+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Compliance with International Lathe modern legal principle of rebus sic stantibus (‘things thus...

Compliance with International Lathe modern legal principle of rebus sic stantibus (‘things thus...

Date post: 17-Jan-2020
Category:
Upload: others
View: 1 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend
29
1 Compliance with International Law Jana von Stein Word Count: 11,128 1. Introduction Compliance with international law (IL) has long puzzled scholars and policymakers. Many early debates centered around the question of whether IL was even law at all, given its lack of a overarching enforcer (Austin 1832; Morgenthau 1948; Hart 1961). Later, IR scholars showed that international cooperation is not only possible and sustainable, but also common (Axelrod 1984; Axelrod and Keohane 1986). Around the same time, Henkin (1979: 47) famously stated, “it is probably the case that almost all nations observe almost all principles of [IL] and almost all of their obligations almost all of the time” (italics are original; see also Fisher 1981). But by and large, most scholars agreed that it was puzzling – even surprising – that states abided by these obligations (Keohane 1984: 99; Franck 1990). If there exists no authority higher than the state, why do governments ever abide by the pacts they make with each other? How, if at all, are these pacts enforced? If states do comply, what does this tell us about law’s utility as a tool for bringing about real changes in how governments treat their citizens, how they apply antidumping measures, whether they curb pollution, and whether they defend their allies when war breaks out? This article engages these and related questions, drawing chiefly from the political science and IL literature. It starts by laying out some definitions, on core concepts like IL, compliance, and enforcement. In then provides a brief overview of foundational works that have helped define key legal doctrines that have helped to structure IR throughout the years. The remainder of the article explores the literature’s three main approaches to the compliance question. First, some scholars view noncompliance as chiefly a problem of enforcement. The lack of an overarching authority to punish rule-breakers poses challenges, but it does not render IL impotent. Rather, international inducements, reciprocity, reputation, and domestic politics/institutions can help to ensure that countries keep their promises – under the right conditions – by driving up the costs of noncompliance. A second group of scholars perceives most noncompliance not as a willful or calculated act, but rather as the result of capacity problems or poor management. From this viewpoint, the best path to compliance lies in writing transparent treaties, ensuring robust dispute resolution, and providing technical/financial assistance. Finally, a third group of scholars approaches compliance through the lens of identity, social context, and legitimacy. Governments keep their international promises when doing so is consistent with their identity, when they care how other actors – domestic and/or international – perceive them, and/or when they perceive the agreement as valid and fair. Throughout, I pay particular attention to what we have learned over the past 15 years. I draw examples from the qualitative and the quantitative literatures, although the emphasis lies more heavily on the latter. Previous reviews provide good overviews of
Transcript
Page 1: Compliance with International Lathe modern legal principle of rebus sic stantibus (‘things thus standing’), whereby treaties may become inapplicable if there is a fundamental change

1

CompliancewithInternationalLawJanavonStein

WordCount:11,128

1.Introduction

Compliancewithinternationallaw(IL)haslongpuzzledscholarsandpolicymakers.ManyearlydebatescenteredaroundthequestionofwhetherILwasevenlawatall,givenitslackofaoverarchingenforcer(Austin1832;Morgenthau1948;Hart1961).Later,IRscholarsshowedthatinternationalcooperationisnotonlypossibleandsustainable,butalsocommon(Axelrod1984;AxelrodandKeohane1986).Aroundthesametime,Henkin(1979:47)famouslystated,“itisprobablythecasethatalmostallnationsobservealmostallprinciplesof[IL]andalmostalloftheirobligationsalmostallofthetime”(italicsareoriginal;seealsoFisher1981).Butbyandlarge,mostscholarsagreedthatitwaspuzzling–evensurprising–thatstatesabidedbytheseobligations(Keohane1984:99;Franck1990).

Ifthereexistsnoauthorityhigherthanthestate,whydogovernmentseverabidebythepactstheymakewitheachother?How,ifatall,arethesepactsenforced?Ifstatesdocomply,whatdoesthistellusaboutlaw’sutilityasatoolforbringingaboutrealchangesinhowgovernmentstreattheircitizens,howtheyapplyantidumpingmeasures,whethertheycurbpollution,andwhethertheydefendtheirallieswhenwarbreaksout?

Thisarticleengagestheseandrelatedquestions,drawingchieflyfromthepoliticalscienceandILliterature.Itstartsbylayingoutsomedefinitions,oncoreconceptslikeIL,compliance,andenforcement.InthenprovidesabriefoverviewoffoundationalworksthathavehelpeddefinekeylegaldoctrinesthathavehelpedtostructureIRthroughouttheyears.Theremainderofthearticleexplorestheliterature’sthreemainapproachestothecompliancequestion.

First,somescholarsviewnoncomplianceaschieflyaproblemofenforcement.Thelackofanoverarchingauthoritytopunishrule-breakersposeschallenges,butitdoesnotrenderILimpotent.Rather,internationalinducements,reciprocity,reputation,anddomesticpolitics/institutionscanhelptoensurethatcountrieskeeptheirpromises–undertherightconditions–bydrivingupthecostsofnoncompliance.Asecondgroupofscholarsperceivesmostnoncompliancenotasawillfulorcalculatedact,butratherastheresultofcapacityproblemsorpoormanagement.Fromthisviewpoint,thebestpathtocomplianceliesinwritingtransparenttreaties,ensuringrobustdisputeresolution,andprovidingtechnical/financialassistance.Finally,athirdgroupofscholarsapproachescompliancethroughthelensofidentity,socialcontext,andlegitimacy.Governmentskeeptheirinternationalpromiseswhendoingsoisconsistentwiththeiridentity,whentheycarehowotheractors–domesticand/orinternational–perceivethem,and/orwhentheyperceivetheagreementasvalidandfair.

Throughout,Ipayparticularattentiontowhatwehavelearnedoverthepast15years.Idrawexamplesfromthequalitativeandthequantitativeliteratures,althoughtheemphasisliesmoreheavilyonthelatter.Previousreviewsprovidegoodoverviewsof

Page 2: Compliance with International Lathe modern legal principle of rebus sic stantibus (‘things thus standing’), whereby treaties may become inapplicable if there is a fundamental change

2

earlier,predominantlyqualitative,literatures(Kingsbury1998;Simmons1998,2010;RaustialaandSlaughter2002).

2. Compliance:DefiningtheTermsoftheDebate

Understandingdebatesaboutcomplianceisinpartanexerciseindefinitions.(Public)ILisgenerallydefinedasrulesthatgovernrelationsbetweenstates,and–insomecases–betweenotherlegallyrecognizedinternationalactors.Thisincludeswritteninternationalagreementsliketreaties,memorandaofunderstanding,etc.ButarenormsandcustomsalsopartofIL,whennotcodifiedinwrittenform?ManyviewcustomaryILasacrucialpartoftheinternationallegalarchitecture.Indeed,theseunwrittenstandardsofconductsometimesformthebasisofcourtdecisions(seeforinstancePaqueteHabana1900).Yetthebulkofthepoliticalscienceliteratureoncomplianceisconcernedwithwrittenagreements.Asaresult,althoughIusethemoreexpansivedefinitionofILthroughout,mostofthediscussionfocusesonwrittenagreements.Later,IconsiderwhynormsandcustomshavegainedlimitedattentionintheIRliterature,andwhatbenefitsanexpansionofscopemightbring.

Idefinecomplianceasthedegreetowhichstatebehaviorconformstowhatanagreementprescribesorproscribes(Young1979:104).Importantly,(non)complianceisaspectrum,notadichotomy.Ifocusonfirst-ordercompliance(adherencetorules),andsetasidesecond-ordercompliance(adherencetorulings).Thisisstraightforwardenough,butitisimportanttodifferentiatecompliancefromeffectiveness–thedegreetowhichanagreementhasanimpactonbehavior,therebyimprovingorsolvingtheproblemthatledtotheagreement’sformation(Young1997;Shelton2000;andMartin2013).

Thedifferencebetweencomplianceandeffectivenessiswellillustratedintheenvironmentalarena.Supposethatgovernmentsratifyatreaty,agreeingtohalvetheiremissionsofsomepollutantby2015.StateAmighthititstargetbecauseaneconomicdownturndrivesdownpollutant-relatedproduction,orbecauseatechnologicalinnovationreducesdemandforthepollutivesubstance.Thisiscompliancewithouteffectivenessbecausetheimprovementshavenothing(directly)todowiththetreatyitself.Conversely,in2015,stateB’semissionsmightremainwellabovethetarget.Butitmaynonethelesshavemadesignificantemissionsreductionsinanticipationofthe2015deadline.Thisiseffectivenesswithout(full)compliance.Inmanycases,ofcourse,complianceandeffectivenessworktogether.In2020,perhapsstateBwillbemuchclosertoitstarget(andthereforemuchclosertocompliance)becauseoftheagreement’scontinuedimpactonitsenvironmentalpractice.

Internationallegalscholarssometimesequateenforcementwithpunishmentbyacourt(e.g.,theICCoradomesticcourt)orotherinternationalauthority(e.g.,theUnitedNations[UN]SecurityCouncil).LikemostIRscholars,Iuseabroaderdefinition:enforcementisthe(threatof)applicationofsanctionsorsomematerialconsequenceifapartydoesnotcomplywithanagreement.

3. ThePoliticsofComplianceandEnforcement:Foundations

PractitionersandthinkersasfarbackasMachiavellihaveaskedwhether/whyleadersshouldcomplywiththeirinternationalcommitments.“AprudentPrince,”Machiavelli

Page 3: Compliance with International Lathe modern legal principle of rebus sic stantibus (‘things thus standing’), whereby treaties may become inapplicable if there is a fundamental change

3

argues(1532:ch.XVIII),“neithercannoroughttokeephiswordwhentokeepitishurtfultohimandthecauseswhichledhimtopledgeitareremoved.”Theseprinciples–thatgovernmentsshouldnotcomplywhenitisnolongerintheirinterestorwhenconditionschange–havecarriedforwardtomorerecentwritings.Indeed,theyformthemodernlegalprincipleofrebussicstantibus(‘thingsthusstanding’),wherebytreatiesmaybecomeinapplicableifthereisafundamentalchangeofcircumstances(Desierto2012).Ifhumanswerehonestandkepttheirpromises,thenthePrinceshoulddothesame.Buttheydonot,andthereforethePrincewouldbefoolishtoabidebyhiscommitments–indeed,hewouldreceivethesucker’spayoff.Ultimately,thisisanargumentaboutreciprocity.ForMachiavelli,humannatureprecludesreciprocityfromprovidingasuccessfulmechanismforensuringthatpromisesarekept.Aswewillseelater,morerecentscholarshipalsolooksatreciprocity,butseesitasareliablemodeofenforcementthatcan,intherightcircumstances,pushgovernmentstokeeptheirpromises.Additionally,clausularebussicstantibushasevolvedovertheyears.Thesedays,mostcourtsonlytakethedoctrineseriouslyinalimitedsetofcircumstances.Article62oftheViennaConventionontheLawofTreatiesprovidesagoodroadmap.

Grotius(1625)expressesaverydifferentperceptionascomparedtoMachiavelli.Thepactsthatleaderssignwithoneanother,heargues,aretoberespectedandfulfilledingoodfaith.Thistenetformsthefundamentalmodern-dayinternationallegalprincipleofpactasuntservanda(‘agreementsaretobeobserved’).Grotiusoutlinesatleastthreereasonswhyinternationalpactsshouldbeobeyed.First,theyarelegallyandmorallybinding.Thisprincipleisfirmlyrootedinhisbelief(Prologue15)that“Itisaruleofthelawofnaturetoabidebypacts”(seealsoBookII.16.1).Second,internationalagreementsareestablishedbymutualconsent.Theirvoluntarynaturemakesthemlegitimateandbinding.Third,andperhapsmostinterestingforsubsequentIRtheoriesthatemphasizethe“shadowofthefuture”(e.g.,AxelrodandKeohane1986),complianceisgenerallyinstates’long-terminterest.Indeed,“thestatewhichtransgressesthelawofnatureandofnationscutsawayalsothebulwarkswhichsafeguarditsownfuturepractice”(Prologue18).However,Grotiusdoesattachcertainexceptionstothegoodfaithprinciple,forinstancewhenthecontractisconcludedunderillegitimatecircumstancesorwhentheotherpartyengagesinlarge-scalenoncompliance.

Hobbes’s(1651)premisesonsovereignty,thestateofnature,andmutualcontractshaveimportantimplicationsforhowweunderstandcomplianceandenforcement.Ontheonehand,theadventofthesovereignnation-stateshouldbegoodnewsforinterstaterelations.Inadditiontoescapinga“solitary,poore,nasty,brutishandshort”lifeanddirectingactivitiestowardthecommonbenefit,citizensalsoreceiveprotectionfromotherstateswhentheyturnoverpowertoaSovereign(Hobbes1651XIIII).Thisleadsdirectlytoimportantprinciplesthatunderpinthemodernstate-system,suchassovereigntyandnon-intervention,whichHobbesviewsascriticaltoensuringpeacewithotherstates.Ontheotherhand,someofHobbes’spremisesaredeeplytroublingforIL.“Covenants,withoutthesword,”heclaims,“arebutwordsandofnostrength”(ch.17).“Wherethereisnocommonpower,thereisnolaw”(ch.13).Inthisview,thelackofan‘internationalLeviathan’meansnotonlythatILisineffectual;italsoimpliesthatILisnotreallylawatall.

