+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Complementizers in Laz are attitude...

Complementizers in Laz are attitude...

Date post: 27-Dec-2019
Category:
Upload: others
View: 0 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend
1
Complementizers in Laz are attitude sensitive Ömer Demirok (MIT) · Deniz Özyıldız (UMass, Amherst) · Balkız Öztürk (Boˇ gaziçi University) NELS 49 · Cornell University · 5–7 Oct. 2018 1. Introduction Articulating attitude verbs and embedded clauses calls for: [Kratzer, 2006, 2016; Hacquard, 2006; Moulton 2009; a.o.] More action for complementizers!The Laz complementizer system provides evidence for: Complementizers that introduce an event predicate akin to “say” or “think,” which we model as their union (S T), Some embedded clauses compose with predicates via event summation (). 2. Complementizers in Laz Laz (< South Caucasian) has 3 types of finite subordination [Öztürk & Pöchtrager (2011), Demirok & Öztürk (2015)] 1 na-subordination: 1 OK across the board, except under manner of speech predicates. (1) [ cp Şana Şana noseri smart na na on] is X aceren believes / / X iduşunams thinks / / *k’iu screamed ‘S/he believes/thinks/*screamed that Şana is smart.’ 2 ya subordination: 2 Restricted to t’k’v (‘say’), ts’v (‘tell’), and iduşun (‘think’). (2) [ cp Şana Şana noseri smart on is ya] ya *aceren believes / / X iduşunams thinks / / *k’iu screamed ‘S/he *believes/ X thinks/*screamed that Şana is smart.’ 3 ya do subordination: 3 Q: How are clauses embedded under manner of speech predicates? 3 A: With ya subordination and the conjunction do. (3) [ cp Şana Şana noseri smart on is ya] ya do do k’iu screamed ‘S/he screamed that Şana is smart.’ 3 Additional fact about ya do: any VP can occur with ya do (4) [ cp Sebap’-on good.deed-is ya] ya do do fuk’aras poor para money niçams gives ‘S/he gives money to the poor, saying/thinking it’s a good deed.’ 3 Plan: i. Derive co-occurence restrictions 3 Plan: ii. Understand what ya do contributes. 3. Proposal 1 na clauses co-occur with semantically transitive attitude verbs. 1 They restrict the internal argument of the attitude verb. [Kratzer 2006, 2016; Chung & Ladusaw 2001] (5) a. X r say z = λx e.say(e)(x) x individuals with content b. × r scream z = λe.scream(e) (6) a. r na z = r that z = λpx .content(x) p b. Restrict( r say z , r na z (p)) =λx e.say(e)(x) cont.(x) p 2 ya introduces a predicate of events we call S T. 2 ya clauses end up having VP meanings. (7) r S T z = r say z r think z Intuition: saying and thinking (inner speech) form a natural class of events that involve linguistic production [cf.*belief] (8) r ya z = λpx . λe.S T(e)(x) content(x) p JnaK(p)(x) 2a They can compose via Predicate Modification. (9) Artek Arte [ cp Şana Şana noseri smart on is ya] ya [ vp iduşunams] thinks ‘Arte thinks that Şana is smart.’ a. r VP z = λx e.think(e)(x) b. r CP z = λx e.S T(e)(x) cont.(x) ⊆{w : smart(ş)(w)} c. Predicate Modification( r VP z , r CP z )= λx e.think(e)(x) content(x) ⊆{w : smart(ş)(w)} This derives the selection facts in (2): r believe z r S T z = This derives the selection facts in (2): r think/say z r S T z = 2b They can compose by a sum forming operator , encoded in do. (10) [ cp it’s a good deed ya] do [ vp gives-money] cf. (4) a. X Event summation: X λe.e 1 , e 2 , x[give-money(e 1 ) S T(e 2 )(x) e=e 1 e 2 content(x) = {w : giving-money-is-a-good-deed(w)}] b. × Event identification/Predicate Modification: × λe.x[give-money(e) S T(e)(x) content(x) = {w : giving-money-is-a-good-deed(w)}] Kratzer (2016): Events introduced by manner of speech verbs are identified (not summed) with saying events. This poster: Event identification doesn’t work in at least cases like (4)/(10) sum-formation is required in general. [see also Özyıldız et al. 2018] 4. Supporting evidence Claim#1: ya encodes the meaning of r S T z = r say z r think z . Claim#2: ya do is compositional. 1 do sums individuals, in addition to being able to sum events (11) Şana Şana do and Arte-k Arte-erg ok’i-coxaman-an recip-call.impf-pl ‘Şana and Arte are calling each other.’ 2 ya do is not a generalized clause linker: S T meaning obligatory (12) #Mç’imu it.rained ya ya do do viğvari I.got.wet a. #‘I got wet, saying/thinking it rained.’ b. Intended: ‘I got wet because it rained.’ 3 ya incorporates r S T z : Bare ya clauses (13) Berepek children [noseri smart voret] we.are ya. ya Lit: The children say/think ‘we are smart.’ Context: The children each said ‘I’m smart.’ (14) Berek child ğoma yesterday uneneli silent uneneli silent vinçirare I.will.swim ya. ya ‘The child 1 yesterday silently said that s/he 1 will swim.’ 4 There is no ellipsis: ya (do) = ya say/think (do) (15) Tsoxle first vizgalare 1.will.walk ya ya *(t’k’u) said do and uk’ule later uk’ap’u ran ‘S/he first said ’I will walk,’ and s/he later ran.’ (16) a. Mi-k who-erg mp’olis in.city vore I.am ya ya X (t’k’u) said ‘Who said ‘I’m in Istanbul?” b. Arte-k Arte-erg nak where vore I.am ya ya *(t’k’u) said ‘Where did Arte say ‘I am t?’ no VP above ya no extraction out of ya clause Acknowledgments: We thank Danny Fox, Sabine Iatridou, Norvin Richards, and the participants of the UMass semantics workshop for feedback and discussion, and—most importantly—our language consultant İsmail Bucaklişi. All errors are our own.
Transcript
Page 1: Complementizers in Laz are attitude sensitivedemirok.scripts.mit.edu/web/wp-content/uploads/2018/10/nels49-poster.pdfComplementizers in Laz are attitude sensitive ÖmerDemirok(MIT)·DenizÖzyıldız(UMass,Amherst)·BalkızÖztürk(BoˇgaziçiUniversity)

