+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Conceptions, Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

Conceptions, Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

Date post: 07-Jan-2016
Category:
Upload: swain
View: 27 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend
Description:
Conceptions, Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming). The Starting Point One ’s conception of something is how one conceives or thinks, or is somehow inclined to think, of it. - PowerPoint PPT Presentation
Popular Tags:
60
Conceptions, Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)
Transcript
Page 1: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

Conceptions, Understanding, andWisdom

John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin)&Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

Page 2: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

The Starting Point

One’s conception of something is how one conceives or thinks, or is somehow inclined to think, of it.

That’s not an analysis or theory, but a way of pointing to a rather familiar phenomenon.

2

Page 3: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

We have conceptions of ourselves, our environment (e.g., as something sacred), motion (Newton’s conception differed from Aristotle’s), how to reason according to modus ponens, a variety of traditional philosophical topics such as freedom, justice, truth, reference, knowledge, and so forth.

What are conceptions? What is their philosophical significance?

3

Page 4: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

A number of philosophers have claimed that conceptions and their kin (e.g., schemas, stereotypes, perspectives, views, “frames”) are indispensable in a wide variety of areas.

4

Page 5: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

This talk will develop an account of the M&E of conceptions that may provide the theoretical resources needed to assess such claims.

The talk will also explore some of the further significance of conceptions.

We’ll argue that an adequate account of conceptions yields insight into the nature of understanding. It also introduces a straightforward treatment of the notion of a worldview. And it illuminates the classical centerpiece of philosophia: the notion of wisdom.

5

Page 6: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

The Plan

Part I: The M&E of Conceptions

Clarify some central features of conceptions and critically examine extant reductionist treatments Introduce an alternative, non-reductionist theory

Part II: The Significance of Conceptions

A new analysis of understanding A new analysis of wisdom Extension to other notions: authenticity and intelligent action

6

Page 7: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

Part I: The M&E of Conceptions

§1. Reductionist Theories

Page 8: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

An Ambiguity

one’s having a conception = a mental attitude (state, event)

the conception that one has = a content

Neither has received much attention, at least not as such. This may be due to a widespread yet largely implicit acceptance of reductive views of conceptions (in terms of concepts or propositions).

8

Page 9: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

Conceptual Reductionism

[CRC] Conceptions (the contents) = concepts concept: non-mentalistic entity (e.g., Fregean sense)

[CRA] Conceptions (the attitudes) = mental relations to concepts, or states of grasping concepts

9

Page 10: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

Assessing [CRC]

In general, a conception of (the content) is not identical to a concept of .

First, it’s plausible that some concepts—perhaps concepts for colors, consciousness, existence—are simple and unanalysable. Even so, it seems possible to have complex conceptions of these things. (Cf. Frege on truth.)

10

Page 11: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

Assessing [CRC]

In general, a conception of (the content) is not identical to a concept of .

Second, consider Tyler Burge’s arthritis example.

Burge has argued convincingly that the patient and doctor share the same concept of arthritis. Regardless, it seems clear that their conceptions of arthritis are quite different (for the confused patient: as possibly occurring in the thigh).

11

Page 12: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

A possible “move” is to hold that a conception of is a concept, but not a concept of —it’s a concept of something else.

But this introduces a general reason against thinking that a conception is identical to any concept (or set of concepts).

12

Page 13: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

Consider once again Burge’s doctor and patient.

They might possess all of the same concepts, including the concept possibly occurring in the thigh. But they could still have different conceptions of arthritis: only for the patient is this concept “oriented towards” arthritis—it as it were purports to say how arthritis is.

The difference lies, not in their conceptual repertoires, but in something else—again, how those repertoires are “oriented towards” the world (here, arthritis). [More on this notion later.]

13

Page 14: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

Assessing [CRA]

For analogous reasons, conceptions (the attitudes) are not identical to states of grasping concepts.

Consider the particular conception of Middle East politics you currently harbor. While this conception plausibly requires grasping various concepts, your current conception of Middle East politics is not (or, not simply) a state of grasping those concepts.

You have to as it were put those concepts to use in characterizing Middle East politics.

14

Page 15: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

These points are compatible with the following ideas: conceptions (the contents) are structured entities constituted, at least in part, by concepts; conceptions (the attitudes) require grasping those concepts.

Both ideas are plausible.

This, together with the observation that conceptions purport to say or characterize how things are, would seem to make them prop- or prop-attitude-like.

Perhaps this is why a number of philosophers have been attracted to a propositional reduction.

