+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Ethology Between Empathy, Standpoint and Perspectivism_ the Case of the Arabian Babblers _ Vinciane...

Ethology Between Empathy, Standpoint and Perspectivism_ the Case of the Arabian Babblers _ Vinciane...

Date post: 01-Jun-2018
Category:
Upload: gabriel-pinto
View: 225 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend

of 10

Transcript
  • 8/9/2019 Ethology Between Empathy, Standpoint and Perspectivism_ the Case of the Arabian Babblers _ Vinciane Despret

    1/21

    Ethology between Empathy,

    Standpoint and Perspectivism: the

    case of the Arabian babblers

    Publié le 28 avril 2010  par Vinciane

    Ethology between Empathy, Standpoint and Perspectivism: the case of the Arabian

    babblers

    Vinciane Despret

    Département de Philosophie

    Université de Liège

    Argument of the paper 

    In the middle of the last century Jabob Von Uexküll addressed harsh criticisms to the

    behaviorists forcing rats to run into a labyrinth: you cannot hope to learn something about

    a living being unless you ask what the actual meaning of the experiment is for those you

    want to know about. It took a long time before scientists could afford to follow this advice.

    Whereas “ animal’s amateurs” would find natural to allocate to their animals a point of 

    view upon the situation, most researchers found that problematic — or anthropomorphic.

    Nowadays, we may find evidences that this situation is slightly changing. For some

    scientists, the animal’s per spective upon the situation should be at the center of the

    researches.

    I propose to address this issue in taking two paths: with the first one, I will draw up an

    inventory of fields in which this tendency appears. In the second one, I propose to analyze

    the practices of two scientists working with the same troupe of birds, the Arabian

    Babblers (Turdoïdes squamiceps) : one of them takes the animals’ point of view into

    account and grounds his theories upon it while the other works according the classical

    methods of ethology. The contrast between the two practices, the “subjectivist one” and

    the “objectivist one” has many effects. Among these effects, we discover that birds do tell

    very different stories accordingly to the one who observes them.

    Ethology between Empathy, Standpoint and Perspectivism: the case of the Arabian

    babblers

    On parrots and philosophers

    Vinciane Despret

    D'un texte à l'autre… Bienvenue dans mon cabinet de curiosités en ligne

    http://www.vincianedespret.be/http://twitter.com/search?q=http%3A%2F%2Fwww.vincianedespret.be%2F2010%2F04%2Fethology-between-empathy-standpoint-and-perspectivism-the-case-of-the-arabian-babblers%2Fhttp://www.vincianedespret.be/2010/04/ethology-between-empathy-standpoint-and-perspectivism-the-case-of-the-arabian-babblers/http://www.vincianedespret.be/author/vinciane/http://twitter.com/search?q=http%3A%2F%2Fwww.vincianedespret.be%2F2010%2F04%2Fethology-between-empathy-standpoint-and-perspectivism-the-case-of-the-arabian-babblers%2Fhttps://twitter.com/intent/tweet?original_referer=http%3A%2F%2Fwww.vincianedespret.be%2F2010%2F04%2Fethology-between-empathy-standpoint-and-perspectivism-the-case-of-the-arabian-babblers%2F&text=Ethology%20between%20Empathy%2C%20Standpoint%20and%20Perspectivism%3A%20the%20case%20of%20the%20Arabian%20babblers%20-%20http%3A%2F%2Fwww.vincianedespret.be%2F2010%2F04%2Fethology-between-empathy-standpoint-and-perspectivism-the-case-of-the-arabian-babblers%2F&tw_p=tweetbutton&url=http%3A%2F%2Fwww.vincianedespret.be%2F2010%2F04%2Fethology-between-empathy-standpoint-and-perspectivism-the-case-of-the-arabian-babblers%2Fhttp://www.vincianedespret.be/

  • 8/9/2019 Ethology Between Empathy, Standpoint and Perspectivism_ the Case of the Arabian Babblers _ Vinciane Despret

    2/21

    Why, asks the philosopher — but also dog and horse trainer — Vicki Hearne, do

    philosophers assume with so much certainty that parrots don’t talk? Let us set up the

    situation, as Hearne describes it, and you will understand how the story goes. “You go up

    to a parrot, and he’s probably in a cage and you’re not, so you feel pretty superior, maybe

    you even think you can feel sorry for the parrot, and you ask the parrot how he is, and he

    says something gnomic like, « so’s you’re old man » or « how fine and purple are the

    swallows of the late summer”. Then the parrot looks at you in a really interested,

    expectant way, to see if you’re going to keep your end up (…) You start trying to figure out 

    what the parrot means by it, and there you are. You haven’t a prayer of reintroducing 

    whatever topic you had in mind .That’s why philosophers keep denying that parrots can

    talk, of course, because a philosopher really likes to keep control of a

    conversation” (Hearne, 1994:5). So do all talking parrots: they refuse to let another 

    individual choose the topic of conversation.

    The same thing, I should add, could be said of behaviorists, although conversation would

    not be at the centre of their problem of control, even less at the centre of what really

    interests them. The fact that parrots have never spoken to any behaviorists testifies to

    this. The reason for the silence of parrots in this kind of situation is simple enough and

    makes Wittgenstein partly right, when he assumed that even if a lion could talk, we would

    not be able to understand it — on condition that one takes into account, in re-reading

    Wittgenstein, not the point of view of the human but the hypotheses the parrots seem to

    forge. In view of the situation suggested to them, parrots deduce that, if they were to

    speak, nobody in the situation would understand them. Because — as later research that

    succeeded in the miracle of having a conversation with them has shown — parrots have a

    pragmatic rather than a referential conception of language[1]. They cannot speak if they

    don’t have the sentiment of speaking to someone. And that someone is cruelly lacking inthe behaviorist’s experiment. Under the banner of objectivity, everything is constructed in

    such a fashion as to render the researcher as impersonal as possible, to make of him

    someone replaceable by anyone — which is precisely the contrary of what defines a

    person.