Complementizers in Laz are attitude sensitiveÖmer Demirok (MIT) · Deniz Özyıldız (UMass, Amherst) · Balkız Öztürk (Bogaziçi University)NELS 49 · Cornell University · 5–7 Oct. 2018

1. Introduction

•Articulating attitude verbs and embedded clauses calls for:[Kratzer, 2006, 2016; Hacquard, 2006; Moulton 2009; a.o.]

“More action for complementizers!”•The Laz complementizer system provides evidence for:

•Complementizers that introduce an event predicate akin to“say” or “think,” which we model as their union (S∪T),

•Some embedded clauses compose with predicates via eventsummation (⊕).

2. Complementizers in Laz

Laz (<South Caucasian) has 3 types of finite subordination[Öztürk & Pöchtrager (2011), Demirok & Öztürk (2015)]

1 na-subordination:1 OK across the board, except under manner of speech predicates.

(1) [cp ŞanaŞana

noserismart

nana

on]is

Xacerenbelieves

//Xiduşunamsthinks

//*k’iuscreamed

‘S/he believes/thinks/*screamed that Şana is smart.’

2 ya subordination:2 Restricted to t’k’v (‘say’), ts’v (‘tell’), and iduşun (‘think’).

(2) [cp ŞanaŞana

noserismart

onis

ya]ya

*acerenbelieves

//Xiduşunamsthinks

//*k’iuscreamed

‘S/he *believes/Xthinks/*screamed that Şana is smart.’

3 ya do subordination:3 Q: How are clauses embedded under manner of speech predicates?3 A: With ya subordination and the conjunction do.

(3) [cp ŞanaŞana

noserismart

onis

ya]ya

dodo

k’iuscreamed

‘S/he screamed that Şana is smart.’

3 Additional fact about ya do: any VP can occur with ya do

(4) [cp Sebap’-ongood.deed-is

ya]ya

dodo

fuk’araspoor

paramoney

niçamsgives

‘S/he gives money to the poor, saying/thinking it’s a good deed.’

3 Plan: i. Derive co-occurence restrictions3 Plan: ii. Understand what ya do contributes.

3. Proposal

1 na clauses co-occur with semantically transitive attitude verbs.1 They restrict the internal argument of the attitude verb.

