q ]?’, would takethe natural English form either of a conditional with interrogative antecedentand declarative consequent, as in

(50) Can ships fall over the edge, if the Earth is flat?

or with a propositional interrogative prefix, followed by a declarative conditional,as in

(51) Is it the case that, if the Earth is flat, then ships can fall over the edge?

Similarly with imperatives. By constrast, the declarative fragment of naturalEnglish is self-contained, and not limited in propositional expressive power.Hence it is convenient to focus on declaratives.

The third major question is whether the concept of truth is the most suit-able central concept for a semantic theory. Dummett (1976) challenged this,and proposed instead the concept of correct assertibility, or alternatively, ver-ifiability. Dummett’s reasons were, first, that if linguistic communication is towork, speakers must be able to tell whether or not they understand each other,and, secondly, this must be possible on a sentence by sentence basis, rather thanholistically, for many sentences together (as is the case in Davidson’s (1973) ac-count of radical interpretation). If meaning is truth conditions, then, according

20

Page 21: Assertion.stanford

to Dummett, this requirement is not met, for a speaker is not always in a po-sition to determine whether or not a sentence is true, which would be the wayof manifesting her understanding of it. By contrast, a speaker is always in aposition to determine whether or not there is evidence enough for a correctassertion of the sentence.

This argument against truth conditional semantics has been much debated.A central issue is the rejection of holism, further discussed in Dummett 1991.

5 Belief and knowledge

Two common ideas about assertion are that the speaker says what she believesand that she says what she knows. Given that assertions often are made thatdon’t fit these descriptions, the question is how those ideas can be worked out.

5.1 Belief

According to Frege (1918:22), an assertion is an outward sign of a judgment(Urteil). The term ‘judgment’ has been used in several ways. If it is used tomean either belief, or act by which a belief is formed or reinforced, then Frege’sview is pretty much equivalent with the view that assertion is the expression ofbelief.

How should one understand the idea of expressing here? It is natural to thinkof a belief state, i.e. a mental state of the speaker, as causally co-responsiblefor the making of the assertion. For instance, a speaker has a belief and wantsto communicate it. This motivates an assertoric utterance. The having of thebelief, i.e. the belief state, together with the desire to communicate, motivatethe action, and jointly cause it (if reasons are causes; cf Davidson 1963). Theassertion therefore gives evidence that the speaker has a belief suitably relatedto the meaning of the sentence uttered. On this conception, an assertion is theexpression of belief like a running nose is the expression of a virus infection, orgroaning is the expression of pain.

However, assertion and groaning can be pretended while a running nosecannot. I can pretend to be in pain by groaning, and pretend to believe thatthere are black swans, by means of an assertoric utterance of

(52) There are black swans.

In this case the utterance isn’t caused by the corresponding belief, but sinceit is an assertion nonetheless, not all assertions are expressions of belief in thesense suggested.

The utterance may still be evidence for the existence the belief state. Nodoubt, a speaker will not try mislead the addressee about the facts, by means ofan assertion, unless she assumes (tacitly, for the most part) that her assertiondoes count as evidence for the addressee that the she does have the belief in

21

Page 22: Assertion.stanford

question. This idea, of intending the addressee to take the utterance as evi-dence for belief of is a key idea in Bach’s and Harnich’s understanding of whatexpressing is. They say that

for S to express an attitude is for S to R-intend the hearer to take S ’s ut-

terance as reason to think S has that attitude (Bach and Harnich 1979:15;

italics in original).

‘R-intend’ is short for ‘reflexively intend’, a notion we will return to in thenext section. On this view, expressing is wholly a matter of hearer-directedintentions.

However, a speaker can clearly make an assertion even if the addressee has aprior conviction that the speaker is dishonest and will not treat the assertion asevidence for belief, and intuitively she can also make an assertion even if she isconvinced that that is so. It can happen e.g. in interrogation situations, wherethe speaker offically insists on an account of what has happened, knowing fullwell she will be taken as a liar. She will not then intend the interrogators to takeher utterance as evidence for belief. Insisting can be a conversational strategy,whether she is lying or not.

Intuitions are surely debatable here, but the possibility of such situationsmakes it problematic to treat the existence of such hearer-directed intentions asa necessary condition for an utterance to be an assertion.

A more neutral way of trying to capture the relation between assertion andbelieving was suggested both by Max Black (1952) and by Davidson (1982:268):in asserting that p the speaker represents herself as believing that p. Thissuggestion appears to avoid the difficulties with the appeal to hearer-directedintentions. However, it is not so clear what representing oneself amounts to. Itmust be a sense different from that in which one represents the world as havingblack swans by means of a normal assertoric utterance of (52) . The speaker doesclaim that there are black swans but does not also claim that she believes thatthere are black swans. It must apparently be some weaker sense of ‘represent’,since it is not just a matter of being, as opposed to not being, fully explicit.By means of answering the question what I believe with an utterance of (52) Ido represent myself as believing that there are black swans, equivalently withasserting it. What I assert then is wrong if I don’t have the belief, despite theexistence of black swans.

On the other hand, it must also be stronger than the sense of ‘represent’ bywhich an actor can be said to represent himself as believing something on stage.The actor says

(53) I’m in the biology department

thereby representing himself as asserting that he is in the biology department,since he represents himself as being a man who honestly asserts that he is inthe biology department. By means of that he in one sense represents himself asbelieving that he is in the biology department. But the hearer is no way invitedto believe that the speaker, i.e. the actor, has that belief.

22

Page 23: Assertion.stanford

Apparently, the relevant sense of ‘represent’ is not easy to specify. An alter-native is again to go normative, with the rule

(Bel) Say only what you believe!

This accords with but is stronger than Grice’s first submaxim of Quality: Donot say what you believe to be false (Grice 1989:27). An immediate objection tothis is that (Bel) is a moral rule rather than a rule that accounts for assertionas such. Speakers may be subject to this rule, but as moral agents more thanas speakers. But this objection can be met. It can be agreed that being honest,or sincere, indeed is something required by a moral rule. However, you can beinsincere in many different ways. What (Bel) specifies is what kind of insincerity,and thereby sincerity, is specific to assertion. That is, you can regard the appealto (Bel) as equivalent with a statement about what counts as being sincere:

(Si) An act of type X is sincere if, and only if, the speaker believes whatshe says

Then you can go on to claim that assertion is a value of X, or even the uniquevalue of X, that makes (Si) come out true. This idea is part of Searle’s account,as we shall in the next section.

By switching to a characterization of sincerity we can drop the appeal torules. Does (Si), then, adequately characterize assertion? There are, in fact,problems both of sufficiency and necessity. Suppose it is reasonable to saythat the speaker is insincere just if she intends to mislead the hearer about thefacts by means of the assertion. In that case, an assertion can be insincereeven though what is asserted is believed by the speaker. This can happen ifthe speaker deliberately tries to make the addressee infer something false. Forinstance, by reporting

(54) A blue Lincoln Continental was parked outside Mrs Jones’s house lastnight

I may deliberately mislead the addressee to believe that her husband has beenunfaithful. It need not even be a case of implicature. This kind of indirectinsincerity cannot be eliminated by requiring that the addressee not arrive ather belief by inference, since it is anyway supposed to be arrived at by inferencefrom the observation of the utterance in the first place. So believing what onesays is apparently not sufficient for an assertion to be sincere. Conversely, I maydeliberately lead the addressee to infer something true by means of assertingwhat I take to be false. For instance, knowing that you take me to be notoriouslyexaggerating, I can inform you by means of

(55) Lisa danced with every guy at the party

that Lisa had danced with many of the guys at the party. I expect you to inferwhat is true from my assertion of a falsehood. Thus I am sincere in intending you

23

Page 24: Assertion.stanford

to acquire a true belief, and it cannot be a necessary condition for an assertionto be sincere that the speaker believes what is said. Again the complexity ofhuman psychology makes appeal to speaker intentions problematic.

Maybe, then, belief, just isn’t essential to assertion. Maybe there simplyis a statistical correlation between utterances being assertoric and the speakersbelieving what they say. This correlation may be more or less characteristic ofassertion as an illocutionary type. However, one reason for thinking that it isn’tmerely a matter of statistics is suggested by Moore’s paradox. Moore’s paradoxis exemplified by means of sentences such as

(56) It is raining and I don’t believe it.

The paradoxical nature of an utterance of (56) is that it is distinctly odd andin some sense self-defeating, despite the fact that it may well be true. Therehave been broadly three kinds of strategy for dealing with the paradox, all threewith the aim of deriving an underlying contradiction by means of some extraassumption (for an overview, see Sorensen 1988). The first, exemplified by G.E.Moore himself (1944), focuses on the nature of assertion, with the purpose ofexplaining the paradoxicality by appeal to some pragmatic property. In Moore’sown case, the idea is that the speaker in some sense implies (but does not assert)that she believes what she asserts (Moore 1944:175-76; cf Moore 1912:63). Soby asserting (56) the speaker induces a contradiction between what she assertsand what she implies.

The first to offer a doxastic analysis of the paradox was Jaakko Hintikka(1962:78-102). On Hintikka’s account, believing what is expressed by (56) willinvolve the speaker in both believing that she believes that it is raining andbelieving that she does not believe that it is raining, thus having inconsistentbeliefs. The problem with asserting (56) is that the speaker asserts what shecannot consistently believe. The argument, however, assumes the controversialBB principle, i.e. the principle that if a subject believes that p, he also be-lieves that he believes that p. According to a Wittgensteinean tradition, sayingassertorically

(57) I believe that it is raining

is a way of asserting that it is raining, albeit in a more guarded way. On thisalternative, the speaker asserts both that it is raining and that it isn’t.

