+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Dole - Religious Experience in Schleiermacher

Dole - Religious Experience in Schleiermacher

Date post: 11-Nov-2021
Category:
Upload: others
View: 5 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend
22
Journal of Analytic Theology, Vol. 4, May 2016 10.12978/jat.20164.001322031404a © 2016 Andrew Dole • © 2016 Journal of Analytic Theology What is ‘religious experience’ in Schleiermacher’s Dogmatics, and why does it matter? Andrew Dole Amherst College Abstract: Schleiermacher is often credited with elevating the notion of ‘religious experience’ to prominence in theology and the study of religion. But his position on religious experience is poorly understood, largely because he is typically read through the lens of his later appropriators. In this essay I make a set of claims about what ‘religious experience’ amounts to in Schleiermacher’s mature dogmatics, The Christian Faith (or Glaubenslehre). What is noteworthy about Schleiermacher’s position is its calculated coherence with religious naturalism, understood as the position that religious phenomena have natural causes. I then argue that Schleiermacher’s understanding of religious experience is actually promising for contemporary discussions– partly because it allows for productive conversation with religious naturalists, and partly in virtue of the utility of Schleiermacher’s claim regarding the kind of religious experience at the heart of Christian religious identity. 1. Clearing the ground and setting the stage My concern in this paper is with the conception of religious experience on offer in Friedrich Schleiermacher’s epochmaking work of systematic theology, Die Christliche Glaube, commonly referred to as the Glaubenslehre (‘doctrine of the faith’). It is likely that there will be a considerable distance between what I will describe as ‘religious experience’ and what has figured in many prominent discussions of the notion. The term ‘religious experience’ can be used to refer to a bewildering variety of phenomena (Wildman 2011, 7789), and it seems to me that scholarly discussions of religious experience have coalesced into a number of conversations that have some independence from each other. One important strand of conversation is centered on the “perceptual model” of religious experience on display in William Alston’s Perceiving God (1991). But a proper understanding of Schleiermacher’s conception of religious experience leads to a different conversation; and it is part of my aim in this paper to make this clear. The topic of religious experience in Schleiermacher’s dogmatics is worth revisiting for two reasons. One is that Schleiermacher is commonly cited as the figure who introduced the notion of ‘religious experience’ into the literature on both Christianity and religion in the nineteenth century; I think it interesting both to
Transcript
Page 1: Dole - Religious Experience in Schleiermacher

 Journal  of  Analytic  Theology,  Vol.  4,  May  2016  

10.12978/jat.2016-­‐4.001322031404a  ©  2016  Andrew  Dole  •  ©  2016  Journal  of  Analytic  Theology  

What   is   ‘religious   experience’   in   Schleiermacher’s  Dogmatics,  and  why  does  it  matter?    

Andrew  Dole  Amherst  College  

 Abstract:   Schleiermacher   is  often  credited  with  elevating   the  notion  of   ‘religious   experience’   to   prominence   in   theology   and   the   study   of  religion.     But   his   position   on   religious   experience   is   poorly  understood,  largely  because  he  is  typically  read  through  the  lens  of  his  later  appropriators.     In   this  essay   I  make  a   set  of   claims  about  what  ‘religious   experience’   amounts   to   in   Schleiermacher’s   mature  dogmatics,   The   Christian   Faith   (or   Glaubenslehre).     What   is  noteworthy   about   Schleiermacher’s   position   is   its   calculated  coherence  with  religious  naturalism,  understood  as   the  position   that  religious   phenomena   have   natural   causes.     I   then   argue   that  Schleiermacher’s   understanding   of   religious   experience   is   actually  promising  for  contemporary  discussions–  partly  because  it  allows  for  productive   conversation   with   religious   naturalists,   and   partly   in  virtue   of   the   utility   of   Schleiermacher’s   claim   regarding   the   kind   of  religious  experience  at  the  heart  of  Christian  religious  identity.  

     1.  Clearing  the  ground  and  setting  the  stage      

My   concern   in   this   paper   is  with   the   conception  of   religious   experience   on  offer   in  Friedrich  Schleiermacher’s  epoch-­‐making  work  of  systematic   theology,  Die  Christliche   Glaube,   commonly   referred   to   as   the   Glaubenslehre   (‘doctrine   of   the  faith’).   It   is   likely   that   there   will   be   a   considerable   distance   between   what   I   will  describe   as   ‘religious   experience’   and   what   has   figured   in   many   prominent  discussions  of   the  notion.  The  term   ‘religious  experience’  can  be  used  to  refer  to  a  bewildering  variety  of  phenomena  (Wildman  2011,  77-­‐89),  and  it  seems  to  me  that  scholarly   discussions   of   religious   experience   have   coalesced   into   a   number   of  conversations  that  have  some  independence  from  each  other.  One  important  strand  of   conversation   is   centered   on   the   “perceptual   model”   of   religious   experience   on  display   in  William   Alston’s  Perceiving  God   (1991).   But   a   proper   understanding   of  Schleiermacher’s   conception   of   religious   experience   leads   to   a   different  conversation;  and  it  is  part  of  my  aim  in  this  paper  to  make  this  clear.       The   topic   of   religious   experience   in   Schleiermacher’s   dogmatics   is   worth  revisiting   for   two   reasons.   One   is   that   Schleiermacher   is   commonly   cited   as   the  figure  who  introduced  the  notion  of  ‘religious  experience’  into  the  literature  on  both  Christianity   and   religion   in   the   nineteenth   century;   I   think   it   interesting   both   to  

Page 2: Dole - Religious Experience in Schleiermacher

What  is  ‘religious  experience’  in  Schleiermacher’s  Dogmatics,  and  why  does  it  matter?    Andrew  Dole    

 45

compare  his  mature  position  on   this   topic  with   the  positions   of   those  who  would  later  claim  to  have  been  inspired  by  him  and  to  trace  the  history  of  the  development  of  those  positions  by  means  of  a  series  of  departures  from  his.  And  the  second  is  that  I   actually   think   that   Schleiermacher’s   conception   of   religious   experience   can   be  made   relevant   for   contemporary   projects   that   have   to   do   with   the   future   of  Christianity.1  To  set   the  stage   for  my   later  expansion  on   this  claim,   let  me   identify  one  point  in  recent  (for  some  values  of  that  term)  history  that  I  claim  as  evidence  for  the   existence   of   a   ‘Schleiermacherian   tradition’—one   that   understands  Schleiermacher  correctly,  or  nearly  so—of  reflection  on  religious  experience:    

Religious   experience   is   ‘the   whole   experience   of   religious   persons’,  constituting  an  awareness  of  God  acting  toward  them  in  and  through  the   events   of   their   lives   and   of   world   history,   the   interpretative  element  within  which  awareness   is  the  cognitive  aspect  of   faith.  And  distinctively  Christian  experience,   as   a   form  of   this,   is   the   Christian’s  seeing  of  Christ  as  his  ‘Lord  and  Saviour’,  together  with  the  pervasive  recreative  effects  of  this  throughout  his   life,   transforming  the  quality  of   his   experience   and   determining   his   responses   to   other   people.  Christian  faith  is  thus  a  distinctive  consciousness  of  the  world  and  of  one’s   existence   within   it,   radiating   from   and   illuminated   by   a  consciousness  of  God  in  Christ.  (Hick  2010,  245)      

  This   passage   is   drawn   from   John   Hick’s   Evil   and   the   God   of   Love,   first  published  in  1966.  I  will  return  to  this  passage  in  my  conclusion.      2.  Brief  remarks  on  reception-­‐history       Having   indicated   that   I   think   the   reception-­‐history   of   Schleiermacher’s  conception  of  religious  experience  is  interesting,  I  will  not  offer  more  than  a  sketch  of  that  history  here.  Here  are  three  quick  claims  that  will  have  to  suffice  to  cover  the  necessary  ground.       First:   Schleiermacher’s   reputation   as   a   prominent   theorist   of   religious  experience  had  been  established  fairly   firmly  by  the  end  of   the   first  quarter  of   the  twentieth   century.   The   author   who   bears   most   of   the   responsibility   for   this  development   is   Rudolf   Otto,   who   in   1899   presided   over   a   new   edition   of   1  Before  proceeding,  I  want  to  contextualize  this  statement.  It  is  unusual  for  me  to  argue  for  a  contemporary  application  of  Schleiermacher’s  theology;  my  work  on  him  to  date  has  mostly  taken  the  form  of  rational  reconstruction.  And  I  am,  I  would  guess,  at  least  as  impatient  as  you  are  with  claims  to  the  effect  that  some  theological  position  buried  deep  in  the  historical  record  is  the  key  to  escaping  from  whatever  predicament  theology  finds  itself  in  at  the  moment.  The  applications  I  will  venture  at  the  close  of  this  essay  are  not  geared  towards  facilitating  more  and  better  textual  productions  by  academic  theologians.  Rather,  I  have  my  eye  on  the  same  phenomenon  as  did  Schleiermacher:  the  fortunes  of  Christian  religious  communities  in  the  present  and  foreseeable  future.  

