+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Domains within Words and their meanings: a case study

Domains within Words and their meanings: a case study

Date post: 09-Feb-2022
Category:
Upload: others
View: 7 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend
28
1 Domains within Words and their meanings: a case study. Elena Anagnostopoulou & Yota Samioti University of Crete [email protected] , [email protected] To appear in: Alexiadou, A., H. Borer & F. Schäfer (Eds.) The syntax of Roots and the roots of Syntax. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 1. Introduction 1 The goal of this paper is to investigate the conditions under which idiosyncratic meaning arises in word formation. More specifically, we investigate the hypothesis put forth in Arad (2003, 2005) and Marantz (2001, 2007) that idiosyncratic meaning derives from locality conditions on the interpretation of roots. This hypothesis is stated in (1): (1) The Marantz / Arad Hypothesis Roots are assigned an interpretation in the context of the first category assigning head/ phase head merged with them, which is then fixed throughout the derivation We test (1) in the domain of Greek verbal adjectives and adjectival participles which provide extensive evidence for attachment below vs. above higher heads (i.e. little v, Voice) of the adjectivizing/participial suffixes tos and menos, respectively. Our investigation leads to the following results: (i) Affixes serving as verbalizers and the little v head contributing eventiveness cannot be collapsed. Greek verbal adjectives are shown to be semantically and syntactically small (i.e. they do not have event implications, a semantic property correlating with the fact that they do not support adverbs and other modifiers), and yet they may contain verbalizers inside the adjectivizing suffix -tos. This leads us to propose that there are two ways of interpreting the Arad/Marantz hypothesis, depending on whether we take (morphological) verbalizers or (abstract) eventivizing heads to qualify as the relevant phase heads in (1). (ii) If we look at the interpretation of an unspecified root, as suggested by Arad (2003, 2005) on the basis of Multiple Contextualized Meaning (MCM) in Hebrew, then Greek provides some support for the view that specified meaning is indeed determined at the point of categorization. Even though many Greek roots have a rather fixed meaning, unlike Hebrew, there are also roots whose meaning is unspecified, similarly to Hebrew. Interestingly, the presence of a verbalizing head in verbal adjectives formed on the basis of the latter type of roots serves as a context determining their interpretation (similarly to prefixes with latinate roots in English and Ancient Greek roots in Greek), as expected under Arad’s hypothesis. More specifically, we propose that roots fall into basic ontological types 1 Different versions of this paper have been presented at the 32 nd GLOW Colloquium (University of Nantes, April 15-18 2009), the Roots Workshop (University of Stuttgart, June 2009) and the Workshop on Linguistic Interfaces (University of Ulster, December 2-4 2010). We would like to thank the audiences for questions, suggestions and discussions, especially Asaf Bachrach, Orin Percus, Peter Svenonius, Gertjan Postma, Danny Fox, Alec Marantz, David Embick, Andrew Koontz Garboden, Hagit Borer, Lisa Travis, Christina Sevdali, Raffi Folli, and Heidi Harley. Special thanks to Winfried Lechner, Artemis Alexiadou and Terje Lohndal for their comments.
Transcript

1

Domains within Words and their meanings: a case study.

Elena Anagnostopoulou & Yota Samioti

University of Crete

[email protected], [email protected]

To appear in: Alexiadou, A., H. Borer & F. Schäfer (Eds.) The syntax of Roots and the roots of

Syntax. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

1. Introduction1

The goal of this paper is to investigate the conditions under which idiosyncratic meaning

arises in word formation. More specifically, we investigate the hypothesis put forth in Arad

(2003, 2005) and Marantz (2001, 2007) that idiosyncratic meaning derives from locality

conditions on the interpretation of roots. This hypothesis is stated in (1):

(1) The Marantz / Arad Hypothesis

Roots are assigned an interpretation in the context of the first category assigning head/

phase head merged with them, which is then fixed throughout the derivation

We test (1) in the domain of Greek verbal adjectives and adjectival participles which provide

extensive evidence for attachment below vs. above higher heads (i.e. little v, Voice) of the

adjectivizing/participial suffixes –tos and –menos, respectively. Our investigation leads to the

following results:

(i) Affixes serving as verbalizers and the little v head contributing eventiveness cannot be

collapsed. Greek verbal adjectives are shown to be semantically and syntactically small (i.e.

they do not have event implications, a semantic property correlating with the fact that they do

not support adverbs and other modifiers), and yet they may contain verbalizers inside the

adjectivizing suffix -tos. This leads us to propose that there are two ways of interpreting the

Arad/Marantz hypothesis, depending on whether we take (morphological) verbalizers or

(abstract) eventivizing heads to qualify as the relevant phase heads in (1).

(ii) If we look at the interpretation of an unspecified root, as suggested by Arad (2003,

2005) on the basis of Multiple Contextualized Meaning (MCM) in Hebrew, then Greek

provides some support for the view that specified meaning is indeed determined at the point

of categorization. Even though many Greek roots have a rather fixed meaning, unlike

Hebrew, there are also roots whose meaning is unspecified, similarly to Hebrew.

Interestingly, the presence of a verbalizing head in verbal adjectives formed on the basis of

the latter type of roots serves as a context determining their interpretation (similarly to

prefixes with latinate roots in English and Ancient Greek roots in Greek), as expected under

Arad’s hypothesis. More specifically, we propose that roots fall into basic ontological types

1 Different versions of this paper have been presented at the 32

nd GLOW Colloquium (University of Nantes,

April 15-18 2009), the Roots Workshop (University of Stuttgart, June 2009) and the Workshop on Linguistic

Interfaces (University of Ulster, December 2-4 2010). We would like to thank the audiences for questions,

suggestions and discussions, especially Asaf Bachrach, Orin Percus, Peter Svenonius, Gertjan Postma, Danny

Fox, Alec Marantz, David Embick, Andrew Koontz Garboden, Hagit Borer, Lisa Travis, Christina Sevdali, Raffi

Folli, and Heidi Harley. Special thanks to Winfried Lechner, Artemis Alexiadou and Terje Lohndal for their

comments.

2

naming events, things and states following Harley (2005). Roots must be classifiable in

terms of this basic ontology. If they are not, a categorizing head serves to classify them. The

classification itself makes them acquire what is sensed as fixed “meaning”, which is then

retained throughout the derivation.

(iii) If we look at idiomatic interpretations, as suggested by Marantz on the basis of

idiomatic interpretations of adjectival passive participles vs. compositional interpretations of

verbal passive participles in English, then (1) is not supported by the Greek data. Verbal

adjectives involving affix attachment below v (whether v is taken to be a verbalizer or an

eventivizer) as well as participles showing affix attachment above v may both have idiomatic

meanings, and there is no necessary correlation between the meaning of verbs and the

meaning of participles which include a verbal head, contra Marantz (2001, 2007). On the

other hand, there is strong evidence from various directions that the head which delimits the

domain for idiomatic interpretations of adjectival participles and verbal adjectives in Greek is

Voice, the little v head introducing the agent, as was proposed in earlier work by Marantz

(1996, 1997). We conclude that the node that syntactically projects an agent serves as a

boundary for special meanings of idioms at the word level, similarly to what has been claimed

for idioms at the phrasal level.

The paper is organized as follows. In section 2, we provide the necessary background

on inner vs. outer affixation focusing on how this distinction has been related to the question

of idiosyncratic interpretation. In section 3, we present an outline of the properties of Greek –

menos participles and –tos verbal adjectives, investigating their architecture in connection to

their syntax, semantics and morphology. We present evidence that morphological verbalizers

should be dissociated from the abstract heads contributing eventiveness. This leads us to

conclude that the categorizing head v (vC), which verbalizes an a-categorial root, cannot be

collapsed with the eventivizing v head (vE), which functions as the BECOME/ RESULT/

FIENT operator identified in recent decomposition analyses. Finally, in section 4 we turn to

the question of domains for idioms. We argue that neither the verbalizing head vC nor the

eventivizing head vE serve as boundaries for special meanings; the relevant domain is defined

by Voice, the head projecting an agent.

2. Background: two domains for word formation, inner and outer affixation.

As is well known, there are two types of word formation, one forming words showing

irregularities, such as paradigmatic gaps, non-predictable meaning, irregular forms, and one

for morphologically productive, semantically transparent and morpho-phonologically

predictable forms. In many theories, this difference has been linked to the hypothesis that

there are two places for word formation: Lexicon vs. syntax (e.g. Wasow 1977, Dubinsky &

Simango 1996, Horvath & Siloni 2008), derivation vs. inflection (e.g. Anderson 1982;

Perlmutter 1988; Spencer 1991) level I vs. level II (e.g. Siegel 1979; Kiparsky 1982;

Mohanan 1986). Adjectival/stative vs. verbal/eventive passive participles in languages like

English have been widely assumed in the literature to present a paradigmatic case

exemplifying the double nature of word formation. Stative/ adjectival participles may show

special morphology, while eventive/ passive participles always show regular morphology:

(2) a. The shaven man

b. The man was shaved by John

Moreover, stative participle formation is associated with idiosyncrasy in meaning, unlike

verbal participle formation:

3

(3) a. The hung jury (#Someone hung the jury)

b. *The jury was being hung

In English and other languages the stative vs. eventive participle distinction correlates with a

split between derivation and inflection (Wasow 1977, Marantz 2001, 2007; Horvath & Siloni

2008). Stative participles are adjectives and passive ones are verbs, as shown by “very” vs.

“very much”-modification in (4) and (5). In English, “very” modifies exclusively adjectives

and “very much” exclusively verbs, as indicated by the contrasts between (4b) vs. (4c) and

(5b) vs. (5c), respectively. The fact that the stative participle respected is modified by “very”

in (4a) presents evidence that it qualifies as an adjective. On the other hand, passive respected

in (5a) is modified by very much qualifying as a verb.