On all three types of account, belief and/or representation of belief plays acentral role. But it is not obvious that it must. For the sentence

(58) It is raining but I have no evidence that it is raining

seems to be odd in pretty much the same way as (56), without mentioning belief,or any attitude at all. A possible explanation is that the truth of the secondconjunct undercuts the information value of the first. An assertion that it israining is potentially information that it is raining, i.e. provides evidence for thehearer about rain, but if the second premise is true, that potential is nullified,

24

Page 25: Assertion.stanford

since the rain claim is asserted not to be based on evidence in the first place.Thus, if what is asserted is true, the first part is not informative. In fact, thestandard Moorean paradox can be seen in this light, too: if the speaker doesn’tbelieve that it is raining, the assertion isn’t informative: it does not provideevidence for the hearer that it is raining, unless the speaker is an oracle, whoreliably speaks the truth without the need of believing what she says.

Although belief is closely connected with assertion as an illouctionary type,it has proved difficult to nail down a relation that is instantiated in every as-sertoric act. If one accepts a negative conclusion here, two alternatives suggestthemselves. The first is to interpret Frege’s idea that assertion is a sign of judg-ment in a different way. We can think of what is communicated by an assertionas a propositional content together with a judgmental force or mode. This wouldbe an abstract component rather than something mental. Judgment or belief isthe mental attitude of the speaker that corresponds to judgmental force, but thecorrespondence need not be realized (i.e. the speaker need not believe). Thissuggestion has the advantage of avoiding the need to require particular mentalstates of the speaker, and the drawback of postulating new abstract entities.

The second alternative is to conclude that belief is simply the wrong stateto relate to assertion. Maybe knowledge is more adequate.

5.2 Knowledge

Inspired by Davidson’s proposal that in asserting one represents oneself as be-lieving, Peter Unger (1975:253-70), and Michael Slote (1979:185) made thestronger claim that in asserting that p the speaker represents herself as know-ing that p. To a small extent this idea had been anticipated by Moore whenclaiming that the speaker implies that she knows that p (Moore 1912:63).

One argument for this view comes from conversational patterns. As a re-sponse to an assertion you can ask ‘How do you know that?’. This response, it isargued, would not be appropriate if the speaker did not automatically representherself as knowing what she asserts.

A second argument comes from considering a knowledge variant of Moore’sparadox:

(59) It is raining and I don’t know that it is raining.

If asserting (59), the speaker cannot know what she asserts. For if she knowsthat p&q, she knows that p and she knows that q. And if she knows that q, thenq. Applied to (59) this gives the result that the speaker knows that it is rainingand also doesn’t know that it is raining, i.e. an open contradiction. (This is aspecial case of the reasoning involved in the so-called knowability paradox, orFitch’s paradox; cf. Sorensen 1988 and Williamson 2000 for overviews).

The idea of the argument is that the strangeness of an assertion of (59) de-pends on the fact that such an assertion cannot be correct (warranted). That itcannot be correct is explained by the appeal to the idea of the self-representationas knower: I cannot correctly represent myself as knowing what I cannot know.Hence, on this veiw, I cannot correctly assert (59).

25

Page 26: Assertion.stanford

Unger and Slote, like Black and Davidson, do no explain exactly whatrepresenting oneself amounts to. Timothy Williamson (2000) has suggesteda version of the knowledge account that makes no appeal to self-representation.Williamson suggests the knowledge rule:

(K) Assert that p only if you know that p

(in Williamson the format is: one must: assert p only if one knows p; Williamson2000:243). This characterizes assertion as the type of acts that are correct justif the speaker knows that what is said is true. The same idea, or almost, is putforward by Per Martin-Lof (1998:108).

Williamson endorses the arguments presented above, and adds a furtherargument to show that inconclusive evidence is too weak for assertion. Heconsiders an assertion about a lottery ticket (2000:246-49). The draw has beenheld, but the result is not known to the speaker. Yet she asserts

(60) Your ticket did not win

on the basis of probabilistic evidence alone. Intuitively, as Willliamson pointsout, the grounds for the assertion were inadequate, no matter how improbableit was that the ticket was in fact a winner. Williamson concludes that onlyknowledge is sufficient for an assertion to be warranted.

Although these arguments to some extent support the knowledge account,they are problematic, as is the account itself. It is, for instance, problematic toplace so much emphasis on ordinary intuitions concerning rather a special ex-ample, such as the lottery example. Williamson does acknowledge (2000:256-57)that most of our ordinary assertions are made on evidence that is not conclusive,e.g. the assertion

(61) It is snowing

made on the basis of observing falling white stuff that may have been put thereby a film crew (Williamson 2000:257). Such assertions are considered acceptable.He explains this by saying that it can be reasonable to assert that p on evidencethat is inconclusive, because it can be reasonable for the speaker to believe thatshe knows that p even if she in fact doesn’t.

However, it is not clear why the intuition of unacceptability in the case of(60) concerns warrant, or correctness in the strict sense, whereas the intuitionof acceptability in the case of (61) concerns some other notion, such as rea-sonableness, rather than the other way around. On the alternative view, theunacceptability of (60) should be given another explanation than lack of properwarrant. Williamson does in fact consider an alternative explanation by appealto conversational implicature (2000:247-48). The speaker somehow implicatesthat she has more evidence than just the probabilistic evidence available toboth speaker and hearer. It is not so clear exactly what pragmatic mechanismis responsible for this, and Williamson refutes one proposal, but that is notenough for refuting the implicature alternative itself, much less that there existsan alternative explanation of some kind or other.

26

Page 27: Assertion.stanford

A problem with any account that appeals to standards of correctness forcharacterizing assertion, including Williamson’s version of the knowledge ac-count, is that standards of correctness can vary, both between contexts andbetween speakers. Standards for what to count as knowledge can be held tovary, too, and Williamson accepts that possibility (2000:254). As a result, whatcounts as an assertion will differ between contexts or between speakers, againa consequence Williamson accepts. This is, however, counterintuitive. Theproperty of being assertoric does not seem to vary with context. Speakers aresometimes more and sometimes less careful in making assertions, depending oncontextual demands, but this is not the same as saying that they are performingspeech acts of different kinds.

The context dependence of assertiveness can be avoided by making the con-text dependence of correctness explicit:

(KC) An utterance u of a sentence s is assertoric iff for any context c, uis correct in c iff the speaker of u knows in c what is expressed by sin c.

However, this move can work only if it is possible to make good sense of theidea that a particular utterance (the event) is straightforwardly evaluated withrespect to contexts where it doesn’t take place, something that is not easy tosee. For instance, it is not clear that a particular utterance with respect tosome other than its proper context need be assertoric at all; we would need toknow why it would even remain assertoric with respect to all context in which itcan be evaluated, and that seems to presuppose another answer to the questionwhat an assertion is.

The context dependence can again be avoided by determining universal stan-dards of correctness, e,g, in the form of universal standards of knowledge. Butthis need not have very much to do with actual linguistic practice. One mighttherefore try another idea: that it is some social, interactional property, ratherthan epistemic or cognitive, that makes an utterance assertoric.

6 Social character

The social character of a speech act can be of two kinds. On the one hand,there can be an institutional change of relation between speaker and addresseeoccurring because of a characteristic property of the act. For instance, by meansof a sincere utterance of

(62) I promise to call the repair shop

the speaker has committed herself, in relation to the addressee, to do something.Both speaker and hearer will regard the speaker as having incurred an obligationto the addressee.

On the other hand, there can be hearer-directed intentions which the speakerhas in performing a speech act. The speaker may intend the hearer to come to

27

Page 28: Assertion.stanford

believe something or other about the speaker, or about something else, or intendthe hearer to come to desire or intend to do something. Such intentions canconcern institutional changes, but need not. Intentions that are immediatelyconcerned with communication itself, as opposed to ulterior goals, are calledcommunicative intentions.

The distinction between these two kinds of social character does not coincidewith the distinction between conventional and non-conventional. For instance,you can hold that there is a form-force convention in English without acceptingany institutional theory about illocutionary types.

The idea of communicative intentions derives from Grice’s 1957 article ‘Mean-ing’, where Grice defined what it is for a speaker to non-naturally mean some-thing. Grice’s idea can be set out as follows:

S non-naturally means something by an utterance u if, and only if,there is a hearer H such that i) S intends u to bring about a responseR in H, and ii) S intends H to recognize that (i), and iii) S intendsH ’s reason for R to be that (i).

(here ‘that (i)’ is short for ‘that S intends u to bring about a response R inH ’). That is, the speaker intends the hearer to react in a certain way becauseof recognizing that the speaker wants him to react in that way. Often, andin Grice’s original examples, the intended reaction is one of coming to believesomething, and that is a reaction that typically fits the speaker’s intentionor at least desire when making an assertion. Although Grice did not explicitlyattempt to define assertion, the idea can be straightforwardly applied to provideone:

(G) S asserts that p by the utterance u iff there is a hearer H such thati) S intends u to produce in H the belief that pii) S intends H to recognize that i)iii) S intends H to believe that p for the reason that i)

In the early to mid 1960s Austin’s speech act theory and Grice’s accountof communicative intentions began to merge. The connection is discussed inStrawson 1964. Strawson inquired whether illocutionary force could be madeovert by means of communicative intentions. He concluded that when it comesto highly conventionalized utterances communicative intentions are largely ir-relevant, but that on the other hand convention does not play much role forordinary illocutionary types. Strawson also pointed out a dfficulty with Grice’sanalysis: it may be the case that all three conditions are fulfilled, but that thespeaker intends the hearer to believe that they aren’t, e.g. by intending thehearer to believe that the speaker wants him to believe that p for an entirelydifferent reason.