Page 3: Dole - Religious Experience in Schleiermacher

What  is  ‘religious  experience’  in  Schleiermacher’s  Dogmatics,  and  why  does  it  matter?    Andrew  Dole    

 46

Schleiermacher’s   youthful   Speeches   on   Religion,   and   who   in   1917   published   Das  Heilige,  a  best-­‐selling  book  that  credited  Schleiermacher  for  anticipating  Otto’s  own  conception  of   ‘numinous  experience’.  Perhaps  equally  influential  for  at  least  a  time  and   in   certain   spheres   was   Emil   Brunner’s   1924   book   Die   Mystik   und   das  Wort,  which   characterized   Schleiermacher’s   theological   position   as   above   all   ‘mystical,’  and  attributed  to  him  the  position  that  God  is  available  to  human  consciousness  via  introspection,   in  virtue  of  the  immanence  of  God  in  the  human  soul  (Helmer  2013,  23).     Second:   later   in   the   twentieth   century,   both   Brunner’s   description   of  Schleiermacher  as  a  proponent  of   ‘mysticism’   in  theology  and  Otto’s  positioning  of  Schleiermacher  as  his  intellectual  predecessor  seem  to  have  been  widely  accepted  in  the  English-­‐language  literature.  By  1975,  for  example,  Eric  Sharpe  could  cite  without  dissent   Otto’s   depiction   of   a   tradition   running   “from   Luther   passing   through   the  Pietists  to  Schleiermacher  and  Fries”  defined  by  commitment  to  the  “the  essence  of  religion  as  consisting  in  a  type  of  immediate,  almost  intuitive  apprehension  of  Deity”  in  his  widely   influential  Comparative  Religion:  a  History   (1975,  164).  And  with   the  rise   of   attacks   on   ‘experiential’   or   phenomenological   approaches   to   the   study   of  religion—as,   for   example,   in   Wayne   Proudfoot’s   Religious   Experience   of   1985—Schleiermacher   was   singled   out   as   the   archetypal   theorist   of   approaches   that  postulate  as  the  defining  feature  of  all  religion  as  such  a  unique  and  irreducible  kind  of  experience  knowable,  properly  speaking,  only   through  direct  acquaintance.  And  so  it  came  to  pass  in  the  fullness  of  time  that  Alston  could,  on  Proudfoot’s  authority,  classify   Schleiermacher   as   “the   fountainhead   of   concentration   on   religious  experience  in  the  study  of  religion”  (1991,  p.  16  n.  5).     And  third:   there   is  a  story   that   to  my  knowledge  has  not  yet  been  properly  told   about   the   interval   between   Schleiermacher   and   Otto.   That   story   is   one   of  progressive   changes   in   the   way   Schleiermacher   was   understood   and   of   shifting  priorities  in  German  theology.  It  is  a  story  of  the  failure  of  Schleiermacher’s  call  for  an  ‘eternal  covenant’  between  religious  faith  and  scientific  inquiry  to  stem  the  tide  of   attempts   to   erect   protective   barriers   around   the   Christian   faith   by   theologians  and   politicians   (who,   it   must   be   remembered,   enjoyed   significant   control   over  academic   appointments).   It   is   the   story   of   the   eventual   construal   of   Christian  religious  experience  as  something  flatly  inaccessible  to  kinds  of  scrutiny  that  might  threaten  its  ability  to  ground  and  validate  Christian  faith.  And  it   is  the  story  of  the  stages   by   which   Schleiermacher’s   strenuous   protestations   against   theological  defensiveness   were   forgotten,   such   that   a   highly   selective   memory   of   his  contributions  could  be  appropriated  for  projects  such  as  Otto’s.  The  best  work  that  approaches   this   topic  with  which   I   am   familiar   is  Brent  Sockness’s  monograph  on  the   disputes   between   Wilhelm   Herrmann   and   Ernst   Troeltsch   over   historicism,  apologetics,  and  the  legacy  of  Schleiermacher  (1998).  But  there  is  more  to  the  story,  involving   as   it   does   the   advance   from   strength   to   strength   of   reactionary   ‘neo-­‐pietism’  both  before  and  after  the  revolutionary  year  1848,  and  the  fortunes  of  those  of   Schleiermacher’s   followers   such   as   Karl   Rudoph   Hagenbach,   Adolf   Hilgenfend,  

Page 4: Dole - Religious Experience in Schleiermacher

What  is  ‘religious  experience’  in  Schleiermacher’s  Dogmatics,  and  why  does  it  matter?    Andrew  Dole    

 47

and  other  defenders  of  ‘mediating’  or  wissenschaftlich  theology  as  Prussia  slouched  towards  power  and  catastrophe.2      3.  Parameters   for  a  discussion  of   ‘religious  experience’   in  the  Glaubenslehre      

In   this   section   I   want   to   call   attention   to   two   broad   characteristics   of  Schleiermacher’s   mature   work   of   dogmatic   theology,   translated   as   The   Christian  Faith  (in  the  original,  Die  Christliche  Glaube,  nach  den  Grundsätzen  der  Evangelischen  Kirche   im  Zusammenhange  dargestellt).3  Schleiermacher   published   the   first   edition  in   two   volumes   in   1820-­‐21,   and   the   second   and   final   edition   in   1830-­‐31.   The  contents  of  this  work  owe  much  to  Schleiermacher’s  several  decades  as  a  lecturer  on  dogmatics   at   the   University   of   Berlin;   they   are   also   profoundly   shaped,   in   ways  described   by   Schleiermacher   himself,   by   his   sense   of   the   place   of   Christianity   in  modern  intellectual  life.     First:   the   fact   that   Schleiermacher’s   Glaubenslehre   is   a   work   of   dogmatics  matters   for   understanding   the   sorts   of   claims   that   it   makes.   The   project   of  dogmatics,  as  Schleiermacher  understood  it,  is  to  gather  together,  work  over,  and  re-­‐present   the   entire   range   of   Christian   doctrines   as   these   are   represented   in   the  contemporary  life  of  a  particular  range  of  Christian  community  (for  Schleiermacher,  the   range   comprising   the   Lutheran   and   Reformed   wings   of   Protestantism).  Dogmatics   aims   at   completeness   and   systematicity:   it   aims   at   a   comprehensive  overview   of   distinctively   Christian   doctrines,   and   aims   to   forge   coherence   among  the   various   doctrines   that   make   up   the   Christian   faith.   Schleiermacher’s   central  device  for  working  over  Christian  doctrines  was  to  evaluate  their  relationship  to  the  ‘essence   of   Christianity,’   the   conviction   that   “redemption   has   been   universally  accomplished   in   Jesus  of  Nazareth,”  and   to   (although  Schleiermacher  does  not  use  this  terminology  in  the  Glaubenslehre)  the  essence  of  religion  in  general,  the  ‘feeling  of  absolute  dependence.’  Schleiermacher’s  procedure  was  to  reject  any  formulation  of  a  Christian  doctrine  that  conflicts  with  either  of  these  essences  (for  example,  by  implying   that   human   dependence   on  God   is   not   absolute,   or   by   implying   that   the  redemption  wrought  through  Jesus  is  incomplete  or  partial),  and  where  necessary,  to   propose   interpretations   of   doctrines   fully   compatible   with   these.  What   results  from  this  work  is  a  set  of  claims,  spelled  out  in  considerable  detail,  regarding  what  should   be   regarded   as   the   official   teachings   of   the   traditions   in   question,   which  deserve  to  be  regarded  as  authentic  in  virtue  of  their  coherence  with  the  essence  of  Christianity.     So  understood,   the  project  of  dogmatics   is  a  bounded  one:   the  project   is   to  say  how  much,  or  what  interpretation  of,  received  doctrines  should  be  regarded  as   2  See  (Bigler  1972),  (Howard  2006).  3  Hereafter  (Schleiermacher  1999)  refers  to  the  German  original  and  (Schleiermacher  1989)  to  the  English  translation.    Where  references  are  to  the  German  original  translations  are  my  own;  otherwise  translations  are  those  of  Mackintosh  et  al.  

Page 5: Dole - Religious Experience in Schleiermacher

What  is  ‘religious  experience’  in  Schleiermacher’s  Dogmatics,  and  why  does  it  matter?    Andrew  Dole    

 48

proper  to  a  tradition’s  distinctive  faith.  Dogmatics  is  thus  concerned  with  discerning  the  common  faith  of  a  particular  strand  of  the  Christian  tradition;  it  is  not  a  species  of  metaphysics,  a  ‘science  of  God,’  a  form  of  inquiry  that  aims  to  discern  what  is  the  case   regarding  God   and  God’s   relationship   to   human  beings.   So,   in   reconstructing  the   Glaubenslehre’s   position   on   religious   experience   I   do   not   take   myself   to   be  reconstructing  an  account  of  what  sorts  of  religious  experience  is  possible  or  actual,  but   rather   an   account   of   what   sort   of   religious   experience   religious   persons  (Lutheran   and  Reformed  Protestants   specifically)   should   regard   as  proper  to  their  particular  form  of  faith.       Second:   in   Schleiermacher’s   hands,   dogmatics   aspires   to   be   a   resource   for  church  leadership  (Kirchenleitung),  or  the  project  of  supervising  and  guiding  the  life  of  church  communities.  As  such,  dogmatics  ought  to  be  shaped  by  the  dogmatician’s  conception   of   the   current   state   of   the   relationship   between   Christianity   and   the  wider  world.   In  open   letters   to  his   friend  Gottfried  C.F.  Lücke  published  alongside  the   second   edition   of   the   Glaubenslehre,   Schleiermacher   opined   that   the   only  dogmatics   that  would   “adequately  meet   the  needs  of  our   time”  would  be  one   that  adheres   to   “an  eternal   covenant  between   the   living  Christian   faith  and  completely  free,  independent  scientific  inquiry,”  and  declared  his  work  dedicated  to  this  project  (1981,  64).     Interpreters   of   Schleiermacher   have   not   always   agreed   in   their  interpretations   of   this   ‘eternal   covenant.’   Perhaps   the   most   common   reading   has  read  Schleiermacher   as   calling   for   a   ‘nonagression  pact’   or   ‘separation  of   spheres’  between   religion   and   science.   I   have   elsewhere   argued   against   this   ‘segregation  model’   of   Schleiermacher’s   eternal   covenant,   largely   because   I   cannot   see   how  an  arrangement   that   is  supposed  to  allow  for  “completely   free,   independent  scientific  inquiry”  can  at  the  same  time  declare  religion  off-­‐limits  to  scientific  investigations.  I  favor   a   reading   according   to   which   it   is   the   duty   of   the   dogmatician   to   avoid  “entanglements  with  science”  by,  simply,  refraining  from  making  claims  known  to  or  likely   to   conflict   with   the   deliverances   of   the   sciences   (Dole   2010a,   144).   I  understand   Schleiermacher   to   have   aimed   to   avoid   such   entanglements   in   his  dogmatics  partly  by  adhering   to  a  policy  of  determined  anti-­‐supernaturalism  with  respect  to  the  course  of  events  in  the  world:  that  is,  to  a  policy  according  to  which  Christian  dogmatics  does  not  advance,  as  part  of  the  common  faith  of  the  traditions  to   and   for  which   it   aims   to   speak,   any   claims   to   the   effect   that  natural   events   are  caused  by  the  interposition  of  supernatural  forces  on  the  natural  order.       I  take  this  reading  to  be  strongly  supported  by  any  number  of  passages  from  The   Christian   Faith;   for   the   present   I   will   refer   to   three.   First,   in   discussing   the  question   of   miracles   Schleiermacher   concluded   that   “the   general   interests   of  science…  and   the   interests  of   religion  seem  to  meet  at   the  same  point,   i.e.   that  we  should  abandon  the  idea  of  the  absolutely  supernatural  because  no  single  instance  of  it  can  be  known  by  us,  and  we  are  nowhere  required  to  recognize  it”  (1989,  §47.3,  183).  Second,  in  discussing  the  question  of  whether  the  vitality  of  religious  feeling  is  threatened  by  a  view  of  human  beings  as  thoroughly  embedded  in  the  natural  causal  order,  he  argued  that  “the  religious  feeling  is  not  destroyed  even  by  the  completest  confidence  with  which  we  accept   this   or   that   explanation”  of   the  phenomena   that  stimulate   it,   and   that  while   it   is   certainly   “an   expedient   often   adopted   by   human  