(4) a. Your family was very respected Adjectival

b. John is very fond of your family

c. *John is very much fond of your family

(5) a. Your family was very much respected by the neighbors Verbal

b. John very much respects your family

c. *John very respects your family

Wasow (1977) argued that the properties distinguishing adjectival from verbal participles may

receive a principled explanation if the two participle types are formed in two different

components of the grammar (an approach widely adopted since then;2 see Horvath & Siloni

2008 for a recent analysis along these lines). On this view, adjectival passives are formed in

the lexicon, and they show idiosyncratic forms and meanings due to the fact that words in the

lexicon have special listed properties. On the other hand, verbal passives are formed in

syntax, the locus of regularity, productivity and compositionality, which in turn explains their

transparency in form and meaning.

For syntactic approaches to morphology such as Distributed Morphology (DM) or

Borer (2005), properties traditionally attributed to lexical listing (e.g. categorization,

argument structure) are reduced to mechanisms of the computational system. In such models,

there can be no well-defined distinction between lexical and syntactic word formation. This

raises the question of how the distinction between regular and irregular word formation can be

derived. In order to capture this distinction, Marantz (2001, 2007) and Arad (2003, 2005)

propose to reconstruct the ‘two places to build words” approach within the syntax, as ‘two

domains for word formation’ (see also Embick 2010). More specifically, they propose that

there are two domains for word formation delimited by a category-defining head, as shown in

(6). Attachment of x directly to the root, as in (6a), leads to irregular word formation, while

attachment above the category defining heads (little v, a, n), as in (6b), leads to regular word

formation:

(6) a. x b. x 3 3 Root x n, v, a 3 Root n, v, a

2 But cf. Strong Lexicalist approaches such as Levin & Rappaport’s (1986) who argue that all participles are

formed in the lexicon, adjectival participles are formed by verbal ones via a category changing rule, and the

properties distinguishing adjectival from verbal participles derive from their difference in category. See

Dubinsky & Simango (1996) for evidence against this view and Marantz (2007) for discussion of Wasow’s

analysis, as compared to Levin & Rappaport’s.

4

On this view, there is a split between “inner” and “outer” morphology, as defined in (7):

(7) “Inner morphology” attaches to roots or complex constituents below the first

little x (x={v,n,a}) node head (phase head) above the root. All morphology

above the first x node is “outer morphology” including all “category

changing” derivational morphology.” (Marantz 2007: 5; Marantz’s (3), (2))

The main properties associated with inner vs. outer affixation are summarized in Table 1:

Table 1

Inner Affixation Outer Affixation

Regularity Potential special form and

special meaning

Predictable form and

predictable meaning

Selection Attaches inside

morphology determining

lexical category

May attach outside

morphology determining

lexical category

According to these authors, phasehood provides the key towards understanding why there is

an inner vs. outer split in word-formation. Assuming that category defining heads are phase

heads in the sense of Chomsky (2000, 2001), they define cyclic domains leading to the

semantic interpretation and phonological spell-out of the chunk of syntactic structure which

includes the root or a more complex constituent plus the category determining head. Once

such phase heads are merged, the structure is shipped off to PF and LF for pronunciation/

interpretation and from that point on, spell-out and interpretation cannot be altered. Moreover,

further affixation cannot reach into properties of the Root. The empirical generalization this

proposal is based on will be called here “the (non-)compositionality generalization” in (8):

(8) The (non-)compositionality generalization

When affixes attach directly to the root, idiosyncratic meanings may arise.

When affixes attach outside category defining heads, the result is a meaning

predictable from the meaning of the stem.

Arad (2003, 2005) presents extensive evidence from Hebrew denominal verbs supporting (8)

and the “inner” vs. “outer” architecture.

3. Greek –menos participles and –tos verbal adjectives: outer and inner architecture

Greek has a rich set of adjectives/ participles based on verbs, ending in -tos and –menos.3 As

has been argued for in Anagnostopoulou (2003) and Alexiadou & Anagnostopoulou (A&A

2008), –menos participles denote states resulting from prior events and are formed by outer

cycle attachment (above vP or above VoiceP). On the other hand, -tos verbal adjectives lack

event implications, a property taken by Anagnostopoulou (2003) and A&A (2008) to provide

evidence for inner-cycle attachment. If this picture is correct, then -menos and –tos forms

present an ideal empirical domain for testing the validity of the Marantz/Arad hypothesis (1),

and the non-compositionality generalization in (8). Assuming (1) and (8), –menos participles

3 Νakas 1978, Setatos 1984, Lascaratou 1991, Lascaratou & Philippaki-Warburton 1984, Anastasiadi-Simeonidi

1994, Markantonatou et al. 1996, Kordoni 2002, Αnagnostopoulou 2003, Alexiadou & Anagnostopoulou 2008,

Samioti 2008; in progress.

5

are expected to have a meaning predictable from the meaning of the corresponding verbs,

while –tos forms are expected to be highly idiosyncratic.

However, as will be shown in this section, a closer investigation of the morphology of

–tos forms in connection to their syntax and semantics reveals that this simple picture needs

to be revised. It turns out that the architecture of –tos verbal adjectives is considerably more

complex than described by Anagnostopoulou (2003) and A&A (2008), for two main reasons:

First, it is actually not easy to decide on the basis of morphology whether –tos verbal

adjectives involve inner or outer cycle attachment: sometimes –tos attaches directly to the

root and sometimes outside a verbalizer, with absolutely no difference in the interpretation

and syntax of the two cases. Importantly, –tos verbal adjectives uniformly lack event

implications and the concomitant syntactic differences associated with them, regardless of

whether –tos attaches directly to the root or to the root+verbalizer complex.

Second, -tos attachment directly to the root provides some evidence for Arad’s

hypothesis based on Multiple Contextualized Meaning (MCM). If the meaning of the root is

completely unspecified the presence of a verbalizer fixes it first, and then –tos attaches to the

Root+verbalizer complex. But idiomaticity is a different issue, and the domain for non-

compositional, unpredictable interpretation of verbal adjectives/ participles turns out to be

bigger than the domain defined by the first categorizing or eventivizing head: idiomatic

meanings may arise at any point in the extended vP domain, provided that the properties

associated with an agent are absent.

The discussion is organized as follows. In section 3.1, we summarize from the

previous literature the main evidence in favor of postulating a more complex architecture for

–menos participles than for –tos forms. In section 3.2, we concentrate on the properties of –tos

verbal adjectives which lead to a revision of the Anagnostopoulou (2003)/ A&A (2008)

picture in two respects: (a) There are classes of –tos verbal adjectives which express negation

and possibility/ability (the latter implicating an agent). These involve attachment above

vP/VoiceP, similarly to –menos participles. (b) A class of –tos verbal adjectives involves

attachment below the little v head contributing eventiveness but not necessarily below

verbalizers. It thus follows that morphological verbalizers cannot be equated with abstract

eventivizing (little v) heads. In section 3.3, we address the generalizations governing (i) the

distribution of –menos vs. –tos in participles/ verbal adjectives and (ii) the presence vs.

absence of verbalizers in Greek verbal adjectives. We argue that the morphological piece –

menos is always associated with the Perfect of Result (Kratzer 1994, 2001), i.e. it is present

with participles expressing that the subject is in the target or result state of a prior event. On

the other hand, –tos is present in a heterogeneous set of cases all having in common that they

uniformly lack event implications. We furthermore propose that verbalizers in Greek verbal

adjectives are required on roots that do not fall under the basic ontological type “event”,

following Harley’s (2005) root-typology. Having revised and refined the Anagnostopoulou

(2003)/A&A (2008) picture of the –menos vs. –tos distinction, we finally proceed to the

question of idiomaticity. In section 4, we test (1)/(8) by comparing the interpretations of the

several types of –tos verbal adjectives to those of -menos participles and of the corresponding

verbs. We conclude that agentivity and not eventiveness is the key property blocking

idiomatic readings from participles, in accordance with Marantz (1996, 1997) and contra

Marantz (2001, 2007).

3.1. The simple A 2003/ A& A 2008 picture: -menos is an outer- and –tos an inner-affix

Next to adjectives, Greek has two adjectival constructions: the participle in –menos and what

traditional grammars call the “verbal adjective” in –tos:

6

(9) anig-men-os anix-t-os “opened”/ “open”

open-men-masc.sg.nom open-t-masc.sg.nom

They have a similar function to adjectives, i.e. they appear in attributive and predicative

positions:4

(10) a. to anih-t-o parathiro

the-neut.sg.nom open-t-neut.sg.nom window

‘the open window’

b. to anig-men-o parathiro

the-neut.sg.nom open-men-neut.sg.nom window

‘the opened window’

(11) a. to parathiro ine anih-t-o

the window is open-t-neut.sg.nom

‘the window is open’

b. to parathiro ine anig-men-o

the window is open-men-neut.sg.nom

‘the window is opened’

Participles and verbal adjectives show a number of semantic and syntactic differences

discussed in Markantonatou et al. (1996), Georgala (2001), Kordoni (2002), Anagnostopoulou

(2003), A&A (2008), among others. The most fundamental one is that –menos participles

denote a state resulting from a prior event, while –tos verbal adjectives lack event

implications. They denote what has been called “a characteristic state” by Markantonatou et

al. (1996). Consider the examples in (12):

(12) a. I patates ine tiganis-men-es

The potatoes are fry-men-fem.pl.nom

‘The potatoes are fried’

b. I patates ine tigani-t-es

The potatoes are fry-t-fem.pl.nom

‘The potatoes are fried’

(12a) conveys the meaning that the potatoes are fried as a result of a frying event: they have

been fried e.g. a minute ago and are now ready to be eaten. On the other hand, (12b) simply

expresses the fact that the potatoes are cooked in a particular way (“characteristic state”

interpretation): they are fried (rather than e.g. cooked). A context bringing out this difference

between the two adjectival forms is (13), based on Embick (2004: 357). As pointed out by

Embick, the complement of verbs of creation cannot be a state resulting from a prior event

because this would be a contradiction. And as can be seen in (13), –tos forms expressing

characteristic states are licit in such a context, while –menos participles are not, due to their

eventive subcomponent:

(13) a. I porta chtistike anix-t-i/ *anig-men-i

The door-Nom built-NAct,3sg open/ opened

‘The door was built open/*opened’

b. Magirepsa to kotopoulo vras-t-o/ *vras-men-o

Cooked-I the chicken boiled/ boiled

4 Passives are verbal in Greek and therefore there is never an ambiguity between verbal and adjectival passives

in Greek, unlike English.