ThequestionofwhetherILisreallylawremainedatopicofdebateforcenturies.IfweuseanAustiniandefinitionoflaw(Austin1832)–acommandgivenbyaSovereign,

Page 4: Compliance with International Lathe modern legal principle of rebus sic stantibus (‘things thus standing’), whereby treaties may become inapplicable if there is a fundamental change

4

backedbythethreatofsanctions–thenitisclearthatILisnotlaw.Mostnowagreethatsuchadefinitionistoorestrictive.Forinstance,Hart(1961)arguesthatitisnottheexistenceofacentralenforcerthatdistinguishesalegalsystem,butrathertheunionofprimaryrules(definingwhatisandisnotallowed)andsecondaryrules(rulesaboutrules).Ultimately,inhisview,ILis“sufficientlyanalogoustolaw”tobeconsideredassuch(Hart1961:231).Bull(1977)concurs,butforslightlydifferentreasons:internationallawhasthestatusoflawbecausethosewhouseit–nationalandinternationalcourts,diplomats,andpoliticians–believetheseruleshavethestatusoflaw.Morgenthau(1948:255),too,acceptsthatILislaw,stating,“todenythatILexistsatallasasystemofbindinglegalrulesfliesinthefaceofalltheevidence.”

MostscholarsandpractitionersnowagreethatILexistsaslaw.Butthatisnotthesameassayingitiseffective.Mearsheimer(1994-95)arguesthatmostagreementssimplyarticulateidenticalorcomplementaryinterests,andthosethatdonotareunlikelytolast.Fromthisperspective,statesabidebytreatiesbecauseitisintheirimmediateinteresttodoso.Morgenthau(1948)maintainsthatintheabsenceofanoverarchingauthority,sanctionsaredecentralizedandbasedonself-help.Thisisaprimitivelegalsystem–andonethatdiffersradicallyfromdomesticlaw–foritplacestherighttoenforcethelawinthevictim’shands(Morgenthau1948:266).Consequently,enforcementisunevenintwomainrespects:(1)gravetransgressionsmayattractnoresponsewhereasminornoncompliancemaysolicitseveresanctions;and(2)thestrongaremuchmorelikelytoescapereprisals.Enforcement,then,isnotamatterofILbutofnationalinterestandthedistributionofpower.

ManydisagreewiththisperceptionthatILisineffective.Ifstateswoulddothesameanyhow,whybotherwritingagreementsdown?Ifstateshaveidenticalinterests,thedesiredoutcomecanbeachievedwithnocommunicationwhatsoever.Iftheyhavecomplementaryinterests,theycansimplyagreeinformally(Keohane1984).Inneithercaseisaformalarrangementneeded.Surelyinternationalagreementsdomorethansimplyspelloutidenticalorcomplementaryinterests;otherwiseitishardtounderstandwhytheyexist.Moreover,manyargue,skepticsofILoverstatethegapbetweenmunicipalandIL(StatonandMoore2011).Inreality,domesticcontractsoftenrelyonnon-governmentalmechanismsfortheirenforcement,whereasanumberofinternationalrulesareinterpretedifnotenforcedbyinternationalbodies.

Forinstance,reputationalconcerns,ratherthanthethreatofpunishmentfromonhigh,arenodoubtthedrivingforcebehindmanybusinesscontracts.Totakeanotherdomesticexample:ifmurderwerelegalized,wouldmostpeoplebeginmurderingeachother?Itseemsunlikely.Mostrefrainfrommurderingbecausetheyhavenodesiretodoso,believeitunethical,and/orfearreciprocation.AmoreaccurateportrayalofIL,then,wouldthinkoflawasaspectrumofcentralizationratherthanadichotomy(Bull1977).Finally,othersmaintainthatskepticsofILrelyonafar-too-narrowunderstandingofenforcement(Henkin1979;Fisher1981).Ratherthanrestinginthehandsofacentralorganizingbody,thesourcesofenforcementresideelsewhere.Thenextsectionconsidersthesesourcesofenforcement.Thespecificmechanismsarevarious,buttheyareunitedbyafocusonthecostsagovernmentpaysfornotabidingbyitsinternationallegalpromises.

4. ComplianceasaProblemofEnforcement

Page 5: Compliance with International Lathe modern legal principle of rebus sic stantibus (‘things thus standing’), whereby treaties may become inapplicable if there is a fundamental change

5

A. InternationalInducements

Adherencemaybeimportantenoughtoastatethatitiswillingtopaythecostofinducingotherstocomply.Why?Insomecases,itisstrictlyamatterofpublicinterest.InthefamousBananasdispute,forinstance,theUnitedStates(US)andseveralLatinAmericancountrieshadamaterialinterestininducingtheEuropeanUnion(EU)tocomplywithGeneralAgreementonTariffsandTrade(GATT)andWorldTradeOrganization(WTO)provisions(AlterandMeunier2006).Inothercases,leaders–oratleasttheindividuals/groupstowhomtheyareresponding–aremotivatedbymorenormativeconsiderations.

Theanti-apartheideconomicsanctionsregime,forexample,cameaboutbecausecitizensandindividuallegislatorshadamoral/ethicalproblemwiththatsystemofracialsegregationandoppression(Black1999).Whilegovernments’motivationsinusinginternationalinducementsarediverse,theinducementsthemselvesrelyonacost-benefitlogic.(Idiscusscompliancemechanismsthatdonotrelyonrewardsorpunishments,suchas‘namingandshaming,’later).Theseinducementsmightbepositive–tradeconcessions,increasedforeignaid,and/orcooperationinotherissue-areas.Alternatively,theymightincludepunishmentssuchasdevelopmentassistancecuts,economicsanctions,and–rarely–militaryintervention.

Linkageisacommonmeansofinducingcompliance.Someissuesarelinkablebecausetheyaresubstantivelyrelatedandaffecteachother.Butthisneednotbethecase:sanctionslinkage,inparticular,isawaytoapplytheenginesofcompliancefromoneissue-areatoanother,presumablymoreintractable,area(Leebron2002).Hafner-Burton(2005,2009)arguesthatWesternstatescancompelabusivegovernmentstorespecthumanrightsbyexplicitlytyingthesetotradeconcessionsinpreferentialtradeagreements.Evengovernmentsthatareperfectlyhappytoabusetheircitizenscanbe“forcedtobegood”whenthecontinuationoftradeconcessionsdependsontheirrespectforhumanrights.

Issuelinkageisalsoaboutexpandingthesetofpossibleinducementsthatcansustaincompliance,whichtiesdirectlyintoideasof‘issuebarter’(Leebron2002:12-13).(Forsome,thistakesusintotheterritoryofreciprocity,wheregovernmentsmakeconcessionsononefrontinexchangeforconcessionsonanotherfront.Ikeepthesedistinct,suchthatreciprocityistrulyaboutmeetingonebehaviorwiththesamebehavior).Forexample,Poast(2012)notesthatmanymilitaryalliances,almostallofthemasymmetric,includetradeprovisions.Theseenhancecompliancebyincreasingthecostsofreneging:ifthestrongerstatedecidesnottodefenditsally,itwilllosethetradeconcessions.Hefindsnotonlythattradeprovisionsmakestatesmorewillingtorespecttheiralliancecommitments,butalsothatallianceswithtradeprovisionsaremorecredible.Intheenvironmentalarena,TingleyandTomz’s(2014)surveyexperimentfindsthatrespondentssupportissue-linkage:ifanothercountryincreasesitsconsumptionofgreenhousegases,respondentsstronglycondonepubliclyshamingand/orcuttingoftradewiththecountry–particularlyifithadbreachedinternationallaw.Interestingly,respondentsdidnotsupportdirectreciprocity(i.e.,raisingconsumptioninresponsetoanothercountry’sincreasedconsumption),evenwhentheothercountryhadratifiedarelevanttreaty.

Page 6: Compliance with International Lathe modern legal principle of rebus sic stantibus (‘things thus standing’), whereby treaties may become inapplicable if there is a fundamental change

6

Internationalinducementsaretypicallydecentralizedandbasedonself-help,placingtherighttopunish/rewardinthehandsofthe(potential)victimand/orthepowerful.Asaconsequence,applicationcanbeuneven.Gravetransgressionsmayattractnoresponse,whereasminornoncompliancemaybemetwithseveresanctions.Additionally,thestrongaremorelikelytoescapereprisals–andtoadministerthem.Internationalinducements,then,mayhavemuchmoretodowithnationalinterestsandthedistributionofpowerthananythingelse(Morgenthau1948;GoldsmithandPosner2005).(However,seeOhlin2015,whoarguesthatinternationallawcanservetheinterestsoftheweakandthepowerfulalike.)

Yet,smallerstatesandnon-stateactorscanandhavepunishednoncompliers.LebovicandVoeten(2009)findthattheWorldBankreducesaidtocountrieswhenthe(nowdefunct)UNHumanRightsCommissionexplicitlycriticizestheirhumanrightsstandards.Schimmelfennigetal.(2003)combinebothmechanisms(afocusonrewardsandinvolvementofnon-stateactors),examiningEUdemocraticconditionalityandhowitworksas‘reinforcementbyreward.’Coordinationofmultilateraleffortscanbedifficult,however(Martin2000).Keyactorssometimesdisagreeonwhetheritisworthwhiletopunishnoncompliance.Alternatively,punishmentorrewardsmightbeinthecollectiveinterestofall,buteachmemberfacesincentivestofree-ride.Thisoftenresultsinanundersupplyofmultilateralinducementstocomply(Barrett2007).

Moreover,internationalinducementsarenotalwaysrenegotiation-proof.Ifapunishment(orareward)istoocostlytodispense,andtheagreementisnotself-enforcing,partiescannotcrediblycommittoimposingit(Barrett2007).Thisisparticularlyacuteinmultilateralcontexts(Guzman2008:66-68).Thepoliticalcostsofpunishingnoncompliancecanalsomakesanctioningparticularlycostly:coercivesanctionscanleadnontargetedstatestofeelthreatenedandtoquestionthesanctioner’smotives.Internationalorganizationscanhelpmakepunishmentlesscostlybyclarifyingambiguousrules,providingtransparencyandmonitoring,andsupplyinginformationaboutpowerfulstates’intentions(Thompson2009,2013).

B. Reciprocity

Scholarsandpractitionershavelongunderstoodreciprocitytobeanengineofcooperation(Schachter1991).Axelrod(1984)showsthat,evenwhenpartieshaveanimmediateincentivetodefect,tit-for-tatstrategiescaneffectivelypromotecooperationbydirectlylinkinganactor’scurrentbehaviortoitsexpectedfuturepayoffs.Applyingthislogictocompliancespecifically,themechanismisasfollows:ifbothpartiesgainfrommutualcomplianceandwillmatchnoncompliancewithnoncompliance,thethreatofreversiontotheno-agreementstatusquopreventseachpartyfromreneginginthefirstplace(Guzman2008;Ohlin2015).

Manyconditionsmustholdforreciprocitytoensurecompliance.Mostobviously,reciprocalnoncompliancemustharmthepartythatistemptedtorenege.Thisisrarelythecaseforhumanrightsagreements(HRAs),whichtypicallydonotcreatecross-nationalexternalities(Moravcsik1999;Hafner-Burton2005).Forinstance,theSwedishgovernmentmaybeoutragedbythetreatmentofwomeninSaudiArabia,butthreateningtomistreatSwedishwomenwillnotinduceSaudiArabiatoabidebythe

Page 7: Compliance with International Lathe modern legal principle of rebus sic stantibus (‘things thus standing’), whereby treaties may become inapplicable if there is a fundamental change

7

ConventionontheEliminationofDiscriminationAgainstWomen(CEDAW).Incontrast,reciprocityoftensufficesforagreementsaddressingwarconductortrade,sincebadbehaviorcreatescross-nationalexternalities,andretaliationcanbetargeted.Morrow(2007)findsthatmutualratificationofwarconducttreatiesproducesfewerviolationsthroughjointdeterrence(seealsoChilton2015).Tit-for-tatcanbeadouble-edgedsword,however:ifonepartyreneges,compliancebreaksdownquicklybecausereciprocityismoreeffectivewhenbothpartieshaveratified(Morrow2007,2014).

Theshadowofthefuturealsomustbesufficientlylongthatthelong-termbenefitsofmutualcomplianceoutweightheshort-termbenefitsofmutualreneging.Iftheydonot,afeudofreciprocalnoncompliancebeginsandtheshadowofthefuture‘burnsup’(Axelrod1984).AxelrodandKeohane(1986)arguethatwhereasactorshavereasontoanticipatethateconomicrelationswillcontinueforanindefiniteperiodoftime,thepossibilityofpreemptivewarcanmaketheshadowofthefuturelesscertaininsecurityaffairs.

Afinalchallengeforreciprocityasanenforcementmechanismisthatitisnotalwayspossibletolimitthe‘punishment’totheviolator.Thisisacommonprobleminenvironmentalaffairs,particularlywhenmultilateralinnature(Barrett2007).Considergreenhousegasemissions.Thepunishmentofreciprocalnoncompliancecannotbetargetedonlyatstatesthatarebreakingtheircommitments.Consequently,thethreatofincreasedemissionsisnotharmfulenoughtoconvincethetemptedpartytorespectitsobligations(Barrett2007;Guzman2008).Inmostcases,evenaseriesofbilateralaccordswouldnotdothejob.

C. Reputation

Henkin(1979:52)noteddecadesagothat“[e]verynation’sforeignpolicydependssubstantially[…]onmaintainingtheexpectationthatitwillliveuptointernationalmoresandobligations.”Whymightareputationforhonoringlegalcommitmentsmatter?Forsome,theansweristhatstatesinherentlyvalueareputationforrespectingIL–aperspectivethatIdiscusslaterinthisarticle.Forothers,theansweristhatreputationhasrealmaterialconsequences.Areputationforkeepingpromisescanmakeiteasierforgovernmentstosecurecooperationmorebroadly.Incontrast,areputationforunreliabilitymighthindercooperationbecausepromisesappearnon-credible(Keohane1984;Guzman2008;Stiles2015).Reputationisimportantforpredictingfuturebehavior,notforpunishingpastactions(Brewster2009).