Such intentions to mislead came to be called sneaky intentions (Grice 1969),and they constituted a problem for speech act analyses based on communica-tive intentions. The idea was that genuine communication is essentially open:the speaker’s communicative intentions are meant to be fully accessible to the

28

Page 29: Assertion.stanford

hearer. Sneaky intentions violate this requirement of openness, and thereforeapparently they must be ruled out one way or another. Strawson’s own solutionwas to add a fourth clause about the speaker’s intention that the hearer recog-nize the third intention. However, that solution only invited a sneaky intentionone level up (cf Schiffer 1972:17-42).

Another solution was to make the intention reflexive. This was proposedby Searle (1969), in the first full-blown analysis of illocutionary types made byappeal to communicative intentions. Searle combined this with an appeal toinstitutional relations as created by rules. Such rules are the so-called constitu-tive rules, as opposed to regulative rules (the terminology is taken from Kant).Roughly, whereas regulative rules regulate a pre-existing activity, such as trafficregulations regulate traffic, constitutive rules in a sense create a new activity.Paradigm examples are rules of games as defining games, and thus making itpossible to play them. The distinction was introduced by Rawls (1955), andalso suggested by C.G.B. Midgley (1959) in the same terms and format as laterby Searle (1969:33-42; cf. Gluer and Pagin 1999).

Searle suggests five rules for the use of force indicating devices. In the caseof assertion, they are as follows. S is the speaker and H the hearer:

1. The proposition content rule: what is to be expressed is any propositionp.

2. First preparatory rule: S has evidence (reasons etc.) for the truth of p.

3. Second preparatory rule: It is not obvious to both S and H that H knows(does not need to be reminded of, etc.) p.

4. Sincerity rule: S believes p.

5. Constitutive rule: Counts as an undertaking to the effect that p representsan actual state of affairs.

The fifth rule is constitutive. That is, according to Searle, without this rulethe practice of assertion would not exist. The existence of the undertaking isan institutional fact created by the utterance. According to Searle (1969:65),the speaker expresses the state required by the sincerity rule, i.e. in the caseof assertion, expresses belief. Also, the speaker implies that the preparatoryconditions are met.

The making of an assertion also involves the speaker’s communicative inten-tions. Searle critcized Grice for requiring the speaker to intend perlocutionaryeffects, such as what the speaker shall come to do or believe, pointing out thatsuch intentions aren’t essential (1969:46-47). Instead, according to Searle, thespeaker intends to be understood, and also intends to achieve this by means ofthe hearer’s recognition of this intention. Moreover, if the intention is recog-nized, it is also fulfilled: ‘we achieve what we try to do by getting our audienceto recognize what we try to do’ (Searle 1969:47). This reflexive intention isformally spelled out as follows:

29

Page 30: Assertion.stanford

(S) S utters sentence T and means it (i.e. means literally what he says)= S utters T anda) S intends (i-1) the utterance U of T to produce in H the knowl-edge (recognition, awareness) that the states of affairs specified by(certain of) the rules of T obtain. (Call this the illocutionary effect,IE)b) S intends U to produce IE by means of the recognition of i-1c) S intends that i-1 will be recognized in virtue of (by means of)H’s knowledge of (certain of) the rules governing (the elements of)T (Searle 1969:49-50).

The illocutionary effect IE is the effect of generating the state specified in theconstitutive rule. That is, in the case of assertion, the speaker intends that herutterance counts as an undertaking that p represents an actual state of affairs.

The analysis is completed by first requiring that normal input and outputconditions obtain, second that the conditions of Rules 1-4 are met, and finallythat the semantical rules of the dialect spoken by S and H are such that T iscorrectly and sincerely uttered if and only if the the aforementioned conditionsare met.

Searle’s account is thus a complicated combination of appeals to linguis-tic conventions, institutional relations, and reflexive communicative intentions.Later social accounts have tended to focus either on the conventional/institutionalor on the intentional features. An example is Brandom (1994). According toBrandom (1994:173-75), the nature of assertion consists in the fact that inassserting the speaker achieves two different normative/institutional results atthe same time: on the one hand she authorizes the hearer to claim anything thatfollows from what is asserted and on the other she undertakes the responsibil-ity of justifying it. Another example is Kotatko (1998:236-39), who like Searlestresses the importance of social conventions about what counts as making acommitment or undertaking.

Bach and Harnich, on the other hand, follow Searle in appealing to reflex-ive communicative intentions. On their analysis (Bach and Harnich 1979:42),assuming a speaker S and a hearer H,

(BH) S asserts that p iff S expressesi) the belief that p, andii) the intention that H believe that p

As we saw in the preceding section, Bach and Harnich’s understanding ofwhat it is for a speaker S to express an attitude is S to R-intend (reflexivelyintend) the hearer to take S ’s utterance as reason to think S has that attitude.They understand the reflexive nature of the intention pretty much like Searle.They say (1979:15) that the intended effect of an act of communication is notjust any effect produced by means of recognition of the intention to produce acertain effect, it is the recognition of that effect.

These appeals to reflexive intentions were later criticized, in particular bySperber and Wilson (1986:256-57). Their point is that if an intention I has as

30

Page 31: Assertion.stanford

subintentions both the intentionJ and the intention that the hearer recognize I,this will yield an infintely long sequence: the intention that: J and the hearerrecognize the intention that: J and the hearer recognize the intention that: Jand ....). If this is an intention content at all, it is not humanly graspable.

Another variant of the communicative intention analysis is Recanati’s. Partof Recanati’s solution to the sneaky intention problem, following Grice (1969),consists in simply demanding that sneaky intentions be absent. This is whatit is for an intention to be open, or default-reflexive (Recanati 1987:191-207).He also follows Sperber and Wilson’s idea of making something manifest, i.e.perceptible or inferable (Recanati 1987:120, 180, Sperber & Wilson 1986:38).Putting the various ingredients together (including prototypicality conditionsof assertion—Recanati 1987:183), we get:

(R) To assert that p is to make an utterance u by which it is mademanifest that the speaker has an open (default-reflexive) intentionthata) u gives the audience reason to believe that the speaker knows thatp and wishes to share that knowledge with the audience, andb) the audience recognize (a), and recognize it as open.

This is another complex analysis. The complexity of these accounts is itselfa problem, since it assumed that ordinary speakers are in the habit of makingassertions, and thereby to have the required intentions for doing it. But sinceit requires detailed analytic work to come up with the accounts, and there evenare competing accounts, it is unlikely that ordinary speakers have the intentionsrequired. If they do, they are clearly not aware of having them agents usuallyare aware of their intentions. Postulating such intentions in ordinary speakersis clearly problematic.

The difficulty appears even worse, as argued by Gluer and Pagin (2003),because there are speakers with a demonstrated inability to understand beliefand other cognitive attitudes. Some speakers with autism, with a verbal mentalage of at least eleven years, who are clearly by everyday standard using languagefor making assertions, fail so-called false-belief tests. Thereby they reveal aninability to distinguish between a proposition being believed and being true,and hence (since they do distinguish between truth and falsity), reveal a lackof understanding of what it is to believe something. If you cannot understandwhat it is to believe something, you cannot intend someone to believe somethingeither.

All in all, the complexity and sophistication required of asserters by thesecommunication-intentions accounts, indicate that they do not provide neces-sary conditions for making assertions. There is a recurring feature of reasoningabout communicative intentions that tends to generate such complexity. It isassumed that if an agent A intends to communicate, and communication es-sentially involves feature X, then A intends feature X to be instantiated. Forinstance, if communication takes place only if the hearer H recognizes A’s in-tention to communicate, then, by this reasoning, A must intend H to recognize

31

Page 32: Assertion.stanford

A’s intention to communicate (cf. Recanati 1987:203). But that inference isnot obviously correct. For it seems a sufficient condition of being able to intendto communicate that the agent can distinguish between communicative eventsand other events (e.g. by perceptual features concerning signs of attention etc),thus able to intend to realize an event of the communicative kind. It may sim-ply be a fallacy to project the theoretical understanding of what is involved incommunication on the intentions of the speakers.

Normative/institutional accounts of assertion do not seem to suffer fromthese problems. For instance, it is plausible that when a speaker asserts that p,she in some sense commits herself to the truth of the proposition that p. She putsher cognitive authority behind it, so to speak, and has to suffer some measureof social humiliation of what she says turns out false. This idea of commitmentcan also serve to distinguish between assertion proper and weaker constativeforms, such as guesses and conjectures, since these differ from assertion withrespect to commitment. So incurring a commitment seems to be a necessarycondition of making an assertion (however, the psychological makeup of somecompulsive liars poses a problem for this generalization, as well).

Nonetheless, institutional accounts and intention accounts share a problemabout sufficient conditions. It is argued in Pagin 2004 that social characteri-zations of assertion fail to be sufficient, for one can use the formulation of theaccount to construct an utterance type that isn’t assertoric but that would beassertoric by the account in question. A simple example is given by

(63) I hereby commit myself to the truth of the proposition that there are blackswans.

Intuitively, a sincere utterance of (63) would not be an assertion that there areblack swans. What is said does not imply that there are black swans. It isonly a declaration of the speaker’s stand on the question. Still, it does incur acommitment to the truth of the proposition that there are black swans. If thisis right, then incurring a commitment to truth is not sufficient for asserting.Similar constructions can be made out of other accounts, e.g. by letting thespeaker declare herself to have certain complex intentions.

Social accounts of either the institutional or the intentional variety risk losingwhat seems to be a core feature of assertion, the judgment expressing character,however that character is to be understood.