7

‘I cooked the chicken boiled’

c. Eftiaksa tis patates tigani-t-es/ *tiganis-men-es

Made-I the potatoes fried/fried

‘I made the potatoes fried’

Crucially, the difference between the two forms with respect to event implications is

associated with a number of syntactic differences. –menos participles can be modified by

manner adverbs (14a) and can license by-phrases and instrument PPs (15a), while –tos verbal

adjectives cannot (14b, 15b):

(14) a. Afto to vivlio ine kala gra-men-o

This the book is well written

‘This book is well-written’

b. *Afto to kimeno ine kala grap-t-o

This the text is well written

(15) a. O tixos ine xtis-men-os me mistri/ apo ton ergati

The wall is built with trowel/ by the worker

‘The wall is built with a trowel/ by the worker’

b. *O tixos ine xtis-t-os me mistri/ apo ton ergati

The wall is built with trowel/ by the worker

Anagnostopoulou (2003), following Kratzer (2001), furthermore points out that -menos

participles can denote target and resultant states (Parsons 1990: 234-235). The former

describe states that are in principle reversible; the latter introduce states that hold forever after

the event that brings them about. Target state participles in (16) are compatible with the

adverbial akoma 'still', while resultant state participles in (17) are incompatible with it:

(16) Ta pedhia ine akoma krimena

The children are still hidden

(17) *To theorima ine akoma apodedigmeno

The theorem is still proven

Target and resultant state –menos participles are not only semantically but also syntactically

distinct. Target state –menos participles cannot license agent and instrument PPs and agentive

adverbials. As shown by (18), by-phrases and instrument phrases are incompatible with

akoma ‘still’:

(18) a. Ta lastixa ine (*akoma) fuskomena apo tin Maria

The tires are (still) inflated by the Mary

‘The tires are still inflated by Mary’

b. Ta lastixa ine (*akoma) fuskomena me tin tromba

The tires are (still) inflated with the pump

‘The tires are still inflated with the pump’

Moreover, note that there are two types of manner adverbials, i.e. (a) manner adverbs that are

result-oriented in that they modify the visible result of an event such as ‘sloppily’, ‘well’ and

(b) manner adverbs that modify the initiator of the action such as ‘carefully’, ‘deliberately’

8

(agent-oriented). As shown below, agent-oriented modifiers are incompatible with akoma

(19), while adverbs denoting the visible result (result-oriented) are compatible with it (20):

(19) To thisavrofilakio itan (*akoma) prosektika anigmeno

The safe was (still) cautiously opened

‘The safe was still cautiously opened’

(20) Ta malia mu ine (akoma) atsala xtenismena

The hair my is still sloppily combed

‘My hair is still sloppily combed’

On the basis of these considerations, A&A (2008) proposed that Greek has three types of

participles with three different structures, depending on the height of attachment of the

participle morpheme. According to A&A (2008), a layer Asp (=stativizer) attaches to the root

in –tos participles, to vP in –menos target state participles and to VoiceP in –menos resultant

state participles:

(21) [AspP Asp X] (where X= Root, vP or VP)

-tos verbal adjectives lack event implications (they are licensed after verbs of creation in (13),

they do not permit result-oriented modification) and agentivity (no agent-oriented

modification, no by-phrases and instruments). A&A (2008) take this to mean that they involve

root-attachment:

(22) ASP root attachment of Asp 3 ANIG ASP

OPEN

-t-

-menos target state participles which include the implication of an event (they are not licensed

after verbs of creation in (13), they license result oriented modifiers) but lack agentivity (no

agent-oriented modification, no by-phrases and instruments) involve v attachment (v is taken

by A&A 2008 to be the eventivizing head):

(23) Asp v attachment of Asp 3 v men 3 ANIG

open

Finally, -menos resultant state participles which include both implication of an event and

agentivity (agent-oriented modification, licensing of by-phrases and instruments) involve

Voice attachment (Voice is taken to introduce the external argument):

9

(24) Asp Voice attachment of Asp 3 Voice men 3 v 3 ANIG v

open

Important for present purposes is the proposal that –tos verbal adjectives instantiate ‘inner-

cycle’ attachment while –menos participles ‘outer-cycle’ attachment:

(25) root-cycle outer-cycle attachment

-menos functional head

-tos root

… root…

The distinction in (25) leads us to expect that –tos forms will show properties of inner

affixation and –menos forms of outer affixation from the perspective of hypotheses (1)/(8).

Prima facie evidence in favor of the “inner” vs. “outer” division in (25) comes from the

observation that there is a striking difference in the productivity of –menos as opposed to –tos

participles. While all verbs of the appropriate semantic type, i.e. all telic, many atelic and

even some (coerced?) statives, can form –menos participles, there are many gaps in the

formation of –tos participles. Some examples illustrating this are listed in (26):5

(26) a. vizag-menos *vizax-tos ‘nursed’

b. rimag-menos *rimax-tos ‘ruined’

c. doule-menos *doulef-tos ‘worked out’

d. louz-menos *lous-tos ‘shampoo bathed’

e. pirag-menos *pirax-tos ‘hurt, tampered

3.2. A more complex picture: different types of –tos participles

A closer look into the properties of –tos verbal adjectives reveals that the Anagnostopoulou

(2003)/ A&A (2008) classification of participles in (25) needs to be refined. As it turns out,

there are some clear cases of –tos involving outer cycle attachment and some more

controversial ones:

(I) A clear case of outer cycle attachment is discussed in Samioti (2008, in progress).

As pointed out by Markantonatou et al (1996), there is also a class of –tos participles denoting

ability/ possibility rather than characteristic state:

(27) a. Afti i dikaiologia ine pistef-t-i

This the excuse is believe-t-fem.sg.nom

‘This excuse can be believed/ is believable’

5

Note that out of 2722 verbs listed in the online Lexicon of Anastasiadi-Simeonidi

(http://www.komvos.edu.gr/dictionaries/dictOnLine/DictOnLineRev.htm) that have been checked so far, 688

verbs form both –menos and tos participles, 1866 form only –menos participles and 168 verbs only –tos

participles. These numbers need to be checked more carefully.

10

b. Afto to asteri ine ora-t-o

This the star is see-t-neut.sg.nom

‘This star can be seen/ is visible’

Other participles of this type are katortho-t-os ‘achievable’, bore-t-os ‘doable’, epitefk-t-os

‘doable’, antilip-t-os ‘perceivable’, aisthi-t-os ‘perceivable’, ap-t-os ‘touchable’, thea-t-os

‘visible’, ia-t-os ‘curable’, fori-t-os ‘transportable’, noi-t-os ‘conceivale, thinkable’, katanoi-t-

os ‘understandable’, anek-t-os ‘tolerable’, ipofer-t-os ‘tolerable’ etc. Samioti (2008, in

progress) argues that –tos in ability participles attaches above v. Evidence for this is drawn

from the fact that they license agent (28a) and instrument PPs (28b) and agent-oriented

adverbs of the type found in English middles (29):

(28) a. I istoria tou ine pistef-t-i apo olous.

The story his is believable by everyone

‘His story can be believed by everyone’

b. To vouno ine ora-t-o me kialia.

The mountain is visible with binoculars

‘The mountain is visible with binoculars’

(29) To mathima ine efkola katanoi-t-o.

the lesson is easily understandable

‘The lesson can be easily understood’

Samioti argues that ability –tos participles pattern syntactically with Greek middles as these

have been described by Lekakou (2005). According to Lekakou, the middle Voice in Greek is

a variant of the passive Voice, unlike English and other languages. An implicit external

argument is present and, therefore, by-phrases and instruments are licit (see Lekakou 2005 for

detailed argumentation). Adopting this analysis for ability/possibility participles, Samioti

proposes that –tos attaches to the (middle) VoiceP (see Samioti 2008, in progress, for details).

(II) A related, though less straightforward, case of high attachment is illustrated in

(30). Greek has a productive process yielding ability/possibility –tos participles which consist

of the verbal root and the adjectival prefix aksio- 'worth-':

(30) a. aksi-agapi-tos : worth loving

b. aksi-o-thavmas-tos: worth admiring

c. aksi-o-meleti-tos worth studying

d. aksi-o-katafroni-tos worth despising

Semantically, such formations clearly implicate an agent (a generic/ impersonal agent

corresponding to English “one”), pointing to the presence of Voice. Syntactically, they differ

from the participles in (27)-(29) in that they do not license adverbs and instruments, and

agentive PPs are marginally tolerated when they express universal quantification:

(31) a. To arthro ine aksiomeletito (*prosektika)

The article is worth-studying carefully

'The article is worth studying carefully'

b. O planitis ine aksiomeletitos (*me to tileskopio)

The planet is worth-studying with the telescope

'The planet is worth studying with the telescope'

11

c. To arthro ine aksiomeletito (?apo olus/ ?apo ton kathena

The article is worth-studying by all/ by the everyone/

?apo ton opjondipote)

by the anyone

'The article is worth being studied by all/ everyone/ by anyone'

Morphologically, these participles involve compounding, as evidenced by the fact that they

systematically employ the compound marker –o- indicated in (30) (see Ralli 2001, 2006 for

discussion of –o- in Greek).6 We tentatively suggest that they indeed contain Voice (perhaps

the type of “middle” Voice also contained in ability/possibility participles), while the

restrictions in (31) reduce to restrictions on compounding.7

(III) Negated participles instantiate a third case where, arguably and more

controversially, –tos participles present an instance of outer cycle attachment. Negated

participles obligatorily surface with –tos in Greek, as shown by the fact that the negated –

menos forms in (35) and ungrammatical. Note that, even in cases when there is no

corresponding non-negated –tos form available, such as (33) and (34), the presence of -tos

instead of –menos is triggered by negation:

(32) a. gra-men-os b. a-graf-t-os (grap-t-os)

written un-written

(33) a. pli-men-os b. a-pli-t-os (*pli-tos)

washed un-washed

(34) a. diavas-menos b. a-diavas-t-os (*diavas-tos)

read un-read

6 Some examples of compounds displaying this marker are the following:

(i) a. xart-o-peksia ‘card playing’

b. trapez-o-ipallilos ‘bank employee’

c. maxer-o-piruno ‘knife & fork’

d. Afstr-o-Ungaria ‘Austria-Hungary’ 7 The issue of compounding deserves further investigation. Samioti (in progress) compares the properties of

aksio-compounds to-tos participles involving compounding with the manner adverbs efkola- ‘easily’ and

dhiskola ‘with difficulty’. These are formations like efkol-o-diavas-tos lit. easy-read-tos “something that can be

easily read” and diskol-o-diavas-tos lit. difficult-read-tos “something hard to read’. Samioti points out the

following: (i) All three types of compounds disallow instrument PPs. (ii) In efkolo- and dhiskolo-compounds, the

adverbs efkola- ‘easily’ and dhiskola ‘with difficulty’ are manner adverbs, a fact which can potentially explain

why further manner adverbs cannot be licensed with them. Note, though, that this explanation does not

immediately carry over to aksio-compounds, because aksio- ‘worth’ is not a manner but rather an evaluative

adverb. (iii) Interestingly, aksio-compounds differ from efkolo- and dhiskolo- compounds w.r.t. the type of

agentive PP they license. While aksio-compounds marginally license PPs introduced by the preposition apo

‘from’, which generally introduces agents in Greek (see e.g. Alexiadou & Anagnostopoulou 2004, Alexiadou,

Anagnostopoulou & Schäfer 2006 for discussion and references), efkolo- and dhiskolo- compounds license

‘agentive’ PPs introduced by the preposition gia ‘for’, as in (i) (we would rather call these PPs ‘relevance’ PPs,

as they express the person for which something is easy or difficult to do):

(i) Afto to fagito ine efkol-o-magirefto gia oles tis nikokires

This the food is easily-cook-to for all the housewives

‘This food is easy to cook for all housewives’

A similar fact has been noted for some (though not all) middles, namely the existence of well-formed examples

like No Latin text translated easily for Bill (compare though to *These books don’t sell for the average

shopkeeper); see among others Stroik (1992, 1995, 1999) and Ackema & Schoorlemmer (1995) for discussion.

12

(35) a. *a-diavas-menos b. *a-pli-men-os

un-read un-washed

At first sight, negated participles behave as if they involve attachment to the root. They do not

imply a prior event, and this correlates with the lack of the key syntactic properties associated

with a vP/VoiceP architecture (see Anagnostopoulou 2003 following Kratzer 1994, and A&A

2008 who adopt a root-attachment analysis based on the facts in (36)-(38)). More specifically,

they resist manner modification, as illustrated in (36b), and they do not license by-phrases and

instruments, as shown in (37b) and (38b), respectively. In all respects they differ from their

non-negated –menos counterparts in (36a), (37a) and (38a):

(36) a. I Maria ine prosektika xtenis-men-i manner adverbs

The Maria is carefully combed

'Mary is carefully combed'

b. *I Maria ine aprosekta a-xtensi-t-i

The Maria is sloppily/not carefully un-combed

'*Mary is sloppily uncombed'

(37) a. To vivlio ine gra-men-o apo tin Maria by-phrases

The book is written by the Mary

'The book is written by Mary'

b. *To vivlio ine a-graf-t-o apo tin Maria

The book is unwritten by the Mary

'*The book is unwritten by Mary'

(38) a. To vivlio ine gra-men-o me grafomixani instruments

The book is written with typewritter

'The book is written with a typewritter'

b. *To vivlio ine a-graf-t-o me grafomixani

The book is unwritten with typewritter

'*The book is unwritten with a typewritter'

From the point of view of their productivity, morphology and interpretation, however, they

behave as if they involve outer cycle attachment (cf. Embick 2004: 359, fn 6 for English

negated un-participles). First, negated –tos participles are fully productive, similarly to –

menos partciples and unlike –tos ones. Second, in cases of morphologically conditioned stem

allomorphy, negated –tos participles do not show the same allomorphy as the corresponding

non-negated –tos form:

(39) a. a-graf-tos b. grap-tos c. *a-grap-tos

un-written written un-written

Third, they clearly form the negation of –menos participles, in cases where there is no

corresponding –tos form (see (33) and (34) above). And fourth, when all three forms exist,

negated participles negate –menos and not –tos participles. For example, a-graf-t-os in (32)

above means ‘something that has not been yet written’ and not ‘something that is not in a

written form’ (see Setatos 1984; Anastasiadi-Simeonidi 1994). But if negated participles

involve the negation of the –menos forms, then this leads to the postulation of an “outer-

cycle” architecture for them (contra Anagnostopoulou 2003 and A&A 2008). Under such an

analysis, the reason why -tos and not -menos surfaces on negated participles might be a

13

morpho-phonological one, related to stress: the suffix -ménos requires stress while the

negation prefix a- triggers obligatory recession of stress, a conflict resolved by the insertion

of -tos.

(IV) The final case we would like to discuss is the most interesting one from the

perspective of hypotheses (1)/(8) discussed in this paper. Note first that Greek productively

employs verbalizing suffixes which have been analyzed as root verbalizers by Alexiadou

(2001, 2009; see Giannakidou & Merchant 1999; Ralli 2001 for discussion of these elements):

(40) Root- verbalizing elements

Greek: -iz, - on-, -en/an, -ev,- -az, -a Alexiadou (2001, 2009):

(41) a. aspr-iz-o, kathar-iz-o b. pag-on-o ler-on-o

whiten cleaned freeze dirty

c. diaplat-en-o, arost-en-o d. sten-ev-o, berd-ev-o

widen, become sick tighten , confuse

e. diav-az-o, mir-az-o f. pul-a-o xal-a-o

read split, share sell destroy

As expected by the “outer-analysis” of –menos participles in (25), verbalizers (or their

allomorphs as in the (c), (f) examples) are systematically present in –menos participles,

providing morphological evidence for outer cycle attachment:

(42) a. aspr-iz-menos, kathar-iz-menos

whitened, cleaned

b. pag-o-menos, ler-o-menos

frozen, dirtied

c. diaplat-i-menos, arost-i-menos

widened, sickened

d. sten-e-menos, berd-e-menos

tightened, confused

e. diav-az-menos, mir-az-menos

read split, shared

f. pul-i-menos xal-az-menos

sold destroyed

Root verbalizers are often disallowed in –tos participles, a fact which was taken by A&A

(2008) as evidence for root attachment on –tos in (25):8

(43) a. *aspr-is-tos, *kathar-is-tos

whitened, cleaned

b. *pag-o-tos, *ler-o-tos

frozen, dirtied

c. *diaplat-i-tos, *arost-i-tos

widened, sickened

d. *sten-ef-tos, *berd-ef-tos

tightened, confused

8 For some of these examples (the ones based on adjectival roots) there is an alternative well-formed formation

based on the root + the adjectival ending:

*kathar-is-tos (cleaned) vs. kathar-os (clean), *aspr-is-tos (whitened) vs. aspr-os (white), *sten-ef-tos

(tightened) vs. sten-os (tight). A&A 2008 analyse this as an instance of blocking. See below for discussion.

14

e. *diav-as-tos, *mir-as-tos

read split, shared

But, quite unexpectedly, many Greek characteristic state –tos participles that do include such

verbalizing elements:

(44) a. axn-is-tos ‘steaming hot’ axn-iz-o ‘steam’

b. koudoun-is-tos ‘ringing’ koudoun-iz-o ‘ring (a bell)’

c. vathoul-o-tos ‘hollow’ vathoul-on-o ‘hollow out’

d. vid-o-tos ‘screwed’ vid-on-o ‘screw’

e. if-an-tos ‘woven’ if-en-o ‘weave’

f. magir-ef-tos ‘cooked’ magir-ev-o ‘cook’

g. fit-ef-tos ‘planted’ fit-ev-o ‘plant’

h. angali-as-tos ‘embraced’ angali-az-o ‘embrase’

i. evodi-as-tos ‘fragrant’ evodi-az-o ‘be fragrant’

Despite the presence of verbalizers, the –tos participles in (44) do not have event implications

(they denote characteristic states), and they do not license manner modification, agent PPs or

instruments:

(45) a. *To fagito ine kala/ prosektika magir-ef-t-o

The food is well/ carefully cooked

b. *To fagito ine magir-ef-t-o apo tin Maria

The food is cooked by the Mary

c. *Ta fita ine fit-ef-t-a me diaforetika ergalia

The plants are planted with different instruments

The characteristic state participles of the type illustrated in (44) are important to our

discussion, as they show that the abstract little v heads described in the decomposition

literature, i.e. the semi-functional heads introducing eventive interpretations (and licensing

result-oriented manner modification) must be dissociated from morphological verbalizers.

This poses an immediate problem concerning the proper understanding of (1) and (8): the

question is raised what counts as a phase head in –menos and –tos participles. The verbalizers

in (40) which are also present in –tos verbal adjectives like (44) or the abstract eventive little

v heads licensing modifiers and PPs, which are consistently absent from characteristic state –

tos verbal adjectives, even when they include a morphological verbalizer?

In the next sections, we will argue that morphological verbalizers indeed serve as

contexts for meaning assignment to unspecified roots, in accordance with (1)/(8), as these

generalizations have been interpreted by Arad (2003, 2005) in her work on Hebrew. But this

is a separate issue from the question of idiomatic interpretations, where the domain for

unpredictable meaning of participles is considerably larger, and neither verbalizers nor

eventivizers have a special status, but rather Voice.