Scholarshavefocusedchieflyonhowapoorreputationendangerscooperationinthefutureorinotherissue-areas.Gibler(2008)arguesthatifreputationmatters,itshouldbeeasierforgovernmentsthatabidebytheirpromisestoconcludeagreementsdowntheline.Insupportofthisidea,hefindsthatstatesthathonoralliancecommitmentsaremorelikelytocreatealliancesinthefuture.Simmons(2000)maintainsthatgovernmentscomplywithArticleVIIIoftheInternationalMonetaryFundTreatybecausetheywantmarketactorstoviewthemastrustworthyintheircommitmentstoprotectpropertyrightsinthefuture(seealsoNelson2010).Henceareputationforlaw-governedbehaviorcanbeusefulforreassuringmarketactorsaboutwillingnesstomaintainthesamepoliciesdowntheroad.

Page 8: Compliance with International Lathe modern legal principle of rebus sic stantibus (‘things thus standing’), whereby treaties may become inapplicable if there is a fundamental change

8

Whetherastate’sreputationinoneissue-areaaffectsitsreputationinotherissue-areasseemstobeasubjectofgreaterdebate.TheSwedishgovernmentmaynotinferfromSaudiArabia’sfailuretorespectCEDAWprinciplesthatitisanunreliableWorldTradeOrganizationpartner.Thereason,DownsandJones(2002)argue,isthatthesourcesofcompliancecostsareunrelated.Totheextentthatgovernmentsareableto‘compartmentalize’theirreputations(Fisher1981:130),reputationmaynottravelwellacrossissue-areas.Guzman(2008:100-06)disagrees,arguingthatalthoughstatesnodoubthavemultiplereputations,thelatterareofteninterrelated(ChayesandChayes1995).Noncomplianceinoneareamighttellastate’spartnerssomethingaboutitsattitudestowardthelawmoregenerally.Italsoconveysinformationaboutagovernment’sunderlyingwillingnesstosacrificelong-termforshort-termgains(seealsoOhlin2015).

Anexampleofissue-areareputationallinkagecanbefoundinMoore(2003),whoarguesthatwhenastatebreaksitsHRApromises,investorsbecomemorewaryofinvestingbecausetheyconcludethatthestateisunwillingtorestrainthepresentuseofpowerintheinterestoflong-termbenefits.Theactofbreakingapromiseiskey,andinvolvesactorsmakinginferencesabouttrustworthinessinoneareafrombehaviorinanother.Tomz’s(2008)surveyoffersanovelapproachtogaugingcross-issuereputationalspillovers.Ifpresentedwithastatethatalwayscompliedwithitsinternationaleconomiccommitments,respondentsweresignificantlymorewillingtobelievethatratificationoftheNuclearNon-ProliferationTreaty‘matters’(i.e.,thataratifierwouldbesignificantlylesslikelythananon-ratifiertopursuenuclearweapons).Thislendscredencetotheideathatindividualsdodrawconnectionsbetweencommitmentsinseeminglyunrelatedissue-areas.

Concernsaboutreputation,however,mightnotalwaysweighinfavorofobeyingtreatythelaw.Governmentsmightinsteadwantareputationforbeingtoughorprotectingtheirinterests(Keohane1997;HiroseandPark2013).Iftheseconflict,governmentsmightdecidenottocomply.Inthelate1990s,forinstance,theUSseemedtohavegainedadditionalleveragefromrefusingtofulfillitsfinancialobligationstotheUN,ratherthanlosinginfluenceasaresultofadamagedreputation(Keohane1997).Additionally,leadershipturnovercallsintoquestiontheidea,oratleastnarrowsthescopeoftheargument,thatconcernsaboutreputationdrivecompliance.Statesusuallycontinueintothefuture;governmentschange.AsBrewster(2009,2013)notes,governmentsdonotbearthefullbruntofabadreputationbecausetheirtenureislimited.Particularlywhenthepartyatthehelmchanges,reputationsmayormaynotcarryover.InthecaseofthetreatmentofdetaineesundertheBushadministration,manyinternationalanddomesticaudiencesexpectedtheObamaadministrationtobehavedifferently.Consequently,thereputationalcoststotheUSasawholemayhavebeenrelativelylimited(Brewster2009,2013).

Testingreputationaltheoriesischallenging.Muchoftheevidencehasbeenanecdotaland/orlimitedbyendogeneityproblems.Themeasuresthatscholarshaveusedoftenpickuponsomanyothermechanismsthatitdifficulttosaywithmuchcertaintythatreputationisthecorecausalvariable(Gibler2008;Tomz2008).Recentsurveyexperimentsovercomethosedrawbacks.Forinstance,inarecentstudy,TomzandWeeks(2015)parseoutthetworeputationalmechanisms.Concernsaboutreputationalspilloverintootherissue-areasplayedasignificantroleinmotivatingrespondentstosupportmilitaryintervention,butthedesiretomaintainagoodmilitaryreputationin

Page 9: Compliance with International Lathe modern legal principle of rebus sic stantibus (‘things thus standing’), whereby treaties may become inapplicable if there is a fundamental change

9

futureinteractionshadanevenstrongereffect.Interestingly,thisresearchalsouncoverssomeofthelimitsofreputation.Indeed,thesurveyfoundthatasenseofmoralobligationhadanevenlargerimpactonrespondents’decisiontosupportintervention.Ireturntothisfindinglater.Furthermore,ifthematerialcase(dollars,troops)fornon-interventionissufficientlycompelling,respondentssupportedviolatingtreatyobligationsfairlyreadily(Tomz2008;TomzandWeeks2015).Thechallengeforsurvey-basedresearch,ofcourse,isexternalvalidity.Citizensandleadersseemtocareaboutareputationforcompliance.Buthowdothesepreferencestranslateintopolicyandpractice?

D. DomesticInstitutionsandPolitics

Importantsourcesofenforcementlieinsidethestate.Scholarsgenerallyfocusontherolesofcourts,elections,legislatures,andnon-stateactors(andtheirinterplay).Slaughter(1995)laidmuchofthegroundworkforadialoguebetweenILandIRscholarsondomesticjudicialinstitutionsandcompliancewithIL.IndependentdomesticjudiciariesarethoughttoaidintheenforcementofILbecausethey(1)empowercitizenstochallengegovernment(in)actionlegally;(2)havetheauthoritytoevaluatewhethergovernment(in)actionadherestoexistinglaw;and(3)basetheirrulingsonlegalprinciplesratherthanongovernmentpreference,popularity,citizens’desires/indifference,etc.Adverserulingsrarelyleadtofull/automaticcompliance,buttheymakeitmoredifficultforgovernmentstocontinuereneging(vonStein2015).Inthehumanrightsarena,Simmons(2009)alsopointsoutthateveniflitigationisunsuccessful,itcanempowerpeopletothink,talk,andstruggleoverrightsthatbecomepartofthenationaldialogueandpoliticalchangeinthefuture.

Otherstakeinsightfromtheliteratureonleaderpunishmentandinternationalcooperation/conflict(McGillivrayandSmith2000),arguingthatdemocraticleadershavestrongerincentivestocomplywiththeirinternationallegalobligationsbecausecompetitiveelectionsmakeitrelativelyeasyforcitizensto‘punish’leaderswhorenegeontheirpromises(seealsoSchachter1991).Thereareatleasttworeasonswhypoliticalaccountabilitymightcompelleaderstobevigilant.First,itforcesatighteralignmentofcitizenpreferencesandpolicy(Stiles2015).Settingasideforthemomentthequestionofwhatcitizenswant,politicalaccountabilitycompelsleaderstobemoreconcernedaboutwhethernoncompliancewillcostthemthesupportofcitizenswhobenefitfromtheparticularagreementorfromthestate’sadherencetoILmorebroadly(Trachtman2008).Second,breakingrulescanreflectpoorlyfromavalencestandpoint,motivatingevencitizenswhohavenointerestinILbutareconcernedaboutcompetencemoregenerally(Leeds2003).

Putnam’s(1988)now-canonical‘logicoftwo-levelgames’ignitedavastliteratureonhowlegislativeconstraintsaffectstates’abilitytoconcludeinternationalagreementsandtosustaincooperation(Milner1977;Mansfield,Milner,andRosendorff2000;Martin2000;Davis2012).Legislaturescanfrustratecompliance–bydelayingorrefusingtopassimplementinglegislation,byrefusingtoshiftbudgetaryresources,andsoon(Pollack2003).Theseexpostmechanismsoflegislativecontrolcompelexecutivestotakelegislators’preferencesintoaccountatthenegotiationstage,particularlyforaccordsthatrequireformallegislativeratification.Legislativeinvolvementmakesnegotiationsmorecomplex,butitisalsoanasset,makingtheagreementsreached

Page 10: Compliance with International Lathe modern legal principle of rebus sic stantibus (‘things thus standing’), whereby treaties may become inapplicable if there is a fundamental change

10

throughthisfractiousbargainingprocessmorecredibleandmorelikelytostick(Martin2000).

ThedomesticenforcementofILviacourts,elections,and/orlegislaturesreliesongovernmentactors.Butprivate(‘non-state’)actorsplayaroleinIL’sdomesticenforcementaswell.Ifocushereonsocialmovementsandfirms,settingaside–duetospaceconstraints–thenumerousothernon-stateactorsinvolvedindomesticenforcement.Thereisavastliteratureonhowsocialmovementsandfirmsaffectcompliancewithinternationallaw(c.f.,Sikkink1999;Stiglitz2007;Tsutsuietal.2012;andMuchlinski2014).Whilethesegroupsregularlyexistandoperatetransnationally,Ifocushereonhowtheyhelp(and,later,hinder)toenforceILdomestically.Socialmovementscanplayacrucialroleinprovidinginformationaboutgovernments’legalobligations,inmonitoringcompliance,andinbringingviolationstotheattentionofcitizensandotherinteresteddomesticactors(KeckandSikkink1999;Sikkink1999).Theseactionsarenotenforcementperse,buttheyaidwithenforcement,particularlyincombinationwiththeotherdomesticmechanismsdiscussedinthissection.

Socialmovementsalsoinvolvethemselvesdirectlyinenforcement,forinstancebyprovidinglegalaidtovictimsandbybringingwitnessestocourt;orbylaunchingcampaignsthatcanbecomepoliticallycostlyforleaders(Tsutsuietal.2012).TheGuantánamoBayDetentionsprovideaninterestingexample.DomesticUSactivists,hand-in-handwithDemocraticpoliticians,madethisapoliticallysalientissueinthe2006midtermelections.TheircriticismsincludedtheUS’sinternationallegalobligations.Socialmovementssometimesalsoengagedomesticenforcementbybringinginternationalactorsintothepicture,whichmightopenupapoliticalspacetopushforcompliancethroughdomesticchannels(KeckandSikkink1999;RisseandSikkink1999).

Ataverygenerallevel,wecansaythatfirmsinvolvethemselvesintheenforcementofILwhenitisintheirinteresttodoso,andwhentheyhavethenecessaryknowledgeandresources(c.f.,Davis2012;Muchlinski2014).Someofthemostcommonmechanismsarelobbyingandfilingcomplaintsand/orlawsuits.ReturningtotheBananasdispute,theUSfirmChiquita–whichhadmassiveoperationsinLatinAmericaandwaslosingmillionsofdollarstotheEU’srestrictiveregime–lobbiedUSpoliticiansintenselyandultimatelyfiledasection301petitiontotheUSTradeRepresentative,whichinturnledtoaWTOdispute.AcrosstheAtlantic,bananaimporterschallengedtheEU’sbananaregimeindomesticcourts.ThemostsuccessfulofthesewereinGermany,whereGermanjudgesconsideredwhethertheregimeviolatedtheGermanconstitutionandwhethertheseimportersdeservedcompensation(AlterandMeunier2006).

Whatdoestheempiricalrecordtellusaboutdomesticpolitics/institutionsandcompliance?Thereiscertainlyevidencethatdemocraciesabidebytheirinternationallegalcommitmentsmorethannon-democracies:theyaremorereliablealliancepartners(Leeds2003);theyare,withsomeexceptions,morelikelytocomplywiththecivilrightstreatiestheyhaveratified(Hathaway2002;Neumayer2005);andtheytaketheirobligationsunderthelawsofwarmoreseriously(Morrow2007,2014).Buttherearemanynullornegativefindingsaswell.DemocraciesarenomorelikelytoabidebytheirobligationsunderArticleVIIIoftheIMFTreaty(Simmons2000);theyarelesslikelytointervenetoprotecttheiralliesintimeofwar(GartzkeandGleditsch2004);

Page 11: Compliance with International Lathe modern legal principle of rebus sic stantibus (‘things thus standing’), whereby treaties may become inapplicable if there is a fundamental change

11

andtheyarenomorelikelytorespecttheircommitmentsundertheInternationalCovenantonEconomic,Social,andCulturalRights(ICESCR)(Cole2015b).

Thesemixedfindingscanbeattributedtotwomainfactors.First,untilrecently,quantitatively-orientedscholarsoftenreliedononemeasure–Polityscore–totestargumentsabouttheimpactofcourts,elections,legislativeconstraints,andevensocialmovements.Thismeasurewasoverlybluntandaninadequateoperationalizationofthespecificcausalmechanisms(PowellandStaton2009).Scholarsarenowusingmorenuancedmeasures,withinterestingfindings.ThisimprovementisparticularlyevidentintheliteratureonHRAs.Initially,thegeneralconsensuswasthattheseagreementshadlittlediscernableimpactonhumanrightsoutcomes.Now,weknowthattheireffectsareconditional.Idiscusssomerelevantfindingsonthenextpage.