     All this reminds us of the harsh criticism that the great naturalist and theorist of 

    the Umwelt   theory, Jabob Von Uexküll addressed to the behaviorists forcing rats to run

    into a labyrinth: you cannot hope to learn something about a living being unless you ask

    what the actual meaning of the experiment is for those you want to know about. And, we

    should add, insofar as the scientist is part of the experiment, he cannot pretend to sayanything that would have a chance of being reliable unless he takes into account the very

    fact that the animal is trying to make sense, to give meaning to, to interpret, and to

    respond to what is asked of him/her.

    So Vicki Hearne is probably right and this may explain another reason why parrots have

    not been able to talk with certain human beings: the parrots were more than likely not

    interested in the subjects.

    It is quite another story with cats. Hearne explains that wise experimenters try to avoid

    working with them — I have also heard that about ravens, for other reasons, but this is yet

    another story[2]. Hearne heard some older experimenters advising younger ones, sayingthat cats are generally fairly good at the beginning of the procedure but, they add, things

    generally go wrong after the first test procedures. If you give cats a problem to solve or a

    task to perform in order to find food, they work it out pretty quickly, and the graph of their 

    http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftn1http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftn2

  • 8/9/2019 Ethology Between Empathy, Standpoint and Perspectivism_ the Case of the Arabian Babblers _ Vinciane Despret

    3/21

    comparative intelligence shows a sharply rising line. But the older experimenters then say

    (although they will never publish on this subject): “the trouble is that as soon as they figure

    out that the researcher or technician wants them to push the lever, they stop doing it;

    some of them will starve to death rather than do it” (Hearne, 2007:225)[3] .

    In human psychology, such a thing could scarcely happen: first, because most of us

    respect academic authority and will work out the problem for “the sake of science”[4].

    Secondly, because, generally, human subjects in psychological experiments do not know

    what is expected from them, insofar as the experimenter cautiously hides it — and most

    often pretends she/he is searching for something else. What is it about cats, then? Vicki

    Hearne (2007: 225-226) suggests that “the refusal of food is a signal made to the cosmos

    itself when one despairs of signaling one’s chums that something deep in nature is

    denied ”. Cats, she says, cannot afford situations in which there is only one choice, that of 

    responding in a linear way to human expectations, a kind of “pleasing” that is in fact

    violation of the cat’s nature. And this is the case because “the pleasures and expectations

    of human beings are profoundly important to cats”. What science shows us, therefore, is

    that cats take the task of pleasing us far more seriously than other animals — even dogs

    — do. Actually, dogs in experiments are fairly compliant — as are rats for reasons that are

    yet to be explored. And what dogs resist, when they try to resist, unlike cats, is more the

    lack of expectations, or more precisely, the lack of meaning behind the expectations. This

    shows us, by the way, how science may transform compliant beings or helpful animals

    into stupid ones — and we shall see, by contrast, how the same experiment, but with

    slight modifications, could do exactly the reverse. Let us first see what it is about dogs in

    laboratories. Hearne (2007:58) clearly points out what actually happens in this scenario

    when she writes “to the extent that the behaviorist manages to deny any belief in the

    dog’s potential for believing, intending, meaning, etc., there will be no flow of intentions,meaning, believing, hoping going on. The dog may try to respond to the behaviorist, but 

    the behaviorist won’t respond to the dog’s response. (…) The behaviorist’s dog will not 

    only seem stupid, she will be stupid ”.

     After re-reading Derrida’s text and Donna Haraway’s (2008) wonderful commentary on his

    work[5], there is, for me, even clearer confirmation of what constitutes the differences

    between experimenters who give a chance to their animals to be interesting, active,

    intelligent and the ones who don’t : The differences lay in the very fact that the first ones

    are aware that their animals respond to them and they respond back to these responses:

    in doing so, they made their subjects more responsive, which is a one of the most reliableways of becoming intelligent. And they do this with care and curiosity, which are the

    conditions of good knowledge[6].

    Talkative parrots, lonely sheep and happy pigs

    The interpretations I make from that situation, and the criticisms I address towards

    behaviorists are historically situated. I probably wouldn’t have made these criticisms in the

    same way a few years ago. And it is not a coincidence that Derrida (2008) and Haraway

    (2008) have been interested in such a question so recently. Indeed, we might suggest that

    we learned to see things from the perspective of an animal from the work of Jacob Von

    Uexküll. However, if von Uexküll taught us to see things from the animal’s perspective,he never mentioned the fact that the animal construes, interprets, give meanings to the

    experiment as an intentional procedure requesting something from him/her, and to the

    human who asks the question. Yes, he criticized behaviorists for not taking meanings into

    http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftn6http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftn5http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftn4http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftn3

  • 8/9/2019 Ethology Between Empathy, Standpoint and Perspectivism_ the Case of the Arabian Babblers _ Vinciane Despret

    4/21

    account — for example he pointed out that while behaviorists thought that rats running in a

    labyrinth were providing answers to the questions of learning, the rats were actually

    showing how they build what is of utmost importance in a rat’s world, that is a “familiar 

    path”. And, yes, Von Uexküll also learned that social beings construe and give meanings

    to other social beings with whom they have relationships. That is why Tschock, the

     jackdaw hand-raised by a human, (Lorenz in this case), gave to his human gardian the

    meaning ‘socius’, followed him everywhere, tried to feed him with worms and (though with

    less success) tried to teach him to fly. And this is also why, Von Uexküll explained, the

     jackdaw displayed the whole jackdaw’s repertoire of courtship for the benefit of Lorenz’s

    maid. And yes, Von Uexküll led us to take into account new perspectives, insofar as he

    practiced a kind of “alter-subjectivity”: a subjectivity that cannot be reached by means of 

    simple analogies (a “like us” kind of thought), but by a system of contrasts and differences

    that searched for, and were grounded in, differences: animals do not feel and think like us;

    they do not share our point of view. However, as far as I know, Von Uexküll did not go as

    far as asking experimenters to take into account the animal’s point of view regarding the

    experiment itself, regarding the experimenter’s demands. Neither did he consider that

    animals respond — of course in ways that need translation — to what is proposed to

    them.