7 Logic

Frege introduced the turnstile, ‘`’, as a so-called assertion sign. It first appearedin the Begriffschrift (Frege 1879). According to Frege, it serves to express ajudgment (1879:11). The sign was meant to be composed from the horizontalpart, the so-called content stroke, and the vertical part, the so-called judgmentstroke.

Frege demanded that what follows the the content stroke must have a contentthat can become a judgment, which is to say a propositional content. With the

32

Page 33: Assertion.stanford

content stroke attached, but not the judgment stroke, we have an expression ofthe kind ‘the circumstance that ...’, or ‘the proposition that ...’ (1879:11). Healso characterized ‘`’ as a common predicate for all judgments, like the predicate‘is a fact’ as occurring in sentences such as

(64) The violent death of Archimedes at the capture of Syracuse is a fact.

Here the argument is a noun phrase denoting an event rather than a stateof affairs. This difference in syntactic format between that-clauses and eventterms is of less significance than the baisc idea that there really is just onekind of judgment. There are not e.g. any hypthetic or disjunctive judgments,only conditional or disjunctive contents. The contents vary, the nature of thejudgment remains the same (1879:13).

This view was retained in the Grundgesetze der Arithmetik (Frege 1893).The assertion sign is here still composed of the vertical part, the judgmentstroke, and the horizontal, no called the horizontal (der Wagerechte). While thejudgment stroke is more or less the same, Frege’s conception of the horizontalhas changed. The horizontal is now part of the expression of content. It denotesa function from objects to truth values (1893:9): it maps the True on the Trueand any other object on the False. It can occur in the interior of formulas.Remember that on Frege’s view at the time, truth values are among the objectsof the universe.

Since the judgment stroke is always followed by a horizontal, this construc-tion has the effect that what is judged always denotes a truth value, at leastif what follows the horizontal is a meaningful closed expression (not containinggaps or free variables). On the view that Frege had devloped since the Be-griffschrift, and which he argued for in ‘Uber Sinn und Bedeutung’, judgingis passing from the level of sense (Sinn) to the level of reference (Bedeutung).Judging that p is passing from the mere thought that p, to acceptance of thetruth of the thought that p. Thus, in judging you advance from a sense to a truthvalue. Conversely, advancing from a sense to a truth value constitutes judging.Therefore, we have a well-formed judgment, correct or incorrect, if what followsthe judgment stroke denotes a truth value. With the new conception of thehorizontal, the judgment is guaranteed to be well-formed.

Frege’s conception of his assertion sign fits well in with his own system ofdeduction. Every sentence occurring in a deduction in the Begriffschrift or theGrundgesetze is either asserted or a proper constituent of a sentence that is as-serted. Each sentence asserted is either an axiom or is derived from axioms bymeans of accepted rules of deduction. There is no such thing as an unassertedassumption occurring as a premise of a deduction step, and a fortiori no con-clusion of a deduction step that depends on an assumption. Correspondingly,the judgment stroke itself only occurs initially in each expression of judgment.There is no such thing as a complex judgment with other judgments as properparts. In particular, there are no hypothetical judgments, in the sense of ajudgment that is the consequent of a conditional.

The first of these limitations was later transcended by Gerhard Gentzen,and, depending on interpretation, maybe the second, too. With Gentzen’s Nat-

33

Page 34: Assertion.stanford

ural Deduction system (Gentzen 1934-35), a system of deduction was formulatedwith the possibility of making assumptions, making inferences from these as-sumptions, and also of discharging assumptions in certain deduction steps (⊃Introduction).

Secondly, Gentzen also introduced the Sequent Calculus (Gentzen 1934-35),with so-called sequents,

(65) A1, . . . , An → B1, . . . , Bm

as the asserted sentences of the calculus. Gentzen originally explained the mean-ing of the arrow as

(66) A1 & A2 & . . . , An ⊃ B1 ∨B2 . . . Bm

By this explanation a sequent is an ordinary construction of propositional logic.However, later on (1934-35, §4), Gentzen introduced another use of the arrowfor a Natural Deduction notation:

(67) A1, . . . , An → A

Here there is only a single formula in the succedent. This is a sentence form aptfor making claims, and it is correct just if there is exists a Natural Deductionderivation from the assumptions A1, . . . , An to the conclusion A. So the arrow isno longer to be interpreted as an ordinary implication construction, but indicatesthat the succedent is derivable from the antecedent, or that the succedent canbe asserted on the basis of the antecedent as a sequence of assumptions. Onthis interpretation, it is like moving Frege’s assertion sign from a sentence initialposition, making an assertion depend on assumptions. The question is how tounderstand this.

It might be natural to think of the advancing of a sequent as a conditionalassertion, i.e. as a type of act where the succedent counts as asserted on con-dition that all the elements of the antecedent are true. This has in fact beenproposed as the best way of understanding natural language conditionals, i.e.(in English) sentences of the form ‘If A, then B ’.

Generalizing the idea that there are forms of judgment with assertions asproper parts, there has been a development of so-called logic of assertion, andeven more generally, illocutionary logic, with complex speech act types, havingthemselves speech act types as proper parts.

These different deviations from the Fregean origins will be briefly touchedupon below.

7.1 Assumptions

In Natural Deduction, as well as in informal reasoning, we make assumptionsand infer new propositions on the basis of those assumptions, as in

(68) Suppose there is life on Mars.In that case, there must also be water on Mars.

34

Page 35: Assertion.stanford

This natural language rendering of the inference step would in a Natural De-duction setting (with the same informal language) look like this:

(69)There is life on Mars (assumption)There is water on Mars

where the premise is written above the horizontal line, and the conclusion below.In this case, the premise is an assumption

It is clear that assuming that p is something different from asserting that p.But it is less clear how to regard the concluding. We cannot simply say that itis of a separate kind, namely inferring or concluding that p. For the differenceat issue is precisely between inferring something from premises that are alreadyestablished, or that one at least asserts or believes, in which case one does assertthe conclusion, and inferring something from premises that are only assumed.In the latter case one does not simply assert the conclusion.

One suggestion is that the conclusion is conditionally asserted, i.e. condi-tionally on the truth of the premise. More fully, the idea is that if the premiseis true, the conclusion is asserted, and if the premise is false, the conclusionis not asserted, nor advanced in any other way. This is completely implausi-ble, however. The conclusion may serve as an essential middle step of a longerargument, such as

(70)There is life on MarsThere is water on MarsIf there is life on Mars, then there is water on Mars

The conclusion, on the third line, is formed by the rule of implication introduc-tion from the preceding derivation. The conclusion is (unconditionally) asserted,on the basis of the preceding step from the first to the second line, i.e. from theinitial assumption to the intermediate conclusion. The intermediate conclusiondepends on the assumption, but the final conclusion does not. But supposethat there is no life on Mars. Then, on the conditional assertion understand-ing, nothing at all is achieved in the second line: no assertion is made, nor anyadvancing of the proposition in any other way whatsoever. That is, it is as if noinferential step is taken. But that the proposition (that there is water on Mars)is advanced in some way or other is essential for reaching the final conclusionin the second inference step. The first step cannot simply be void.

We shall return below to the idea of conditional assertion in connectionwith conditionals (also, however, in Barker 1995, there is a non-standard use of‘conditional assertion’ which largely agrees with what I call ‘dependent assertion’below).

Maybe one could see the advancing of the proposition that there is water onMars, in (69), as an assertion of the proposition as depending on the the truthof the premise that there is life on Mars. That is, the act taken would be anassertion proper, but the object would not be simply a proposition, but a quaobject, the proposition qua depending on the truth of the premise. But this isnot a viable option either, even apart from general doubts about qua objects,

35

Page 36: Assertion.stanford

since inferring that there is water on Mars from the premise that there is life onMars in no way implies that the truth of the conclusion depends on the truthof the premise. There might well be water on Mars without any life on Mars,and the speaker who makes the inference is not required to think otherwise.

So neither the truth of the conclusion, nor the assertoric force itself, seemsto depend or be conditional on the truth of the premise. It remains, I think, twomain alternatives. The first I shall call the Prawitz alternative, which consistsin viewing the conclusion as asserted under an assumption. This amounts to ageneralization of the concept of assertion, and it remains to work out how thatis to be done.

The other I shall call the Martin-Lof-Sundholm alternative. It consists inviewing inferring from assumptions as advancing a sequent-like content of theform (67), i.e. A1, . . . , An → A. This is what Martin-Lof (e.g. 1998:108) hascalled a hypothetical judgment. It is supposed to be distinct from the assertionof a corresponding propositional implication

(71) A1 & A2 & . . . , An ⊃ A

Viewed this way, the argument (70) is recast as

(72)There is life on Mars → there is life on MarsThere is life on Mars → there is water on Mars→ There is life on Mars ⊃ there is water on Mars

where we have hypothetical judgments on the first and second line, and a cate-gorical judgment of an implication on the third line.

These two approaches have complementary virtues and vices as regards con-servatism. The Prawitz view is conservative about contents, but generalizesthe concept of an assertion, while the Martin-Lof view is conservative aboutassertion but generalizes the notion of assertoric content (this is done anywayin Martin-Lof’s type theory). The Prawitz view is closer to the surface form ofnatural language reasoning.

A possible way to flesh out the Prawitz view is to introduce a distinctionbetween dependent and independent assertions: Ordinary assertions, so far con-sidered are independent, and to assert that p, depending on q (and only on q),is an act such that when combined with an assertion of q yields an independentassertion of p.