Page 6: Dole - Religious Experience in Schleiermacher

What  is  ‘religious  experience’  in  Schleiermacher’s  Dogmatics,  and  why  does  it  matter?    Andrew  Dole    

 49

indolence  to  attribute  what  is  not  understood  to  the  supernatural  immediately…  this  does  not  at  all  belong  to  the  tendency  to  piety”  (1989,  §46.1,  172).  And,  third,  later  in  this  same  discussion  he  remarked  that  “It  has  always  been  acknowledged  by  the  strictest   dogmaticians   that   divine   preservation,   as   the   absolute   dependence   of   all  events  and  changes  on  God,  and  natural  causation  as  the  complete  determination  of  everything   that   occurs   by   the   general   Naturzusammenhang   [interconnection   of  nature],   are   one   and   the   same   thing   simply   from   different   points   of   view”   (1989,  §46.2,  174).       There  are  nuances  to  Schleiermacher’s  position  that  are  subtler  than  what  I  have   indicated   here.   But   for   present   purposes,   the   upshot   of   Schleiermacher’s  ‘eternal   covenant’   is   that  a  conception  of   religious  experience   that   finds  a  place   in  Schleiermacher’s  dogmatics   can  be  expected  not   to   involve   reference   to   the  direct  causal  activity  of  God  or  of  other  supernatural  beings:  religious   experience  will  be  natural  experience,  in  the  sense  of  being  naturally  caused.       Before   proceeding,   I   want   to   quickly   note   that   the   existing   translation   of  Schleiermacher’s   dogmatics   obscures   the   details   of   his   discussion   of   religious  experience  for  interesting  reasons.  As  I  have  noted  elsewhere,  sections  32-­‐61  of  the  text  were   translated  by  Walter  Matthews  and  Edith  Sandbach  Marshall.  Matthews  and  Marshall  favored  the  term  ‘religious  experience’  as  an  occasional  rendering  for  a  variety  of  terms  that  Schleiermacher  used  in  a  technical  sense:  fromme  Erregungen  (‘pious   emotions’),   fromme   Momenten   (‘pious   moments’),   and   fromme  Lebensmomenten  (‘pious  life-­‐moments’).  I  regard  this  choice  as  an  unfortunate  one,  as   I   think   a   more   literal   rendering   of   these   terms   of   Schleiermacher’s   does   not  unduly  burden  the  reader;  and  I  believe  the  choice  to  be  the  product  of  the  influence  of  Rudolf  Otto’s  The  Idea  of  the  Holy,  as  there  is  good  evidence  that  both  Matthews  and   Sandbach   were   partial   to   Otto   (Dole   2010b,   458).   The   result   is   that   the  translation   is   simply   not   a   reliable   guide   for   one   in   search   of   Schleiermacher’s  understanding  of  religious  experience.      4.  Religious  Experience  in  the  Glaubenslehre       In  this  section  I  want  to  make  two  claims,  one  negative,  and  one  positive.  The  negative   claim   is   that   there   is   in   the   Glaubenslehre   no   account   of   ‘religious  experience’   in   the   sense   of   an   experience   that   is   common   to   all   religions.   The  positive   claim   is   that   Schleiermacher   does   place   an   experience   at   the   heart   of   his  account  of  Christianity:   the  experience  of  redemption  by  Jesus.   It   is   this   latter   that   I  think   constitutes   the   ‘religious   experience’   that   is   on   offer   in   Schleiermacher’s  dogmatics.     My   negative   claim   is   not   a   trivial   one.   For   in   the   Glaubenslehre  Schleiermacher   argued,   famously,   that   all   religion   is   grounded   in   a   “feeling   of  absolute   dependence”;   and   if   the   feeling   of   absolute   dependence   is   an   experience,  then  there   is   indeed  a  distinctive  kind  of   ‘religious  experience’  at   the  ground  of  all  religions.    

Page 7: Dole - Religious Experience in Schleiermacher

What  is  ‘religious  experience’  in  Schleiermacher’s  Dogmatics,  and  why  does  it  matter?    Andrew  Dole    

 50

  Schleiermacher   introduces   the   feeling   of   absolute   dependence   (das  schlechthinniger   Abhängigkeitsgefühl)   in   §4   of   the   Glaubenslehre.   This   feeling   is  presented   in   the   train   of   discussion   of   the   “feeling   of   freedom”   and   the   simple  “feeling  of  dependence,”  which  Schleiermacher  understood   to  be   feelings  of  acting  upon   and   being   acted   upon   respectively.   He   categorizes   these   feelings   not   as  distinctive  forms  of  experience  but  as  “commonalities”  (Gemeinsamen)  among  active  and   receptive   determinations   of   self-­‐consciousness   (Bestimmtheiten   des  Selbstbewußtseins)   (1999,   §4.2,   25).   Thus   the   ‘feeling   of   freedom’   is   the   common  element  of  all  states  of  mind  in  which  I  am  aware  of  being  active,  and  the  ‘feeling  of  dependence’   is   the   common   element   of   all   states   of  mind   in  which   I   am   aware   of  myself  as  receptive  or  acted  upon.     Schleiermacher   accompanies   his   introduction   of   the   feeling   of   absolute  dependence  with   two   important   claims.   First,   this   feeling   does   not   constitute   any  moments  of  self-­‐consciousness,  but  rather  accompanies  such  moments.  And  second,  the  content  of  this  feeling  can  be  expressed  in  propositional  form,  such  that  it  can  be  described  not  only  as  a  ‘feeling  of’  but  a  ‘consciousness  that.’      

…a  feeling  of  absolute  dependence,  strictly  speaking,  cannot  exist  in  a  single  moment  as  such,  because  such  a  moment  is  always  determined,  as  regards  its  total  content,  by  what  is  given,  and  thus  by  that  towards  which  we  have  a  feeling  of  freedom.  But  the  self-­‐consciousness  which  accompanies  all  of  our  self-­‐activity,  and  therefore  …  accompanies  our  whole   existence   (Dasein),   and   negates   absolute   freedom,   is   itself  precisely   a   consciousness   of   absolute   dependence;   for   it   is   the  consciousness  that  our  entire  self-­‐activity  comes  to  us  from  elsewhere  (von  anderwärts  her  ist)…  .  (1989,  §4.3,  16)  

    As  I  understand  this  section  of  the  Glaubenslehre,  Schleiermacher  argues  that  ‘feelings’   of   freedom,   dependence,   and   absolute   dependence   are   aspects   or  components  of  experience  rather   than  distinct  kinds  of  experience.  One  never   feels  oneself   to  be   free   simpliciter;   rather,   one   feels   oneself   to  be   free   inasmuch  as   one  feels  oneself  to  be  acting  upon  things  other  than  oneself,  and  the  specific  content  of  the   ‘feeling   of   freedom’   is   identifiable   only   by   way   of   abstraction   from   the  particulars  of  actual  experience.  In  the  same  way,  the  specific  content  of  the  feeling  of  absolute  dependence  is   identifiable  only  by  way  of  abstraction  from  experience;  one  never  experiences  absolute  dependence  simpliciter.       In   the   abstract   of   §4   Schleiermacher   describes   the   feeling   of   absolute  dependence   as   the   Gemeinsam   of   all   “expressions   of   piety,”   and   identifies  consciousness   of   absolute   dependence  with   consciousness   of   “being   in   relation   to  God.”   Both   of   these   claims   require   comment.   In   developing   the   latter   claim  Schleiermacher  makes  it  clear  that  he  means  the  term  ‘God’  to  refer  to  that  on  which  we  are  absolutely  dependent:  “in  the  first  instance  God  signifies  for  us  that  which  is  the  co-­‐determinant  in  this  feeling  and  to  which  we  trace  our  being  in  such  a  state.”  With   this  meaning   of   the   term   ‘God’   established,   Schleiermacher   unpacks   the   two  claims  in  the  abstract:    

Page 8: Dole - Religious Experience in Schleiermacher

What  is  ‘religious  experience’  in  Schleiermacher’s  Dogmatics,  and  why  does  it  matter?    Andrew  Dole    

 51

The   feeling   of   absolute   dependence   becomes   a   clear   consciousness  only  as  this  idea  [of  God]  becomes  such.  In  this  sense  it  can  indeed  be  said   that   God   is   given   to   us   in   feeling   in   an   original  way;   and   if  we  speak  of  an  original  revelation  of  God  to  man  or  in  man,  the  meaning  will   always   be   just   this,   that,   along   with   the   absolute   dependence  which  characterizes  not  only  man  but  all  temporal  existence,  there  is  given   to   man   also   the   immediate   self-­‐consciousness   of   it,   which  becomes   a   consciousness   of   God.   In  whatever  measure   this   actually  takes   place   during   the   temporal   course   of   a   personality,   in   just   that  measure  do  we  ascribe  piety  to  the  individual.  On  the  other  hand,  any  givenness  (Gegebensein)  of  God  is  entirely  excluded,  because  anything  that   is   outwardly   given   must   be   given   as   the   object   of   counter-­‐influence,  however  slight.  (1999,  §4.4,  30)  