    Of course, Hearne did this years ago and took into account the very perspective of each

    animal she was dealing with: but Hearne was a trainer and, as she reminded us, trainers

    do that all the time. This is why scientists have discounted trainers for having an

    anthropomorphic and morally loaded language. This shows us that scientific thinking could

    not afford to address this question — partly, as Marion Thomas (2003) has shown,

    because they have historically built their practices and theories against the “amateur-

    naturalist” ways of thinking. Indeed, the old experimenter saying that cats do not performtheir experimental task if they feel they are not given the choice might act as

    counterevidence against that: we could construe it as the possibility of the behaviorist

    taking an animal perspective seriously. However, no one has ever published on this

    matter [7]. Moreover, if this experimenter was really taking that fact seriously, how could

    he still trust his experimental set-up and his results as long as this finding would lead him

    to concede that cats — as well as all other animals — do not answer the question that is

    addressed (about learning) but instead answer another question, for example, the question

    “what am I able to do, and in which conditions, to fulfill a particular human desire?”

    It now seems possible for scientists to answer this kind of question (though not allscientists, not yet). This is particularly true for scientists who, sometimes for the actual

    purpose of their research, are engaged in a close relationship with their animals — among

    those, wolves, bears, ravens, dogs. Interestingly, although we may not assess with

    certainty what is cause and what is effect, the practices and the narratives of these

    scientists are, in some ways, very similar to those of the amateur — or to the 19 century

    naturalists and amateurs if we compare them with the 20 century animal

    psychologists[8]. The scene is full of beings, both human and animal, who credit each

    other with intention, will, perspectives, meanings and who respond to each other.

    These scientists do not study what an animal is, rather what an animal becomes inresponding to the way he/she is questioned, in responding to what is expected from

    him/her. The situation is a co-inventive situation of knowledge, which creates

    opportunities for new behaviors. The animal’s perspective upon the situation is, for these

    th

    th

    http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftn8http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftn7

  • 8/9/2019 Ethology Between Empathy, Standpoint and Perspectivism_ the Case of the Arabian Babblers _ Vinciane Despret

    5/21

    few scientists, at the center of the whole matter. This is, I suggest, the area in which I

    can detect things changing slightly in the world of animal sciences.

    I will, however, not try to explore what, in our present socio-cultural and political context

    may explain these changes. I will merely propose that something is becoming possible,

    and that this “something”, whatever form it takes in different aspects of work with animals,

    is interesting. I will simply assess how it makes scientific work more interesting, and how

    it may change the way we perceive animals in the future — as well as showing how it has

    already changed the way we perceive animals, for example through the researches in the

    fields of animal welfare.

    The trend is not sharply drawn in these fields, but we may notice that some of the “welfare

    scientists” have recently reoriented their work in that direction. “See things from their 

    perspective”, as the New Scientist’s issue of September 2006 entitled one of its articles

    reporting on a conference held at the Royal Society of London (Coghland, 2006). This

    topic is clearly on the agenda. In France, some of the researchers from the INRA

    (National Institute for Agronomic Research) have recently published articles that seem to

    take this orientation.

    Xavier Boivin (2003) is one of these scientists working in the field of animal welfare. The

    criticisms he addresses towards the way research regarding stress and fear in animals is

    conducted makes me turn to him to find evidence of the process I have identified. Most of 

    this research, he notes, aims to assess the effects of human-animal relationships. The

    author considers it surprising what the scientific literature assumes constitutes

    a relationship between a man and an animal. Fifty-nine original papers from 1986 to 2002

    dealing with the relationship between sheep and humans were analyzed and classified.

    Most of them, Boivin notes, actually investigated thereactions  of sheep to handling 

     procedures  such as shearing, muzzling, laparoscopy etc. and measured the generalreactivity of the animals (fear and stress). These findings, Boivin concludes, illustrate how

    the human-animal relationship is only perceived by the scientists to occur through handling

    procedures and not as a real relationship between two individuals. Moreover, most of the

    time, the human involved in the test was unknown to the sheep and the variables

    measured were interpreted as a general reactivity or fear towards humans. None of them

    studied, for example, the relationship between shepherd and sheep. How can we say that

    the simple response to an unfamiliar human is in reality highly correlated with the animals’

    reaction to a handling procedure such as shearing by a familiar shepherd?

     All these criticisms and more, and particularly the author’s conclusion, show which kind of new trend of research we may be beginning to see emerge: “it is important,” Boivin

    writes,  “to describe the stockperson-farm animal relationship not only from the human

     point of view but also through the perception of the animals. Welfare is not the human

     perception of the animal state but really how the animals perceive their environment.”