3.3. Revisions and Generalizations

The discussion in the previous sections has led us to revise the typology of Greek verbal

adjectives in two respects:

a) First, –tos does not always attach below little v. There is one clear case where -tos attaches

above little v (ability –tos, Samioti 2008; in progress) and two more cases where -tos possibly

15

attaches above little v (aksio-compounding, negated –tos participles). It is an open question at

this point whether the different types of –tos verbal adjectives involve a single morphological

piece -tos inserted in stative environments lacking event implications, with the three different

interpretations resulting from the specific environments of insertion (a case of polysemy) or

whether Greek has three different -tos, i.e. ability -tos, negation -tos, characteristic state –tos

(a case of homophony). It is interesting though that Greek is not unique in showing the same

morphology for stativized expressions and for expressions denoting ability/possibility, i.e. the

counterparts of –able adjectives in English. Chichewa (Dubinsky & Simango 1996: 759, ex.

(17)) and Malagasy (Travis 2005) are similar in this respect.

b) Second, the morphological decomposition of –tos characteristic state verbal adjectives

leads to the identification of verbalizing heads in a number of cases, as was shown by the

examples (44). Crucially, as shown by (45), these morphological verbalizers do not have the

syntactico-semantic properties of the abstract little v head identified and discussed in the

decomposition literature (Embick 2004; Alexiadou, Anagnostopoulou & Schäfer 2006;

Marantz 2001, 2007; Harley 2012 and related literature), i.e. they do not contribute

eventiveness nor do they license modifiers and argumental PPs. Alexiadou (2009) reaches

exactly the same conclusion for result nominals in Greek, which may contain a verbalizer

which however does not contribute eventiveness and does not license arguments.

In view of these revisions, what are then the generalizations governing (i) the

distribution of –menos vs. –tos in participles/ verbal adjectives and (ii) the presence vs.

absence of verbalizers in Greek verbal adjectives?

Starting from the first issue, the affix –menos signifies the Perfect of Result, i.e. it is

present whenever the participle denotes a target or resultant state resulting from a prior event

(Kratzer 1994; 2001). For –tos it is unclear whether it presents a case of polysemy or

homophony. Under the first option, there is a single morphological piece –tos inserted

whenever there is no prior event implied, maybe as an elsewhere form in the absence of a

Perfect of Result operator. Alternatively, there are three different –tos morphemes, namely

ability -tos, characteristic state –tos, and the negated Perfect of Result -tos inserted for

morphophonological reasons. We conclude that verbal adjectives with –tos involve either

inner- or outer-cycle attachment, contra A&& (2008), namely:

(i) Ability/ possibility –tos forms clearly show outer-cycle attachment, and they contain a

(middle) VoiceP.

(ii) –tos forms involving ‘aksi-o-’ compounding (e.g. aksi-o-meletitos ‘worth-studying’)

possibly also contain a VoiceP and hence are formed by outer-cycle attachment.

(iii) When a target/ resultant state participle is negated there are semantic and

morphological reasons for positing –tos attachment above vP or VoiceP, though the syntactic

evidence is less clear.

(iv) Characteristic state verbal adjectives do not have event implications and lack all

syntactic properties associated with a little v head providing evidence for inner-cycle

attachment. They pose, however, a puzzle. While –tos attaches directly to the root in a

number of cases, it attaches to the Root+verbalizer in another set of cases. This leads to the

second question that needs to be addressed, namely what is the explanation for the presence

vs. absence of morphological verbalizers in –tos characteristic state participles. In answering

this question, we would like to pursue hypothesis (46):

(46) Selection hypothesis:

-tos selects expressions naming events

16

With Harley (2005) we assume that roots fall into basic ontological types naming events,

things and states. We can then formulate the following generalizations concerning the

absence or presence of verbalizers inside –tos:

Generalization I: -tos directly attaches to roots which can be characterized as

Rootevent in terms of Harley’s ontology, as shown in (47). These forms involve roots with a

specified meaning (they express particular types of events) yielding verbs (as in the first

column of 47) by combining with the verbal inflectional ending either directly (as in

47b,d,e,f,g) or via the formative –n- (in 47a,c).9

(47) a. ftiax-n-o ‘make’ ftiax-tos ‘made’

b. lin-o ‘loosen’ li-tos ‘loose’

c. per-n-o ‘take’ par-tos ‘taken’

d. klev-o ‘steal’ klef-tos ‘stolen’

e. din-o ‘give’ do-tos ‘given’

f. plek-o ‘knit’ plek-tos ‘knitten’

g. klin-o ‘close’ klis-tos ‘closed’

In these cases, the selection requirement of –tos stated in (46) is satisfied because –tos

directly combines with roots naming events (and see fn. 6 on the question of whether root or

stem is the appropriate notion).

Generalization II: -tos does not combine with Rootthing. It combines with Rootthing +

verbalizer10

. In a number of cases illustrated in (48) roots have a specified meaning naming a

thing and can be combined directly with nominal inflection forming a noun (first column in

48). –tos cannot directly combine with such roots. As shown by the third column in (48), they

first become verbal by combining with a verbalizer (cf. the second column in (48) where such

roots are turned into verbs by a verbalizer plus the verbal inflection), and then –tos attaches to

the root + verbalizer complex:

(48) a. afr-os ‘foamN’ afr-iz-o ‘foamV’ afr-is-tos ‘foaming’

b. axn-os ‘steamN’ axn-iz-o ‘steamV’ axn-is-tos ‘steaming hot’

c. vid-a ‘screwN’ vid-on-o ‘screwV’ vid-o-tos ‘screwed’

d. koudoun-i ‘ringN’ koudoun-iz-o ‘ringV’ koudoun-is-tos ‘ringing’

e. koumb-i ‘buttonN’ koumb-on-o ‘buttonV’ koumb-o-tos ‘buttoned’

f. skep-i ‘roof’ skep-az-o ‘cover’ skep-as-tos ‘covered’

Note that in some cases, such as (49), the denominal verb formed by the Rootthing + verbalizer

is deviant (second column in 49, i.e. such expressions cannot name events and therefore they

cannot be verbs), while the corresponding –tos participle is perfect:

(49) kamban-a ‘bellN’ ??kamban-iz-o ‘bellV’ kamban-is-tos ‘sounding like a bell’

We propose that the presence of a verbalizer in formations of this kind is necessary to satisfy

the selection requirements of –tos in (46).

9 There are a number of further observations one can make here. First, the absence of –n- in the verbal adjectives

as in (47a) could be viewed as evidence that –tos directly attaches to the root and not to the verb, if it can be

ensured that the reason for the absence of –n- is not morpho-phonological. Second, in (47c, e, g) –tos attaches to

the perfective stem (marked by stem allomorphy in 47c, e and by the presence of –s- in 47g), a fact that could, in

principle, receive either a semantic or a phonological explanation. The question raised by such examples is to

what extent it is legitimate to talk in these cases about –tos attachment to roots rather than stems. We have to

leave these questions open for now. 10

See Alexiadou, 2009, for discussion of such formations.

17

An issue that needs to be discussed at this point concerns the criteria by which the

verbal and adjectival forms in the second and third columns of (48), (49) above are indeed

root derived (based on Rootthing), as opposed to being derived from zero related nouns (e.g.

based on Root plus a little n with a zero exponent). A way to decide this is to apply Kiparsky's

(1982) criteria. Kiparsky argues that root-based formations do not entail the existence of the

corresponding nouns while noun-derived ones do entail the existence of the corresponding

nouns (see Arad 2003, 2005 for extensive discussion of Hebrew based on Kiparsky). For

many of the forms in (48), (49) it can indeed be demonstrated that they are root derived. For

example, vidono and vidotos in (48c) do not entail the existence of a screw but rather they

refer to the type of movement required for putting two pieces together. In a similar manner,

koumbono and koumbotos in (48e) do not entail the existence of a button (they refer to closing

something by making use of a particular device), koudounizo and koudounistos (48d)

/kambanistos (49) do not entail the existence of a ring/bell (they mean sounding like a

ring/bell), skepazo and skepastos (48f) do not entail a roof (they mean cover and being

covered) and axnizo and axnistos (48b) do not entail steam (they mean hot and cosy like

anything that is steaming hot).11

Generalization III: As shown in (50), -tos does not combine with Rootstate + verbalizer

because there is an adjective blocking the –tos form (as pointed out by A&A 2008).

(50) aspr-iz-o 'whiten' aspr-iz-men-os aspr-os/i/o 'white' *is-tos

mavr-iz-o 'blacken' mavr-iz-men-os mavr-os/i/o 'black' *is-tos

kitrin-iz-o 'yellow' kitrin-iz-men-os kitrin-os/i/o 'yellow' *is-tos

prasin-iz-o 'green' prasin-iz-men-os prasin-os/i/o 'green' *is-tos

kathar-iz-o 'clean' kathar-iz-men-os kathar-os/i/o 'clean' *is-tos

megal-on-o 'grow' megal-o-men-os megalos 'big' *o-tos

In principle, however, the formation Rootstate + verbalizer + tos is possible. And indeed, such

forms do exist, but they have specialized uses. For example, the –tos form in (51) is used only

for food:

(51) kokin-iz-o 'redden' kokin-os/i/o 'red' kokin-is-tos ‘with a red sauce’

Overall, we have checked many –tos participles containing the verbalizers –iz-, -az-, -ar-, -

on-, -ev-, and it turns out that the majority of them are as in (48)/(49), i.e. they are based on

Rootthing+ verbalizer. These have corresponding nouns of the form Rootthing+ nominal

inflection. A few –tos participles with a verbalizer are based on Rootstate (adjective or adverb/

preposition), as in (51) and (52) below:

(52) a. stogil-ev-tos round-ef-tos ‘round/ rounded’

b. thab-o-tos misty-o-tos ‘misty/ blurred’

c. xor-is-tos without-is-tos ‘separate’

d. antam-o-tos together-o-tos ‘together’

There is a final set of cases, to be discussed immediately, which leads to a particular

interpretation of the hypothesis (1)/(8).

11

Of course, one would have to check all such formations available in the Greek lexicon in order to draw firm

conclusions concerning this issue. For example, by Kiparsky’s criteria the verbal and adjectival forms in (48a)

seem to qualify as being based on a zero-derived noun.