Asecondreasonwhytheempiricalrecordhasbeensomixedisthatwithfurtherscrutiny,itisevidentthatforeachmechanism,therearemanycontingenciesandevencountervailingpressures.Domesticcourtshavecomplexdoctrinedetailingwhentreatiescanbeinvoked(Dunoffetal.2010).Hencetheymaychoose,orbeobligated,nottoorderotherdomesticactorstofollowinternationalrules.Thismayhelpexplainsomeofthemixedfindings.Therelationshipbetweenelectionsandcompliancedependscruciallyonwhatvoterswantandonwhocarriespoliticalleverageandinformationaladvantages(Dai2006).Indeed,democraticleadersmayfinditmoredifficulttostickbyinternationalpromisesifthosepromisesaredomesticallyunpopular(GartzkeandGleditsch2004).Rickard(2010)alsooffersinterestinginsight,lookingatdemocraciesandfindingthatthosewithmajoritarianelectoralrulesaremorelikelytoviolateGATT/WTOrestrictionsonnarrowtransfers.Althoughlegislative-executiverelationscanenhancethecredibilityofpromises,theycanalsofrustratecompliancebymakingpolicychangemoreonerous(Setear2002).ThisiswhycompliancewithnegativeWTOrulingsishardfortheUSwhenthematterrequiresCongressionalinvolvement,butmucheasierwhenthePresidentcanmakechangesunilaterally(Davey2006).ThisisalsowhyEUmember-stateswithmoredomesticveto-playerstakemuchlongertobringdomesticlegislationintocompliancewithEUlaw(Börzel,etal.2012).

Armedwithbetterdatathatgaugedifferentmechanisms,researchersarebeginningtounderstandbetterunderwhatconditionsdomesticpolitics/institutionscanaidincompliance.Somescholarstakea‘moreisbetter’stance–i.e.,thatratificationmatterswhendomesticinstitutionsaresufficientlyrobust.Forinstance,vonStein(2015)findsthatadherencetoachildlabortreatyleadstonotablechildlaborreductionswhencourtsaresufficientlyindependent,incountrieswithcompetitiveelections,andwhencivilsocietyprotectionsaresufficientlystrong.Lupu(2015)lookstotheInternationalCovenantonCivilandPoliticalRights(ICCPR),andarguesthatratificationgeneratespalpablecivilrightsimprovementswhentherearesufficientdomesticvetoplayerstoplaceconstraintsonwhatexecutivescando.Otherscholarsarguethatratificationmatters‘inthemiddle’–whendomesticinstitutionsarerobustenoughthatcitizenscanusetreatiestodefendthemselves,butnotsorobustthatratificationisredundant(Simmons2009).

Stillothersarguethatdomesticinstitutions/politicstuggovernmentsindifferentdirections.Independentjudiciaries,chargedwithupholdingconstitutionsandprotectingminorityrights,canenhancecompliancewiththeConventionAgainstTorture(CAT)bymakingitcostlierforleaderstoallow/engageintorture(Conradand

Page 12: Compliance with International Lathe modern legal principle of rebus sic stantibus (‘things thus standing’), whereby treaties may become inapplicable if there is a fundamental change

12

HenckenRitter2013;Conrad2014;Conradetal.2015).Butanother‘democraticinstitution’–contestedelections–canhavetheoppositeimpact,incentivizingleaderstoabuseweaklyenfranchisedindividualswhoareviewedasthreatsto‘order’(Conradetal.2015).Theseconflictingincentivesaffectgovernmentdecisionsatvariousstages:when/whethertoratify,when/whethertotorture,andwhattypeoftorturetoengagein.

5. ComplianceasaProblemofCapacity/Management

Statesareundernolegalobligationtojointreaties;hencetheyareboundonlytotreatiestowhichtheyconsent.ThisisoneofthemostfundamentalprinciplesofIL.Theimplicationisthatgovernmentstypicallyonlytakeoninternationallegalobligationsthatareintheirinterest(ChayesandChayes1995).Thisidearesonateswellwiththe‘enforcement’lineofthinking,discussedabove.Here,however,iswherethedivergencesbegin,firstaboutthe‘baseline’ofstateincentives.Scholarswhoseenoncomplianceasaproblemofenforcementtypicallyassumethat,intheabsenceofconstraints,governmentswillcheat.ThestartingpointforscholarslikeChayesandChayes–sometimescalled‘managerialists’–isquitetheopposite:governmentshaveageneralpropensitytokeeptheirinternationalpromises.Indeed,thecarestatestakewhennegotiatingandenteringintoagreementsisevidencethattheyhaveastrongunderlyingsenseofobligationtocomply.Inacontextoflimitedresources,itisoftenmoreefficienttofollowanestablishedruleratherthanconstantlyrecalculatingthecostsandbenefitsof(non)compliance.

Fromthisperspective,breachesoftreatyobligationsarerarelywillfulandcalculatedacts(RaustialaandVictor1998).Instead,theyarelargelyinadvertent(Cole2015a),resultingfrominadequateplanning,agreementambiguities,capacitylimitations,and/orsignificantchangesovertime.Inthiscontext,itisnotdifficulttounderstandwhyscholarsinthistraditionareskepticalofmechanismsthatdriveupthecostsofnoncompliance.Punitivesanctionsaredifficulttomobilizeandthereforeonlypracticallyavailableinspecialcircumstances(Young1994;ChayesandChayes1995).Insupportofthisidea,ChayesandChayes(1995)notethatevenwhenviolationsareunambiguous,retaliationisrare.Evenwhensanctionsaremobilized,theyareofteninefficientandsometimesmakemattersworse(Young1994;ChayesandChayes1995).Reprisalcanbeparticularlyproblematicwhenviolationsresultfromcapacityproblems,fortheysimplyexacerbatetheconditionsthatledtononcompliance.

Fromthisviewpoint,thebetterpathtocomplianceliesinmoretransparentagreementdesign,disputeresolution,andtechnicalandfinancialassistance(ChayesandChayes1991,1995;Young1994;BrownWeissandJacobson1998).Insupportofthisconclusion,ChayesandChayes(1991)findthatagreementsrarelyprovideforformalpunitivesanctions.Moreover,whenagreementsdoincludedisputeresolutionprovisions,thesefocusmoreonnegotiationthanonwhattodowhencooperationbreaksdownentirely.Thetreatiestheexamineemphasizetechnologytransferandtechnicalassistance(theMontrealProtocolisagoodexample)andtypicallydonotconditiontheseoncompliance.

Mitchell’s(1994)studyofintentionaloilpollutionatseaoffersaninterestingcomparisonoftwoverydifferentcompliancesystems.Onerequiredtankerownerstoinstallexpensiveequipment.Theotherestablishedpollutionlimits.Thefirstsystem

Page 13: Compliance with International Lathe modern legal principle of rebus sic stantibus (‘things thus standing’), whereby treaties may become inapplicable if there is a fundamental change

13

madeviolationsmoretransparentinavarietyofways,whichultimatelyledtomuchhighercomplianceratesthandidthesecondregime.Althoughmanagerialistshaveoftenbeencriticalofeffortstopunishnoncompliance,Mitchell(1994)emphasizesthatequipmentstandards,byimprovingtransparency,canmakemonitoringandsanctioningmoreefficient.Thisresonateswithenforcement-basedapproaches(AbbottandSnidal2000).

Oftheauthorsdiscussedhere,Haas(1989)reliesperhapsmostheavilyonmanagerialandnorm-drivenarguments.EpistemiccommunitiesofecologistsandmarinescientistsinvolvedintheMediterraneanActionPlanprovidedcrucialtechnicalexpertise,buttheywerefarmoreconcernedwithenablingpartiestofollowtherulesthantheywerewithdesigningstringentpunishmentmechanisms.Inaddition,thesegroupscontributedtotheregime’ssuccessbyhelpingtodefinethetermsofthedebateandbyarticulatingapersuasiveargumentabouttheneedtotakeaction.

Fewwouldquestionwhethercapacitymattersforcompliance.Thatsaid,itisprobablynocoincidencethatthisapproachgetsthemosttractioninareaswherescientificand/ortechnicalexpertisearecrucial,suchastheenvironment.Inotherrealms,itislessevidentthatcapacity/managementgiveusasmuchpurchase.Itisnothardtofindexampleswheregovernmentswillfullydecidetoflouttheirinternationallegalobligations,havingcarefullyconsideredthecostsandbenefits.(And–perhapsmoredifficultbecausethesearethe‘dogsthatdidn’tbark’–countriesregularlydebatetheprosandconsoffollowingrules,andcomply.)Intradeaffairs,theUS’s2002steeltariffsarebutoneexample.Inthehumanrightsarena,examplesabound:governmentsinmanypartsoftheworldoperateexpensive,intricate,repressiveapparatusesincontraventionoftheirinternationalhumanrightsobligations.Managementorexpertisecannotsolvewillfulnoncompliance.Changingtheleader’scost–benefitcalculus–whetherwithcarrotsorsticks–hasbeenfoundtoworkinsomecases(Hafner-Burton2005;Simmons2009;ConradandRitter2013).

Treatycompliancedebatesinitiallytendedtoviewenforcementandcapacity-basedexplanationsascompeting,andevenconflicting,mechanisms(ChayesandChayes1995;Downsetal.1996).Morerecently,scholarshavetakenamorepragmaticapproach,emphasizingthatenforcementandcapacitycanaffectcompliancesimultaneously;theymayinfactbemutuallyreinforcing(Tallberg2002;Urpelainen2010;Thompson2012).TheEU’scompliancesystem,forinstance,reliesonmechanismsthatimprovecapacityandonmechanismsthatdetectand,whennecessary,‘punish’violations(Montoya2008;Börzeletal.2012).Eveninthehumanrightsarena–arealminwhichnoncomplianceoftenresultsfromwillfuldisobediencebyactorswhochoosetobreakinternationalrules(Hafner-Burton2005)–severalrecentstudiesshowthatcompliancefailuresalsoresultfrombasicstructuralchallengessuchaslimitedbureaucratic/financialcapacitytotranslatetreatycommitmentsintopractice(Sanchez2009;Cole2015a,2015b;vonStein2015).Cole(2015a),forinstance,findsthatbureaucraticallystrongstatesaresignificantlybetterabletoimplementtheircivilandpoliticalrightsdutiesasdelineatedintheICCPR.InotherworkontheICESCR(2015b),hefindsthatratificationhasitsstrongestimpactsindevelopedcountries,whichheargueshavethestrongestcapacitytoimplementthosetreatyobligations.

Anothercritiqueofthecapacity/managementapproachtotreatycompliancecomesfromDownsetal.(1996),whoarguethatthereareseriousinferenceproblems.

Page 14: Compliance with International Lathe modern legal principle of rebus sic stantibus (‘things thus standing’), whereby treaties may become inapplicable if there is a fundamental change

14

Capacity/management-focusedscholarsviewtherelativelygoodcomplianceandtherarityofpenalizinginstitutionsasgoodnewsforcooperation.Downsetal.(1996)arguethattheseobservationsinsteadindicatethatstatesareavoidingdeepcooperationbecausetheycannotdevelopthepunishmentmechanismsnecessarytosustainit.Themanagerialschool’sfindingsmaysimplytellusthatstatesareonlycommittingtoagreementsthatrequireminordeparturesfromwhattheywouldhavedoneintheabsenceofanagreement.Ireturntothisquestionlaterinthechapter.

6. ComplianceasaFunctionofIdentity,SocialContext,andLegitimacy

Scholarswhoemphasizeenforcementorcapacity/managementasdriversof(non)compliancerelychieflyoninstrumentalist,cost-benefit,logics.Thisisnottheonlywaytoapproachcompliance.Otherscholarsarguethatthisprovidesamyopicviewofgovernmentdecision-making.Leadersarealsoaffectedbytheiridentity(ies)andsocialcontext,aswellastheirperceptionsofagreements’legitimacy.Theseaffectcomplianceincomplexways,oftenoverlookedbystrictcost-benefitapproaches.

A. IdentityandSocialContext

Constructivistsemphasizethecomplexwaysinwhichnormsandidentityreshapeand/orcarrygreaterweightthandocost-benefitconsiderations(Jeppersonetal.1996;Koh1997).Akeyconcepthereisinternalization:thepointatwhichanormissodeeplyingrainedthatithasa‘takenforgranted’character(FinnemoreandSikkink1998).Thisistheendstageofmanyaccounts,butthemechanismsthatmotivatethisprocessaremany.Somearedubiousofthiscausalwayoflookingatthings(KratochwilandRuggie1966).Ireturntothisquestionlater.

Koh(1997,1998)emphasizestransnationallegalprocesses.Thistypicallystartswithaninternationalactor,A,incitinganinteractionwithanotheractor,B,inaninternationallegalforum.Thisforcesaninterpretationoftheglobalnorm(whichmayormaynotbecodifiedinaninternationalagreement)thatstructuresthesituation.Importantly,thetransactioncreates(oractivates,iftherulealreadyexists)alegalrulethatguidessubsequentrelationsbetweenAandB.Overtime,thisprocessreshapesB’sinterestandidentities,leadingittointernalizethenormsindomesticlaw,policy,andsocialpractice.Atthispoint,B‘obeys’thelaw–anactthatcarriesgreatersignificancethancompliancebecauseitresultsfromB’ssenseofobligation(Koh1997,1998).

ConstructivistIRscholarsoftenfocusonsocialization,aprocessbywhichbeliefsaboutrightandwrongbecomenorms(FinnemoreandSikkink1998),whichinturnreshapeinterests,identities,andbehavior(RisseandSikkink1999).(Isetasidethequestionofhowprincipledbeliefsbecomenorms,asitdoesnotpertaindirectlytocomplianceandinternalization).Theculminationisinternalizationofthenorm,buthowdostatesgetthere?Scholarsfocusonthreecoremechanisms:materialinducement,persuasion,andsocialization(Koh2005).Idiscussedthefirstoftheseearlier.Iexplorethelattertwoprocessesbelow.