    (2003:12)

    In another paper, Boivin adds: “Concepts of ‘relationship’ and ‘animal’s perception of the

    humans are not only relevant for the animal welfare aspect (…), they allow us to address

    the complex motivation of the animal when interacting with a human. It is important to

    understand that when we are watching animals, they are also watching us.” [9]  It seemsthat the concept of “response” is at the core of what I would label as a “ philosophically 

    responsible”  story, the story Boivin wants both to reveal and to create between scientists

    and animals. It is the responding, the “looking back”, which, as Donna Haraway (2008:19)

    http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftn9

  • 8/9/2019 Ethology Between Empathy, Standpoint and Perspectivism_ the Case of the Arabian Babblers _ Vinciane Despret

    6/21

    so beautifully put it and as Boivin asks his colleagues to take into account, reminds us of 

    the etymology of respect — respecere, to hold in regard, to respond, to look back

    reciprocally[10].

    Boivin is not the only scientist working in the field of animal welfare who makes us hope

    for some changes. Another team of researchers, for example, has recently redefined what

    welfare should mean: it should mean happiness. Recent papers show this new trend of 

    research: welfare, Alain Boissy and his colleagues write, should not be reduced to the

    absence of negative experiences but should include positive affects or emotions, such as

    pleasure. What, from a pig’s point a view, might be a positive emotion? What makes a pig

    “happy”? Interestingly, all these scientists raise the very questions Vicki Hearne asked 20

    years ago, the very anthropomorphic question, in the morally loaded language that trainers

    generally speak, the question that has been so long to come to scientists: what is animal

    happiness? The amateurs’ questions are back. And they have become philosophically 

    responsible  (Hearne, 2007:14). Still more interestingly, the responses of the amateur-

    trainer and the scientists now converge: animals are happy when they do well   what is

    difficult for them (Hearne 2007:12; 1991)— scientists, of course, call that “coping” and

    “challenge”[11].

    In the field

    Can we imagine these new trends emerging in field studies? Of course, some difficulties

    may arise that could seriously preclude the possibility of such a change. One of the most

    obvious among these difficulties is the way ethologists consider both objective science

    and nature, objectivity being defined in this case as: anyone in the same place should

    observe exactly the same behaviors. Like obsessive comedians, animals should always

    play the same role, whatever the audience. This means that there is no interaction

    between the observer and the observed. Trained in the conventions of objective science,scientists try to be as neutral as possible. As Haraway puts it (2008:24), good scientists

    are those who, learning to be invisible themselves, can see the scene of nature close up,

    as if through a peep-hole.

    In such a situation, when two observers end up observing radically different behaviors for 

    the same animals, the possibility of the animal’s subjectivity is immediately discarded in

    favor of another interpretation: the differences may be totally explained by the observer’s

    subjectivity, whatever this concept refers to (Despret, 2002).

    This happened, for example, when primatologist Thelma Rowel (1966) came back from

    her field work in Uganda and claimed that the baboons she observed did not behave theway baboons had hitherto behaved everywhere else. From her very first descriptions, at

    the beginning of the 1960s, Rowell’s observations contrasted sharply with those of her 

    colleagues working with similar animals. Baboons had hitherto been unanimously

    described as extremely competitive, intensively aggressive towards each other and

    involved most of the time in fights over food or females. In Rowell’s troop, males were

    extremely peaceful: they formed a coherent cohort, constantly aware of each other’s

    movements, but with scarcely any aggressive interactions. Not only were Rowell’s

    baboons peaceful, but the males were bizarrely uncompetitive. There was much positive

    or friendly interaction. Aggression was rare, even in feeding places: baboons almost never stole food from each other. “The dominant impression of interaction between

    males”, Rowell concluded, “was that of active cooperation.”   (Rowell, 1972:44).

    Zuckerman, one of the most respected silver-back primatologists, assumed that these

    http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftn11http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftn10

  • 8/9/2019 Ethology Between Empathy, Standpoint and Perspectivism_ the Case of the Arabian Babblers _ Vinciane Despret

    7/21

    differences were solely a matter of observer differences:“among field workers, he

    claimed,  the observer’s own temperament and sex might be an important filter in

    determining, for example, the amount of agonistic behavior observed and reported in

    groups of primates”   (Rowell, 1967:222).

    We are reminded of Bertrand Russell’s (1927) astonishment at the high incidence of 

    animals conforming to the behavior expected of them by observers. Before Rousseau, he

    notes, they were ferocious beasts, subsequently conforming to his noble savage cult.

    During the Victorian period, primates were virtuous monogamists; during the post-Freudian

    era of sexual liberation, one would have been appalled by the considerable deterioration of 

    their moral standards. These are the arguments usually put forward by experts in scientific

    studies who conclude that animals are guided by the expectations of those who study

    them.

    However, one may think that it is hard to compare the open field and the laboratory:

    expectations should work differently on the one hand in laboratories and on the other hand

    in the open field. In laboratories, bonds are inevitable — even if scientists try to avoid

    them. Therefore, if we assume that scientists, in the open, are invisible — or, almost

    invisible, or at least, that they try not to interfere — how might we explain the differences

    between two observers studying the same animal? Scientific experts have almost always

    assumed that the differences lie in something other than the animals themselves, such as

    interpretations, expectations, narratives, standpoint, empathy, ideological bias, or political

    preferences in reading nature. And this was, in fact, the hypothesis that led me to the field

    station of Hatzeva, in the Neguev Desert, to meet the Arabian babblers and their Israeli

    ornithologist, Amotz Zahavi — a hypothesis that I will radically revisit today. These birds

    did not behave like birds usually do; they didn’t act according to what could legitimately

    count as the typical bird’s script[12]; besides that, their ethologist did not describe themas ethologists usually do — except when they produce popular writings [13]. Something

    was wrong in that situation; a good case for philosophy (Despret, 1996).