15

Page 16: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

Propositional Reductionism

[PRC] Conceptions (the contents) = propositions prop: the semantic value of a full indicative sentence

[PRA] Conceptions (the attitudes) = mental relations to props, or prop attitudes

16

Page 17: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

In Truly Understood, Christopher Peacocke says conceptions are states of knowledge. [Problem: Arist vs. Newton on motion.]

Frank Jackson equates “folk conceptions” with “folk theories”—presumably these are often opinions or beliefs, not necessarily knowledge.

David Wiggins: “A conception of horse is a set of beliefs concerning what horses are, or what it is to be a horse.”

Anil Gupta: conceptions or “views” involve judgments.

17

Page 18: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

Against a Propositional Reduction

While conceptions are certainly like props and prop-attitudes in many ways, there are also several (subtle) differences.

For example, propositions are bearers of truth/falsity, the contents of belief, and possible objects of judgment. By contrast,

Conceptions aren’t true or false (rather, they’re correct/incorrect).# ‘The conception of nature as something sacred is true.’

Conceptions aren’t the contents of belief.# ‘A believes the conception of nature as something sacred.’

Conceptions aren’t possible objects of judgment.# ‘What I judge to be true is the conception of nature as something sacred.’

18

Page 19: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

Interestingly, conceptions are possible objects, not of judgment, but rather of broadly evaluative attitudes like respect, admiration, and abhorrence.

‘I have a deep respect for the conception of nature as sacred.’

Contrast:# ‘I have a deep respect for the proposition that nature is sacred.’

19

Page 20: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

Further, propositions are introduced by certain expressions involving that-clauses.

‘A believes the proposition that nature is sacred.’

By contrast, conceptions are canonically introduced by certain expressions involving as- or by-clauses.

‘A’s conception of nature is as something sacred.’‘A’s conception of how to reason according to modus ponens is by inferring q from (p, pq).’

20

Page 21: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

If the preceding is correct, conceptions (the contents) are not identical to props, and conceptions (the attitudes) are not identical to prop attitudes.

Of course, it doesn’t follow that conceptions (the contents) are not somehow associated with propositions, and that conceptions (the attitudes) are not grounded in prop attitudes.

Both ideas are quite plausible, and a non-reductive theory can accept them.

Let’s now try to develop such a theory.

21

Page 22: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

Part I: The M&E of Conceptions

§2. A Non-reductive Theory

Page 23: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

The Foundations

i. Pointer: One’s conception of δ is how one conceives of δ.

ii. Relational Constraint: Conceptions (the attitudes) relate thinkers to conceptions (the contents).

iii. Constitution Thesis: Conceptions (the contents) are structured entities constituted by concepts.

23

Page 24: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

iv. Orientation Constraint: Unlike concepts, conceptions (the contents) are “oriented towards” the world.

v. As/by constraint: Unlike props, they are canonically introduced with certain expressions involving as- and by-clauses (e.g., as something sacred).

vi. Grounding Thesis: They serve as contents of mental states (conceptions, the attitudes) that are distinct from but nevertheless grounded in prop attitudes.

24

Page 25: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

We think these constraints identify features of conceptions that any theory of conceptions must capture.

In a moment we’ll float a proposal that looks to satisfy this desideratum.

Of course, conceptions also have a variety of other features that must be respected. Here are four.

25

Page 26: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

Some Broadly Logico-semantical Properties of Conceptions

a. Non-factivity: A conception of can be correct or incorrect, and to a greater or lesser degree.

Burge’s arthritis patient

b. Non-exhaustiveness: A conception of can be complete or incomplete, and to a greater or lesser degree.

My current conception of black holes

26

Page 27: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

c. Diversity: There can be many distinct conceptions of a single . Aristotle vs. Newton on motion

d. Publicity: Two distinct individuals can share a single conception of . Augustine and Descartes on the soul (as immaterial and immortal)

27

Page 28: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

In some ways conceptions are proposition-like or prop-attitude-like. In other ways they are more concept-like or grasp-of-concept-like.

Conceptions are neither, though intimately related to both. Perhaps they can be viewed as “lying in-between”.

At any rate, they belong to their own category. They have (types of) properties which neither concepts nor props have; they lack (types of) properties which either concepts or props have.

28

Page 29: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

A Proposal

[NRc] What it is for a conception of (the content) to exist is for there to be a (possibly ordered or singleton) set C of concepts C1, ..., Cn oriented towards in such a way as to characterize ,

where what it is for C to be oriented towards in such a way as to characterize is for there to be some corresponding set P of propositions P1, …, Pn, where P1 = [ is C1], …, Pn = [ is Cn], such that is wholly correct iff every member of P is true.