Persuasionisaboutchangingmindsandattitudesintheabsenceofovertcoercion(Johnston2001:496).Pro-compliancegroupsenhancetheirpersuasiveappealbyframingissuessotheyresonatewithacceptednormsand/orarousestrongfeelings(KeckandSikkink1998).Argumentationisimportant.Forinstance,Finnemoreand

Page 15: Compliance with International Lathe modern legal principle of rebus sic stantibus (‘things thus standing’), whereby treaties may become inapplicable if there is a fundamental change

15

Sikkink(1998)andRisseandSikkink(1999,2013)notethatgovernmentsoftenratifyHRAsevenwhentheydonotgenuinelyintendtocomply.Butoncetacticalconcessionssuchastheseareinplace,the‘logicofarguing’takesover.Governmentsmakeargumentativeconcessionsandofferjustifications.Domesticoppositiongroupsandotheradvocacynetworkstaketheseseriouslyandattemptanearnestdialogueabouthowtocurtailabuses.Continueddialogueandinstitutionalreformoftenleadtocomplianceand,eventually,norminternalization.Thomas(2001),forinstance,arguesthatEasternbloccountriesratifiedtheHelsinkiFinalActbecausetheywantedtogainlegitimacy,expectingthattheywouldneverhavetomakegoodonthosepromises.Butratificationhadunintendedconsequences.Therepeatedappealsto,andmobilizationaround,thesenormsarecreditedwithhelpingtoundermineSovietrule,therebypavingthepathfordemocratictransition.

Successfulpersuasionresultsincomplianceandinternalization.Successfulsocialinfluence,incontrast,oftenresultsincompliancewithoutinternalization(Johnston2001).Whymightgovernmentsconformtorulespubliclyeventhoughtheydonot(necessarily)accepttheirdesirabilityprivately?Governmentscare(tovaryingdegrees)abouttheperceptionsoftheircitizens,advocacynetworks,andotherstates.Here,FinnemoreandSikkink(1998)emphasizethreemotivations.First,governmentswanttolooklegitimateintheeyesofpeers,whichalsoaffectstheirdomesticlegitimacy.Second,governmentstypicallywantto‘belong’tosomedesirablereferencegroup.Finally,leaderswanttomaximizenational(andpersonal)esteem;theywantotherstolikethem,andtheywanttofeelgoodaboutthemselves.Thethreatofsocialpunishments–exclusion,shaming,dissonancefromtakingactionsinconsistentwithaparticularidentity–alsolooms(Johnston2001).Internationalconferencesplayaroleintheseprocessesbyimpartingnewinformationanddiffusingnewnorms.

‘Acculturation’–adoptingthebehaviorsofareferencegroup–isonemechanismofsocialinfluence(GoodmanandJinks2004,2008,2013).Ascomparedtotheliteratureinthepreviousparagraph,acculturationplacessomewhatgreateremphasisonthedisconnectthatcanemergebetweenpracticesandbeliefs.Inanacculturationmodel,themimickingstatemaynotviewthereferencegroup’sruleaslegitimate.Rather,itsimplyneedsto(1)carehowitisperceived;and(2)understandthatthereferencegroupvaluestherule.Hence,itisthesocialstructure–ratherthanrulecontent–thatdrivescompliance.ThisresonateswiththeWorldSocietyliteratureon‘decoupling,’whichnotesthattheactoftreatyratificationisoftendivorcedfromtherelevantpractice(Hafner-BurtonandTsutsui2005,2007).However,GoodmanandJinks(2013)emphasizethatdecouplingisnotalwaysabadthing;itfact,theyargue,itcansometimesfacilitatecompliance,byopeningupdomesticpoliticalopportunities,exposinghypocrisymoreclearlytoforeignanddomesticaudiences,andcreatingopportunitiesforstatestolearn(GoodmanandJinks2005,2013).

Criticsoftheliteratureonidentityandsocialpressureraiseseveralobjections.Someoftheliteraturediscussedabovemapsattributesofindividuals–discomfort,esteem,adesiretoconform–ontogovernments,whichisanuncomfortablefit.Statesdonothavefeelings.Leadersdo,butthisbegsmorequestions.Howcanweknowwhatleadersfeel?Howdoleaders’feelingstranslateintopolicy?Moreover,muchofthisliteraturefocuseson‘successful’cases.Weknowlessaboutpartiallysuccessfulorunsuccessfuloutcomes,althoughthisischanging(C.f.Carpenter2007;andseveralchaptersinRisseetal.2013).Finally,althoughmuchofthisresearchhasmadegreatereffortstospecifyunderwhat

Page 16: Compliance with International Lathe modern legal principle of rebus sic stantibus (‘things thus standing’), whereby treaties may become inapplicable if there is a fundamental change

16

conditionsnormsandidentitymatter,itisstillchallengingtovalidateempirically(Keohane1997).Themovetowardindividual-levelanalysisinrecentquantitativeassessmentsoftreatycompliance,discussedlaterinthisarticle,hasgivenussometractiononsomeofthesequestions,whileleavingothersunanswered.

B. LegitimacyandFairness

Othersarguethatlegitimacyandfairnessarekeytounderstandingcompliance.ForFranck(1990),aruleislegitimatewhentheindividualsitaddressesbelieveithascomeintoexistenceandisappliedwithrightprocess.Thiscomprisesfourelements.First,thelawclearlycommunicateswhichbehaviorsarepermittedandwhicharenot.Second,therulecommunicatesauthorityviasymbolicritualsorotherformalities.Third,thelawrelatestootherrulesinthesysteminaprincipledmanner;likecasesreceivethesametreatment.Fourth,theruleisnotmadeinanadhocfashion,butratherthroughproceduresthatanorganizedcommunityaccepts(Franck1990).Whenalawfulfillsthesecriteria,itexertsa‘compliancepull’independentofthematerialconditionsthataffectstatepractice.

Criticschargethatinholdinglegitimacy,ratherthanjustice,asthechiefgoal,Franck(1990)favorsproceduralregularityandadherencetoruleseveniftheyareimmoralorunjust(Tesón1992).Franck’s(1995)subsequentworkisinpartanefforttoaddressthisquestion(Koh1997).Arule’sfairness,heargues,dependsontwoelements.First,thesubstantivecomponent:aruleisfairifitmeetsparties’expectationsofjustifiablecostsandbenefits.Second,theproceduralcomponent:legitimacy(asdefinedabove)isanimportantelementoffairness,althoughitaloneisinsufficient.Theseelementsareoftenintension,but“fairnessistherubricunderwhichthistensionisdiscursivelymanaged”(Franck1995:7).Here,Franckemphasizesdiscourse,reasoning,andrenegotiation–practicesthatarereminiscentofthoseintheconstructivistresearchdiscussedearlier.However,Franckplacesgreateremphasisonprocessthanonpersuasion:theback-and-forthinvolvedindiscussionanddebateleadsustofairerrulesanddecisions,whichinturnelicitbettercompliance.

Theseargumentsaboutlegitimacyandfairness,andtheirrelationtocompliance,leaveseveralquestionsopen.Legitimacyisdifficulttogaugeindependentlyofthecomplianceitismeanttoexplain(Bodansky2013).Arule’s‘compliancepull’isitsindexoflegitimacy(Franck1990),butlegitimacyalsoexplains‘compliancepull,’makingthereasoningcircular(Keohane1997).Moreover,therearequestionsaboutwhyandhowthediscursiveprocessthatunderliesthefairnessmechanismmakesrulesmoreobligatory(Koh1997).Moreover,Franck’sargumentsbegthequestion:iflegitimacyandfairnessleadtocompliance,whydogovernmentsnotalwayscreate‘legitimate’and‘fair’agreements?

Empiricaltestingofargumentsaboutlegitimacyandfairnesshasprovendifficultinthepast.However,scholarshavemadesomeprogressonthisquestioninrecentyears,thankstorecentdevelopmentsinvolvingsurveyexperiments.Inarecentsurvey,BechtelandScheve(2013)findthatrespondentsaresignificantlymoresupportiveofa‘polluterpays’agreementascomparedtooneinwhichonlyrichcountriespayforemissionsreductions.Theirinterpretationisthattheformerarrangementisfairer.Iffutureresearch,itwouldbeinterestingtoexplorethisquestionfurther,focusingmore

Page 17: Compliance with International Lathe modern legal principle of rebus sic stantibus (‘things thus standing’), whereby treaties may become inapplicable if there is a fundamental change

17

specificallyoncompliance(ratherthaninstitutionaldesign,BechtelandScheve’semphasis),perhapsacrossvariousissue-areas.

7. AdditionalQuestions:SomeOld,SomeNew

A. DefinitionsofCompliance

Followingmuchoftheliterature,Ihaveusedaparticulardefinitionofcompliance:conformitytorules.Thisapproachfacesatleasttwocriticisms.OnecomesfromKingsbury(1998),whoarguesthattheconceptofcompliancedependsonone’stheoryoflaw.Mydefinitionisappropriateifweperceivelawasrulesintendedtoregulatebehavior.Butifwehaveaprocess-basedtheory,whichseeslawassomethingthatcreatesandshapesidentitiesandsocialrelations,thisdefinitiondoesnotwork.Attitudinalalignmentbecomesacoreconcern.Fromthisperspective,wecannotcomprehendhowILworkswithoutunderstandinghowitmoldsidentities(BrunéeandToope2010).Instead,weshouldbeexploringwhatreallymakesIL‘matter’:intentandinternalmotivation(HowseandTeitel2010).Becauserulesarebothregulativeandconstitutive,itisimpossibletoseparatethemfrombehaviorortomakecausalstatementsaboutthetwo(KratochwilandRuggie1986).SeealsoAgon2016foradiscussionofhowinstitutionalgoals,includingcomplianceobjectives,shiftovertimeanddependonthediscursivepracticesofinvolvedactors.

Asecondcritiquesuggeststhatafocusoncomplianceisitselfmisguided.Infixatingtheirattentiononconformitytorules,scholarshavemistakenlyascribedstatebehaviortoinstitutionalparticipation.Theyhavealsounderestimatedtheimpactofinstitutionsonstatesthat,despitemakingimprovements,arenotcompliant.Instead,weshouldbeinterestedineffectiveness(theextenttowhichatreatysolvestheproblemthatledtoitsformation)andimplementation(effortstoadministerpolicydirectives)(Young1994;BrownWeissandJacobson1998;Martin2013).Thiscritiquehastwomainimplications.First,weneedtothinkinamoreconsideredfashionaboutcounterfactuals,whichalsoinvolvescarefulinvestigationofwhatthetreatyisintendedtoaccomplish.Second,scholarsrelyingonquantitativemethodsneedtothinkmorethoroughlyabouttheirdependentvariable.

Theseareimportantpoints,buttheproblemmaynotbeasgraveasMartin(2013)suggests.Onthetheoreticalside,muchoftheliterature,whileusingthelanguageofcompliance,isinterestedineffects.Thisislargelyaproblemofvocabularyratherthantheory.Ontheempiricalside,weshouldcertainlyconsideralternatewaysofmeasuringtheoutcomeofinterest.Considerahypotheticaltreatyrequiringequalrepresentationofwomeninlegislatures.Astandardapproachwouldsimplymeasurethepercentageofparliamentarianswhoarewomen.Butthatisnottheonlywaytoevaluatetreatyeffects.Onemightarguethatsuchanapproachmissesimportantimprovementsincountrieswithhistoricallylowwomen’srepresentation.Accordingly,onemightinsteadmeasurechange,inrelationtosomebaseyearorthepreviousyear.Alternatively,onemightfocusonlegislationintendedtoimprovewomen’srepresentationinparliament.Alloftheaboveareviablemeasurements.Importantly,theyallcomebacktothebasicquestionofconformitytorules.Compliance,farfrombeingorthogonaltounderstandingcausaleffects,isanimportantcomponentofmeasureswemightdevelop.

B. EndogeneityandSelection

Page 18: Compliance with International Lathe modern legal principle of rebus sic stantibus (‘things thus standing’), whereby treaties may become inapplicable if there is a fundamental change

18

Asdiscussedabove,scholarslikeDownsetal.(1996)arguethatcompliancedoesnot,byitself,demonstratethatILimposesmeaningfulrestraintsongovernmentpractice.Statesmaysimplybecreatingandjoiningagreementsthatrequireminordeparturesfromwhattheywouldhavedoneintheabsenceofanagreement.ThishasimportantimplicationsforhowwestudyIL’simpactonstatebehavior.Anytheoryofcompliancemustrecognizethatinstitutionaldesign,and/orthedecisiontoratify,isatleastinpartendogenous:statesareonlylikelytoinvesttimeandresourcesinagreementswithwhichtheyhavesomeinterestincomplying.Answeringthe‘whydostatescomply?’questionrequiresthatwealsounderstandwhystatesjoininthefirstplace(Downsetal1996;vonStein2005).

Mostscholarsnowagreewiththeabovepointsandrecognizetheneedformoresophisticatedstatisticalmodelingthatcontrolsforendogeneity/selectioneffects.Here,however,thereissignificantdisagreement.SomestudiesrelyonHeckman-styleapproaches(vonStein2005;MitchellandHensel2007;ConradandRitter2013).Othersemployinstrumentalvariable(s)(Simmons2009;Cole2015a,2015b;vonStein2015)orbivariateprobitmodeling(PowellandStaton2009;Conrad2014).Stillothersusematchingtechniques(SimmonsandHopkins2005;Hill2010;SpilkeandBöhmelt2013),sometimescombinedwithothermethods(Lupu2013,2015;Fariss2015).Ideally,theorywouldtelluswhichstatisticalapproachismostappropriate,analysisofthedatawouldprovideclues,andresultswouldnotvarysubstantiallydependingonthetechniqueemployed.Thisseemstobetheexceptionratherthantherule.

Therearemanycritiquesandquestionstoraisehere.OneimportantquestionforscholarslikeDownsetal.(1996)isthis:iftreatiessimplyembodyoutcomesinwhichstateswerealreadygoingtoengage,whyevenbothertocreateorratifytreaties?Imaginingforamomentthatthisextremeversionistrueforallstatesallthetime,treatiesstillfulfillimportantpurposes.Simplyhavingacleardefinitionofwhatconstitutes(non)compliancecanbeuseful(Morrow2002;2014).Thisisparticularlytrueinhighlytechnicalareas,wheremuchofthebattleliesinarticulatingacommonstandardandensuringthatallpartiesunderstandit(Urpelainen2010).Moreover,treatiescanserveanimportant‘screening’function,separatingstatesthatarewillingtoupholdthestandardfromthosethatarenot(Morrow2002).Asgametheoristshavelongunderstood,screeningcanrelyonexanteand/orexpostcosts.Theideabehindscreeningviaexantecostsisstraightforward.Iftheprocessofbeingapartyisonerous,orifmembershipisonlyavailabletostatesthathaveconvincinglydemonstratedtheirabilitytomeettheagreement’sterms,thenratificationisusefulbecauseitconveysinformationabout‘type’tootheractors(domesticgroups,markets,otherstates…).TheEU’sstringentaccessionprocessreliesinpartonsuchamechanism,combinedwithmanagerial-typemechanismssuchaspre-accessionassistance(Tallberg2002).