    So,  Schleiermacher’s  dogmatics  denies  the  possibility  of  God’s  being  given  in  experience,   on   the   grounds   that   the   source   of   absolute   dependence   could   not   be  internal   to   the   Zusammenhang   that   comprises   the   sensory   realm.   What  Schleiermacher   calls   ‘God-­‐consciousness’   develops   out   of   an   awareness   of   the  feeling  of  absolute  dependence.  God-­‐consciousness  is  a  matter  of  reflective  thought  concerning  that  on  which  we  feel  ourselves  to  be  absolutely  dependent,  i.e.  God;  and  piety   is   a   matter   of   having   God-­‐consciousness,   i.e.   a   matter   of   being   reflectively  aware  of  one’s  absolute  dependence  and  in  some  way  mindful  concerning  its  source  (or  more   precisely,   concerning  whatever   its   source  might   be).   As   Schleiermacher  puts   the   point   later,   “We   really   have   a   relationship   to   God   only   in   our   quiescent  (ruhend)   self-­‐consciousness,   as   it   holds   itself   fast   in   reflective   thought,   and   only  insofar  as  God-­‐consciousness  is  co-­‐posited  within  it”  (1999  vol.  2,  §107.1,  150).     The   feeling  of   absolute  dependence,   then,   is  not   an  experience  or   a  kind  of  experience.   It   is  a  component  of  experience—not   just   ‘religious  experience,’  but   in  fact   all   experience.4  What   distinguishes   ‘pious   life-­‐moments’   or   ‘pious   states   of  mind’  from  their  non-­‐pious  counterparts  is  not  they  are  grounded  in  a  specific  kind  of   experience,   but   that   they   are   characterized   by   a   distinct   kind   of   awareness   or  mindfulness   regarding   a   conceptually   distinguishable   component   of   experience   as  such—regarding,  that  is,  the  feeling  of  absolute  dependence.      This   conclusion  notwithstanding,   Schleiermacher   does   have   a   robust   place  for  appeals  to  experience  in  his  dogmatics,  as  can  be  seen  from  his  clear  statement,  at   the   beginning   of   the   second  doctrinal   section   of   the  Glaubenslehre,   that   “in   our  presentation   all   proper   doctrines   must   be   taken   from   Christian   pious   self-­‐consciousness,  or  from  the  inner  experience  (innere  Erfahrung)  of  Christians”  (1999  §64.1,  348).   I  proceed  now  to  my  positive  claim:   that  Schleiermacher  describes  an   4  In  §33  Schleiermacher  argues  that  one  cannot  understand  the  feeling  of  absolute  dependence  in  the  manner  he  has  described  it  and  also  maintain  that  “it  may  or  may  not  emerge  in  a  man’s  existence  (Dasein)  according  to  whether,  in  the  course  of  his  life,  he  encounters  this  or  that.  For  its  appearance  does  not  depend  at  all  upon  the  fact  that  something  specific  is  outwardly  given  to  a  partially  developed  subject,  but  only  on  the  fact  that  the  sensory  self-­‐consciousness  is  somehow  stimulated  from  without”  (1999,  §33.1,  175).  

Page 9: Dole - Religious Experience in Schleiermacher

What  is  ‘religious  experience’  in  Schleiermacher’s  Dogmatics,  and  why  does  it  matter?    Andrew  Dole    

 52

“experience  of  redemption  by  Jesus,”  and  that  it  is  this  that  deserves  to  be  regarded  as  the  ‘religious  experience’  on  offer  in  the  Glaubenslehre.     I  will  structure  my  exposition  of  Schleiermacher’s  ‘experience  of  redemption  by   Jesus’   as   responses   to   three   questions.   First:  what   does   the   term   ‘redemption’  mean   in   the   context   of   Schleiermacher’s   dogmatic   system?   Second:   what   is   the  phenomenal   content   of   the   experience   of   redemption   by   Jesus,   as   far   as   we   can  gather  this  from  Schleiermacher’s  description?  And  third:  what  does  this  experience  owe  to  the  environments  in  which  it  occurs?      

1.   Schleiermacher   introduces   ‘redemption’   in  §11  as  a   term  accepted  by  all  Christians  to  describe  the  central   task  accomplished  by  Jesus.  He  accepts  an   initial  understanding  of  the  term  as  referring  to  “a  passage  from  an  evil  condition,  which  is  represented  as  a  state  of  captivity  or  constraint,  into  a  better  condition—this  is  the  passive  side  of  it.  But  it  also  signifies  the  help  that  is  given  in  that  process  by  some  other   person,   and   this   is   the   active   side   of   it”   (1989,   §11.2,   54).   His   detailed  discussion  of  redemption  involves  offering  accounts,  in  turn,  of  the  ‘evil  condition’  at  issue  and  of  the  activity  of  Jesus  in  delivering  Christians  from  this  condition.  The  evil  condition—what   Schleiermacher   eventually   identifies   with   the   terms   ‘sin’,  ‘alienation  from  God’,  and  ‘turning  away  from  God’  (1989  §62-­‐3,  259-­‐64)—is  in  his  terminology   ‘God-­‐forgetfulness.’   God-­‐forgetfulness   is   an   “obstruction”   of   God-­‐consciousness:  “we  can  only  designate  this  as  an  absence  of  facility  for  introducing  the   God-­‐consciousness   into   the   course   of   our   actual   lives   and   retaining   it   there”  (1989  §11.2,  45).  In  the  course  of  his  discussion  of  the  “consciousness  of  sin”  in  the  second   doctrinal   section   Schleiermacher   argues   that   Christians  must   regard   God-­‐forgetfulness   as   a   “derangement   of   our   nature”   and   that   it   is   a   cause   of   pain   and  suffering.  Thus  if  the  condition  of  the  one  who  possesses  perfect  God-­‐consciousness  is   the   state   of   Seligkeit   (‘blessedness’),   the   state   of   the   person   subject   to   God-­‐forgetfulness   is   the   state   of   Unseligkeit   (rendered   ‘misery’   in   the   English  translation).     Redemption  (Erlösung),  then,  is  the  overcoming  of  ‘God-­‐forgetfulness’,  or  the  restoration   of   the   ability   to   integrate   God-­‐consciousness   into   one’s   life.   The  mechanism  of  redemption  is  the  influence  upon  the  person  of  Jesus’s   ‘perfect  God-­‐consciousness’,  which  influence  comes  to  bear   in  the  course  of  participation  in  the  life  of  Christian  community:  “In  this  corporate  life  which  goes  back  to  the  influence  of   Jesus,   redemption   is   effected  by  Him   through   the   communication  of  His   sinless  perfection”  (1989,  §88,  361).  Thus  “the  new  life  of  each  individual  springs  from  that  of  the  community,  while  the  life  of  the  community  springs  from  no  other  individual  life  than  that  of  the  Redeemer”  (1989,  §113.1,  525).     I   will   not   defend   Schleiermacher’s   account   of   redemption   as   a   plausible  rendering  of  that  notion  as  it  has  figured  in  the  life  of  the  Christian  traditions.  I  take  Schleiermacher’s  theology  to  be,  here  as  elsewhere,  radically  revisionary.   I   think  it  possible   to   make   use   of   Schleiermacher’s   conception   of   distinctively   Christian  experience  without   accepting   his   claim   that   redemption   just   is   the   overcoming   of  God-­‐forgetfulness;  but  I  have  neither  the  space  nor  the  need  to  develop  that  position  here.    

Page 10: Dole - Religious Experience in Schleiermacher

What  is  ‘religious  experience’  in  Schleiermacher’s  Dogmatics,  and  why  does  it  matter?    Andrew  Dole    

 53

2.  What  phenomenal  content  does  Schleiermacher  ascribe  to  the  experience  of   redemption?   That   is,   what   is   it   like   to   experience   redemption?   Schleiermacher  makes  no  references  to  “hearts  strangely  warmed,”  disembodied  voices,  or  visions  of   opening   heavens   in   his   various   references   to   this   experience.   In   fact   he  dramatically   under-­‐describes   the   phenomenal   content   of   the   experience,   instead  offering  a  higher-­‐level  description  that,  I  think,  could  be  realized  in  a  wide  variety  of  ways.   On   my   reading—particularly   of   Schleiermacher’s   discussion   in   §§86-­‐88,  where  the  topic  is  the  “explication  of  the  consciousness  of  grace,”  two  elements  are  common  to  the  varieties  of  this  experience.  The  first  (and,  I  think,  core)  element  is  “approximation   to  blessedness”—or   in  other  words,   the  experience  of  particularly  powerful   God-­‐consciousness   in   particular   moments,   in   which   as   a   result   the  Unseligkeit  of  God-­‐forgetfulness  is  (partially)  removed.  And  the  second  element  is  an  association  of   these   approximations   to  blessedness  with   the   influence  of   religious  community   in   its   remembrances   of   Jesus.   The   combination   of   these   two   elements  yields   a   general   description   of   the   phenomenal   content   of   the   experience   of  redemption:   it   is   the  experience  of  a  previously  unknown  and  unavailable  degree  of  mindfulness   of   God   in   virtue   of   one’s   participation   in   religious   community’s  remembrances  of  Jesus.     The  clearest  textual  support  for  this  reconstruction  is  found,  I  think,   in  §87,  the   Grundsatz   or   leading   proposition   of   which   reads,   “We   are   conscious   of   all  approximations  to  the  state  of  blessedness  which  occur  in  the  Christian  life  as  being  grounded  in  a  new  divinely-­‐effected  corporate  life,  which  works  in  opposition  to  the  corporate   life   of   sin   and   the   Unseligkeit   which   develops   in   it”   (1989,   §87,   358).  Schleiermacher’s  initial  remarks  on  this  statement  refine  the  claim  in  the  direction  of  my  reconstruction:    

This  proposition  does  not  yet  appear   to  be  a  complete  expression  of  specifically   Christian   piety,   since   it   does   not   yet   specify   that   every  approximation   to   the   state   of   blessedness   essentially   contains   a  relation   to   Christ.   But   it   does   undeniably   express   the   content   of   the  consciousness   of   divine   grace,   insofar   as   it   is   opposed   to   the  consciousness   of   sin.   For   approximation   to   the   condition   of  blessedness  is  the  real  opposite  of  Unseligkeit,  and  this  approximation  is  accepted  as  divine  grace  in  the  same  sense  and  degree  in  which  the  corporate   life   in   which   such   moments   become   ours   is   posited  (gesetzt)  as  divinely  effected.  Consequently  all  further  development  of  what  is  specifically  Christian  can  easily  be  attached  to  our  proposition.  (Schleiermacher  1989,  §87.1,  358f.)    