18

Generalization IV: verbalizers turn undefined roots into Constructevent and then –tos attaches

to the Rootundefined + verbalizer. A group of –tos participles is based on a Root with no clear

meaning (call it Rootundefined ) which combines with a verbalizer. This type of root has

unspecified meaning in the sense that (a) one couldn’t assign an exact meaning to it and (b)

there is no corresponding noun or adjective or verb of the form Rootundefined + Inflection. Two

different subcases fall under this category.

(i) A number of undefined roots represent sounds or movements or shapes (they are often

formed by reduplication). A verbalizer must necessarily attach to them before they become

verbs (surfacing with verbal inflectional endings), and then they enter further derivation

(becoming adjectives, as in (53), or nouns):

(53) a. kakar-is-tos ‘cackling’

b. tsitsir-is-tos ‘sizzling / frizzling’

c. trekl-is-tos ‘staggering’

d. tourtour-is-tos ‘shivering / shuddering’

e. gourl-o-tos ‘goggling’

f. koxl-as-tos ‘bubbling’

g. xarxal-ef-tos ‘rummaging’

h. paspat-ef-tos ‘fiddling’

(ii) There is a residue of roots which seem completely and totally undefined before a

verbalizer attaches to them, making them of type “event”. –tos suffixation follows:

(54) a. kt-is-tos ‘built’

b. sk-is-tos ‘slit’

c. str-o-tos ‘smooth, regular’

d. lig-is-tos ‘bent’

e. sik-o-tos ‘raised’

The two types of roots described above, especially the ones in (54), seem to us to be very

close to what Arad (2003, 2005) describes for Hebrew. One couldn’t exactly tell what they

mean. According to Arad (2003, 2005), there are two types of languages: In Hebrew-type

languages (also Georgian, Russian) roots may be assigned numerous interpretations in

different morphophonological environments (MCM). This correlates with the fact that (i)

roots are semantically underspecified and (ii) the inventory of roots in the languages in

question is small. On the other hand, in English-type languages most roots are assigned

meaning in one environment only (exception to this are Latinate bound roots like √fer, √cieve

etc.; see fn 12 below). This correlates with the fact that (i) they are semantically specified and

(ii) the inventory of roots is large. Greek seems to be an English-type language. A large

number of Greek roots are semantically specified.12

However, there are exceptions to this in

both English (the latinate roots mentioned above; see also fn. 12) and Greek (see Alexiadou &

Anagnostopoulou 2011, to appear for discussion of the Greek counterparts of words based on

proto-indoeuropean roots, where prefixes drawn from the Ancient Greek prepositional

inventory fix the meaning of unspecified roots). The examples in (53), (54) constitute a

further class of exceptions. In the cases listed in (53) and (54) lack of clear/ stable meaning

correlates with the inability to classify the roots according to Harley's ontology. Adding a

verbalizer to these roots on the one hand makes them classifiable in terms of Harley’s basic

12

As in English, exception to this are roots with a proto-Indo-European origin like √fer. These form multiple

verbs with very different interpretations depending on the prefix they combine with: dia-fer-o: differ, pro-fer-o:

pronounce, ana-fer-o: report, pros-fer-o: offer, ek-fer-o: formulate.

19

ontology and at the same time it fixes their meaning, which is then retained throughout the

derivation. We believe that this double function of verbalizers in the case at hand provides a

key towards understanding why categorizers serve as contexts for meaning assignment to

unspecified roots. Roots must be classifiable in terms of a basic ontology naming events,

things and states. If they are not, as in (53), (54) or in the cases of the Hebrew type MCM

Arad discusses, a categorizing head serves to classify them. The classification itself makes

them acquire what is sensed as fixed “meaning”, which is then retained throughout the

derivation. We conclude that the Greek facts in (53) and (54) support an interpretation of

(1)/(8) along the lines of Arad (2003, 2005), where the crucial head is the categorizing head

(in the cases we discuss vC) which makes roots classifiable in terms of Harley’s (2005) basic

ontology.

3.4. Summary: How many participles?

We have arrived at the following picture of Greek adjectival participles and verbal adjectives

w.r.t. the question of outer vs. inner cycle architecture:

(55) Greek Participles and Verbal Adjectives

1) Two types of -menos participles:

a) target state -menos participles outer attachment

b) resultant state -menos participles outer attachment

2) Four types of -tos participles:

a) ability -tos participles, outer attachment

b) aksio- compounding -tos participles outer attachment (possibly)

c) negation -tos participles outer attachment (possibly)

d) characteristic state -tos participles : direct attachment to Rootevent

attachment to Rootthing+ verbalizer

attachment to Rootstate+ verbalizer

attachment to Rootundefined+ verbalizer

(56) root-cycle = tos + Rootevent outer-cycle attachment= ability-tos

-tos VoiceP

-tos root

Voice … root…

Does not count as outer-cycle = tos + [Rootthing/state/undefined + verbalizer]

3 -tos 3

v root

There is one question raised by these participles which will only be mentioned briefly and

will not be answered here concerning the polysemy vs. homophony issue mentioned earlier in

20

the paper. In principle, this question can be asked for both –menos participles and –tos

participles. For –menos participles the question is the following. Are there two different –

menos suffixes one yielding target states and one yielding resultant states which have

different selection requirements and different syntax (target state –menos necessarily

attaching below Voice) or is there one –menos yielding resultant states or target states

depending on the context of insertion? In view of the close similarity in meaning between

resultant and target state participles, we are inclined to think that the second option is more

plausible: there is only one –menos suffix yielding states resulting from events; the resultant

vs. target state difference must derive from the context, e.g. the idiosyncratic properties of the

root, the size of the complement (if the complement is VoiceP then the state is necessarily a

resultant state), plus some further properties of the structure. For example, the presence of

adverbs has been noted by Kratzer to provide the component necessary for a target state to

verbal roots otherwise yielding resultant states ((57) is Kratzer’s example (21)):

(57) a. * Meine Haare waren immer noch geschnitten.

My hairs were still cut

‘My hair was still cut’

b. Meine Haare waren immer noch schlampig geschnitten

My hairs were still sloppily cut

‘My hair was still cut sloppily’

For –tos the issue is more involved since it is not clear that –tos has a uniform semantics in

characteristic state participles, negated participles and ability/possibility participles.

Moreover, the cross-linguistic evidence we reviewed does not provide straightforward support

in favor of the one over the other alternative hypothesis. On the one hand, English

distinguishes –ed (in negated and simple state adjectival participles) from –able (for

ability/possibility adjectives) supporting the homophony hypothesis. On the other hand,

Chichewa and Malagasy use the same element for both types of adjectives, like Greek,

providing crosslinguistic support in favor of the polysemy alternative (the unifying property

of all three kinds being the absence of a prior event).

Turning to the issue of non-compositionality discussed in this paper, characteristic state –

tos verbal adjectives are particularly relevant to the hypothesis (1)/(8) for two reasons:

a) First, they present evidence that the presence of a verbalizer does not, in itself,

contribute eventiveness and the syntactic properties associated with it.

b) Second, they present evidence that the presence of a verbalizer fixes the meaning of

unspecified roots which cannot be classified according to Harley's typology.13

We are now in a position to turn to the question of idiomaticity. We do so in the next section,

and we refer the reader to Anagnostopoulou & Samioti (in progress) for a more complete

discussion.

4. A bigger domain for Idioms

4.1. Neither vC nor vE are not boundaries for idioms

We assume a working definition of idioms along the lines of Svenonius (2005: 1): “....listed

syntactic structures which […] have unpredictable meanings in the way words do, but consist

of more than one “piece”. In multi-word idioms, “piece” is the phonological word. In single-

13

The cases where aspectual prefixes determine the meaning of verbal (i.e. event denoting) roots, as in English

with words based on Latinate roots, in Russian (Arad 2003: 775, 2005) and in Greek (mentioned in footnote 12)

should also be taken into account and might lead to a partial modification of this statement.

21

word idioms “piece” is the head (Roots, affixes). Here we are looking at single word

idioms. In view of the dissociation between verbalizing heads (categorizing heads, vC) and

little v (the head contributing eventiveness, licensing arguments etc., vE) introduced in the

previous discussion, the Marantz/ Arad hypothesis as a hypothesis about idioms can, in

principle, be tested in two ways:

a) Taking literally the proposal that once a root is categorized it is assigned a range of

meanings fixed for the rest of the derivation, what should be tested is whether the presence of

a verbalizer in –tos participles yields such an effect. In other words, are there significant

differences between –tos verbal adjectives with a verbalizer and –tos adjectives without a

verbalizer w.r.t. idiomaticity, in comparison to the corresponding verbs?

b) Assuming, alternatively, that it is the presence of eventive v which defines a cyclic

domain for interpretation (phase), it should be tested whether the presence of an eventive

little v fixes meaning in a way that affixes attached above it always lead to predictable

interpretations (outer affixation). In other words, are there significant differences between –

tos and –menos forms and the corresponding verbs w.r.t. idiomaticity?

The answer to the first question is negative. The internal composition of –tos verbal

adjectives denoting characteristic states does not correlate in any way with (non-)idiomaticity.