    Babblers and babblers

    The Arabian Babbler (Turdoides squamiceps) inhabits extreme deserts and is the only bird

    species in Israel that lives in groups year round. These groups are territorial, with numbers

    of birds per group generally being between 3 and 5 individuals, although they can range

    between 2 and 22. Each group usually contains one breeding pair; young birds do not

    disperse for one to three years, during which time they act as helpers. Babblers are long-

    lived and may reach the age of twelve or fourteen. Babblers seemed to be very peculiar birds: not only do they help at the nest, all members of the group taking care of a single

    nest, but they also cooperate to protect their territory against neighboring groups of 

    babblers and non-territorial individuals (refugees as Zahavi calls the latter). The birds’

    dealings with each other involve providing a great deal of assistance to others. They offer 

    presents to feed each other — seeds, insects, flowers — before they are full themselves:

    when offered a crumb of bread right after they have fed their fellows with a similar crumb,

    they will eat with relish — something, Zahavi explains, that satiated babblers do not do.

    They endanger themselves by mobbing raptors and snakes. They imperil themselves by

    coming to the rescue of group members who get caught in a net or by a predator, or byenemy babblers during a fight. They play together. They also dance together in the

    morning, sometimes after bathing. In short, through their whole life, they cooperate. And if 

    they sometimes compete with each other, and they actually do, they also compete to act

    http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftn13http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftn12

  • 8/9/2019 Ethology Between Empathy, Standpoint and Perspectivism_ the Case of the Arabian Babblers _ Vinciane Despret

    8/21

    as sentinel of the territory or to feed their comrades. Babblers, in fact, are very interested

    in the issue of prestige (Zahavi 1990)[14]. When one babbler feeds another, he/she draws

    attention to him/herself: he/she emits a special thrill and lifts his/her beak above the beak

    of the one he/she is feeding. But generally, a babbler tries to avoid being fed by another 

    bird of about the same age: he/she might try to escape or, in some cases, close his/her 

    beak tightly, despite being hungry — and, Zahavi says, he/she will eagerly accept one of 

    the observers’ crumbs of bread immediately after refusing a juicy insect from another 

    babbler. If a lower ranked individual attempts to feed a higher-ranking one, he/she might

    be beaten up. The babblers will construe the proposal as a declaration of open revolt.

    They may fight: but they fight seriously with a member of their group only once in their 

    whole life — if ever.

    First, it should be mentioned that each bird observed (nowadays among 250) is

    individually identified: they are all tagged with a combination of 3 colored bands and 1

    numbered band. They are all habituated, (i.e. “used to our presence”) and observers may

    walk among them without scaring them — “as far as they are concerned, we are not so

    different from the herd of goats and camels with which they share the desert”   (Zahavi &

    Zahavi, 1997). Observers working with Zahavi usually give the birds tiny amounts of 

    breadcrumbs. Most often, when going to the field and trying to find a particular group,

    Zahavi calls them with a whistle… and they come — which is, he explains, rather easier 

    than trying to find them or run after them. Babblers seem to prefer to live on the ground

    and are slow flyers, which makes the observations still easier.

    Zahavi’s description of the birds is rather unusual in ethological discourse: “Because they 

    are habituated to our presence,”   Zahavi explains, “we can hear the soft, widely varied calls

    they use to communicate, calls that don’t carry more than a few yards. Some individuals

    are talkative, others taciturn, and still others grumble all day long. When a higher-ranking individual approaches a lower-ranking one, the latter often makes a soft sound to

    acknowledge the other, as if saying ‘Yes, sir’ .” The theory itself is still stranger: babblers

    do help, do assist, do protect, do feed others in order to gain prestige. For example,

    Zahavi explains, a babbler who finds food may not swallow it right away but instead may

    hold it in his/her beak and look around to see whom he/she can feed. If he/she sees only

    individuals whose rank is higher than his/her own, he/she may waver briefly, then swallow

    the food. “When the beta male, the number two male of a group, goes up to the top of a

    tree to stand up as sentinel, we often see the alpha male, his superior, busily looking for 

    food; he then gives it to the sentinel in full view of the other members of the group and replaces him on guard duty. In many cases, we can tell when the sentinel notices the

    alpha male’s preparation to feed him from the direction of the sentinel’s gaze, and often

    because the sentinel abandons his lofty post before the alpha male arrives to displace

    him” (Zahavi & Zahavi, 1997:126).

    In the field, I also met Jon, an ethologist who had studied at Oxford. Jon was young but

    he was already an experienced ethologist. He was also (and still is) a sociobiologist. He

    was there while I was visiting and he was also working with babblers. Jon definitively

    does not agree with Zahavi’s theory. According to Jon, if babblers help, it is because they

    want to maximize their inclusive fitness (or because altruism has been selected for). Inhelping close kin, each individual may expect to pass on part of his genetic pool.

    Following and listening to either Jon or Zahavi gave me the feeling that we were not

    dealing with the same birds. The first difference between Jon and Zahavi was obvious:

    http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftn14

  • 8/9/2019 Ethology Between Empathy, Standpoint and Perspectivism_ the Case of the Arabian Babblers _ Vinciane Despret

    9/21

    they totally disagreed about what could be said, or more precisely what could count as a

    true hypothesis. For Zahavi, a hypothesis about babblers is true in some way because

    babblers provide evidence of it. Or, to put it another way, humans may assume a

    particular hypothesis about babblers because babblers never act without good reason. For 

    Jon, a hypothesis is true only if you can prove it. And to prove is to experiment. In other 

    words, Zahavi trusts what the babblers show; John trusts the experiment that will make

    them behave in such a way that it confirms a hypothesis. Zahavi follows, moves inside

    the group, listens to the babblers, and explains, for example: “we move easily among the

    babblers; we see what they are looking at and become aware of their intentions ”. He has

    learned to pay attention to each tiny difference of vocalization: why does a babbler shout

    so loud when it threatens another one? Of course, we  shout when we are angry. But in the

    case of the babblers, the shouting is not aimed at the purported listener but rather at other 

    babblers that are farther away: the shouting makes them witnesses [15]. Only confident

    babblers can afford to shout their threats in front of the crowd. “This principle, Zahavi

    adds, is well-known in politics: a publicly declared intention is likelier to be carried out than

    one agreed upon in secret ”( Zahavi and Zahavi, 1997:75). Why do babblers sometimes

    spring their wings upward when approaching a snake — making themselves more visible?