  I  draw  three  conclusions  from  these  remarks.  The  first  is  that  Schleiermacher  thinks   that  any  moment   in  which  a  Christian  experiences  particularly   strong  God-­‐consciousness—any   ‘approximation   to   blessedness’—will   also   contain   some  reference  or  connection  to  Jesus;  I  will  return  to  this  topic  below.  The  second  is  that  the  state  of  affairs  of  the  ‘new  corporate  life’—that  is,  the  Christian  tradition—being  divinely  effected  is  not  something  that  is,  as  it  were,  part  of  the  phenomenal  content  of   the   experience   of   grace.   Rather,   Schleiermacher   describes   this   claim   as   a  

Page 11: Dole - Religious Experience in Schleiermacher

What  is  ‘religious  experience’  in  Schleiermacher’s  Dogmatics,  and  why  does  it  matter?    Andrew  Dole    

 54

postulate,   acceptance   of   which   is   a   necessary   condition   for   accepting  ‘approximations   to   blessedness’   as   instances   of   grace   (not,   nota   bene,   for  experiencing  these  in  the  first  place).  And  the  third  is  that  if  the  ascription  to  divine  agency  is  something  posited  rather  than  directly  experienced,  Schleiermacher  does  seem  to  want  to  claim  in  the  leading  proposition  that  the  state  of  affairs  of  individual  blessedness   being   caused   by   participation   in   religious   community   is   directly  experienced.   I   admit   that   I  may   be  wrong   about   this   last   claim,   as   in  many   cases  Schleiermacher  ascribes  content  to  Bewußtsein  that  are  clearly  not  derived  directly  from  experience;  but  this  seems  to  be  a  case  where  he  associates  “consciousness  of”  with  “experience  of.”     An  important  question  that  I  have  not  yet  addressed  is  this:  to  what  extent  is  the   connection   to   Jesus   that   Schleiermacher   claims   is   essential   to   ‘pious   life-­‐moments’   registered   in   the  phenomenal   content  of   the  experience  of   redemption?  Or  more  pointedly,   is   the  state  of  affairs  of  redemption’s  being  due  to  the  activity  of  Jesus   something   that   Christians   directly   experience   when   they   experience  redemption  by  Jesus?  I  think  the  correct  answer  to  this  question  is  a  negative  one.  But  an  argument  for  this  answer  will  require  discussion  of  the  third  question  of  this  section  of  my  paper,  to  which  I  now  turn.    

3.  The  experience  of  redemption  owes  a  great  deal  to  the  context  in  which  it  occurs;  and   it   is  not  difficult   to  see  this.  The  key  to  my  argument   in   this  section   is  Schleiermacher’s   position   on   the   ‘work   of   Christ’   and   the   role   played   by   religious  community  in  this  work.  And  the  core  of  that  position  is  Schleiermacher’s  claim  that  Jesus’s  influence  proceeds  exclusively  through  historical  (i.e.  natural)  means.  That  is,  in   line  with  his  denial  of  supernatural   intervention   in   the  course  of  natural  events  generally   (“everything   does   and   can   happen   only   by   means   of   all   of   the   powers  distributed  and  contained  in  the  world,  as  God  originally  and  has  always  willed  it”  (1999,  §46  p.s.,  232)),  Schleiermacher  denies  that  Jesus  brings  about  redemption,  or  any  other  effect,  in  a  way  that  bypasses  historical/natural  causality.     The  medium  through  which  the  influence  of  Jesus  is  historically  transmitted  is   religious   community;   and   in   fact   Schleiermacher’s   identification   of   Christian  religious   community   as   the   community   that   ‘mediates’   the   influence   of   Jesus   to  successive  generations  is  the  basis  for  his  approval  of  a  strong  form  of  the  principle  of   extra   ecclesia   nulla   salus   (no   salvation   outside   the   church).   The   Grundsatz   or  leading  proposition  of  §87  excludes,  Schleiermacher  argues,  the  idea  that  “a  share  in  redemption  and  a  blessing   (Beseligung)   through  Christ   could  be   given  outside   the  corporate   life   which   he   instituted,   such   that   a   Christian   could   dispense   with   the  latter  and  be  with  Christ,  as  it  were,  alone.”  He  continues:    

This   separatism,  which  we  must   characterize   as   fanatical   because   it  disregards   the   fact   that   anything   originally   divinely   caused   can  nevertheless   be   apprehended   only   in   its   historical   appearance   and  also  can  continue   to   function  only  as  an  historical  phenomenon,  and  which   can   consistently   only   arise   in   isolation   and   so   must   always  disappear  again,  destroys  the  essence  of  Christianity  by  postulating  an  activity  of  Christ  without   temporal  and  spatial  mediation;  and  at   the  

Page 12: Dole - Religious Experience in Schleiermacher

What  is  ‘religious  experience’  in  Schleiermacher’s  Dogmatics,  and  why  does  it  matter?    Andrew  Dole    

 55

same   time   it   so   isolates   itself   that  what   has   been   achieved   in   it   can  have  no  continuing  influence.  (1999  vol.  2,  §87.3,  17)  

    It  is  this  principle  that  Schleiermacher  has  in  mind,  I  think,  when  he  remarks  in   §27   that   “Christian   piety   never   arises   in   independently   and   of   itself   in   an  individual,   but   only   out   of   the   communion   and   in   the   communion”   (1999,   §24.4,  141).  The  claim  I  extract  from  these  passages  is  that  the  experience  of  redemption,  if  it  is  ultimately  caused  (as  is  everything  else)  by  the  “divine  causality,”  is  proximately  caused  by  the  individual’s  exposure  to  and  participation  in  religious  community.       Being   proximately   caused   in   this   way,   fairly   obviously,   opens   up   the  experience   of   redemption   to   the   influence   of   environmental   factors.   Prominent  among   these   will   be   the   concepts   and   linguistic   terms   that   figure   in   religious  discourse.  Schleiermacher  is  quite  clear  about  the  fact  that  participation  in  religious  community   provides   the   basic   set   of   terms   in   which   Christians   understand   the  experience  of  redemption;  he  credits  such  participation  not  only  with  transmitting  the   influence   of   Jesus   which   effects   the   removal   of   Unseligkeit,   but   also   with  awakening   the   awareness   of   sin   itself   (1989,   §88.3,   364).   In   Schleiermacher’s  description   not   only   the   experience   of   redemption   but   also   the   conditions   for   its  occurrence   are   hardly   independent   of   the   contents   of   the   tradition   involved.   His  position,  stated  plainly,  is  that  the  experience  of  redemption  is  a  product  of  religion  in  at  least  two  important  respects:  its  ideational  parameters  are  impressed  upon  the  individual   by   religious   tradition,   and   qua   event   it   is   caused   by   participation   in  religious  activities.     On   the   grounds   of   this   understanding   of   the   ‘mediated’   nature   of   the  influence  of  Jesus,  Schleiermacher  makes  a  strong  claim  regarding  one  aspect  of  the  phenomenal   content   of   the   experience   of   redemption.   That   claim   is   this:   if   the  defining  experience  of  Christian   religious   identity   is   the  experience  of   redemption  by   Christ,   then   the   experienced   connection   to   Christ   that   it   contains   is   itself   a  proximate   product   of   the   influence   of   the   community.   I   espy   this   claim   in   the  following  passage:    

our   proposition   depends   upon   the   presupposition   that   in   the  Christian   fellowship,   outwardly   so   constituted,   there   is   still   that  communication  of   the  absolutely  potent  God-­‐consciousness   in  Christ  as   a   thing   that   is   inward,   and   yet,   since   faith   can   rest   upon   nothing  except   an   impression   received,   capable   of   being   experienced  (erfahrbar).  This  experience  is  made  up  of  two  elements,  one  of  which  belongs   to   the   personal   consciousness,   the   other   to   the   common  consciousness.  The   former   is   that   the   individual  even   today  receives  from  the  depiction  (Bild)  of  Christ,  which  exists   in  the  community  as  at  once  a  corporate  act  and  a  corporate  possession,  the  impression  of  the   sinless   perfection   of   Jesus,   which   becomes   for   him   at   the   same  time   the  perfect  consciousness  of  sin  and   the  removal  of  Unseligkeit.  (1989,  §88.3,  364)  

 

Page 13: Dole - Religious Experience in Schleiermacher

What  is  ‘religious  experience’  in  Schleiermacher’s  Dogmatics,  and  why  does  it  matter?    Andrew  Dole    

 56

  In   other  words,   through  participation   in   religious   community   the  Christian  receives   a   depiction   or   ‘picture’   of   Christ,   and   the   experience   of   redemption   is  caused   by   the   impact   of   this   depiction   on   the   individual’s   psychology—as  Schleiermacher   says   elsewhere,   the   sort   of   regret   for   sin   that   begets   conversion  “must  always  in  the  end  arise  out  of  the  impression  (Anschauung)  of  the  perfection  of  Christ”  (1989,  §108.2,  484).5  I  do  not  take  Schleiermacher’s  position  to  be  that  the  state  of  affairs  of   the  community’s  depiction  being  in  fact   the  historical  medium  of  the   perfect   God-­‐consciousness   of   Jesus   is   phenomenally   available   to   the   one  who  experiences   redemption,   and   I   take   him   to   have   positioned   that   claim   as   a  presupposition   (Voraussetzung)   for   this   reason.   In   other   words,   the   one   who  experiences  redemption  by  Christ  does  not  experience   the   influence  of   Jesus  upon  her  in  so  direct  and  immediate  a  fashion  that  she  thereby  knows  Jesus,  as  it  were,  by  acquaintance.  What   is   available   to   the   Christian   is   the   community’s   claim   that   its  influence   is   the   influence   of   Christ.   Schleiermacher’s   dogmatics   presupposes   that  this  claim  is  in  fact  true;  but  this  truth  is  not  something  that  can  be  ‘read  off’  of  the  experience  of  redemption  itself.     This   subject   returns   when   Schleiermacher   considers   the   phenomenon   of  conversion  (Bekehrung)  in  §108.  Conversion  he  defines  as  “the  beginning  of  new  life  in  fellowship  with  Christ,”  the  components  of  which  are  repentance  (Buße)  and  faith  (Glaube).  Much  of  the  discussion  is  taken  up  by  protestations  against  the  notion  that  “every  Christian  must  be  able  to  point  to  the  very  time  and  place  of  his  conversion”  and   in  particular  with   the   “most   extreme   form”  of   this  notion,  namely   that   “every  true   Christian   must   be   able   to   allege,   as   the   beginning   of   his   state   of   grace,   a  penitential  crisis  of  soul…  followed  by  a  feeling  of  divine  grace  reaching  to  the  limit  of   inexpressible   felicity”   (1989,   §108.3,   487).   But   more   importantly   for   my  purposes,   Schleiermacher   distances   himself   from   the   notion   that   redemption   is  brought  about  by  the  agency  of  the  Holy  Spirit.  “The  essential  identity  of  redemption  and   of   the   Christian   fellowship   would   be   imperiled,”   he   argues,   “if   our   faith   had  either  another  content  or  another  origin—the  one  implies  the  other—than  it  had  in  the  case  of  the  first  disciples.”  In  those  disciples,  conversion  and  faith      

were   effected  by   the  Word   in   its  widest   sense,   that   is,   by   the  whole  prophetic  activity  of  Christ.  And  we  must  be  able   to  understand   this  that  we  have  in  common  with  them,   if  need  be  without  a  doctrine  of  the  Holy   Spirit,   just   as   the  disciples  understood   their   own   condition  without  any  such  doctrine.  The  constant  factor  is  above  all  the  divine  power   of   the   Word—taking   the   expression   in   its   widest   sense—by  which  conversion  is  still  effected  and  faith  still  arises.  The  difference  is  simply  that  the  self-­‐revelation  of  Christ  is  now  mediated  by  those  who  preach  him;  but   they  being   appropriated  by  him  as  his   instruments,  