Characteristic state verbal adjectives of both types (simplex without a verbalizer or complex

with a verbalizer) can have idiomatic readings lacking from the corresponding verbs. This is

illustrated in (58) and (59) below:

Characteristic state -tos verbal adjectives showing direct attachment of –tos to Rootevent:

Verb Participle Idiomatic interpretation

of participle only

(58) a. sfing-o sfix-tos

tighten tight ‘careful with money’

b. ftin-o ftis-tos

spit lit. spitted ‘spitting image’

c. klin-o klis-tos

close lit. closed ‘introverted’

Characteristic state -tos verbal adjectives showing attachment of –tos to Root+ verbalizer:

Verb Participle Idiomatic interpretation

of participle only

(59) a. kol-a-o kol-i-tos ‘close friend’

glue-1sg lit. glued

b. xtip-a-o xtip-i-tos ‘striking’

bang, hit, whip lit. whipped

c. xon-ev-o xon-ef-tos ‘inside the wall’

digest no lit. meaning

d. karf-on-o karf-o-tos ‘very fast/ direct’

nail no lit. meaning

The answer to the second question is again negative. -menos participles may have

idiosyncratic meanings, just like the –tos verbal adjectives in (58) and (59):

(60) striv-o stri-menos geros strif-to tsigaro

twist 'crotchety old man’ lit. twisted (rolled) cigarette

22

Strikingly, the –menos participle in example (60) only has the idiomatic reading when

modifying a [+human] noun, while the verb and the –tos participle can only have the literal

meaning. But this is the reverse of what is expected if (1)/(8) are understood as applying to

idioms and if the relevant phase head is taken to be vE (the abstract eventivizing head). What

would be expected under such an interpretation of (1)/(8) is that the characteristic state –tos

participle has the idiomatic reading and the –menos participle the compositional meaning. It

is furthermore expected that the idiomatic reading of the –menos participle depends on the

idiomatic interpretation of the corresponding verb, i.e. exactly the opposite of what we see in

(60). As we discuss in detail in Anagnostopoulou & Samioti (in progress), there is extensive

evidence that there is no necessary correlation between the meaning of verbs and the meaning

of the corresponding –menos participles. We distinguish between the following three cases:

i. Idiomatic verb Non-idiomatic participle

kathar-iz-o kathar-iz-menos

lit. ‘clean’ only lit. ‘cleaned’

idiom. ‘kill’

(61) a. ton katharisan xtes to vrady

him cleaned-3sg yesterday the evening

‘They killed him yesterday evening’

b. ?aftos o anthropos ine katharismenos

this the man is cleaned

‘This man is cleaned’

ii. Non-idiomatic verb Idiomatic participle

trav-a-o trav-ig-menos

only lit. ‘pull’14

lit. pulled

idiom ‘far fetched’

Verb

(62)

a. O Janis travik-s-e tin porta

The Janis pulled the door

‘Janis pulled the door’

b. *O Janis travik-s-e to epixirima

The Janis pulled the argument

‘*Janis pulled the argument’

Participle

(63) a. ?I porta ine trav-ig-meni

The door is pulled

‘Janis is pulled’ lit interpretation

14

This verb can have an idiomatic reading as a phrasal idiom (i) either when it combines with the prefix para

(meaning exaggeration) or when combined with clitic doubled object to skini ‘the rope’:

(i) a. O Janis to paratravikse

The Janis it para-pulled

‘John went too far’

b. O Janis to travikse to skini

The Janis it pulled the rope

‘John went too far’

Crucially, for present purposes, one does not ‘pull the argument’ or ‘pull the story’; compare (62b) to (63b).

23

b. To epixirima ine trav-ig-meno

The argument is pulled

‘The argument is far fetched’ Only idiom. interpretation

iii. Idiomatic verb: one meaning Idiomatic participle: another

(64) xon-ev-o xon-e-menos

lit. ‘digest’ lit. ‘digested’

idiom. ‘like’ idiom. ‘understood’

Verb – Participle literal

(65) a. O Janis xonep-s-e to fagito

The Janis digested the food

‘Janis digested the food’

b. To fagito ine xone-meno

The food is digested

‘The food is digested’

Verb idiomatic – Participle idiomatic

(66) a. O Janis den xonevi ta mathimatika

The Janis not digests the math

‘Janis dislikes mathematics’

b. Ta mathimatika den ine xone-mena

The mathematics not are digested

‘Math is not understood

In conclusion, neither vC nor vE constitute boundaries for idiosyncratic/ un-predictable/ non-

compositional meanings of participles in Greek, contrary to what one might expect on the

basis of (1)/(8).

4.2. Agentive Voice is a boundary for idioms

While idiomatic interpretations are not blocked by vC or vE, agentive features systematically

destroy non-compositional interpretations of –tos and –menos forms. Specifically:

(a) –tos verbal adjectives denoting ability/ possibility which implicate an agent, never

have idiomatic readings. All participles belonging to this class have exactly the same

meanings as the corresponding verbs, and their interpretations are always predictable. Some

of these forms are listed below:

(67) katortho-t-os ‘achievable’, bore-t-os ‘able’ ‘doable’, epitefk-t-os ‘doable’, antilip-t-os

‘perceivable’, aisthi-t-os ‘perceivable’, ap-t-os ‘touchable’, thea-t-os ‘visible’, ia-t-os

‘curable’, fori-t-os ‘transportable’, noi-t-os ‘conceivale, thinkable’, katanoi-t-os

‘understandable’, anek-t-os ‘tolerable’, ipofer-t-os ‘tolerable’ etc.

(b) Whenever the adjectival prefix aksio- (‘worth’) combines with a idiomatic

participle yielding a modal ability/possibility interpretation which implicates an implicit

agent, the non-compositional meaning is lost, as shown in (68):

24

(68)

a. trav-ig-menos aksi-o-travix-tos

lit. pulled only lit: worth pulling

idiom ‘far fetched’

b. stri-menos aksi-o-strif-tos

lit. twisted only lit: worth twisting

idiom. ‘crotchety’

(c) Agentive adverbs like ‘deliberately’ and agent-oriented manner adverbs like

´carefully’ systematically block idiomatic interpretations (see Alexiadou, Anagnostopoulou &

Schäfer among many others for discussion of these properties in connection to agentive

Voice):

(69)

a. trav-ig-menos prosektika / skopima travigmenos

lit. pulled only lit.: carefully/ deliberately pulled

idiom ‘far fetched’

b. stri-menos prosektika/ skopima strimenos

lit. twisted only lit: carefully/ deliberately twisted

idiom. ‘crotchety’

(d) The same effect is trigerred by agentive and instrument PPs in (70):

(70) stri-menos jeros idiom. ‘crotchety man’

BUT

stri-menos apo kapion/ me kati only lit. ‘twisted by someone / with something’

The effects of agentivity illustrated above are consistent with Marantz’s (1996, 1997)

generalization that the syntactic head that projects an agent defines a locality domain for

special meanings:

(71)

3 boundary for domain of special meaning (Marantz’s 1997 (6))

agent 3 v

head projecting agent

Predictions: (Marantz’s 1997 (7)):

(72) a. No idioms with fixed agents

(root in agent position, context for special meaning)

b. No eventive-passive idioms, but possible non-eventive stative idioms)

c. No idioms with causative morpheme and lower agentive verb, but

possible idioms with causative and lower non-agentive verb)

In Marantz’s (1997) system, the difference between verbal and adjectival participles w.r.t.

idiomaticity, i.e. prediction (72b), is linked to agentivity; in Marantz (2001, 2007), on the

other hand, it is linked to the verbal/eventive vs. adjectival/stative nature of English

participles. While the two hypotheses are difficult to tell apart on the basis of English

participles which collapse agentivity with eventiveness and verb-hood, and lack of agentivity

25

with stativity and adjective-hood, the Greek data discussed in this paper show that agentivity

and not eventiveness or verb-hood is crucial. Throughout the paper and in this section, we

have only looked at adjectival/ stative forms with or without verbalizers, event implications

and agentivity. We saw that idiomatic meanings freely occur with –menos participles and -tos

verbal adjectives as long as the relevant morphological constructs do not implicate an agent.

But when agentivity features are present, compositional interpretations are enforced on both –

tos and –menos forms preserving the literal meanings of the corresponding verbs. Assuming,

furthermore, that agentivity is linked to the head Voice, this leads to the conclusion that Voice

is a boundary for special meanings within the word. In an approach based on phasehood, this,

in turn, entails that Voice and not v qualifies as a phase head (in line with Chomsky 2001;

contra Marantz 2007).

5. Concluding remarks

In this paper, we discussed the issue of (non-)compositionality of meaning on the basis of a

case study, namely Greek –menos participles and –tos verbal adjectives denoting

characteristic state, negation and ability/possibility. We investigated the Marantz/Arad

hypothesis in (1)

(1) The Marantz / Arad Hypothesis

Roots are assigned an interpretation in the context of the first category assigning

head/ phase head merged with them, which is then fixed throughout the derivation

and addressed two questions:

First, which head counts as a phase head for meaning assignment, the abstract

eventivizing head vE or the verbal categorizing head vC? We provided evidence in favor of

dissociating the two heads based on Greek characteristic state –tos verbal adjectives which

lack event implications but can include verbalizing heads. We offered some evidence that

verbalizing heads lacking event implications indeed serve as contexts for meaning assignment

to roots that have completely unspecified meaning and are therefore not classifiable in terms

of a basic typology “thing”, “event”, “state” (Harley 2005). This is in line with what Arad

(2003), (2005) proposes for Hebrew.

The second question concerns idiomaticity within words, what is the domain for

special meaning in single word idioms. We argued that this domain is larger than the first

phase head, whether we take the relevant head to be vE or vC. The boundary for special

meanings is Voice, i.e. the head that syntactically projects and agent, as proposed by Marantz

(1996, 1997) and contra Marantz (2001, 2007).

After we wrote the first draft of this paper, it came to our attention that Marantz (2011)

revises his 2001/2007 position with respect to idioms and adopts a view very close to the one

argued for in the present paper. Marantz (2011) distinguishes between two meaning domains:

(a) What he calls “the domain for contextual allosemy”. This is determined immediately, by

the first phase head, a contentful categorizing head, vE in our terms. Marantz argues that the

vC head we identify in our work on Greek participles (i.e. the verbalizer included in

characteristic state –tos participles) should be viewed as a semantically null head, akin to do

in English do-support, which, being semantically empty, does not block the (meaning

assignment) relationship between the phase head above it (taken to be little a, the adjective

forming head) and the root below it. (b) The domain for idioms. This must be separated from

contextual allosemy, and it has as a boundary the Voice head that introduces the external

argument, in accordance with Marantz (1996, 1997). We discuss Marantz (2011) in more

26

detail in Anagnostopoulou & Samioti (in progress), where we focus on the domains for

idioms.

References Ackema, P. & Schoorlemmer, M. (1995), Middles and nonmovement. Linguistic Inquiry 26:173–197.

Alexiadou, A. (2001), Functional structure in nominals: nominalisation and ergativity (Amsterdam:

John Benjamins,).

Alexiadou, A. 2009. On the role of syntactic locality in morphological processes: the case of Greek

nominals. A. Giannakidou & M. Rathert, QP, Nominalizations and the role of DP. Oxford

University Press.