[NRA] What is it for an individual x to have a conception of (the attitude) is for there to be a conception of (the content) and for x to stand in the having relation to ,

where what it is for x to stand in the having relation to is for x to possess a set PA of acceptance-entailing prop attitudes such that every member of PA is true iff is wholly correct.

29

Page 30: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

A Proposal

[NRc] What it is for a conception of (the content) to exist is for there to be a (possibly ordered or singleton) set C of concepts C1, ..., Cn oriented towards in such a way as to characterize ,

where what it is for C to be oriented towards in such a way as to characterize is for there to be some corresponding set P of propositions P1, …, Pn, where P1 = [ is C1], …, Pn = [ is Cn], such that is wholly correct iff every member of P is true.

[NRA] What it is for an individual x to have a conception of (the attitude) is for there to be a conception of (the content) and for x to stand in the having relation to ,

where what it is for x to stand in the having relation to is for x to possess a set PA of acceptance-entailing prop attitudes such that every member of PA is true iff is wholly correct.

30

Page 31: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

These theses offer a substantive characterization of conceptions which captures their core features and connects them to concepts and props (non-reductive but not “brute”).

These are some of the specific virtues of the proposal.

31

Page 32: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

Broader Virtues

The theory also has a variety of potential theoretical implications and applications, showing that conceptions are not explanatorily idle.

Some were mentioned earlier: a priority, anti-individualism, conceptual analysis, imaginative resistance, meaning, and perception.

Here, we’ll focus on the theory of understanding, then turn briefly to wisdom.

32

Page 33: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

Part II: The Significance of Conceptions

§3. An Analysis of Understanding

Page 34: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

Varieties of Understanding

We’ll focus on objectual understanding, not propositional or factual understanding.

understanding global warmingvs. understanding that global warming is thus and so.

(NB: We realize there may be a difference between understanding and an understanding of . Our primary concern is the former, if and when they diverge.)

34

Page 35: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

Arguably, understanding-that may serve as a useful means when the comparatively more fundamental end of achieving a general understanding-of.

For example, to understand that global warming is partly caused by the accumulation of CFC’s in the atmosphere may be of some help in achieving an understanding of global warming. But clearly more is wanted.

What else? What is understanding-of?

35

Page 36: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

A Proposal

To understand is to have a certain type of conception of : a noetic conception.

36

Page 37: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

Noetic Conceptions

Like all conceptions, noetic conceptions come in degrees, e.g., degrees of correctness and completeness.

This is desirable, for understanding comes in degrees. One can understand better or worse, or have a greater or lesser degree of understanding. Correspondingly, one’s conception may contain greater or fewer gaps and errors, which may be corrected and completed (or vv).

Specifically, one can correct one’s conception by adding suitable true props to P. One can complete one’s conception by adding suitable concepts to C.

So the proposal makes sense of how one’s understanding may change: improve, strengthen, weaken, regress, etc.

Noetic conceptions also have several distinctive features.37

Page 38: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

To explain what is distinctive about noetic conceptions, two notions are needed:

the notion of the core of a conception

the notion of a central attribute (property, relation, etc.)

38

Page 39: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

The Core

In general, what a conception of does is characterize : it specifies attributes of (corresponding to various members of C, e.g. C1).

Part of the conception characterizes what is: it specifies what attributes are part of what it is to be (corresponding to different members of C, e.g. C2). This is the ‘core’ of the conception.

For example, it might be part of my conception of the rainforest that it has been inhabited for most of human history, and so it is appealing to people as a natural habitat. But its being an appealing natural habit isn’t part of the core of my conception of the rainforest, of what the rainforest is.

As we shall see, much of what’s distinctive of noetic conceptions concerns what’s happening in the core.

39

Page 40: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

Central Attributes

Central attributes may be context sensitive in various ways. They are sometimes essential attributes (what is essentially), as perhaps in the context of Descartes’ project in the Meditations. Other times they are not essential, but central in some other relevant way.

For instance, accumulation of CFC’s may be a central attribute of global warming given our current overuse of fossil fuels. However, different technological developments might generate global warming in different ways and in those circumstances other (bio)chemical mechanisms may be central (given our interests and concerns).

Very roughly, noetic conceptions “place” the central attributes in the core.

40

Page 41: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

Unlike other conceptions, noetic conceptions are:

1. Correct in the core their core does not include any of ’s non-central attributes

Suppose that the failure to plant lots of trees is not a central attribute of global warming (e.g., because planting trees is not by itself an effective means to reducing carbon). This should be reflected in a noetic conception of global warming: to conceive of global warming otherwise is to harbor a confusion.

To include non-central attributes in the core is to conceive of incorrectly. Having such a conception indicates a certain kind of error in understanding.