5  It  is  worth  noting  that  after  1805,  with  his  first  revision  of  On  Religion,  Schleiermacher  abandons  the  usage  of  the  term  Anschauung  on  which  he  relied  in  the  first  edition.  By  1830,  with  the  second  edition  of  the  Glaubenslehre,  that  term  has  little  in  the  way  of  a  precise  technical  definition.  

Page 14: Dole - Religious Experience in Schleiermacher

What  is  ‘religious  experience’  in  Schleiermacher’s  Dogmatics,  and  why  does  it  matter?    Andrew  Dole    

 57

the   activity   really   proceeds   from   him   and   is   essentially   his   own.  (1989,  §108.5,  490)    

  In   commenting   on   this   point   Schleiermacher   offers   two   remarks   on   the  possibility   and   significance   of—as   I   understand   it—phenomenally   immediate  experience  of  Jesus.  First:  

 if   it  be  allowed  that  there  are  divine  workings  of  converting  grace  in  no   actual   historical   relation   to   the   personal   efficacy   of   Christ   (even  though   it   is   as  workings   of   Christ   that   they   come   to   consciousness),  there   would   be   no   security   that   this   inward   mystic   Christ   was  identical  with  the  historical  Christ.    

  In   speaking   of   an   ‘inward  mystic   Christ,’   I   take   Schleiermacher   to   have   in  mind   the   idea   that   Jesus  might  manifest   to  human  awareness   through  some  other  channel  independent  of  immersion  in  tradition—in,  say,  a  vision  of  the  risen  Christ  had  by  a  non-­‐Christian  (such  as,  for  example,  Paul  on  the  road  to  Damascus).  Fairly  clearly,   his   position   is   that   to   allow   that   such   experiences   might   be   redemptive  would  be  to  weaken  theology’s  commitment  to  the  claim  that  redemption  is  brought  about  by  the  influence  of  Jesus.6     And  second:    

The   influence   of   Christ,   therefore,   consists   solely   in   the   human  communication   of   the   Word,   but   only   insofar   as   this   carries   on  (fortbewegt)  Christ’s  word  and  the  indwelling  divine  power  of  Christ  himself;  whereby  if,  for  the  consciousness  of  the  person  in  the  grip  of  conversion,   any   human   intermediation   (Zwischenwirkung)   vanishes,  and   Christ   is   imagined   immediately   by   him   (Christus   sich   ihm…  unmittelbar  vergegenwärtigt)  in  his  entire  activity,  from  the  prophetic  through   the   kingly,   which   takes   possession   of   him,   this   is   fully   in  accordance  with  the  truth.  (1999  vol.  2,  §108.5,  167)  

    Here  Schleiermacher  seems  to  be  accepting  that  in  some  cases  of  conversion,  Christ  is  experienced  as  immediately  present.  His  claim  about  such  cases  is  that  the  phenomenal   characteristic  of   immediate  presence  comes  about  not   in  virtue  of  an  unmediated  causal  influence  by  Christ  on  the  person  experiencing  conversion,  but  in  virtue   of   the   disappearance   from   the   awareness   of   that   person   of   the   causal   links  through  which  the  redeeming  influence  of  Jesus  is  transmitted.  

6  If  Schleiermacher’s  claim  is  that  a  person  could  never  have  Sicherheit  of  the  identity  of  a  person  whom  they  experience  directly  (in,  say,  a  vision),  I  find  the  claim  debatable;  someone  who  had  known  Jesus  during  his  lifetime,  for  example,  might  recognize  an  envisioned  person  as  Jesus.  I  suspect  that  what  he  really  wants  to  argue  here  is  that  there  could  be  no  Sicherheit  at  second  hand  —  thus  none  for  a  religious  community  or  a  dogmatic  theologian  —that  in  such  visions  it  is  Jesus  who  is  experienced.  And  this  seems  to  me  to  be  a  reasonable  position.  

Page 15: Dole - Religious Experience in Schleiermacher

What  is  ‘religious  experience’  in  Schleiermacher’s  Dogmatics,  and  why  does  it  matter?    Andrew  Dole    

 58

  To  summarize:  in  the  Glaubenslehre  Schleiermacher  describes  an  ‘experience  of  redemption  by  Christ’  that  is  central  to  his  broader  understanding  of  distinctively  Christian  piety.7  This  experience   is   the  experience  of  an   increase   in  the  power  and  clarity  of  one’s  God-­‐consciousness  in  virtue  of  the  work  of  Jesus.  This  experience  is  proximately  caused  by  the  influence  of  a  religious  community’s  claims  regarding  the  perfect  piety  of   Jesus—its  depiction  of   Jesus—on   individuals  who  encounter   these  claims   through  participation   in   religious   community.   This   experience  may  or  may  not  take  the  form  of  a  dramatic  ‘experience  of  conversion.’  And  it  may  or  may  not  be  a  component  of  the  experience  that  Jesus  is  experienced  as  ‘immediately  present’  in  his  redeeming  activity.     In   developing   his   typology   or   ‘map’   of   the   overall   territory   of   religious  experience,   Wesley   Wildman   classifies   such   experiences   as   Confucian   self-­‐cultivation   and   Christian   sanctification   as   “extended   ultimacy   experiences,”   or  “gradual  and  chronic  experiences  of  personal  change  or  self-­‐transcendence”  (2011,  85).   Schleiermacher’s   “experience   of   redemption   by   Jesus”   fits   well   into   this  category.   This   sort   of   experience   differs   from   Perceiving   God-­‐style   religious  experience   in   at   least   two   notable   ways.   First,   Schleiermacher’s   experience   of  redemption   is,   in  keeping  with  his  stated  working  method   for  dogmatics,   first  and  foremost   awareness   of   the   self.   The   term   ‘inner   experience’   is   sometimes   used   to  describe  non-­‐sensory  experience  of  something  other  than  the  self—more  precisely,  experience   of   something   other   than   the   self   that   does   not   come   by   way   of   the  perceptual   experience   of   anything   in   one’s   material   environment.   But  Schleiermacher’s   experience   of   redemption   is   an   ‘inner   experience’   in   a   more  straightforward   way:   it   is   an   experience   of   one’s   own   mental   conditions.   And  second,   Schleiermacher’s   experience   of   redemption   is   temporally   complex  (“extended”).   It   comprises   subsidiary   experiences   of   the   self’s   own   mental  conditions,  since  at  the   ‘top   level’   it   is   the  experience  of  change  over  time  in  those  conditions.   While   one   form   the   experience   can   assume   is   that   of   a   sudden   and  dramatic   change   from   God-­‐forgetfulness   to   God-­‐consciousness—an   experience  confined,   as   it   were,   to   a   single   moment—the   experienced   change   can   also   be  gradual.  Thus  the  experience  of  redemption  can  in  some  instances  be  more  like  the  experience   of   seeing   sunlight   for   the   first   time,   and   in   other   instances   like   the  experience  of  becoming  an  adult.  In  either  case,  part  of  the  content  of  the  experience  involves  awareness  of  the  difference  between  experiences  at  different  times.      5.  Commentary    

7  I  do  not  know  whether  Schleiermacher  should  be  understood  as  describing  a  kind  of  experience  that  is  peculiar  to  Evangelisch  Christians,  or  whether,  in  contrast,  he  should  be  understood  as  describing  a  generically  Christian  kind  of  experience.  I  incline  towards  the  latter  reading,  largely  because  I  cannot  find  a  way  to  attach  his  claim  regarding  the  core  distinction  of  Protestant  from  Roman  Catholic  Christianity  (see  CF  §24)  to  his  description  of  the  experience  of  redemption.  But  I  have  not  thought  long  about  the  matter.  