Then, if we look at the little argument (69), we can see the advancing ofthe conclusion as an assertion, of the proposition that there is water on Mars,based on and depending on the proposition that there is life on Mars, in case thepremise is only assumed, and as based on but not depending on that proposition,in case the premise is itself asserted. In this way we could see the force of theconclusion as in a sense functional: the dependent force is a function that takesan independent assertion of the premise as argument and yields an independentassertion of the conclusion as value. This would be an analogy to functionalanalyses in other areas, in e.g. categorial grammar and proof theory. And it fitswell with regarding force as an abstract category, related to but not identicalwith elements of speaker psychology.

36

Page 37: Assertion.stanford

7.2 Conditionals

The so-called paradoxes of the material conditional have shown that there arediscrepancies between the use of ordinary indicative conditionals, such as

(73) If Reagan lost the 1980 election, he lost because people who didn’t likehim voted for him

and the meaning of a material conditional such as

(74) Reagan lost the 1980 election ⊃ he lost because people who didn’t likehim voted for him.

Since the antecedent is false, the material conditional (74) is true, but theconditional (73) does not appear highly assertible. Not even the fact that wehave good evidence that the antecedent is false makes us inclined to assert it.

The discrepancies also show up in reasoning, especially in combination withthe use of negation. The following is an example from Edgington (1995:281):

(75) If God does not exist, then it’s not the case that if I pray my prayers willbe answered. I do not pray. Therefore God exists.

If the conditional is material, then the negated conditional is equivalent with aconjunction of the antecedent and the negation of the consequent. So under-stood, the argument is valid.

If good evidence for the truth of the material conditional does not make anatural language conditionals correctly assertible, what does? Good evidence(by subjective standards) for the truth of proposition can be equated with highsubjective probability for that proposition. Ernest Adams (1965:176-77) pro-posed that a conditional if A, then B is assertible just if the correspondingconditional subjective probability of B given A, p(B/A), is high. This has cometo be known as Adams’ Thesis, and it is widely accepted (as usual, p(B/A)is equal to p(A&B)/p(A)), in case p(A) is positive, and undefined otherwise).Many examples in the literature illustrate that p(B/A) may be low even thoughp(A ⊃ B) is high. Frank Jackson has the following (1979:568):

(76) If the sun goes out of existence in ten minutes time, the earth will not beplunged into darkness in eighteen minutes time.

The conditional probability of the consequent given the antecedent is low, butthe probability of the corresponding material conditional is high, simply becausethe probability of the falsity of the antecedent and of the truth of the consequentare both high.

As noted above, the standard idea of of correct assertibility is that an asser-tion is correct provided there is good evidence for the truth of the propositionasserted. In terms of subjective probability, it is correct iff the subjective prob-ability is high. This equivalence is violated, given Adam’s Thesis, if naturallanguage conditionals are material conditionals. Keeping Adams’s Thesis, thereare three ways out:

37

Page 38: Assertion.stanford

a) Modify correctness conditionsb) Reinterpret the conditionalsc) Make utterances non-assertoric

All three have been tried.

7.2.1 Modify correctness conditions

Grice suggested (1989a) that there is a conversational explanation of why aconditional, when interpreted materially, can fail to be assertible even thoughsomething from which it follows, like the negation of its antecedent, is assertible.Asserting Jackson’s (76) on the basis of the high subjective probability of thefalsity of the antecedent would be misleading, since what one asserts is logicallyweaker than the proposition on which the assertion based: A ⊃ B follows from¬A, but not conversely. Therefore, the hearer is lead to believe that the groundsfor the assertion are other than they in fact are.

This line won sympathy. David Lewis (1976) followed and elaborated Grice’sidea. According to Lewis (1976:142-43), two factors detract from assertibility ofa conditional if A, then B : first, that the probability of vacuity p(¬A) is high,and second that the probability of falsity p(¬B&A) is a large fraction of theprobability of non-vacuity (p(A)). The product

p(¬A) · p(¬B&A)/p(A)

of these factors gives a measure of the reduction of assertibility, and the resultingdegree of assertibility is

p(A ⊃ B)− (p(¬A) · p(¬B&A)/p(A))

This in turn is equal to p(B/A), in accordance with Adams’ Thesis.Lewis’s application of Grice gave a kind of explanation of Adams’ Thesis. In

Lewis 1986, however, Lewis retracts his account in favor a related one offeredby Jackson (1979). Jackson criticizes the principle that one assert the strongerinstead of the weaker, and provides counterexamples such as

(77) If the sun goes out of existence in ten minutes, the earth will be plungedinto darkness in about eighteen minutes.

(1979:567). Here both the negation of the antecedent and the conditional havepossibilities close to 1, with the latter only marginally greater. So this wouldbe a case where the maxim of asserting the logically stronger should apply. But(77) is highly assertible (as it also is on Lewis’s account, but not by the simplemaxim). Jackson instead advocates the idea that we as speakers aspire to twothings: a high probability of the proposition asserted and robustness. Robust-ness of a proposition A with respect to another B amounts to preservation ofhigh probability of A given the truth of B. The official definition is then that Ais robust with respect to B iff p(A) and p(A/B) are close and high (1979:569).

This is applied to the case of conditionals with the further idea that assertionsof natural language conditionals are made both with claiming the truth of the

38

Page 39: Assertion.stanford

corresponding material conditional and to signal that this conditional is robustwith respect to its own antecedent (1979:576). Given this combination, andthe definition of robustness, the resulting assertibility of A ⊃ Bis high providedthe robustness condition is met, i.e. provided p(A ⊃ B/A) is high, and since(A & A ⊃ B) ≡ (A & B) we also have

p(A ⊃ B/A) = p(B/A)

and the requirement of Adams’ Thesis is met.One problem with this approach is that the general relation between truth

and assertibility, that that the proposition is correctly assertible just if thespeaker has good evidence for its truth, or high subjective probability, is vio-lated in the case of conditionals. Jackson’s idea of robustness does not havea straightforward general applicability. So it is not clear why the exceptionaltreatment of conditionals should not count against the interpretation of condi-tionals as material.

Another problem is that the difficulties get worse in the case of embddingconditionals in larger sentences (cf Edgington 1995:282-83). In general, theprobability of the negation of a proposition varies inversely with the probabilityof the proposition itself: p(¬A) = 1 − p(A). If we apply this to a conditionalwith Adams’ Thesis we have

p(¬(ifA, thenB)) = 1− p(ifA, thenB) = 1− p(B/A) = p(¬B/A)

That is, the negation of a conditional if A, then B is highly assertible just ifthe contrary conditional if A, then ¬B is highly assertible. Under the mate-rial interpretation, the negation of the conditional if A, then B is A&¬B. Thedefender of the material interpretation therefore has to come up with a furtherexplanation why a sentence that means the same as A&¬B still has the sameassertibility conditions as if A, then ¬B. Since the claim is strongly counterin-tuitive, no explanation is likely to come forth.

7.2.2 Reinterpret the conditionals

Robert Stalnaker (1970) suggested what is known as the Stalnaker conditional,A > B, as interpretation of if, then. The Stalnaker conditional is true iff theleast drastic revision of the facts (actual world) that would make A true wouldmake B true as well. Stalnaker then conjectured that p(A > B) would be equalto p(B/A) whenever p(A) is positive.

This conjecture was refuted by Lewis (1976), who proved that there is noconnective → such that p(A → B) = p(B/A) for any A, B and all probabilitydistributions p, except in extremely impoverished languages. The result waslater strengthened by Lewis himself and others. In Edgington (1995:273-74) itis proved that there are no propositions A, B and X, with A and B both contin-gent, such that p(X) = p(B/A) for all probability functions p. The argumentassumes probability distributions over possible worlds. The crucial considera-tion is that X will have to be true both in some A worlds and in some ¬A worlds,

39

Page 40: Assertion.stanford

and hence p(X) will depend on the probability distributions over both A worldsand ¬A worlds. But p(B/A) does not depend on the probability distributionover ¬A worlds. Therefore two distributions p′ and p′′ can agree on p(B/A) butdisagree on p(X).

These arguments do establish that there is in general no fixed propositionalinterpretation of a sentence if A, then B, if Adams’ Thesis is true. This does not,however, imply that a speaker using that sentence on an occasion of utterancedoes not express a proposition, even in case the antecedent is false. There mightbe scope for a theory of context sensitivity, according to which the meaning ofif A, then B combines with the speaker’s background beliefs to determine thetruth conditions of the utterance. Theories of this kind have been proposed,e.g. in Lycan 2001.

7.2.3 Make utterances non-assertoric

The last way out is to simply give up the idea that utterances of conditionalsare assertoric at all. Minimally, this amounts to the view that advancing aconditional is not putting forth a proposition as true, i.e. it is not an assertionin the usual sense. So views by which conditionals are not propositional, ordon’t have truth conditions, are views of this kind. Defenders include Adams,Edgington, Appiah (1985), Bennett (2003).

You take a further step by providing an alternative speech act account. Oneproposal of this kind has been prominent: that such utterances are conditionalassertions, not assertions proper. The idea of a conditional assertion is thatan assertion of B conditional on A is an assertion of B if A is true, and noassertion at all if A is false. Early suggestions that an utterance of a conditionalis to be understood as a conditional assertion were made by Quine (1952:19,crediting Philip Rhinelander), and by G H von Wright (1957:130). A fuller andmore systematic treatment was given by Nuel Belnap (1973). It is defended byEdgington (1995:288-91). For a more comprehensive history, see Milne 1997.

The description that a conditional assertion is an assertion of the consequentprovided the antecedent is true is highly misleading. On this description, ifspeaker X utters if A, then C and speaker Y utters if B, then C, then if bothA and B are true X and Y have done the very same thing, namely assertedC. Similarly, if both A and B are false, then again on this description theyhave done the same thing, namely made no assertion. But clearly they havemade utterances of different kinds, with different significance, in either case. Sowhat we should say is that if the antecedent is true, the conditional assertiongenerates an assertion of the consequent, and does not generate anything if theantecedent is false. This takes care of the immediate difficulty.