Ofcourse,toarguethattheendogenousnatureoftreatyratificationisaproblemforinferenceisnotthesameassayingthattreatiesnevermatter.Governmentstypicallyfacemultipleincentiveswhentheyconsiderjoininganinternationalagreement:ontheonehandtheymightbeconcernedabouttheirabilitytocomply,butontheotherhandtheymightfacestrongdomesticorpeerpressuretoratify(WotipkaandTsutsui2008).Hence,evenundercompleteinformation,governmentsmightfindthemselvespartiestotreatiesthatarechallengingtocomplywith(vonStein2015).Nordoesthecompleteinformationscenarioalwayshold.Indeed,governmentsare,toatleastsomedegree,behindaveilofignorancewhentheynegotiateandratifytreaties(Keohane1997).

Page 19: Compliance with International Lathe modern legal principle of rebus sic stantibus (‘things thus standing’), whereby treaties may become inapplicable if there is a fundamental change

19

Governmentscanhedgeagainsttheseuncertaintiesviaescapeclausesandotherflexibilityprovisions(KucikandReinhardt2008;Helfer2012),butnotalltreatiescontaintheseprovisions.

Ifgovernmentsratifyandconditionsthenchange,makingcompliancemoredifficult,howdotheybehave?(Ofcourse,clausularebussicstantibuswasdesignedforsituationsinwhichconditionschangeandmakecompliancedifficult.Asdiscussedearlier,thisclausecanonlybereasonablyinvokedinlimitedcircumstances).Surprisingly,therehasbeenlittlesystematicinquiryspecificallyintothisquestion.OneexceptionisGriecoetal.(2009),whoexplorewhathappenswhenapoliticalpartywithanti-compliancepreferences‘inherits’atreatyratifiedbyapro-compliancegovernment.TheyfindthatpartisanshiftstotheleftleadtomorecurrentaccountrestrictionsandhencenoncompliancewithArticleVIIIoftheIMFTreaty.Nonetheless,beinglegallycommitteddoesappeartoimposesomeconstraint:facedwithashifttotheleft,signatoriesengageinfewerrestrictionsthandononsignatories.Similarly,vonStein(2015)positsthatcertainHRAscanbeexpectedtohavetheirstrongesteffectsincountriesthatratifyasnon-democraciesbutlatertransitiontodemocracy.

BacciniandUrpelainen(2014)makeaninterestingcorollarypoint,whichisthattreatiesmaystill‘matter’evenifweobservenodifferencebetweenpre-andpost-ratificationbehavior.Thereasonissimple:governmentsoftenbeginbringingpoliciesintoconformitywithrulesinthepost-negotiationphase,inthelead-uptoratification.‘Phase-ins’areusefulforreassuringcooperationpartners,anditisofteneasiertoadjustpoliciesincrementallyratherthanallatonceonthedayofratification.Insupportofthisargument,theyfindthatdevelopingcountriesbringtheirenvironmentalpracticesintocomplianceinthelead-uptoratificationofpreferentialtradeagreements.Thisisanimportantfinding,butitisunclearhowbroadlyitapplies.Foragreementsthatdonotinvolveexplicitissue-linkageortheneedtoreassurecooperationpartners,theoutcomesmightlookdifferent.

Awareoftheproblemsofselectionandendogeneitythatoftenplagueobservationaldata,severalscholarsarenowusingsurveyexperimentstogaugetheimpactofinternationallaw(ChiltonandTingley2013).Whilethisareaofresearchisstillbudding,wecanstillmakeafewobservationsaboutit.First,thesestudiesarevirtuallyunanimousinfindingthatinternationallaw‘matters.’Respondentsaresignificantlymorewillingtoopposeabehaviorifitviolatesinternationallaw,beittorturingcitizens(Wallace2013),emittinggreenhousegases(TomzandTingley2014),erectingtradebarriers(Tomz2008;Chaudoin2014),engagingindeadlybombingcampaigns(Chilton2015),orinterveninginmilitaryconflicts(TomzandWeeks2015).Second,theeffectofpoliticalideologyismixed.Forinstance,Wallace(2013)examinessupportfortheuseoftorture,andfindsthatILhasitsstrongestimpactonmoderatesandliberals,andpossiblynoeffectonheavyconservatives.Incontrast,Chilton(2015)exploressupportforbombingcampaignsthatcauseexcessiveciviliancasualties,andfindsthatILhasmuchlargerimpactsonRepublicansthanonDemocrats.Tomz(2008)looksatsupportforseveringtradewithBurma/Myanmar,andfindsthatDemocratsandRepublicansalikearesensitivetointernationallegalarguments.

Third,institutionaldesignhasmixedimpactsoncompliancepreferences.Acoredebateintheliteratureiswhetherbindinglaw(e.g.,aratifiedagreement)ismorepowerfulthannon-bindinglaw(e.g.,adeclaration).Hafner-Burtonetal.(2016)surveyNGO

Page 20: Compliance with International Lathe modern legal principle of rebus sic stantibus (‘things thus standing’), whereby treaties may become inapplicable if there is a fundamental change

20

professionalsintheenvironmentalandhumanrightsarenas.Acrosstheboard,thesegroupsbelievethatinternationalagreementsareusefulforinducinggovernmentstocomply.However,thetwogroupsdivergeonthequestionoflegalform.Humanrightsactivistsviewbindingandnon-bindinglawasequallyuseful.Incontrast,environmentalistspreferbindingaccords.Wallace(2013)surveysasampleofthegeneralpopulationandfindsnoevidencethatrespondents’willingnesstocondonetheuseoftorturedependsontheanti-tortureconvention’sdegreeofbindingness.Interestingly,respondentsaremuchlesssupportiveoftheuseoftortureiftheagreementwasverypreciseand/ordelegatedauthoritytoaninternationalinstitution.

Finally,internationallawcompeteswithotherfactorsthatdrivecompliance.Themostobviousoftheseisinterests.Tomz’s(2008)respondents,forexample,weremuchmorewillingtobreakinternationallawbyseveringtradewithiftoldthatsuchanactionwouldhelptheUSeconomy.Similarly,TomzandWeeks’s(2015)respondentsweresubstantiallylesssupportiveofinterventiononbehalfofanallyinhigh-costsituations.Interestingly,moralityisalsoanimportantengineofcomplianceinIR/ILsurveyexperiments.TomzandWeeks(2015:12)reportthatrespondents’senseofmoralobligationhasthestrongestimpactonwillingnesstoabidebyalliancecommitments–evenstrongerthanreputation.Hafner-Burtonetal.’s(2015)findingthatelitesarewaryofmakingfalsepromiseseveniftheyareunenforceableopensupthepossibilitythatleadersareconcernedaboutthemoralimplicationsofreneging,althougha‘shadowofthefuture’explanationisalsopossible.

C. Quantification

Empirically,weknowagreatdealmoreaboutcompliancethanwedidjustadecadeorsoago.Throughoutthisprocess,researchershavemadechoicesaboutwhichquestionsandresearchtoolstoprivilege.Oneexampleofthisisthe‘quantification’ofthestudyofIL,atrendthatisevidentthroughoutthisarticle.Thismovehasbeenbeneficialinavarietyofways.Theabilitytocomparecountriesovertimehasmadeitpossibletomovebeyondtheidiosyncrasiesofaparticularcountryortime-periodtomakegeneralizableassessmentsofhowILworks.Insomecases,datahaveallowedcomparisonsacrossagreementsandissueareas,ataskthatisdifficultinacasestudy.Cutting-edgestatisticaltechniqueshavemadeitpossibletograpplewithchallengingquestionsofendogeneity.Therecentinjectionofsurveyexperimentsintoourtoolkithasenabledscholarstosidesteptheendogeneityproblem,bringingfreshinsightintohowinternationallawworks.

Atthesametime,thequantificationofthestudyofILhasitsperils.Wegaintheabilitytomakegeneralstatements,butlosetherichnessofunderstandingonegetsfromhoninginononecountryorafewcases.Existingmeasuresareoftenunabletodistinguishbetweendifferentmechanisms.Afinaldrawbackofquantitativeresearchisthatdebatesometimescomestofocusonmethodratherthansubstance.Tosomeextent,thisisunderstandable:masteryofthemethodsometimesrequiressophisticatedtechnicaldebate.Nonetheless,itbecomesproblematiciftheresultisadecouplingofmethodologicalandsubstantivediscussions,orifscholarswhousedifferentmethodologiesstoptalkingtoeachother–and/ortothepolicycommunity.

Insightfromqualitativeresearchbreatheslifeintoregressiontables;italsohelpsusto(better)naildowncausalmechanisms.Quantitatively-orientedscholarsdonot

Page 21: Compliance with International Lathe modern legal principle of rebus sic stantibus (‘things thus standing’), whereby treaties may become inapplicable if there is a fundamental change

21

necessarilyneedtoconductin-depthcasestudiesorfieldresearchoftheirown,althoughtheymightfindthatsuchanapproachgivesthemaricherandmorerealisticunderstandingofhowinternationalworksinpractice.Conversely,scholarswhoemploycasestudiesandsimilarapproachesdonotnecessarilyneedtostartcollectinglargedatasets,buttheydoneedtoconsiderhowthecasesand/oroutcomesonwhichtheyfocusaffecttheirinferences(Geddes1990).Dialogacrossfields(politicalscience,IL,sociology,andsoon)andmethodologicalapproachescanonlyhelptoimprovethequalityoftreatycomplianceresearch.

8. Conclusion

ILisrarelyenforcedthroughinternationalcourts,backedbythethreatofinterventionbyastandingpoliceorarmy.Thisdoesnotmeanthatstatesconstantlybreaktheirinternationallegalpromises.Indeed,thisarticlehasshownthatvariousmechanisms–theproverbialcarrotsandsticks;technicalandfinancialassistance;tyinggoodbehaviortoaparticularidentity–can,dependingonone’sperspective,helptoensurethatstateskeeptheirinternationalpromisesmuchofthetime.Thisdoesnotmeanthatstatesalwaysabidebythetreatiestheysign/ratify.Indeed,akeyfindingtoemergefromthisoverviewisthatitisnotthecasethatalmostallstatesrespecttheirobligationsalmostallthetime(Henkin1979:47).

Recentresearchhastakenusalongwaytowardunderstandingbetterunderwhatconditionsgovernmentskeepthesepromises,buttherearemanyoutstandingquestions.Onepertainstotheuseofsurveyexperiments,whichhavebreathednewlifeintotreatycompliancedebates.Surveys,itiswellknown,haveexternalvalidityproblems(Hyde2015).Howmuchcanweinferfromthemaboutinternationallegalpracticeinthe‘realworld?’Researchersusingthistoolneedtodoasmuchastheycantoreplicatethat‘realworld,’inwhichleaders,activists,andordinarycitizensgrapplewithtradeoffs,uncertainty,limitationsoncognitivecapacity,andemotions.

Anotherquestionregardsthecomplianceliterature’sheavyfocusonwrittenagreements.Lessformalinstitutions,especiallycustomaryinternationallaw,havereceivedlimitedattentionintheIRliterature.FormanyIRscholars,unwrittenlawderivedthroughpracticefeelsslippery.Butcustomaryinternationallawmatterstolegalpractitionersandscholars.Arewemissingimportantelementsofthecompliancepuzzlebyfocusingonwrittenagreements?Theanswerstotheseandotherquestionswillhelpshapetheoreticalandempiricalapproachestocompliancewellintothefuture.

Page 22: Compliance with International Lathe modern legal principle of rebus sic stantibus (‘things thus standing’), whereby treaties may become inapplicable if there is a fundamental change

22

ReferencesAbbott,K.,andSnidal,D.(2000)HardandSoftLawinInternationalGovernance.

InternationalOrganization54(3),421–56.Agon,S.(2016)IsCompliancetheNameoftheEffectivenessGame?Goal-Shiftingand

theDynamicsofJudicialEffectivenessattheWTO.WorldTradeReviewpp.1-31.Alter,K.(2001)EstablishingtheSupremacyofEuropeanLaw:TheMakingofan

InternationalRuleofLawinEurope.NewYork:OxfordUniversityPress.Alter,K.,andMeunier,S.(2006)NestedandOverlappingRegimesintheTransatlantic

BananaTradeDispute.JournalofEuropeanPublicPolicy13(3):362-82.Arend,A.,andBeck,R.(1993)InternationalLawandtheUseofForce:BeyondtheUN

CharterParadigm.NewYork:Routledge.Austin,John.1832[1995].TheProvidenceofJurisprudenceDetermined.Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress.

Axelrod,R.(1984)TheEvolutionofCooperation.NewYork:BasicBooks.Axelrod,R.,andKeohane,R.(1986)AchievingCooperationunderAnarchy:Strategies

andInstitutions.InK.Oye(ed.)CooperationunderAnarchy.Princeton:PrincetonUniversityPress,pp.1–24.

Baccini,L.,andUrpelainen,J.(2014)BeforeRatification:UnderstandingtheTimingofInternationalTreatyEffectsonDomesticPolicies.InternationalStudiesQuarterly58(1):29-43.

Barrett,Scott(2007)WhyCooperate?TheIncentivetoSupplyGlobalPublicGoodsOxford:OxfordUniversityPress.