    They must have good reasons to act in such a dangerous way: babblers want to show off 

    their courage to other members of their group; that is why they call their attention to

    themselves in that situation.

    I would suggest that Zahavi may be very confident because his theory claims that signals

    are always reliable, or honest. “What you see is what it’s worth” could define the way

    babblers behave, according to Zahavi, since signals for prestige are costly. Feeding

    others, or acting as sentinel involves time and resources: if a babbler cannot afford it,

    he/she will be prevented from doing it[16]. By showing off how much they can invest instanding guard, in feeding others, in taking serious risks, babblers show off their ability to

    win in a fight and their desirability as group-mates. In other words, “the altruist’s

    investment in the altruistic act offers a reliable, concrete index of that ability .” (Zahavi &

    zahavi, 1997:142)

    From Jon’s point of view, you cannot simply claim whatever you want in order to explain

    the birds’ behavior if you cannot yourself experience it— i.e. make an experiment about it.

    For example, in order to prove that the behaviors of helping at the nest and feeding chicks

    are not governed by motives of prestige, you would need to show that these behaviors are

    determined by other rules, in that case by sociobiological rules of kinship selection. Jonaimed to show that helpers and parents provision for nestlings at similar rates, irrespective

    of sex or dominance rank within the group. If, for example, the nestling were very hungry,

    parents would enhance their effort; on the other hand, helpers-at-the-nest, if this were

    solely a matter of prestige, wouldn’t be sensitive to the change of conditions. Jon put the

    hypothesis to the test: some playbacks of tapes showing chick-begging enhancing the

    feeding from both the parents and the helpers-at-the-nest showed evidence that the

    helpers have the same provisioning rule as the parents and therefore do not use nestling

    feeding as an altruistic signal to gain social prestige.

    When I asked Zahavi about experimentation, he told me “of course we do experimentswith babblers. We ask them to come, and we tell them what we want them to do and the

    question we are dealing with. And they do it” . I will never be sure Zahavi wasn’t   serious.

    Flying primates or vehicles for genes?

    http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftn15http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftn16

  • 8/9/2019 Ethology Between Empathy, Standpoint and Perspectivism_ the Case of the Arabian Babblers _ Vinciane Despret

    10/21

    But interestingly, especially in the field situation, what might be expected often happens in

    an unexpected way, and turns out most of the time to be much more worthwhile than what

    could have been originally expected (Latour, 1991). With Jon, we could be sure the birds

    wouldn’t be thought to be acting like a human, albeit a scientist, nor would they be led by

    anthropomorphic motives. Things are sometimes more complicated. Once, both Jon and I

    were observing a group of babblers feeding at the nest. At one particular moment, I

    noticed that one of the bird made the vocal signal that, according to Zahavi’s theory, calls

    the attention of their nearby comrades to the effort they are making. But I was almost sure

    this babbler was not offering any food. I asked Jon. He told me I was right. Therefore, I

    wondered why the bird had done that — if I could see that the babbler was deceiving,

    surely the other babblers would not miss this either. “Very easy to understand,”   said

    Jon, “this bird is carrying out a real experiment. He just wants to assess the real state of 

    hunger of the chicks, so he just modifies one of the variables” . This story shows us that

    what scientists call anthropomorphism is always “someone’s anthropomorphism”, i.e.,

    “common sense” anthropomorphism, or more precisely the lay-person’s

    anthropomorphism. I other words, if the birds are acting and thinking as a scientist would

    think and act, this is not anthropomorphism; it is nature’s rules — naturomorphism  is not a

    sin.

    But this also shows us the real contrast between two ways of thinking: Jon and Zahavi

    inhabit the two extremes of a continuum between “scientist” and “naturalist” ways of 

    construing behavior: you may find their position on that continuum by taking into account

    the role of models, the question of methodology, or the issue of anthropomorphism.

    However, the issue of anthropomorphism, which is generally what gives most of the

    characteristics to this continuum, has slightly shifted from its usual conception. Jon does

    not reproach Zahavi’s babbler for thinking like an “anthropos”, he reproaches the bird for thinking like a naturalist: Zahavi’s babblers neither follow regular rules nor seek them; they

    trust what they see; they live anecdotically— all naturalist’s way of acting and thinking.

    By contrast, Jon’s babbler, as a matter of fact, does not think like an “anthropos”, he/she

    thinks like someone who obeys cognitive rules of nature — he/she thinks and acts like a

    good scientist.

    More generally, it was clear that Zahavi’s ways of observing and thinking were very close

    to the naturalist’s style, whereas Jon was working within the classical ethological

    tradition. Zahavi talks about his babblers as anthropologists talk about their human

    subjects: they have agency, intentions, hopes, desires, and he may adopt their perspective. Jon’s descriptions are highly abstract and technical — for example: “ Arabian

    babblers provide an interesting focus for discussions regarding unselected helping,

    because this system involves apparent costs and benefits of helping that are very similar 

    in scale to those of parental provisioning (…)” (Wright, 1999).Moreover, Jon’s babblers are

    determined by simple and rigid rules: according to kin selection theory, the variation in

    chick-feeding efforts by helpers reflects their evolutionary interest in provisioning the

    young. Helpers increase their effort “in accordance with the net fitness returns from

    “investment” in the brood. Hence, more related chicks should be fed at higher rates, and 

    helping should be adjusted according to both its energetic cost and current brood demand for food.” (Wright, 1997:1440).