Dummett objected (1973:241, 1991:115) that the idea of a conditional as-sertion is like the idea of handing somone an envelope saying ‘open in case ofA’, and when opened proves to contain a letter saying ` B. He first commentsthat there is no such linguistic device, but retracts after considering conditionalbets and conditional commands. Clearly, if the condition of a conditional bet isunfulfilled, then the bet is simply off. It doesn’t have to be concealed what bet

40

Page 41: Assertion.stanford

it would have been, had the condition been met.More serious problems concern the embedding of conditionals in more com-

plex sentences. As Dummett, Edgington and others have pointed out, it isdifficult to make intuitive sense of conditionals that themselves have condition-als as antecedents, such as

(78) If, if Barcelona beats Real, then Barcelona will beat Dynamo, then Dy-namo will beat Lazio.

However, in some cases it is a lot easier, such as

(79) It holds either that if Barcelona beats Real, then Barcelona will beat Dy-namo too, or that if Dynamo beats Lazio, then Dynamo will beat Borussiaas well.

and one may therefore wonder whether the problem with (78) is not merely aprocessing problem due to the complexity of the sentence. Moreover, there arefurther problems with embedding the ‘if, (then)’ particle in quantified contexts,as in

(80) If any player shows up late, he will be kicked out of the team.

(80) is not a conditional, but a quantified conditional. An utterance of it cannotbe regarded as a conditional assertion, since the consequent does not express aself-contained proposition. Nonetheless, it does not seem hard to understand.

These difficulties are handled in Belnap 1973. Belnap develops the semanticsfor conditional assertion pretty much as a three-valued possible worlds seman-tics. A sentence s at a world w is either non-assertive or expresses a proposition.The semantics is given recursively over sentence complexity. For instance, a neg-ative sentence ¬A is assertive just if the negated sentence A is assertive, andwhat is asserted is the negation of what is asserted by A. This accords withAdams’ Thesis for simple conditionals, on the assumptions that i) Adams’ The-sis concerns conditional assertibility rather than assertibility proper, and thatii) negation inverts conditional assertibility.

In the case of the universal quantifier, the clause is

(81) 1. ∀xAx is assertivew just in case for some t ∈ C, At is assertivew

2. (∀xAs)w = &{(At)w: At is assertivew}t∈C

Applied to (80), this means that an assertion is generated, in a world w, onlyif there are terms t1, . . . , tn, 1 ≤ n, such that t_i ‘shows up late’ is true at w,for 1 ≤ i ≤ n. It further means that what is asserted in w is the conjunctionof what is asserted in w by t_i ‘will be kicked out of the team’, for 1 ≤ i ≤ n.Hence if Bill and George show up late, what is asserted is that

(82) Bill will be kicked out of the team and George will be kicked out of theteam

and if nobody shows up late, nothing is asserted.This is counterintuitive, since the speaker will then usually not know what

she has asserted until later, if at all. But worse, a speaker S might agree with(82) but may want to express denial of (80) by means of stating its negation

41

Page 42: Assertion.stanford

(83) It is not the case that, if any player shows up late, he will be kicked outof the team.

The reason might be the the speaker thinks it holds for every team memberexcept for Harry:

(84) Harry is on the team, and Harry will show up late, but he will not bekicked out of the team.

S might have excellent reasons for this belief, and from (84), S validly infers(83). However, by Belnap’s clauses, if Bill and George show up late but Harrydoesn’t, what S has asserted by means of uttering (83) is that

(85) It is not the case that (Bill will be kicked out of the team and George willbe kicked out of the team)

and this is even more counterintuitive: S is represented as inconsistent becauseof both asserting and deying that Bill and George will be kicked out of the team.

In a slightly different format, focusing on existential rather than universalquantification, this argument was advanced by Kolbel (2000) against Edgingtonand Belnap. Edgington (2000) responds that she has no general method forhandling generality problems (but insists that if a truth conditional theory wereright, there would be no problems with such sentences in the first place). Allin all, it is difficult to make the conditional assertion theory of conditionals fitintuitions.

7.3 Assertion logic

If we set out principles specifically valid for reasoning with sentences of the form

(86) x asserts that p

we may be said to have set out an assertion logic or logic of assertion. Exactlywhat to count as a logic of assertion is not so clear, since it depends on whetherthe term ‘assertion’ in this context is taken in its default sense of an overtlyperformed speech act, or in some other sense, such as that of implicitly assertingsomething, or being rationally committed to asserting something. In these lattersenses a logic of assertion tends to be a form of doxastic logic (logic of belief),or a related kind of modal logic. We shall here look at the assertion logics byRescher and Gullvag, and the illocutionary logic by Searle and Vanderveken.

Nicholas Rescher’s Assertion logic, (Rescher 1968), is concerned with whata speaker (individual or collective) implicitly is committed to i virtue of overtlymade assertions (Rescher 1968:250). Rescher sets out several systems of logicswith principles governing sentences of the form (86), abbreviated into ‘Axp’.Most of his systems contain a rationality postulate, that no speaker commitsherself to a contradiction:

∼ (∃x)Ax(p & ∼ p)

Reschers first system A1 contains three axiom schemata and one rule ofinference:

42

Page 43: Assertion.stanford

(A1) (∀x)(∃p)Axp (Nonvacuousness)(A2) (Axp & Axq) ⊃ Ax(p & q) (Conjunction)(A3) ∼ Ax(p & ∼ p) (Consistency)(R) If p ` q, then Axp ` Axq (Commitment)

By (A1) every speaker (assertor) asserts at least one proposition. By (R),a speaker asserts (is committed to) everything entailed by what she asserts.Specifically, it then follows that every speaker asserts every truth of logic:

If ` p, then ` Axp

Rescher gets the stronger system A2 by adding

(A2) (∀x)Axp ⊃ p (Lincoln)

an axiom to the effect that whatever is asserted by all speakers is true (youcan’t fool all the people all the time). An alternative strengthening of A1 isgenerated by adding A3:

(A3) p ⊃ (∃x)Axp (Collective Omniscience)

that is, whatever is true, is asserted by someone. Rescher notes that within A1

(A2) follows from (A3) (because of Consistency and Conjunction).The system A4 is generated from A3 with the axiom

(A4) Ax(Axp) ≡ Axp

of which the if part is called ‘Metahonesty’ and the only-if part ‘Metacandor’.The system A5, finally comes from A4 by the axiom

(A5) Axp ∨Ax(∼ p)

by which every speaker is complete in the sense of taking a stance towards everyproposition.

Speakers according to these logics, and especially A5, can be modelled assets of propositions, and thereby as possible worlds. One can therefore definea box operator 2p as ∀xAxp, and investigate what is needed to get the usualmodal systems (section 13). If axiom A5 doesn’t hold, one can apply a three-valued logic, where the third value corresponds to indifference. Rescher alsoconsiders, among other things, adding deontic and alethic modal operators tothe assertion operator language.

A related perspective on assertion is taken by Ingemund Gullvag (1979).Gullvag is more interested than Rescher in overt assertions, but still adoptsa similar consistency requirement (1979:79): you cannot, in one act, assertincompatible propositions. This serves to partly define what to count as oneact of assertion. If an overtly inconsistent assertion seems to be taking place,the utterance cannot really count as an assertion (1979:80). Gullvag’s formatis ‘Sxstp’, meaning that speaker x at time t by uttering sentence s asserts that

43

Page 44: Assertion.stanford

p. The consistency requirement is then set out as the axiom

∼ (Sxstp & Sxst ∼ p).

Gullvag also has a conjunction axiom (or assumption) corresponding to Rescher’s:

Sxst(p&q) ≡ (Sxstp & Ssxtq).

However, when it comes to setting out consequences of an assertion, Gullvagturns to a notion of a speaker’s pragmatically implying something by means ofan assertion. What the speaker implies is what she is committed to (1979:89).Among other things, Gullvag adopts the axioms and rules of inference

(A11) Ixstp ⊃ Ixst(Ixstq ⊃ q)(A12) Ixst(p & q) ≡ (Ixstp & Ixstq)(A13) IxstIxstp ⊃ Ixstp(RI) ` p ⊃ q → ` Ixstp ⊃ Ixstq(RTF) ` p → ` ∼ Ixst ∼ p

(I have changed the notation slightly). By A11 if a speaker implies anything,then she implies that whatever she implies is true. By A13, if a speaker impliesthat she implies that p, then she implies that p.

Later on (1979:103) Gullvag defines the S operator in terms of both express-ing and implying a proposition p, by which it follows that

Ssxtp ⊃ Isxtp.

To this Gullvag adds axioms about belief and implied belief:

(A14) IxstBxstp ≡ Ixstp(A15) IxstBxstp ⊃ Ixst(∼ Bxt ∼ p)(A16) IxstBxt(p ⊃ q) ⊃ Ixst(Bxtp ⊃ Bxtq)

Here, by A14, speakers imply that what they believe is true. By A15, if a speakerimplies that she believe that p, then she implies that she does not believe thenegation of p. Finally, if she implies that she believes a conditional, then sheimplies that she believes the consequent if she believes the antecedent.

With the help of these axioms and rules Gullvag derives a number of theo-rems, including the theorem

∼ Sxst(p & ∼ Bxtp)

(1979:108), saying that Moorean propositions are not assertible, thereby offer-ing a treatment of Moore’s paradox. Gullvag has some related theorems onpragmatic inconsistency. He offers a Hintikka style possible worlds semanticsvalidating the axioms.