Page 16: Dole - Religious Experience in Schleiermacher

What  is  ‘religious  experience’  in  Schleiermacher’s  Dogmatics,  and  why  does  it  matter?    Andrew  Dole    

 59

  In  concluding  I  want  to  attend  to  two  broad  projects  to  which  one  might  seek  to  apply  a  particular  conception  of  religious  experience,  and  to  remark  on  the  utility  of  Schleiermacher’s  conception  of   the  experience  of  redemption  for  these  projects.  Both  projects   are   theological  ones   in  a  Schleiermacherian   sense—that   is,   both  are  concerned   with   the   business   of   (as   I   would   put   it)   managing   religion   in   the  contemporary  world.     The   first   task   is   one   to  which   Schleiermacher   spoke   explicitly,   but  which   I  will  describe  using  different  terminology.  Schleiermacher’s  concern  to  establish  an  ‘eternal  covenant’  between  religion  and  science  is,  I  think,  one  variant  of  the  project  of  positioning  religion  within  a  secular  environment   in  a  way  that  will  provide   for  both   religious   and   non-­‐religious   flourishing.   As   indicated   by   his   letters   to   Lücke,  Schleiermacher   foresaw  a  hostile   separation  between  religion  and   intellectual   life;  his   eternal   covenant  was   a   strategy   for  heading  off   not  only  unnecessary  hostility  among  different   sectors  of   society,  but  also   the   “intellectual   starvation”  of   religion  that  would  result  from  such  a  separation.  Schleiermacher  also  had  a  concern  for  the  preservation   of   the   freedom   of   Wissenschaft   (including,   but   not   limited   to,   the  freedom   of   what   later   generations   would   term   Religionswissenschaft)   against   its  constriction   by   fearful   religionists;   I   suspect   this   concern   to   have   been   equally  important   to  him  as  his  concern   for   the  well-­‐being  of  religion,  although  I  have  not  done  the  textual  work  necessary  to  document  the  matter.     It  is  the  naturalness  of  the  experience  of  redemption  by  Jesus  as  understood  by  Schleiermacher  that  contributes  to  this  task.  By  this  point  the  respects  in  which  this  experience  is  natural  experience  should  be  clear.  The  experience  is  proximately  caused  by  natural  entities  and  circumstances—specifically,  the  impact  of  a  religious  community’s  depiction  of  Christ  on  the  psychology  of  the  individual  adherent,  which  depiction  is  a  matter  of  the  continued  circulation  of  the  stories,  claims,  and  practices  of   earlier   generations   of   Christians.   The   conceptual   structure   of   the   experience   is  also  determined  by  the  context  that  produces  it,  and  this  applies  as  well  to  the  sense  of  the  presence  of  Jesus  that  it  sometimes  involves.       Above   I   quoted   a   passage   from   §46   of   the   Glaubenslehre   in   which  Schleiermacher   argues   that   pious   feeling,   properly   understood,   is   not   threatened  “even  by  the  completest  confidence  with  which  we  accept  this  or  that  explanation”  of   the   phenomena   that   stimulates   it,   and   that   explanatory   recourse   to   the  supernatural   is   more   of   a   sign   of   intellectual   laziness   than   of   piety   (1989,   §46.1,  172).  I  want  to  venture  a  present-­‐day  application  of  this  principle.  The  pyschologist  Lee  Kirkpatrick  specializes  in  attachment  theory  and  its  role  in  religion,  making  use  of   the   conceptual   apparatus   of   empirical   and   evolutionary   psychology.   In  Attachment,  Evolution,  and  the  Psychology  of  Religion,  Kirkpatrick  has  advanced  a  set  of  conjectures  regarding  the  psychological  mechanisms  at  work  in  the  phenomenon  of  religious  conversion.8  In  broad  outline,  Kirkpatrick  argues  that  deeply   ingrained  in   the   human  mind   is   a   set   of   propensities   that   dispose   individuals   to   one   or   the  other  of  two  orientations  to  a  host  of  activities  centered  around  reproduction.  One  is  the   ‘quantity’  orientation,  which  prioritizes  high-­‐risk  activities,  broad  and  frequent   8  This  material  is  drawn  in  broad  outline  from  (Kirkpatrick  2005,  ch.  8).  

Page 17: Dole - Religious Experience in Schleiermacher

What  is  ‘religious  experience’  in  Schleiermacher’s  Dogmatics,  and  why  does  it  matter?    Andrew  Dole    

 60

sexual   activity,   and   low   levels   of   commitment   and   caregiving.   The   other   is   the  ‘quality’   orientation,   which   prioritizes   high   investment   in   caregiving,   higher  selectivity   and   lower   frequency   in   sexual   activity,   and   the   avoidance   of   risk.  Kirkpatrick  argues  for  the  existence  of  a  mechanism  that  ‘tracks’  the  human  mind  as  it  develops  into  one  or  another  of  these  orientations  in  response  to  cues  as  to  which  reproductive   strategy   is   more   appropriate,   from   a   “genes’   eye   view,”   to   the  environment.  If  it  is  possible  for  human  minds  to  ‘jump’  from  one  track  to  another—specifically,  from  the  ‘quantity’  track  to  the  ‘quality’  track—then  we  should  expect  to  see   cases   in   which   human   individuals   abandon   a   thrill-­‐seeking,   promiscuous,  responsibility-­‐averse   lifestyle   for   a   risk-­‐averse,   sexually   faithful,   responsibility-­‐tolerant  one.  Kirkpatrick  hypothesizes  that  the  psychological  mechanism  underlying  some   cases   of   sudden   religious   conversion   is   the   activation   of   an   “otherwise  dormant   love   mechanism,”   which   effectively   rewrites   a   suite   of   motivational  valuations  within   the   individual;  and   this  activation   is   the  result  of  an   individual’s  being  exposed  to  persuasive  portrayals  of  God  as  an  “attachment  figure,”  or  a  person  with  which   one   can   have   a   long-­‐term   and   fulfilling   loving   relationship.   Thus   “the  Christian   metaphor   of   being   ‘born   again’   is   apt:   the   convert   in   effect   really   does  begin,  in  many  ways,  a  new  life,  this  time  on  the  ‘quality’  rather  than  the  ‘quantity’  track”  (Kirkpatrick  2005,  212).     I  have  no  particular   interest  at  present   in  defending  Kirkpatrick’s   theory  of  sudden  religious  conversion,  in  case  you  are  inclined  to  be  skeptical  of  it.  What  I  do  want  to  argue  is  that   it  was  a  goal  of  Schleiermacher’s  dogmatic  project  to  bring  it  about  that  a  commitment  to  a  Christian  religious  identity  should  by  itself  generate  no   reason   to   object   to   such   a   theory.   This   application   of   Schleiermacher’s  commitment  (so  I  claim)  to  naturalism  requires  one  bit  of  bridge-­‐building,  for  which  there   is   textual   support.   Thus   far   my   discussion   of   the   ‘naturalness’   of   the  experience   of   redemption   has   attended   principally   to   the   role   played   by   factors  external   to   the   experiencer.   Kirkpatrick’s   theory,   in   contrast,   attends   to   factors  internal   to   the   one   who   experiences   conversion.   Is   there   textual   warrant   for  thinking  that  the  sort  of  naturalism  that  Schleiermacher  envisioned  would  extend  to  explanations  of  this  kind?     I  believe  that  there  is.  Schleiermacher  used  the  term  “philosophy  of  religion”  to  refer  to  a  science  that  would  include  both  historical  and  theoretical  knowledge  of  religion  “from  above”  rather  than  “from  within”  particular  religious  traditions;  thus  the   term  refers   to  a  non-­‐confessional  and  comparative  “science  of   religion”   (1966,  §23,  25).  Were  such  a  science  to  be  developed  completely,  Schleiermacher  remarked  in  §11  of  the  Glaubenslehre,      

…   all   the   principal   moments   of   the   pious   consciousness   would   be  systematized,  and  from  their  interconnection  it  would  be  seen  which  of   them  were   fitted   to  have  all   the  others   related   to   them  and   to  be  themselves  a  constant  concomitant  of  the  others.  If   it  should  become  evident   that   that   which   we   describe   by   the   term   ‘redemption’  becomes   such   [a   moment]   as   soon   as   into   a   region   where   God-­‐consciousness  is  constrained  a  fact  which  liberates  this  consciousness  enters:  then  Christianity  would  be  made  secure  as  a  particular  form  of  

Page 18: Dole - Religious Experience in Schleiermacher

What  is  ‘religious  experience’  in  Schleiermacher’s  Dogmatics,  and  why  does  it  matter?    Andrew  Dole    

 61

faith,   and   in   a   certain   sense   understood   (construiert).   However   this  itself   could   not   be   called   a   proof   of   Christianity,   since   even   the  philosophy   of   religion   could   establish   no   necessity   either   to  acknowledge   a  particular   fact   as   redemptive   (erlösend)  nor   to   really  grant   a   central   place   within   one’s   own   consciousness   to   a   moment  which  can  be  such.  (1989,  §11.5,  59)    

It  seems  to  me  that  here  Schleiermacher  was  imagining  the  possibility  that  a  branch  of  scientific  inquiry  outside  Christian  theology  might  arrive  at  a  grasp  of  the  interior  dynamics  of  the  life  of  Christian  piety,  such  that  the  theological  claim  that  the  Bild  of  Jesus   “liberates   the   God-­‐consciousness”   might   receive   independent  (wissenschaftlich)  corroboration.  I  expect  that  the  one  who  accepts  Schleiermacher’s  understanding   of   the   experience   of   redemption   will   suppose   that   the   phrase  ‘liberation  of  the  God-­‐consciousness’  refers  to  a  process  involving  successive  mental  states  in  the  mind  of  an  individual.  She  will  also  understand  that  this  process,  no  less  than  the  process  of  the  transmission  of  the  influence  of  Jesus  through  history,  will  be  a  natural  one,  and  that  inasmuch  as  the  process  unfolds  similarly  within  the  lives  of  multiple   persons,   it   will   be   susceptible   to   generalized   description.   She   will   also  accept   the   possibility   that   a   science   that   can   investigate   the   mental   dynamics   of  human  persons  will  be  in  a  position  to  discern  the  existence  of  this  process  (if  it  in  fact  exists);  to  describe  it  using  its  own  conceptual  vocabulary,  which  may  of  course  differ   from   that  of  Christian   theology;   and   to   investigate   the   relationship  between  this  process  and  other  phenomena  within  its  purview.     It  seems  to  me  that  Kirkpatrick’s  account  of  sudden  religious  conversion  is  an  instance   of   the   sort   of   investigation   that   Schleiermacher   had   in  mind.   Kirkpatrick  supposes   that   sudden   religious   conversion  may  well   be,   in   some   cases,   a   case   of  falling   in   love   for   the   first   time:   it  may  well   involve   the   first   activation   of   the   love  mechanism  in  a  person’s  life,  an  activation  triggered  by  the  persuasive  presentation  of  the  idea  of  God  as  an  attachment  figure.  I  think  it  plausible  to  think  that  falling  in  love  with  God  and  having  one’s  God-­‐consciousness  liberated  by  the  Bild  of  Jesus  can  be  different   descriptions   of   the   same   experience.   And   if   Kirkpatrick’s   account   claims  that   the   experience   of   sudden   conversion   turns   around   an   evolved   psychological  mechanism  that  has  nothing  to  do  with  God  and  everything  to  do  with  sex,9  then  I  think   Schleiermacher’s   position   encourages   us   to   think   not   that   this   or   any   other  theory  of  Christian  experience  is  correct,  but  that  supposing  it  to  be  correct  would  pose  no   threat   to  Christian  piety.   In  effect,   this  would  allow  conversations  around  the   question   of   whether   or   not   to   accept   accounts   such   as   Kirkpatrick’s   to   turn  around  considerations  of   theory  choice   rather   than  around   issues  of   compatibility  with   religious   sensibilities:   more   precisely,   it   would   allow   for   both   religious  adherents  and  non-­‐religious  adherents  to  take  part  in  the  same  set  of  conversations  around  such  questions.   I   follow  Schleiermacher  in  regarding  this  as  a  considerable  improvement   over   cases   in   which   religious   adherents   carry   on   separate   9  This  way  of  putting  the  matter  is,  of  course,  both  simplistic  and  question-­‐begging.  I  think  it  polite  to  notify  one’s  readers  of  this  when  one’s  argument  does  not  depend  on  such  features  going  unnoticed.  