    Eileen Crist (1999:89) remarks that, despite their intellectual continuity, there is a great

    disparity between ethologists and naturalists with respect to their use of language. “In

  • 8/9/2019 Ethology Between Empathy, Standpoint and Perspectivism_ the Case of the Arabian Babblers _ Vinciane Despret

    11/21

    contrast to the naturalists’ language of the life-world, ethologists use a technical 

    vocabulary, in part constructed by themselves and in part appropriated from behaviourist 

     psychology. The linguistic and argumentative edifice created by the pioneer ethologists led 

    to the representation of animals as natural objects. Yet it is quite certain that neither 

    Tinbergen nor Lorenz wanted to “desubjectify” animals[17] . In using a technical, highly 

    theoretical language, they aimed to establish the study of animal behavior as a rigorous

    science; they presupposed a specific idea of “science”, on the model of natural science as

    well as of comparative psychology (…). The inexorable if unwitting consequence of 

    applying a technical language was the epistemological objectification of animals and 

    ultimately their mecanomorphic portrayal ”. Sociobiology has driven this tendency to the

    extreme: models are the main goal of field studies[18].

    Zahavi, by contrast, is very close to the figures I gathered together earlier to show how

    some scientists were changing. He is more interested in individual differences than in

    models. And he assumes that he ought to be interested in individual differences because

    that is of the utmost importance for the babblers themselves. They endlessly seek and

    show off differences between themselves. Indeed, Zahavi’s way of thinking and

    construing behavior is entangled in a model, a sort of “common sense” model — which, as

    a matter of fact, seems very close to anthropomorphism. But Zahavi’s strong interest in

    individual differences leads him to refute theoretical models, be they from classical

    ethology or from sociobiology[19]. We find a clear example of that when he criticizes the

    use of “species-specific patterns” to identify members of a group “after those patterns

    have evolved to show off differences among individuals within the group” (Zahavi &

    Zahavi, 1997:72). This last sentence may help us to speculate about how Jon and Zahavi

    may observe such differences between birds. Jon is seeking a model, and he is therefore

    paying attention to the behaviors that can either be integrated into or that will fulfill or confirm the model. He probably actively selects. Far be it from me to suggest that Zahavi

    is not selecting: he does select, but he selects different events. Jon is selecting

    “variations” in patterns; Zahavi is selecting “varieties”. Jon’s approach is close to the

    experimental way of collecting data. I like to think that Zahavi is a true successor to

    Darwin: he collects facts that do not fit with classical theories, he looks for varieties — in

    anecdotes, in little stories, in individual bird biographies. He compares the experiences of 

    humans and birds, and as we shall see, for example, those of dogs and birds, assessing

    the “good reasons” they have to act in some odd ways. He fills their life with motives,

    intentions, singular aims. Jon asks the babblers to be experimental objects, theexperimental device mirrors the work of nature: birds are being controlled and constrained

    by the same external rules; Zahavi reconstructs their experience, and he safeguards

    authorship and meanings. He works and thinks like a naturalist: “Naturalists’ attention to

    the detailed nuances …”, Eileen Crist writes (what she calls episodic descriptions)“… and 

    variations of actions is connected with their focus on episodes of animal life. In

    documenting animal life, they choose to narrate concrete behavioral events, episodes

    actually witnessed .” (1999 :73).

    In focusing on different events, Jon and Zahavi construct different narratives in which still

    more different events matter and may be observed. Jon, for example, concedes that hemight not have paid attention to some subtle events while he was observing, and that (the

    fact of not taking these events into account) might have (but in reality has not) favored

    one hypothesis (babblers’ help at the nest is kin-oriented) over another (babblers compete

    http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftn17http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftn18http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftn19

  • 8/9/2019 Ethology Between Empathy, Standpoint and Perspectivism_ the Case of the Arabian Babblers _ Vinciane Despret

    12/21

    for prestige and for feeding nestlings). In the same vein, he raises a question much

    studied by another scientist observing babblers at the site (Roni Osztreiher), whether the

    close presence of the observer may or may not influence the way babblers behave (Roni

    relates that once, a dominant bird felt forced to act as sentinel because of the observer’s

    presence and he therefore could not feed the chicks). In order to assess this possibility,

    Jon — as a good experimenter — compared observations at different distances and found

    no differences[20]. But the question of the observer’s influence, if we can put it that way

    — as I have suggested, as an experimental question — makes another difference less

    visible. The difference is not only between observers; it rests between the ways observers

    take into account the differences between groups and how their questions will enhance or 

    decrease these differences. For Jon, all groups behave in approximately the same

    way,with regard to his hypothesis. This means that the hypothesis may easily discard as

    innocuous parasites the differences between groups, and that these differences will not be

    perceived. For Zahavi, by contrast, each group is unique. Of course, each group faces the

    same problems and they find similar solutions, but each group has its own style of facing

    the problem or of achieving this solution. For example, Zahavi explains that the

    relationship between the first and the second males is not the same in all groups. It

    depends a great deal on the make-up of the particular group. Even when the two males

    are brothers, this relationship varies from group to group. The prestige of one vis-à-vis

    another may be radically different from one group to another, which dramatically changes

    the way they behave. Since prestige means, for babblers, “the respect accorded an

    individual by others”, it also changes the behavior of the whole group.