41

Page 42: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

Unlike other conceptions, noetic conceptions are:

1. Correct in the core

2. Complete in the core their core does not omit any of ’s central attributes

Suppose that A1, …, AM are central attributes of global warming. This should be reflected in a noetic conception. A conception of global warming that omits any of these central attributes from the core is lacking or deficient in a crucial respect.

To omit central attributes from the core is to conceive of incompletely. It indicates a certain kind of gap in understanding.

42

Page 43: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

Unlike other conceptions, noetic conceptions are:

1. Correct in the core

2. Complete in the core

3. Internally connected their core identifies substantive connections between ’s central attributes

Suppose that planting trees doesn’t offset increased carbon caused by widespread deforestation, unless the planted trees manage to be carbon-neutral (e.g., they enter the geology or become part of a self-sustaining forest). Identifying such connections (here, centered on carbon) may be important to understanding global warming.

43

Page 44: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

Unlike other conceptions, noetic conceptions are:

1. Correct in the core

2. Complete in the core

3. Internally connected

4. Externally coherent their core coheres with their non-core, as well as with related conceptions (in particular, with conceptions of ’s central attributes themselves)

Suppose one conceives of global warming as the result of excessive carbon; at the same time, one conceives of carbon as a chemical element that is very rare and precious. This tension may impede one’s understanding of global warming. 44

Page 45: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

To summarize, noetic conceptions are:

1. Correct in the core

2. Complete in the core

3. Internally connected

4. Externally coherent

Other conditions (e.g., anti-luck) might be proposed. We demur, and in any case regard (1) - (4) as “centerpieces”.

45

Page 46: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

The Proposal, Restated

To understand is to have an internally connected and externally coherent conception of that is correct and complete in the core.

This is perfect understanding (this assumes an upper bound is coherent). There is also imperfect understanding, or degrees thereof—which are approximations of perfect understanding (this assumes some scale is coherent).

46

Page 47: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

A Comparison: Kvanvig’s proposal

“Understanding requires the grasping of explanatory and other coherence-making relationships in a large and comprehensive body of information. One can know many unrelated pieces of information, but understanding is achieved only when informational items are pieced together by the subject in question.”

—Jonathan Kvanvig, The Value of Knowledge . . . (2003, 192)

Whether this is plausible, presumably it’s not meant as an analysis. The shift from understanding to grasping is hardly an advance.

In any case, it would just move the question: what is ‘grasping’?

One can interpret our analysis as doing away with the need to appeal to ‘grasping’. Alternatively, it can be interpreted as explicating such ‘grasping’ in terms of noetic conceptions.

47

Page 48: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

This is of course just the beginning of a full theory of understanding.

If it is correct (at least in outline, even if not in detail), then explicating understanding is one important job that conceptions might do.

Analyzing wisdom and related notions is perhaps another.

48

Page 49: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

Part II: The Significance of Conceptions

§3. Wisdom, Worldview, and Related Notions

Page 50: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

Wisdom

It’s sometimes suggested that the aim of philosophy is wisdom.

If understanding is constituted by a noetic conception, then wisdom is plausibly constituted by an appropriate noetic conception—for instance, a noetic conception of the world and one’s place in it.

Call this a noetic self-world conception.

One could just be wise about this or that (domain-specific wisdom). In such a case, we can regard one as having a noetic conception of and ’s place in the world: a noetic -world conception.

We’ll focus on wisdom (full stop).

50

Page 51: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

It seems to be a platitude that the wise “see things aright”, or without illusion—things broadly construed.

This is what we intend to capture with the notion of a noetic self-world conception.

What is the precise content of such a conception? Perhaps, recalling the Tao Te Ching:

Those who say, don’t know; those who know, don’t say.

51

Page 52: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

A Comparison: Zagzebski’s Proposal

In Virtues of the Mind, Linda Zagzebski suggests thatWisdom “is a matter of grasping the whole of reality”.

Here, again, the appeal to ’grasping’ makes it difficult to regard this as an analysis (or, at least, an informative one).

As before, our approach can be interpreted as discarding ‘grasping’, or as explicating it in terms of noetic conceptions.

Our approach might also be seen as replacing ‘whole of reality’ with something slightly more focused (which takes into account the standpoint of the individual), yet equally abstract.

52

Page 53: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

Remaining at an abstract level, then:

To be wise is to have an internally connected and externally coherent conception of the world and one’s place in it that is correct and complete in the core.

This is full-blown wisdom: perfect wisdom, as it were. There are also lesser degrees of wisdom—which are, in effect, approximations of a noetic self-world conception.