Bechtel,M.,andScheve,K.(2013)MassSupportforGlobalClimateChangeAgreementsDependsonInstitutionalDesign.ProceedingsoftheNationalAcademyofSciences11(34):13763-68.

Black,D.(1999)TheLongandWindingRoad:InternationalNormsandDomesticPoliticalChangeinSouthAfrica.InT.Risse,S.Ropp,andK.Sikkink(eds.)ThePowerofHumanRights.Cambridge,UK:CambridgeUniversityPress,78-108.

Bodansky,D.(2013)LegitimacyinInternationalLawandInternationalRelations.InDunoff,J.,andPollack,M.,InterdisciplinaryPerspectivesonInternationalLaw:TheStateoftheArt.NewYork:CambridgeUniversityPress,pp.321-44.

Börzel,T.,Hofmann,T.,andPanke,D.(2012)CavinginorSittingitOut?LongitudinalPatternsofNon-complianceintheEuropeanUnion.JournalofEuropeanPublicPolicy,19(4):454-71.

Brewster,Rachel(2009)UnpackingtheState’sReputation,HarvardInternationalLawJournal,Vol.50,No.2,pp.231–69.

Brewster,R.(2013)ReputationinInternationalRelationsandInternationalLawTheory.InDunoff,J.,andPollack,M.,InterdisciplinaryPerspectivesonInternationalLaw:TheStateoftheArt.NewYork:CambridgeUniversityPress,pp.524-43.

BrownWeiss,E.,Jacobson,H.(1998)EngagingCountries:StrengtheningCompliancewithInternationalEnvironmentalAccords.Cambridge:MITPress.

Bull,H.(1977)TheAnarchicalSociety.NewYork:ColumbiaUniversityPress.Brunée,J.,andToope,S.(2010)LegitimacyandLegalityinInternationalLaw:An

InteractionalAccount.Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress.Byers,Michael(ed.)(2000)TheRoleofLawinInternationalPolitics.NewYork:Oxford

UniversityPress.Carpenter,C(2007)SettingtheAdvocacyAgenda:IssuesandNon-IssuesAround

ChildrenandArmedConflict.InternationalStudiesQuarterly51(1):99-120.

Page 23: Compliance with International Lathe modern legal principle of rebus sic stantibus (‘things thus standing’), whereby treaties may become inapplicable if there is a fundamental change

23

Chayes,A.,andChayes,A.H.(1991)CompliancewithoutEnforcement:StateBehaviorunderRegulatoryTreaties.NegotiationJournal7(3),311–30.

Chayes,A.,andChayes,A.H.(1995)TheNewSovereignty.Cambridge:HarvardUniversityPress.

Checkel,J.(2001)WhyComply?SocialLearningandEuropeanIdentityChange.InternationalOrganization55(3),553–88.

Chilton,A.(2015)TheLawsofWarandPublicOpinion:AnExperimentalStudy.JournalofInstitutionalandTheoreticalEconomics171(1):181-201.

Chilton,A.,andTingley,D.(2013)WhytheStudyofInternationalLawNeedsExperiments.ColumbiaJournalofTransnationalLaw,52(1):173-237.

Cole,W.(2015a)MindtheGap:StateCapacityandtheImplementationofHumanRightsTreaties.InternationalOrganization69(2):405-41.

Cole,W.(2015b)InternationalHumanRightsandDomesticIncomeInequality:ADifficultCaseofComplianceinWorldSociety.AmericanSociologicalReview.DOI:10.1177/0003122415571582(accessedOctober1,2015).

Conrad,C.(2014)DivergentIncentivesforDictators:DomesticInstitutionsand(InternationalPromisesNotto)Torture.JournalofConflictResolution58(1):34–67.

Conrad,C.,andHenckenRitter,C.(2013)Treaties,Tenure,andTorture:theConflictingDomesticEffectsofInternationalLaw.TheJournalofPolitics75(2):397–409.

Conrad,C.,Hill,D.,andMoore,W.(2015)TortureandtheLimitsofDemocraticInstitutions.Workingpaper.

Dai, X. (2006) The Conditional Nature of Democratic Compliance. Journal of ConflictResolution50(5),690–713.

Davey,W.(2006)TheWTO:LookingForwards.JournalofInternationalEconomicLaw9(1):3-29.

Davis,C.(2012)WhyAdjudicate?EnforcingTradeRulesintheWTO.Princeton:PrincetonUniversitypress.

Desierto,D.(2012)NecessityandNationalEmergencyClauses.Leiden:MartinusNijhof.Downs,G.,Rocke,D.,andBarsoom,P.(1996)IstheGoodNewsaboutComplianceGood

NewsaboutCooperation?InternationalOrganization50(3),379–406.Downs,G.,andJones,M.(2002)Reputation,Compliance,andInternationalLaw.Journal

ofLegalStudies31,S95–S114.Dunoff,J.,Ratner,S.,andWippman,D.(2010)InternationalLaw:Norms,Actors,Process:

AProblem-OrientedApproach.NewYork:AspenPublishers.Farber,D.(2002)RightsasSignals.JournalofLegalStudies31(1),83–98.Fariss,C.(2015)TheChangingStandardofAccountabilityandthePositiveRelationship

betweenHumanRightsTreatyRatificationandCompliance.Forthcoming,BritishJournalofPoliticalScience.papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2517457(accessedOctober5,2015).

Fearon,J.,andWendt,A.(2002)Rationalismv.Constructivism:ASkepticalView.InW.Carlsnaes,T.Risse,andB.Simmons(eds.)HandbookofInternationalRelations.London:Sage,pp.52–72.

Finnemore,M.,andSikkink,K.(1998)InternationalNormDynamicsandPoliticalChange.InternationalOrganization52(4),887–917.

Fisher,R.(1981)ImprovingCompliancewithInternationalLaw.Charlottesville:UniversityofVirginiaPress.

Franck,T.(1990)ThePowerofLegitimacyAmongNations.NewYork:OxfordUniversityPress.

Page 24: Compliance with International Lathe modern legal principle of rebus sic stantibus (‘things thus standing’), whereby treaties may become inapplicable if there is a fundamental change

24

Franck,T.(1995)FairnessinInternationalLawandInstitutions.NewYork:OxfordUniversityPress.

Gartzke,E.,andGleditsch,K.(2004)WhyDemocraciesMayActuallybeLessReliableAllies.AmericanJournalofPoliticalScience48(4),775–95.

Geddes,B.(1990)HowtheCasesYouChooseAffecttheAnswersYouGet:SelectionBiasinComparativePolitics.PoliticalAnalysis2(1):131-50.

Gibler,D.(2008)TheCostofReneging:ReputationandAllianceFormation.JournalofConflictResolution52(2),426–54.

Goldsmith,J.,andPosner,E.(2005)TheLimitsofInternationalLaw.NewYork:OxfordUniversityPress.

Goodman,Ryan,andDerekJinks(2004)HowtoInfluenceStates:SocializationandInternationalHumanRightsLaw.DukeLawJournal,Vol.54,No.3,pp.621–703.

Goodman,R.,andJinks,D.(2008)IncompleteInternalizationandCompliancewithHumanRightsLaw.EuropeanJournalofInternationalLaw19(4):725-48.

Goodman,R.,andJinks,D.(2013)SocializingStates:PromotingHumanRightsthroughInternationalLaw.NewYork:OxfordUniversityPress.

Grieco,J.,Gelpo,C.,andWarren,T.(2009)WhenPreferencesandCommitmentsCollide:TheEffectofRelativePartisanShiftsonInternationalTreatyCompliance.InternationalOrganization63(2):341-55.

Grotius,H.(1625)OntheLawofWarandPeace.Whitefish:Kessinger.Guzman,A.(2008)HowInternationalLawWorks:ARationalChoiceTheory.NewYork:

OxfordUniversityPress.Haas,P.(1989)DoRegimesMatter?EpistemicCommunitiesandMediterranean

PollutionControl.InternationalOrganization43(3),377–403.Haas,P.(2002)UNConferencesandConstructivistGovernanceoftheEnvironment.

GlobalGovernance8(1),73–91.Hafner-Burton,E.(2005)TradingHumanRights:HowPreferentialTradingAgreements

InfluenceGovernmentRepression.InternationalOrganization59(3),593–629.Hafner-Burton,E.(2009)ForcedtoBeGood:WhyTradeAgreementsBoostHuman

Rights.Cornell:CornellUniversityPress.Hafner-Burton,E.,LeVeck,B.,andVictor,G.(2015)HowtheProspectofNon-

ComplianceAffectsElitePreferencesforInternationalCooperation:Evidencefroma“LabintheField”Experiment.ILARWorkingPaper#28.pages.ucsd.edu/~ehafner/pdfs/ILAR_Working-Paper_28.pdf(accessedOctober6,2015).

Hafner-Burton,E.,LeVeck,B.,andVictor,G.(2016)PunitivePower:HowInternationalLawHelpsActivists.Forthcoming,JournalofPolitics.pages.ucsd.edu/~ehafner/pdfs/ILAR_working-paper_23.pdf(accessedOctober6,2015).

Hafner-Burton,E.,andTsutsui,K.(2005)HumanRightsinaGlobalizingWorld:TheParadoxofEmptyPromises,AmericanJournalofSociology,Vol.110,No.5,pp.1373–411.

Hafner-Burton,E.,andTsutsui,K.(2007)JusticeLost!TheFailureofInternationalHumanRightsLawtoMatterWhereNeededMost.JournalofPeaceResearch44(4),407–25.

Hart,H.L.A.(1997[1961])TheConceptofLaw.NewYork:OxfordUniversityPress.Hathaway,O.(2002)DoHumanRightsTreatiesMakeaDifference?YaleLawJournal

111(8),1935–2042.Hathaway,O.(2007)WhyDoCountriesCommittoHumanRightsTreaties?Journalof

ConflictResolution51(4),588–621.

Page 25: Compliance with International Lathe modern legal principle of rebus sic stantibus (‘things thus standing’), whereby treaties may become inapplicable if there is a fundamental change

25

Helfer,L.(2013)FlexibilityinInternationalAgreements.InDunoff,J.,andPollack,M.,InterdisciplinaryPerspectivesonInternationalLaw:TheStateoftheArt.NewYork:CambridgeUniversityPress,pp.175-96.

Henkin,L.(1979)HowNationsBehave.NewYork:ColumbiaUniversityPress.Hill,D.(2010)EstimatingtheEffectsofHumanRightsTreatiesonStateBehavior.

JournalofPolitics72(4):1161-74.Hobbes,T.(2006[1651])Leviathan.Cambridge,UK:CambridgeUniversityPress.Howse,R.,andTeitel,R.(2010)BeyondCompliance:RethinkingWhyInternationalLaw

ReallyMatters.GlobalPolicy,Vol.1,No.2,pp.127–36.Hyde,S.(2015)ExperimentsinInternationalRelations:Lab,Survey,andField.Annual

ReviewofPoliticalScience18:403-24.Jepperson,R.,Wendt,A.,andKatzenstein,P.(1996)Norms,Identity,andCulturein

InternationalSecurity.InP.Katzenstein(ed.)TheCultureofNationalSecurity.Ithaca:CornellUniversityPress,pp.33–75.

Keck,M.,andSikkink,K.(1999)TransnationalAdvocacyNetworksinInternationalandRegionalPolitics.InternationalSocialScienceJournal51(159):89-101.

Kelley,J.(2007)WhoKeepsInternationalCommitmentsandWhy?TheInternationalCriminalCourtandBilateralNonsurrenderAgreements.AmericanPoliticalScienceReview101(3),573–89.

Keohane,R.(1984)AfterHegemony:CooperationandDiscordintheWorldPoliticalEconomy.Princeton:PrincetonUniversityPress.

Keohane,R.(1995)ReciprocityinInternationalRelations.InternationalOrganization40(1),1–27.

Keohane,R.(1997)InternationalRelationsandInternationalLaw:TwoOptics.HarvardInternationalLawJournal38(2),487–502.

Kingsbury,B.(1998)TheConceptofComplianceasaFunctionofCompetingConceptionsofInternationalLaw.MichiganJournalofInternationalLaw19(2):345-72.

Koh,H.H.(1997)WhyDoNationsObeyInternationalLaw?YaleLawJournal106(8),2599–659.

Koh,H.H.(1998)BringingInternationalLawHome,HoustonLawReview,Vol.35,No.3,pp.623–81.

Koh,H.H.(2005)InternalizationthroughSocialization.DukeLawJournal54(4):975-83.

Koremenos,B.(2001)LooseningtheTiesthatBind:ALearningModelofAgreementFlexibility.InternationalOrganization55(2),289–325.

Koremenos,B.(2005)ContractingaroundInternationalUncertainty.AmericanPoliticalScienceReview99(4),549–65.

Koremenos,B.,Lipson,C.,andSnidal,D.(2001)TheRationalDesignofInternationalInstitutions.InternationalOrganization55(4),761–99.

Krasner,S.(ed.)(1982)InternationalRegimes.InternationalOrganization36(2),185–510.

Kratochwil,F.,andRuggie,J.(1986)InternationalOrganization:AStateoftheArtonanArtoftheState,InternationalOrganization,Vol.40,No.4,pp.753–75.

Kucik,J.,andReinhardt,E.(2008)DoesFlexibilityPromoteCooperation?AnApplicationtotheGlobalTradeRegime.InternationalOrganization62(3),477–505.

Lebovic,J.,andVoeten,E.(2009)TheCostofShame:InternationalOrganizationsandForeignAidinthePunishingofHumanRightsViolators.JournalofPeaceResearch46(1),79–97.

Page 26: Compliance with International Lathe modern legal principle of rebus sic stantibus (‘things thus standing’), whereby treaties may become inapplicable if there is a fundamental change

26

Leeds,B.A.(2003)AllianceReliabilityinTimesofWar:ExplainingStateDecisionstoViolateTreaties.InternationalOrganization57(4),801–27.

Lupu,Y.(2013)TheInformativePowerofTreatyCommitment:UsingtheSpatialModeltoAddressSelectionEffects.AmericanJournalofPoliticalScience57(4):912-25.