The approach of John Searle and Daniel Vanderveken in Foundations of Il-locutionary Logic (Searle and Vanderveken 1985), differs from the two precedingones, in two important respects. First, it builds on a full-fledge theory of speech

44

Page 45: Assertion.stanford

act, a version of Searle’s. Second, it does not simply add special new operatorsto an existing logical language, but rather defines new relations of pragmaticconsequence between speech acts and mental states. The language of this il-locutionary logic is made up of event- or state-denoting terms, operators onthese terms, and defined relational expressions. It is not stated by means of theordinary logical constants.

The theory of illocutionary forces is set out with a set-theoretic machinery.An illocutionary force F is defined as a septuple

〈ΠF ,mode(F ),degree(F ),PropF ,ΣF ,ΨF , ηF 〉

where

a) ΠF is the illocutionary point of F (the assertive point is to say how thingsare),

b) mode(F ) is the manner in which the point can be achieved (in the case ofassertion there is no restriction),

c) degreeF is the characteristic degree of strength with which the illocution-ary point is achieved (the strength of an assertion is higher than that of aconjecture)

d) PropF is the condition on propositional content associated with F (no re-striction in the case of assertion, whereas it must be future in the case ofprediction and promise),

e) ΣF is the set of preparatory conditions that must be met if an act with forceF is to be performed (in the case of an assertion that p, the preparatorycondition is that the speaker at the time of utterance has reasons or evidencethat it is true that p),

f) ΨF is the set of sincerity conditions associated with F , i.e. the conditionsthat must be met if the act of force F is to be sincerely performed (in thecase of an assertion that p it is the condition that the speaker believes thatp),

g) ηF is the characteristic degree of strength to which the sincerity conditionsmust be fulfilled. Normally, this value (integer) is identical with degree(F )(1985:36-48, cf section 6 above).

Illocutionary forces include the basic types, and complex forces generatedfrom them with three different operations:

1) Conjunction: an act of type A1 & A2 is performed in a context if the speakerperforms both an act of type A1 and an act of type A2 in that context.

2) Denegation: a speaker performs an act of type qA if she makes explicit thatshe does not perform an act of type A.

3) Conditional: a speaker performs an act of type p ⇒ A if she performs an actwith the purpose of performing an act of type A on condition that it is truethat p (1985:76-78).

Then a number of logic-like relations between illocutionary acts are defined(1989:78-82), including:

45

Page 46: Assertion.stanford

1) An illocutionary act A1 strongly commits the speaker to an illocutionary actA2 (A1B−A2) iff it is not possible to perform A1 without performing A2.

2) Two acts A1 and A2 are relatively incompatible (A1 >< A2) iff they are notsimultaneously performable.

3) An act A1 commits the speaker to an act A2 (A1 �A2) iff it is not possibleto perform A1 without being committed to A2.

In the last case, a speaker is comitted to an act iff she is committed to realizingall the elements of the force of the act.

Searle and Vanderveken exemplify a number of relations in these terms andstate a number of laws. For instance, two acts are relatively incompatible if theyhave relatively inconsistent illocutionary points, such as a promise Pr(p) to carryout a future act and an assertion ` (∼ p) that one will not carry out that act.The commitments of the two acts cannot be simulataneously fulfilled (1985:148).Similarly, two acts with preparatory conditions that cannot be simultaneouslyfulfilled are relatively incompatible; one cannot both congratulate and condolea hearer for the same event, since congratulations preusppose that the eventwas good for the hearer and condolences that it was bad (1985:149).

As examples of laws, we have the law that a speaker who performs the propo-sitional negation of an illocution is committed to the illocutionary denegationof that illocution (F (∼ p) � qF (p)). For instance, forbidding the hearer toleave the room commits the speaker not to order him to leave the room, sinceforbidding something is ordering not to do it (1985:162).

We also have a counterpart to modus ponens (1985:168); where F is a simplenon-expressive illocutionary force,

(F (p) & F (p → q)) � F (q)

A final example is the law that any illocution can be performed by way ofperforming a declaration (1989:175). For instance, a speaker who successfullyutters the performative sentence ‘I assert that it is snowing’ asserts that it issnowing (compare the argument to the contrary in section 6 above).

This work is further developed in Vanderveken 1990, but illocutionary logicis not yet established as a major area of logic. Nor is there reason to think thiswill happen any time soon.

References

[1] Adams, E, 1965, ‘A logic of conditionals’, Inquiry 8:166-97.

[2] Appiah, A, 1985, Assertion and Conditionals, Cambridge University Press,Cambridge.

[3] Austin, J L, 1956, ‘Performative utterances’ , in Austin, PhilosophicalPapers, 232-52, Oxford University Press, Oxford.

[4] Austin, J L, 1975, How to do Things with Words, second edition, OxfordUniversity Press, Oxford.

46

Page 47: Assertion.stanford

[5] Austin, J, L, 1979, Philosophical Papers, third edition, Oxford UniversityPress, Oxford.

[6] Bach, K and Harnich R M, 1979, Linguistic Communication and SpeechActs, MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass.

[7] Barker, S J, 1995, ‘Towards a pragmatic theory of “if”’, PhilosophicalStudies 79:185-211.

[8] Belnap, N D, Jr, 1973, ‘Restricted quantification and conditional asser-tion’, in H. Leblanc (ed), Truth, Syntax and Modality, North-Holland,Amsterdam.

[9] Bennett, J, 2003, A Philosophical Guide to Conditionals, Oxford Univer-sity Press, Oxford.

[10] Boghossian, P, 1989, ‘The rule-following considerations’, Mind 98:507-49.

[11] Brandom, R, 1976, ‘Truth and assertability’, The Journal of Philosophy73:137-49.

[12] Brandom, R, 1994, Making it Explicit, Harvard University Press, Cam-bridge.

[13] Cappelen, H and Lepore E, 1997, ‘On an alleged connection between thetheory of meaning and indirect speech acts’, Mind & Language 12:278-96.

[14] Davidson, D, 1963, ‘Actions, reasons, and causes’, Journal of Philosophy60:685-700. Reprinted in Davidson, Essays on Actions and Events, Claren-don Press, Oxford.

[15] Davidson, D, 1967, ‘Truth and meaning’, Synthese 17:304-23. Reprinted inDavidson, Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation, 17-36, Clarendon Press,Oxford, 1984. Page references to the reprint.

[16] Davidson, D, 1973, ‘Radical interpretation’, Dialectica 27:313-28.Reprinted in Davidson, Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation, 125-39,Clarendon Press, Oxford 1984. Page references to the reprint.

[17] Davidson, D, 1979, ‘Moods and performances’, in A Margalit (ed), Mean-ing and Use, Reidel, Dordrecht. Reprinted in Davidson, Inquiries intoTruth and Interpretation, 109-21, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1984.

[18] Davidson, D, 1982, ‘Communication and convention’, in Davidson, In-quiries into Truth and Interpretation, 265-80, Clarendon Press, Oxford,1984.

[19] Davidson, D, 1984, Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation, ClarendonPress, Oxford.

47

Page 48: Assertion.stanford

[20] Dummett, M, 1976, ‘What is a theory of meaning (II)?’, in G Evans andJ McDowell (eds), Truth and Meaning, Oxford University Press, Oxford.Reprinted in Dummett, The Seas of Language, 34-93, Clarendon Press,Oxford, 1993. Page references to the reprint.

[21] Dummett, M, 1981, Frege. Philosophy of Language, 2nd edition, HarvardUniversity Press, Cambrdige, Mass.

[22] Dummett, M, 1993, The Logical Basis of Metaphysics, Duckworth, Lon-don.

[23] Dummett, M, 1998, ‘Truth from the constructive standpoint’, Theoria54:122-38.

[24] Dewey, J, 1938, Logic:the theory of inquiry, Henry Holt and Company,New York.

[25] Edgington, D, 1995, ‘On conditionals’, Mind 104:235-329.

[26] Edgington, D, 2000, ‘General conditional statements: A response toKolbel’, Mind 109:109-116.

[27] Engel, P, 2004, ‘Truth and the aim of belief’, in Donald Gillies (ed), Lawsand Models in Science, London: King’s College Publications.

[28] Frege, 1879, Begriffsschrift, eine der arithmetischen nachgebildete Formel-sprache des reinen Denkens, Halle. Translation in J van Heijenoort (ed),Frege and Godel. Two Fundamental Texts in Mathematical Logic, HarvardUniversity Press, Cambridge, Mass. 1970. Page references to the transla-tion.

[29] Frege, G, 1892, ‘Uber Sinn und Bedeutung’, Zeitschrift fur Philosophieund Philsophische Kritik, NF 100, pp 25-50. In English as ‘On sense andreference’, Philosophical Review 57:207-30, 1948. Reprinted in P Ludlow(ed), Readings in the Philosophy of Language, MIT Press, Cambridge,Mass. 1997. Page references to the reprint of the translation.

[30] Frege, G, 1893, Grundgesetze der Arithmetik, Jena.

[31] Frege, G, 1918, ‘Der Gedanke. Eine logische Untersuchung’, Beitrage zurdeutschen Idealismus 2, 1918-19, pp 58-77. In English as ‘The thought. Alogical inquiry’, Mind 65, 1956: 289-311. Reprinted in P.F. Strawson (ed),Philosophical Logic, Oxford University Press, Oxford 1967. Page referencesto the reprint.

[32] Geach, P T, 1960, ‘Ascriptivism’, Philosophical Review 69:221-25.Reprinted in Geach, Logic Matters, 250-54, Basil Blackwell, Oxford, 1981.

[33] Geach, P T, 1965, ‘Assertion’, Philosophical Review 74:449-65. Reprintedin Geach, Logic Matters, 254-70, Basil Blackwell, Oxford, 1981.