Page 19: Dole - Religious Experience in Schleiermacher

What  is  ‘religious  experience’  in  Schleiermacher’s  Dogmatics,  and  why  does  it  matter?    Andrew  Dole    

 62

conversations   in   which   they   evaluate   scientific   theories   according   to   their  coherence  with  (formal  or  informal)  doctrine.     To   discuss   the   second   project   to   which   Schleiermacher’s   understanding   of  the  experience  of  redemption  might  be  applied,  let  us  return  to  the  quotation  from  John   Hick   presented   above.   Hick’s   claim   about   generic   (that   is,   non-­‐tradition-­‐specific)   religious   experience   does   not,   I   think,   correspond   to   Schleiermacher’s  position,   for  reasons  that   I  hope  are  clear  at   this  point.  But  here  are   the  claims  by  Hick  that  I  think  do  channel  Schleiermacher:    

distinctively  Christian  experience…  is  the  Christian’s  seeing  of  Christ  as  his   ‘Lord  and  Saviour,’   together  with   the  pervasive  recreative  effects  of  this  throughout  his   life,   transforming  the  quality  of  his  experience  and  determining  his  responses  to  other  people.  Christian  faith  is  thus  a  distinctive  consciousness  of  the  world  and  of  one’s  existence  within  it,  radiating  from  and  illuminated  by  a  consciousness  of  God  in  Christ.  

    It   is   the   provenance   of   this   remark   that   captures  my   attention.  Hick  wrote  prior  to  the  resurgence  of  Protestant  fundamentalism  in  the  United  States,  during  a  time  when  liberal  Christians  might  be  excused  for  feeling  assured  by  the  signs  of  the  times   that   the   Scopes   trial   had   proven   a   momentary   distraction   and   that   the  Christianity  of  the  future  would  be,  on  balance,  a   force  for  good.  Hick  combined  in  his  person   theological   seriousness  and  a  broad-­‐mindedness   that  would  eventually  lead  him  to  an  advocacy  of  religious  pluralism  that  to  this  day  has  no  rival  (1989).  If  Hick’s  optimism  now  looks  misplaced,  and  the  mainline  Christians  of  the  1960s  now  look   blissfully   unaware   of   the   storm   clouds  massing   to   the   south,   I   think   there   is  some  point   to   recalling   the   reappearance   of   a   formulation   of   religious   experience  like  Schleiermacher’s  from  avant  le  deluge.     It   would,   I   think,   be   naïve   for   anyone   now   living   to   expect   to   witness   a  widespread   rapprochement   between   liberal   and   conservative   variants   of  Christianity.   But   here   are   two   historical   counterfactuals   in   which   I   have   a   fair  amount   of   confidence,   on   which   I   want   to   premise   a   worthwhile   project   of  Kirchenleitung.  Consider  the  claim  that  by  around  the  turn  of  the  twentieth  century,  some   variant   of   “Babylonian   captivity”   had   caused   the   Christianity   of   the   day   to  abandon   the   centrality  of  personal   redemption  by  Christ   and   thereby   to   fall   away  from  authentic  Christian  identity.  My  first  counterfactual  is:  if  that  claim  had  struck  large   numbers   of   relevantly   nonpartisan   American   Protestants   as   implausible,   it  would  not  have  been  as  easy  as  it  seems  to  have  been  for  a  small  number  of  aspiring  movement  leaders  to  anathematize  such  things  as  historical  biblical  criticism,  higher  education,   social   insurance,   market   regulation,   and   other   phenomena   with  considerable  currency  at  the  time  in  the  world  of  Christian  letters.  And  the  second  is:   if   established   Christianity   had   preserved   through   the   nineteenth   century  Schleiermacher’s   understanding   of   the   ‘experience   of   redemption   by   Jesus’   as   the  defining  feature  of  Christian  religious  identity,  fundamentalist  claims  regarding  the  ‘apostasizing’   of   the   (proto-­‐mainline)   churches  would   have   gotten   less   traction   in  the  public  sphere.    

Page 20: Dole - Religious Experience in Schleiermacher

What  is  ‘religious  experience’  in  Schleiermacher’s  Dogmatics,  and  why  does  it  matter?    Andrew  Dole    

 63

  I   certainly  do  not  know  whether   the  political  polarization   that   came   to   full  expression   in   the   last   quarter   of   the   twentieth   century   in   both   Protestant   and  Catholic  forms  of  Christianity  could  have  been  avoided.  But  if  secularization  theory  is   wrong,   it   may   yet   be   early   days   for   Christianity,   and   if   so,   it   is   reasonable   to  suppose  that  its  future  will  be  different  from  its  past.  Two  current  trends  suggest  a  shifting  landscape.  One  of  these  is  the  shrinkage  of  mainline  traditions  to  the  point  that   some   are   actively   seeking   evangelical   transfusions   for   the   sake   of   their   very  survival.  And  another  is  some  degree  of  exhaustion  with  culture-­‐war  Christianity  on  the  part  of  younger  Christians  across  the  political  spectrum,  for  whom  the  stories  of  second-­‐wave   fundamentalism   describe   their   grandparents’   battles   and   not   their  own.   A   valuable   project   of   church   leadership,   it   seems   to  me,   would   be   to   try   to  rebuild   Christian   identity   around   some   idea   that   both   liberals   and   conservatives  could  accept,  in  hopeful  preparation  for  the  day  when  that  simplistic  and  destructive  distinction   will   be   regarded   as   quaint.   And   perhaps   for   that   project   the   name   of  Schleiermacher  will  come  to  stand  not  for  a  retreat  into  mysticism,  abandonment  to  feeling,  or  an  undifferentiated  loss  of  Christian  good  sense,  but  rather  for  a  tradition,  perhaps  amounting  to  a  ‘minority  report’  for  the  past  two  centuries,  that  begins  but  does  not  end   both   its   self-­‐reflection   and   its   broader   activity   in   the  world  with   the  transformation   of   persons   in   the   direction   of   God-­‐mindedness   by   the   agency   of  Jesus.10            

10  A  version  of  this  paper  was  delivered  at  the  Logos  2015  Workshop  at  the  University  of  Notre  Dame.  I  am  grateful  to  audience  members  for  helpful  comments  and,  in  particular,  to  Ian  McFarland  for  his  insightful  criticisms  and  suggestions.  

Page 21: Dole - Religious Experience in Schleiermacher

What  is  ‘religious  experience’  in  Schleiermacher’s  Dogmatics,  and  why  does  it  matter?    Andrew  Dole    

 64

Bibliography    Alston,  William.  1991.  Perceiving  God:  the  Epistemology  of  Religious  Experience.    

Cornell  University  Press.    Bigler,  Robert.  1972.  The  Politics  of  German  Protestantism:  the  Rise  of  the  Protestant    

Church  Elite  in  Prussia,  1815-­‐1848.  University  of  California  Press.    Dole,  Andrew.  2010a.  Schleiermacher  on  Religion  and  the  Natural  Order.  Oxford    

University  Press.    ______.  2010b.  “On  ‘Nothing  to  Distinguish’  Schleiermacher  and  Otto:  Reply    

to  Smith.”  Religious  Studies  46:  449-­‐68.      Howard,  Thomas  Albert.  2006.  Protestant  Theology  and  the  Rise  of  the  Modern    

German  University.  Oxford  University  Press.    Helmer,  Christine.  2014.  Theology  and  the  End  of  Doctrine.  John  Knox  Press.    Hick,  John,  2010.  Evil  and  the  God  of  Love.  New  edition.  Palgrave  MacMillan.    ______.  1989.  An  Interpretation  of  Religion:  Human  Responses  to  the    

Transcendent.  Yale  University  Press.    Kirkpatrick,  Lee.  2005.  Attachment,  Evolution,  and  the  Psychology  of  Religion.    

Guilford  Press.    Otto,  Rudolph.  1950.  The  Idea  of  the  Holy.  Second  edition.  Translated  by  John    

Harvey.  Oxford  University  Press.    Proudfoot,  Wayne.  1985.  Religious  Experience.  Columbia  University  Press.    Schleiermacher,  Friedrich.    1966.  Brief  Outline  of  the  Study  of  Theology.  Translated  by  Terence  Tice.  John  Knox  Press.    ______.  1981.  On  the  Glaubenslehre.  Translated  by  James  Duke    

and  Francis  Fiorenza.  Scholars  Press.    ______.  1989.  The  Christian  Faith.  Translated  by  H.R.  Mackintosh    

et  al.  T&T  Clark.    ______.  1991.  Über  die  Religion:  Reden  an  die  Gebildeten  unter    

ihren  Verächtern.  In  der  Ausgabe  von  Rudolf  Otto.  Vandenhoek  &  Ruprecht.    ______.  1999.  Die  Christliche  Glaube  nach  den  Grundzätzen  der    

Evangelischen  Kirche  im  Zusammenhange  dargestellt.  Walter  de  Gruyter.  

Page 22: Dole - Religious Experience in Schleiermacher

What  is  ‘religious  experience’  in  Schleiermacher’s  Dogmatics,  and  why  does  it  matter?    Andrew  Dole    

 65

 Sharpe,  Eric.  1975.  Comparative  Religion:  A  History.  Scribner’s.      Sockness,  Brent.  1998.  Against  False  Apologetics:  Wilhelm  Herrmann  and  Ernst    

Troeltsch  in  Conflict.  Mohr  Siebeck.    Wildman,  Wesley.  2011.  Religious  and  Spiritual  Experiences.  Cambridge  University    

Press.  


Recommended