[Kratzer 2006, 2016; Chung & Ladusaw 2001]

(5) a. Xrsay

z= λx.λe.say(e)(x) x ∈ individuals with content

b. ×rscream

z= λe.scream(e)

(6) a.rna

z=

rthat

z= λp.λx.content(x) ⊆ p

b. Restrict(rsay

z,

rna

z(p)) =λx.λe.say(e)(x) ∧ cont.(x) ⊆ p

2 ya introduces a predicate of events we call S∪T.2 ya clauses end up having VP meanings.

(7)rS∪T

z=

rsay

z∪

rthink

z

Intuition: saying and thinking (inner speech) form a naturalclass of events that involve linguistic production [cf.*belief]

(8)rya

z= λp.λx. λe.S∪T(e)(x) ∧ content(x) ⊆ p

︸ ︷︷ ︸JnaK(p)(x)

2a They can compose via Predicate Modification.

(9) ArtekArte

[cp ŞanaŞana

noserismart

onis

ya]ya

[vp iduşunams]thinks

‘Arte thinks that Şana is smart.’a.

rVP

z= λx.λe.think(e)(x)

b.rCP

z= λx.λe.S∪T(e)(x) ∧ cont.(x) ⊆ {w : smart(ş)(w)}

c. Predicate Modification(rVP

z,

rCP

z) =

λx.λe.think(e)(x) ∧ content(x) ⊆ {w : smart(ş)(w)}

→ This derives the selection facts in (2):rbelieve

z∧

rS∪T

z= ∅

→ This derives the selection facts in (2):rthink/say

z∧

rS∪T

z6= ∅

2b They can compose by a sum forming operator ⊕, encoded in do.

(10) [cp it’s a good deed ya] do [vp gives-money] cf. (4)a. X Event summation:X λe.∃e1, e2, x[give-money(e1) ∧ S∪T(e2)(x) ∧ e = e1 ⊕ e2∧content(x) = {w : giving-money-is-a-good-deed(w)}]

b. × Event identification/Predicate Modification:× λe.∃x[give-money(e) ∧ S∪T(e)(x)∧content(x) = {w : giving-money-is-a-good-deed(w)}]

→Kratzer (2016): Events introduced by manner of speech verbs areidentified (not summed) with saying events.This poster: Event identification doesn’t work in at least cases like(4)/(10) sum-formation is required in general.[see also Özyıldız et al. 2018]

4. Supporting evidence

Claim#1: ya encodes the meaning ofrS∪T

z=

rsay

z∪

rthink

z.

Claim#2: ya do is compositional.1 do sums individuals, in addition to being able to sum events

(11) ŞanaŞana

doand

Arte-kArte-erg

ok’i-coxaman-anrecip-call.impf-pl

‘Şana and Arte are calling each other.’

2 ya do is not a generalized clause linker: S∪T meaning obligatory

(12) #Mç’imuit.rained

yaya

dodo

viğvariI.got.wet

a. #‘I got wet, saying/thinking it rained.’b. ‘Intended: ‘I got wet because it rained.’

3 ya incorporatesrS∪T

z: Bare ya clauses

(13) Berepekchildren

[noserismart

voret]we.are

ya.ya

Lit: The children say/think ‘we are smart.’Context: The children each said ‘I’m smart.’

(14) Berekchild

ğomayesterday

unenelisilent

unenelisilent

vinçirareI.will.swim

ya.ya

‘The child1 yesterday silently said that s/he1 will swim.’

4 There is no ellipsis: ya (do) 6= ya say/think (do)

(15) Tsoxlefirst

vizgalare1.will.walk

yaya

*(t’k’u)said

doand

uk’ulelater

uk’ap’uran

‘S/he first said ’I will walk,’ and s/he later ran.’(16) a. Mi-k

who-ergmp’olisin.city

voreI.am

yaya

X(t’k’u)said

‘Who said ‘I’m in Istanbul?”b. Arte-k

Arte-ergnakwhere

voreI.am

yaya

*(t’k’u)said

‘Where did Arte say ‘I am t?’no VP above ya → no extraction out of ya clause

Acknowledgments:

We thank Danny Fox, Sabine Iatridou, Norvin Richards, and the participants of theUMass semantics workshop for feedback and discussion, and—most importantly—ourlanguage consultant İsmail Bucaklişi. All errors are our own.

Recommended