53

Page 54: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

The Connection between Wisdom, Understanding, and Conceptions

Here is the Dalai Lama on the path to wisdom:

[D]efilements of the mind such as lust, hatred, jealousy, and belligerence are based on a fundamental misconception of the nature of persons and objects… In order to overcome this misconception of the nature of persons and things, you have to understand their true nature. (2002, 57)

A consciousness that conceives of [reality as having] inherent existence does not have a solid foundation. A wise consciousness, grounded in reality, understands that living beings and other phenomena—minds, bodies, buildings, and so forth—do not inherently exist. This is the wisdom of emptiness. Understanding reality exactly opposite to the misconception of inherent existence, wisdom gradually overcomes ignorance. (140)

54

Page 55: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

The Socrates Example

This approach to wisdom in terms of understanding, rather than knowledge-that, renders intelligible (without endorsing) the Oracle’s claim: Socrates was wisest because he knew he was ignorant.

In this respect, our view is like other understanding-based views. But one specific advantage of our version is that it provides a general analysis which reveals the basic “shape” of wisdom; as a result, it allows an underlying diagnosis of what’s happened in the example.

Despite his lack of knowledge-that, Socrates is being claimed to have a noetic self-world conception: viz., a conception of the world as something of which he is ignorant.

Of course, other traditions will dispute whether this specific “Socratic” conception is in fact a noetic self-world conception (recall the Dalai Lama). Our analysis makes sense of this dispute (a further advantage).55

Page 56: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

Theoretical Wisdom vs. Practical Wisdom

It might be said that while a noetic self-world conception may illuminate theoretical wisdom, it does not capture practical wisdom (this assumes a theoretical/practical distinction is coherent or compulsory).

This isn’t a problem for our approach. Practical wisdom can be analyzed as a different noetic conception.

For instance, a noetic action-oriented conception—that is, a noetic conception of how to live well.

(NB: There is a natural connection to know-how here. Elsewhere we have analyzed knowledge-how in terms of conceptions of ways of acting, which would vindicate the connection.)

56

Page 57: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

An Extension to Action

Suppose the foregoing analysis of wisdom is correct. Then we could say:

To act wisely is to act in a way that exercises a noetic action-oriented conception.

This can be seen as an instance of a more general view of intelligent action:

To act intelligently is to act in a way that exercises an appropriate noetic conception.

In this way, conceptions enable a plausible “intellectualist” view of wisdom and wise action, and of intelligence and intelligent action more generally (which we develop in other work).

57

Page 58: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

The Notion of a Worldview

By contrast with wisdom, when one has a non-noetic conception of the world, one merely has a worldview. More generally:

A worldview is a conception of the world.

Correlatively, we can say:

A selfview is a conception of oneself.

This might enable an analysis of the ordinary notion of authenticity:

To act authentically is to act in a way that exercises one’s selfview.

58

Page 59: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

Summary

A non-reductive (but not “brute”) theory of conceptions. An analysis of understanding in terms of noetic conceptions. Analyses of wisdom, worldview, and related notions also in terms of conceptions.

The core idea: conceptions are a distinctive type of entity that may illuminate understanding, and such a link between conceptions and understanding may help to illuminate wisdom and related phenomena.

59

Page 60: Conceptions,  Understanding, and Wisdom John Bengson (ANU/Wisconsin) & Marc Moffett (Wyoming)

Thanks to Chad Carmichael, Dan Korman, Anat Schechtman, Zoltan Szabo, David Sosa, Daniel Stoljar, and audience members at the SEP.

ReferencesBurge, T. 1979. Individualism and the mental. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 4: 73–122.Burge, T. 1986. Intellectual norms and foundations of mind. Journal of Philosophy, 83: 697–720.Burge, T. 2003. Concepts, conceptions, reflective understanding: Reply to Peacocke. In M. Hahn and B.T. Ramberg, eds., Reflections and replies: Essays on the philosophy of Tyler Burge. Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books. Gendler, T.S. 2000. The puzzle of imaginative resistance. The Journal of Philosophy, 97: 55–81. Gupta, A. 2006. Empiricism and experience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.His Holiness the Dalai Lama. 2002. How to Practice.Jackson, F. 1998. From metaphysics to ethics: A defence of conceptual analysis. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Kvanvig, J. 2003. The value of knowledge and the pursuit of understanding. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Peacocke, C. 1998. Implicit conceptions, understanding and rationality. Philosophical Issues, 9: 43–88.Peacocke, C. 2008. Truly understood. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Wiggins, D. 2001. Sameness and substance renewed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Zagzebski, L.T. 1996. Virtues of the mind. An inquiry into the nature of virtue and the ethical foundations of knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

60


Recommended