48

Page 49: Assertion.stanford

[34] Gentzen, G, 1934-35‘Untersuchungen uber das Logische Schliessen’, Math-ematische Zeitschrift 39:176-210, 405-31. Translated as ‘Investigations intological deduction’, in M E Szabo (ed.), The Collected Papers of GerhardGentzen, North-Holland, Amsterdam 1969.

[35] Gluer, K, 2001, ‘Dreams and nightmares. Conventions, norms and meaningin Davidson’s philosophy of language’, in P Kotatko et al (eds), Interpret-ing Davidson, CSLI Publications.

[36] Gluer, K and Pagin, P, 1999, ‘Rules of meaning and practical reasoning’,Synthese 117:207-27.

[37] Gluer, K and Pagin, P, 2003, ‘Meaning theory and autistic speakers’, Mind& Language 18:23-51.

[38] Grice, H P, 1957, ‘Meaning’, Philosophical Review 66:377-88.

[39] Grice, H P, 1975, ‘Logic and conversation’, in P Cole and J L Morgan(eds), Syntax and Semantics. Speech Acts, 41-58, Academic Press, NewYork. Reprinted in Grice 1989.

[40] Grice, H P, 1969, ‘Utterer’s meaning and intentions’, Philosophical Review78:147-77.

[41] Grice, H P, 1989, Studies in the Ways of Words, Harvard University Press,Cambridge, Mass. –bibitemgrice89aGrice, H P, 1989a, ‘Indicative condi-tionals’, in Grice 1989, 59-85..

[42] Groenendijk, J and Stokhof, M, 1991, ‘Dynamic predicate logic’, Linguis-tics and Philosophy 14:39-100.

[43] Gullvag, I, 1979, ’The logic of assertion’, Theoria xx:75-116.

[44] Hintikka, J, 1962, Knowledge and Belief, Cornell University Press, Ithaca,NY.

[45] Kamp, H and Reyle, U, 1993, From Discourse to Logic, Kluwer, Dordrecht.

[46] Kotatko, P, 1998, ‘Two notions of utterance meaning’, Proceedings of theAristotelian Society, 225-39.

[47] Kolbel, M, 2000, ‘Edgington on compounds of conditionals’, Mind 109:97-108.

[48] Larson, R and Segal, G, 1995, Knowledge of Meaning. An Introduction toSemantic Theory, MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass.

[49] Levi, P, 1958, Se questo e un uomo, Giulio Einaudi, Turin. In English asIf this is a man, Penguin.

[50] Levinson, S C, 1983, Pragmatics, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

49

Page 50: Assertion.stanford

[51] Lewis, D K, 1969, Convention. A Philosophical Study, Harvard UniversityPress, Cambridge, Mass.

[52] Lewis, D K, 1975, ‘Languages and language’, in K Gunderson (ed), Lan-guage, Mind and Knowledge, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Sci-ence, University of Minnesota Press, 3-35, Minneapolis.

[53] Lewis, D K, 1976, ‘Probabilities of conditionals and conditional probabili-ties’, The Philosophical Review 85:297-315. Reprinted in Lewis, Philosoph-ical Papers, Vol II, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1986, 133-52. Pagereferences to the reprint.

[54] ‘Postscript to “Probabilities of conditionals and conditional probabili-ties”/’, in Lewis, Philosophical Papers, Vol II, Oxford University Press,Oxford, 1986, 152-57.

[55] Lewis, D K, 1979, ‘Scorekeeping in a language game’, Journal of Philo-sophical Logic 8:339-59. Reprinted in Lewis, Philosophical Papers. VolumeI. Oxford University Press, Oxford 1983.

[56] Lycan, W, 2001, Real Conditionals, Clarendon Press, Oxford.

[57] Martin-Lof, P, 1998, ‘Truth and knowability: on the principles C andK of Michael Dummett’, in H G Dales and G Oliveri (eds.), Truth inMathematics, Clarendon Press, Oxford.

[58] Midgley, G C J, 1959, ‘Linguistic Rules’, Proceedings of the AristotelianSociety 59:271–290.

[59] McDowell, J, 1980, ‘Meaning, communication and knowledge’, in Z. vanStraaten (ed), Philosophical Subjects, Oxford University Press, Oxford.

[60] Milne, P, 1997, ‘Brund de Finetti and the logic of conditional events’ TheBritish Journal for the Philosophy of Science 48:195-232.

[61] Moore, G E, 1912, Ethics, Home Philosophy Library. Second edition: Ox-ford University Press, Oxford 1966. Page references to the second edition.

[62] Moore, G E, 1944, ‘Russell’s theory of descriptions’, in P A Schilpp (ed),The Philosophy of Bertrand Russell. Reprinted in Moore, PhilosophicalPapers, Allen & Unwin, London 1959. Page references to the reprint.

[63] Pagin, P, 2004, ‘Is assertion social?’, Journal of Pragmatics 36:833-59.

[65] Prawitz, D, 1998, ‘Truth and objectivity from a verificationistic point ofview’, in H G Dales and G Oliveri (eds), Truth in Mathematics, ClarendonPress, Oxford.

[65] Prawitz, D, 1998b, ‘Comments on Michael Dummett’s paper: Truth fromthe constructive standpoint’, Theoria 54:283-92).

50

Page 51: Assertion.stanford

[66] Price, H, 1987, ‘Truth and the nature of assertion’, Mind 96:202-20.

[67] Putnam, H, 1981, Reason, Truth and History, Cambridge University Press,Cambridge.

[68] Quine, W V O, 1952, Methods of Logic, Routledge and Kegan Paul, Lon-don.

[69] Quine, W V O, 1970, Philosophy of Logic, Prentice Hall, Englewodd Cliffs,NJ.

[70] Rawls, J, 1955, ‘Two Concepts of Rules’, Philosophical Review 64, 3–32.

[71] Recanati, F, 1987, Meaning and Force. The Pragmatics of PerformativeUtterances, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

[72] Recanati, F, 1993, Direct Reference. From Language to Thought, Blackwell,Oxford.

[73] Recanati, F, 2001, ‘Unarticulated constituents’, Linguistics and Philosophy25: 299-345.

[74] Rescher, N, 1968, ‘Assertion logic’, in Rescher, Topics in PhilosophicalLogic, Reidel, Dordrecht.

[75] Schiffer, S, 1972, Meaning, Clarendon Press, Oxford.

[76] Schlick, M, 1936, ‘Meaning and verification’, Philosophical Review 45:339-69.

[77] Searle, J, 1969, Speech Acts. An Essay in the Philosophy of Language,Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

[78] Searle, J, 1975a, ‘Indirect Speech Acts’, in P Cole and J L Morgan (eds),Syntax and Semantics. Speech Acts, 59-82, Academic Press, New York.

[79] Searle, J, 1975b, ‘A taxonomy of illocutionary acts’, in K Gunderson (ed),Language, Mind and Knowledge, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy ofScience, University of Minnesota Press, 344-69, Minneapolis.

[80] Searle, J and Vanderveken, D, 1985, Foundations of Illocutionary Logic,Cambridge, University Press, Cambridge.

[81] Sorensen, R, 1988, Blindspots, Clarendon Press, Oxford.

[82] Sperber, D and Wilson, D, 1986, Relevance: Communication and Cogni-tion, Blackswell, Oxford.

[83] Stainton, R J, 1995, ‘Non-sentential assertions and semantic ellipsis’, Lin-guistics and Philosophy 18:218-96.

51

Page 52: Assertion.stanford

[84] Stainton, R J, 1997, ‘What assertion is not’, Philosophical Studies 85:57-73.

[85] Stalnaker, R, 1970, ‘Probability and conditionals’, Philosophy of Science37:64-80.

[86] Stalnaker, R, 1974, ‘Pragmatic presuppositions’, in M K Munitz and PUnger (eds), Semantics and Philosophy, New York University Press, NewYork. Reprinted in Stalnaker, Context and content, 47-62, Oxford Univer-sity Press, Oxford 1999.

[87] Stalnaker, R, 1978, ‘Assertion’, Syntax and Semantics 9, Academic Press,New York. Reprinted in Stalnaker, Context and content, 78-95, OxfordUniversity Press, Oxford 1999.

[88] Stanley, J, 2000, ‘Context and logical form’, Linguistics and Philosophy23:391-434.

[89] Strawson, P F, 1949, ‘Truth’, Analysis 9:83-97.

[90] Strawson, P F, 1964, ‘Intentions and convention in speech acts’, Philosoph-ical Review 73:439-60. Reprinted in Strawson, Logico-Linguistic Papers,149-69, Methuen, London 1971.

[91] Sundholm, G, 1997, ‘Implicit epistemic aspects of constructive cogic’ Jour-nal of Logic, Language, and Information 6: 191–212.

[92] Travis, C, 1985, ‘On what is strictly speaking true’, Canadian Journal ofPhilosophy 15:187-229.

[93] Vanderveken, D, 1990, Meaning and Speech Acts, Cambridge UniversityPress, Cambridge.

[94] Warnock, G J, 1973, ‘Some types of performative utterances’, in I Berlinet al (eds), Essays on J L Austin, Clarendon Press, Oxford.

[95] Williams, B, 1966, ‘Consistency and realism’, Proceedings of the Aris-totelian Society 60. Reprinted in Williams, Problems of the Self, 187-206, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge 1973. Page references to thereprint.

[96] Williamson, T, 2000, Knowledge and its Limits, Oxford University Press,Oxford.

[97] von Wright, G H, 1957, Logical Studies, Routledge and Kegan Paul, Lon-don.

52