Lupu,Y.(2015)LegislativeVetoPlayersandtheEffectsofInternationalHumanRightsAgreements.AmericanJournalofPoliticalScience59(3):578-94.

Machiavelli,N.(1989[1532])ThePrince.Cambridge,UK:CambridgeUniversityPress.Mansfield,E.,Milner,H.,andRosendorff,B.P.(2002)WhyDemocraciesCooperateMore:

ElectoralControlandInternationalTradeAgreements.InternationalOrganization56(3),477–513.

Martin,L.(2000)DemocraticCommitments.Princeton:PrincetonUniversityPress.Martin,L.(2013)AgainstCompliance.InDunoff,J.,andPollack,M.,Interdisciplinary

PerspectivesonInternationalLaw:TheStateoftheArt.NewYork:CambridgeUniversityPress,pp.591-612.

McGillivray,F.,andSmith,A.(2000)TrustandCooperationthroughAgent-SpecificPunishments.InternationalOrganization54(4),809–24.

Mearsheimer,J.(1994-95)TheFalsePromiseofInternationalInstitutions.InternationalSecurity19(3):5-49.

Mitchell,R.(1994)RegimeDesignMatters:IntentionalOilPollutionandTreatyCompliance.InternationalOrganization48(3),425–58.

Mitchell,S.M.,andHensel,P.(2007)InternationalInstitutionsandCompliancewithAgreements.AmericanJournalofPoliticalScience51(4),721–37.

Montoya,C.(2008)TheEuropeanUnion,CapacityBuilding,andTransnationalNetworks:CombatingViolenceAgainstWomenThroughtheDaphneProgram.InternationalOrganization62(2):359-72.

Moore,DH.(2003)ASignalingTheoryofHumanRightsCompliance.NorthwesternUniversityLawReview97(2),879–910.

Moravcsik,A.(1999)IsSomethingRottenintheStateofDenmark?ConstructivismandEuropeanIntegration.JournalofEuropeanPublicPolicy6(4),669–81.

Morgenthau,H.(1948)PoliticsamongNations.NewYork:McGraw-Hill.Morrow,J.(2002)TheLawsofWar,CommonConjectures,andLegalSystemsin

InternationalPolitics.JournalofLegalStudies31(S1):S41-60.Morrow,J.(2007)WhenDoStatesFollowtheLawsofWar?AmericanPoliticalScience

Review101(3),559–72.Morrow,J.(2014)OrderwithinAnarchy:TheLawsofWarasanInternationalInstitution.

Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress.Muchlinski,P.(2014)CorporationsinInternationalLaw.MaxPlanckEncyclopediaof

PublicInternationalLaw.Nelson,S.(2010)DoesComplianceMatter?AssessingtheRelationshipBetween

SovereignRiskandCompliancewithInternationalLaw.ReviewofInternationalOrganizations5(2):107-39.

Neumayer,E.(2005)DoInternationalHumanRightsTreatiesImproveRespectforHumanRights?JournalofConflictResolution49(6),925–53.

ThePaqueteHabana.175U.S.677;20S.Ct.290;44L.Ed.320(1900).Park,J.H.,andHirose,K.(2013)DomesticPolitics,ReputationalSanctions,and

InternationalCompliance.InternationalTheory5(2):300-20.Pollack,M.(2003)TheEnginesofEuropeanIntegration:Delegation,Agency,andAgenda

SettingintheEU.Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress.Ohlin,J.(2015)TheAssaultonInternationalLaw.Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress.

Page 27: Compliance with International Lathe modern legal principle of rebus sic stantibus (‘things thus standing’), whereby treaties may become inapplicable if there is a fundamental change

27

Rajagopal,B.(2003)InternationalLawfromBelowDevelopment,SocialMovementsandThirdWorldResistance.NewYork:CambridgeUniversityPress.

Raustiala,K.,andSlaughter,A.M.(2002)Compliance,InternationalRelations,andInternationalLaw.InW.Carlsnaes,T.Risse,andB.Simmons(eds.)HandbookofInternationalRelations.London:Sage.

Raustiala,Kal,andDavidG.Victor(1998)Conclusions,inDavidG.Victor,KalRaustiala,andEugeneB.Skolnikoff(eds.),TheImplementationandEffectivenessofInternationalEnvironmentalCommitments:TheoryandPractice(Cambridge,MA:MITPress),pp.659–708.

Rickard,S.(2010)DemocraticDifferences:ElectoralInstitutionsandCompliancewithGATT/WTOAgreements.EuropeanJournalofInternationalRelations16(4):711-29.

Risse,T.,andSikkink,K.(1999)TheSocializationofInternationalHumanRightsNormsintoDomesticPractices:Introduction.InT.Risse,S.Ropp,andK.Sikkink(eds.)ThePowerofHumanRights.Cambridge,UK:CambridgeUniversityPress,pp.1–38.

Risse,T.,andSikkink,K.(2013)Conclusion.InT.Risse,S.Sikkink,andS.Ropp(eds.)ThePersistentPowerofHumanRights..NewYork:CambridgeUniversityPress,pp.275-95.

Risse,T.,Ropp,S.,andSikkink,K.(2013)ThePersistentPowerofHumanRights.NewYork:CambridgeUniversityPress.

Rosendorff,B.P.,andMilner,H.(2001)TheOptimalDesignofInternationalTradeInstitutions:UncertaintyandEscape.InternationalOrganization55(4),829–57.

Sanchez,T.(2009)AfterRatification:TheDomesticPoliticsofTreatyImplementationandCompliance.Ph.D.dissertation,ColumbiaUniversity.

Schechter,M.,andBochenek,M.(2008)WorkingtoEliminateHumanRightsAbusesofChildren:ACross-NationalComparativeStudy.HumanRightsQuarterly30,579–606.

Schimmelfennig,F.,Engert,S.,andKnobel,H.(2003)Costs,CommitmentandCompliance:TheImpactofEUDemocraticConditionalityonLatvia,SlovakiaandTurkey.JournalofCommonMarketStudies41(3),495–518.

Setear,J.(2002)ThePresident’sRationalChoiceofaTreaty’sPreratificationPathway:ArticleII,Congressional-ExecutiveAgreement,orExecutiveAgreement?JournalofLegalStudies31(1):S5–S31.

Shelton,D.(ed.)(2000)CommitmentandCompliance:TheRoleofNon-BindingNormsintheInternationalLegalSystem.NewYork:OxfordUniversityPress.

Sikkink,J.(2003).ATypologyofRelationsBetweenSocialMovementsandInternationalInstitutions.ProceedingsoftheAnnualMeetingoftheAmericanSocietyofInternationalLaw97:301-5.

Simmons,B.(2000)InternationalLawandStateBehavior:CommitmentandComplianceinInternationalMonetaryAffairs.AmericanPoliticalScienceReview94(4),819–35.

Simmons,B.(2009)MobilizingforHumanRights:InternationalLawinDomesticPolitics.NewYork:CambridgeUniversityPress.

Simmons,B.andHopkins,D.(2005)TheConstrainingPowerofInternationalTreaties:TheoryandMethods.AmericanPoliticalScienceReview99(4),623–31.

Slaughter,A.(1995)InternationalLawinaWorldofLiberalStates.EuropeanJournalofInternationalLaw6,1–39.

Spilker,G.,andBöhmelt,T.(2013)TheImpactofPreferentialTradeAgreementsonGovernmentalRepressionRevisited.ReviewofInternationalOrganization8(3):343-61.

Page 28: Compliance with International Lathe modern legal principle of rebus sic stantibus (‘things thus standing’), whereby treaties may become inapplicable if there is a fundamental change

28

Staton,J.,andMoore,W.(2011)JudicialPowerinDomesticandInternationalPolitics.InternationalOrganization65(3):553-87.

Stiglitz,J.(2007)MultinationalCorporations:BalancingRightsandResponsibilities.ProceedsoftheAnnualMeetingoftheAmericanSocietyofInternationalLaw101:3-60.

Stiles,K.(2015)StateResponsestoInternatioanalLaw.NewYork:Routledge.Sykes,A.(1991)Protectionismasa“Safeguard”:APositiveAnalysisoftheGATTEscape

ClausewithNormativeSpeculations.UniversityofChicagoLawReview58,255–306.Tallberg,J.(2002)PathstoCompliance:Enforcement,Management,andtheEuropean

Union.InternationalOrganization56(3):609-43.Tesón,F.(1992)TheKantianTheoryofInternationalLaw,ColumbiaLawReview92(1):

53-102.Thomas,D.(2001)TheHelsinkiEffect:InternationalNorms,HumanRights,andthe

DemiseofCommunism.Princeton:PrincetonUniversityPress.Thompson,A.(2013)CoerciveEnforcementinInternationalLaw.InDunoff,J.,and

Pollack,M.,InterdisciplinaryPerspectivesonInternationalLaw:TheStateoftheArt.NewYork:CambridgeUniversityPress,pp.502-23

Thompson,A.(2009)TheRationalEnforcementofInternationalLaw:SolvingtheSanctioners’Dilemma,InternationalTheory1(2):307-21.

Tingley,D.,andTomz,M.(2014)ConditionalCooperationandClimateChange.ComparativePoliticalStudies47(3),344-68.

Tomz,M.(2008)ReputationandtheEffectofInternationalLawonPreferencesandBeliefs.Workingpaper,StanfordUniversity.http://web.stanford.edu/~tomz/working/Tomz-IntlLaw-2008-02-11a.pdf.

Tomz,M,andWeeks,J.(2015)MilitaryAlliancesandPublicSupportforWar.Workingpaper,StanfordUniversityandUniversityofWisconsin.http://web.stanford.edu/~tomz/working/TomzWeeks-Alliances-2015-02-14.pdf.

Trachtman,J.(2008)TheEconomicStructureofInternationalLaw.Cambridge:HarvardUniversityPress.

Tsutsui,K.,Whitlinger,C.,andLim,A.(2012)InternationalHumanRightsLawandSocialMovements:States’ResistanceandCivilSociety’sInsistence.AnnualReviewofLawandSocialScience8:367-96.

Urpelainen,J.(2010)EnforcingInternationalEnvironmentalCooperation:TechnologicalStandardsCanHelp.ReviewofInternationalOrganizations5(4):475-96.

vonStein,J.(2005)DoTreatiesConstrainorScreen?SelectionBiasandTreatyCompliance.AmericanPoliticalScienceReview99(4):611–22.

vonStein,J.(2008)TheInternationalLawandPoliticsofClimateChange:RatificationoftheUnitedNationsFrameworkConventionandtheKyotoProtocol.JournalofConflictResolution52(2):243-68.

vonStein,J.(2015)MakingPromises,KeepingPromises:Democracy,Ratification,andComplianceinInternationalHumanRightsLaw.BritishJournalofPoliticalScience,doi:10.1017/S0007123414000489.

ViennaConventionontheLawofTreaties.1155U.N.T.S.[UnitedNationsTreatySeries]331.1969.

Wallace,G.(2013).InternationalLawandPublicAttitudesTowardTorture:AnExperimentalStudy.InternationalOrganization67(1):105–40.

Page 29: Compliance with International Lathe modern legal principle of rebus sic stantibus (‘things thus standing’), whereby treaties may become inapplicable if there is a fundamental change

29

WorldTradeOrganization(2012)HistoricSigningEnds20YearsofEU-LatinAmericanBananaDisputes.www.wto.org/english/news_e/news12_e/disp_08nov12_e.htm(accessedSeptember30,2015).

Wotipka,C.,andTsutsui,K(2008)GlobalHumanRightsandStateSovereignty:NationStates’RatificationsofInternationalHumanRightsTreaties,1965-2001.SociologicalForum23(4):724-754.

Young,O.(1979)ComplianceandPublicAuthority.Baltimore:JohnsHopkinsPress.Young,O.(1994)InternationalGovernance:ProtectingtheEnvironmentinaStateless

Society.Ithaca:CornellUniversityPress.Zürn,M.(2004)LawandComplianceatDifferentLevels.InM.ZürnandC.Joerges(eds.)

LawandGovernanceinPostnationalEurope:CompliancebeyondtheNation-State.NewYork:CambridgeUniversityPress.

Abstract:Ifthereisauthorityhigherthanthestate,whydogovernmentseverabidebythepactstheymakewitheachother?Forsome,theanswerissimple:statesonlyrespectagreementsthatfulfilltheirimmediateinterests.Othersaremorenuanced.Onegroupofscholarsviewscomplianceasaproblemofenforcement,arguingthatinternationalinducements,reciprocity,reputationalconcerns,and/ordomesticpolitics/institutionsregularlyhelpsustaincompliance.Othersdrawourattentiontocapacityormanagementproblemsasdriversofnoncompliance.Fromthisperspective,governmentsabidebytheircommitmentsthroughtheprovisionoftransparentagreements,technicalandfinancialassistance,andsoliddisputeresolution.Seenfromthisangle,mechanismsthat‘punish’noncompliance,forinstancebysuspendinginternationalinducementslikeforeignaid,infacttendtomakemattersworse.Finally,somescholarsperceivecompliancethroughthelensofsocialcontext,identity,and/orlegitimacy.Governmentskeeptheirpromisesbecausetheycarehowothersperceivethem,internalizenorms,and/orviewagreementsasvalidandfair.Thisarticleprovidesanoverviewofthesearguments,withastrongemphasisonrecentdevelopmentsininternationallawandinternationalrelations.SEEALSO:ForeignPolicyAnalysisandRationalChoiceModels;FormalInternationalInstitutionsandtheRegulationofFlowsofGoodsandServices;HumanRights:EffectivenessofInternationalandRegionalMechanisms;IdentityinInternationalRelations;TheInteractionofTheoryandData;InternalizationofInternationalLaw;InternationalEnvironmentalLaw;InternationalRelationsandComparativePolitics;TreatyLaw:NewTrends;TransnationalHumanRightsNetworks:SignificanceandChallenges


Recommended