Alexiadou, A & E. Anagnostopoulou. 2004 Voice Morphology in the Causative-Inchoative

Alternation. Evidence for a Non-Unified Structural Analysis of Unaccusatives. In: A. Alexiadou,

E. Anagnostopoulou and M. Everaert (Eds.) The Unaccusativity Puzzle,114-136. Oxford: OUP.

Alexiadou, A. & E. Anagnostopoulou. 2008. Structuring participles. Proceedings of WCCFL 26.

Alexiadou, A & E. Anagnostopoulou. 2011. Decomposing the Greek verb. The view from the clear-

alternation. Paper presented at Approaches to the Lexicon (Roots II), The Hebrew University of

Jerusalem, June 13-16.

Alexiadou, A & E. Anagnostopoulou. To appear. Manner vs. Result Complementarity in Verbal

Alternations: A View from the Clear-Alternation. To appear in the Proceedings of NELS 42,

University of Toronto.

Alexiadou, A., E. Anagnostopoulou & F. Schäfer. 2006. The Properties of Anticausatives Cross-

linguistically. In M. Frascarelli (ed.), Phases of Interpretation. Mouton de Gruyter, 187-212.

Anagnostopoulou, E. 2003. Participles and Voice. In A. Alexiadou, M. Rathert & A. von Stechow

(eds.) Perfect Explorations. Mouton de Gruyter.

Αναστασιάδη-Συμεωνίδη, Α. 1994. Το τεμάχιο –τος στα ρηματικά επίθετα της Νεοελληνικής. Studies

in Greek linguistics 15: 473- 484.

Anderson, S. 1982. Where's Morphology? Linguistic Inquiry 13: 571-612.

Anderson, S. 1992. A-Morphous Morphology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Arad, M. 2003. Locality constraints on the interpretation of roots: The case of Hebrew denominal

verbs. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 21: 737–778.

Arad, M. 2005. Roots and patterns: Hebrew morpho-syntax. Dordrecht: Springer.

Aronoff, M. 1976. Word formation in generative grammar. Linguistic Inquiry Monograph 1.

Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Baker, M. 1985. The Mirror Principle and Morphosyntactic Explanation. Linguistic Inquiry 36: 373-

416.

Baker, M. 1988. Incorporation. A Theory of Grammatical Function Changing. Chicago, Illinois:

University of Chicago Press.

Borer, H. 2003. Exo-skeletal vs. endo-skeletal explanations: syntactic projections and the lexicon. M.

Polinsky & J. Moore (eds.) Explanation in Linguistic Theory. Stanford: CSLI.

Borer, H. 2005. Structuring Sense. Oxford: OUP.

Chomsky, N. 1970. Remarks on Nominalization. Studies on Semantics in Generative Grammar, 11-

61. The Hague: Mouton.

Chomsky, N. 2000. Minimalist inquires: The framework. In: Martin, R./Michaels, D./uriagereka, J.

(ed.) Step by step. Essays on Minimalist Syntax in Honor of Howard Lasnik, 89-151. Cambridge

Mass: MIT Press.

Chomsky, N. 2001. Derivation by phase. Ken Hale: a life in language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Dubinsky, S. & Simango, R. 1996. Passive and stative in Chichewa: Evidence for Modular

Distinctions in Grammar. Language 72: 749-81.

Embick, D . 2004. On the structure of resultative participles in English, Linguistic Inquiry 35: 355-

392.

Embick, D. 2010. Localism vs. Globalism in Morphology and Phonology. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.

27

Georgala, E. 2001. The translational correspondence between the Modern Greek formations ending in –tos

and –menos and their equivalent forms in German. Ms. Institute for Natural Language Processing of the

University of Stuttgart.

Giannakidou, A. & J. Merchant. 1999. Why Giannis can’t scrub his plate clean: On the absence of

resultative secondary predication in Greek. In A. Mozer (ed.) Greek Linguistics’ 97: Proceedings of

the 3rd

International Conference on Greek Linguistics, 93-103. Athens: Ellinika Grammata.

Hale, K, & Keyser, J. 1993. On argument structure and the lexical expression of syntactic relations.

K. Hale & S. J. Keyser. (eds.) The View from Building 20: 53-109. Essays in Honor of Sylvain

Bromberger. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

Hale, K. & Keyser, J. 1998. The basic elements of argument structure. In. H. Harley (ed.) MIT

Working Papers in Linguistics 32. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

Halle, M. & Marantz, A. 1993. Distributed Morphology and the Pieces of Inflection. K. Hale & S. J.

Keyser (eds.) The View From Building 20, 111-176. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

Harley, H. 2005. How do verbs take their names? Denominal verbs, manner incorporation and the

ontology of roots in English. In N. Erteschik-Shir & T. Rapoport (eds). The syntax of Aspect.

Oxford University Press.

Harley, H. 2012. Lexical decomposition in modern generative grammar. In Handbook of

Compositionality, edited by Wolfram Hinzen, Markus Werning and Edouard Machery. Oxford:

OUP.

Horvath, J. & T. Siloni. 2008. Active Lexicon: Adjectival and verbal passives. 2008. In Sharon Armon-

Lotem, Gabi Danon and Susan Rothstein (eds.) Current Issues in Hebrew Linguistics. 105-134.

John Benjamins. Kiparsky, P. 1982. Lexical Phonology and Morphology. Seoul: Linguistics in the Morning Calm,

Hanshin.

Kordoni, V. 2002. Participle-adjective formation in Modern Greek. LFG Meeting, July 2002. Athens,

Greece.

Kratzer, A. 1994. The Event Argument and the Semantics of Voice. Ms., University of Massachusetts

at Amherst.

Kratzer, A. 2001. Building statives. Berkeley Linguistic Society, 26.

Lascaratou, Ch. 1991. How "adjectival" are adjectival passive participles in Modern Greek and

English? Glossologia 7-8: 87-97.

Lascaratou, Ch. & Philippaki-Warburton I. 1984. Lexical versus transformational passives in Modern

Greek. Glossologia 2-3: 99-109.

Lekakou, M. 2005. In the middle somewhat elevated. The semantics of middles and its crosslinguistic

realization. Ph.D dissertation, UCL.

Levin, B. & Rappaport, M. 1986. The formation of adjectival passives. Linguistic Inquiry 17: 623-661.

Marantz, A. 1996. “Cat” as a phrasal idiom. Consequences of late insertion in Distributed

Morphology. Ms. MIT.

Marantz, A. 1997. No escape from Syntax: Dont' try morphological analysis in the privacy of your

own lexicon. In: Dimitriadis, A, Siegel, L (eds) University of Pennsylvania Working Papers in

Linguistics, Philadelphia:University of Pennsylvania, pp 201-225.

Marantz, A. 2001. Words and Things. Ms., MIT & NYU.

Marantz, A. 2007. Phases and words. S. H. Choe et al, (eds.) Phases in the theory of grammar. Seoul:

Dong In Publisher.

Marantz, A. 2011. Locality Domains for Contextual Allosemy in Words. Handout. NYU.

Markantonatou, S., Kaliakostas, A., Bouboureka, V., Kordoni, V. & Stavrakaki, V. 1996. Μία

(λεξική) σημασιολογική περιγραφή των ρηματικών επιθέτων σε –τός. Studies in Greek Linguistics

17: 187-201.

Mohanan, K. 1986. The Theory of Lexical Phonology. Dordrecht: Reidel.

Νάκας, Θ. 1978. Για τη μετοχή και το ρηματικό επίθετο σε –τος όπως εμφανίζονται στην κοινή Νέα

Ελληνική και στις διαλέκτους. Β’ Συμπόσιο Γλωσσολογίας του Βορειοελλαδικού Χώρου (Ήπειρος-

Μακεδονία-Θράκη), 241-262.

Parsons, T. 1990. Events in the Semantics of English. A Study in Subatomic Semantics. Cambridge Mass:

MIT Press.

28

Perlmutter, D. 1988. The split Morphology Hypothesis: Evidence from Yiddish. Theoretical

Morphology, 79-101.

Pesetsky, D. 1995. Zero Syntax: Experiencers and Cascades. Cambridge Mass.: MIT Press.

Ράλλη, Α. 2001. Μορφολογία. Athens: Patakis.

Ράλλη, Α. 2006. Η Σύνθεση Λέξεων. Athens: Patakis.

Σετάτος, Μ. 1984. Παρατηρήσεις στα ρηματικά επίθετα σε –μένος και –τος της κοινής νεοελληνικής.

Studies in Greek Linguistics. Proceedings of the 5th Annual Meeting of the Department of

Linguistics of the Aristotle University of Thessaloniki, Thessaloniki.

Samioti, Y. 2008. The structure of –tos participles expressing ability/possibility. Studies in Greek

Linguistics 29.

Samioti, Y. In progress. Issues in the Lexicon – Syntax Interface and applications in Modern Greek as

a 2nd

Language. The case of Participles. Ph.D. dissertation University of Crete.

Siegel, D.1979. Topics in English Morphology. New York: Garland.

Spencer, A. 1991. Morphological Theory. Oxford: Blackwell.

Stroik, T. 1992. Middles and movement. Linguistic Inquiry 23: 127-137.

Stroik, T. 1995 On middle formation: A reply to Zribi-Hertz. Linguistic Inquiry 26: 165-171.

Stroik, T. 1999. Middles and reflexivity. Linguistic Inquiry 30: 119-131.

Svenonius, P. 2005. Extending the Extension Condition to Discontinuous Idioms. Linguistic Variation

Yearbook 5: 227-263.

Travis, L. 2005. Agents and Causes in Malagasy and Tagalog. In The Syntax of Aspect: Deriving

Thematic and Aspectual Interpretation, eds. Nomi Erteschik-Shir and Tova Rapoport, 174-189.

New York: Oxford University Press.

Wasow, T. 1977. Transformations and the Lexicon. P. W. Culicover, T.Wasow & J. Bresnan (eds.)

Formal Syntax, 327-360. New York: Academic Press.


Recommended