    Groups have their own style, depending partly on the respect accorded, and babblers have

    according Zahavi, personalities or temperaments. But we also found evidence that Zahavi

    adopts the perspective of the animal he observes; moreover he embodies thoseperspectives. If one re-reads some extracts from his work, one will see that the

    methodology includes this very embodiment and that it is a kind of bodily identification:

    following the gaze of the sentinel and knowing exactly what it should do next (and what

    the observer should look at next), thinkingwith  it, looking with the bird rather than looking

    at the bird, and knowing its intentions. Babblers and humans share something in common,

    built by the work and the narratives of the ethologist: body posture, the shifting of glances,

    common anticipations (what happens next?), and last but not least, common stories.

    When Zahavi tells us, for example, that babblers compete for rank or in order to lay eggs,

    stories proliferate. Both humans and babblers seem to enjoy the narrative this competitionproduces, and they enjoy just as much the sharing of the same questions about these

    narratives: “Such contests are complex and fascinating.” Zahavi writes,“Each is a unique

    story, reminiscent of historical epics, Shakespearean dramas, and biblical tableaux. In one

    case three males were copulating with four females, all of whom laid eggs. It was

    impossible for anyone — human or babbler — to tell which of the fledglings in the common

    nest were whose offspring; it would have take DNA analysis for us — the babblers

    themselves had no idea” ((Zahavi & Zahavi, 1997: 130).

     Although babblers may fiercely compete, an adult fights seriously with another adult only

    once, if ever — since, as already mentioned, the quest for prestige has replaced fighting.The “real” fight almost always occurs between the most dominant male or female and the

    one next in rank: “there is no point in risking everything for anything less than the top

     position”. Such a fight is savage. It starts all of a sudden, and Zahavi explains, most

    http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftn20

  • 8/9/2019 Ethology Between Empathy, Standpoint and Perspectivism_ the Case of the Arabian Babblers _ Vinciane Despret

    13/21

    observers fail to see any sign that it is imminent. “It is as though all grievances and 

    suppressed antagonisms between two brothers or between a father and son who have

    lived together peacefully for years burst out in this one life-and-death fight ” (Zahavi &

    zahavi, 1997:130-131). Each story is a scene full of actors, inhabiting an existential world,

    living adventures that give them a history, a bibliography, a personality, and a full

    repertoire of will, intention, and agency: “In one case (…) an eight-month-old female tried 

    to feed her ten-month-old sister; the latter stood up, snatched the food out of her younger 

    sister’s beak, forced her to crouch like one begging for food, and then stuffed the food 

    down her throat. Once the younger bird had swallowed the food, the dominant sister 

     pecked her until she fled. The frustrated younger sister then took another crumb and went 

    to feed her subordinate younger brother, who was hunting quietly for food some thirty feet 

    away (…) Babblers behave as though it was the act of giving, rather than the benefit 

    given, that matters” (p. 138).

    This conclusion is worthy of our attention: this is the actual question we are searching for 

    in the field, the question that makes the perspective something other than simply a

    problem of point of view: for Zahavi, the right question to ask his animals, the question

    that produces interest is this very question: what matters to babblers?

     A final babbler eccentricity will clearly illustrate this. They dance. Why does it matter?

    Why do babblers dance?

    The most impressive social activity of the babblers is the morning dance. It happens only

    once every several days and it takes place almost exclusively at the first light of the day.

    One of the babblers suddenly stops at a “suitable dancefloor” and starts preening himself 

    nervously or sprawling with his throat touching the ground. Sometimes, there is no

    response, and there is no dance. But a second babbler may come and join together with

    the first, preening his own body. This is an invitation for others. The dancers form a line(sometimes a circle) and they press against each other, squeezing under and over and

    between their partners.

    This dance has raised another controversy. This time, it involved another scientist we

    have already mentioned: Roni Osztreiher. According to Roni, babblers dance mostly in the

    spring and before the mating season. For him, it is clear that the dancers try to get at the

    center of the line formed by the dancers, by jumping over each other — his comrades try

    to prevent him/her from doing this by squeezing firmly with their body. According to Roni,

    the dance is used by the babblers to attest and assess their respective strengths: this a

    ritual that will determine each babbler’s rank in the hierarchy, and this is why it is donewhen coming out of the nest and just before mating time.

    Zahavi, on the other hand, emphasizes the particular moment and the particular place

    chosen for the ritual: babblers dance in the open, near a bush, even though they could

    dance more safely under trees and they do it before sunrise. This is the most dangerous

    place and the most dangerous time of day: the danger from raptors is greatest, since they

    can exploit the low light and surprise the babblers with relative ease. This is also the best

    time for babblers to feed, since many night creatures are still active — termites, insects,

    … . According to Zahavi, this explains why babblers dance: they do it at the most

    inconvenient time and place because to undertake this is the most reliable way of showingtheir reliable commitment to their group. “The dancing of babblers,” Zahavi

    writes, “reminded us of stories our parents’ generation told about the dancing of members

    of pioneering kibbutzim in Israel in the earliest, most difficult and exhausting years: For 

  • 8/9/2019 Ethology Between Empathy, Standpoint and Perspectivism_ the Case of the Arabian Babblers _ Vinciane Despret

    14/21

    months we had nothing to eat, but we danced all night…” (Zahavi & Zahavi, 1997: 117).

    Dancing is a way to test the quality of the relationship and to reassess it. Even dogs do

    this with their human partners. Large dogs like German shepherds, Zahavi explains, use

    their weight to test the bond with humans. “They approach and stand next to a visitor in a

    friendly manner, leaning against the visitor’s legs, gradually transferring more and more of 

    their weight, until they are pushed off. How much of this treatment a visitor will take

    before pushing the dog off enables the animal to assess the visitor’s attitude toward it ”

    (Zahavi & Zahavi, 1997: 112). Once again, Zahavi’s style looks like that of a naturalist:

    socially sophisticated babblers are compared to bright dogs well equipped with agency, to

    explain how social animals invent creative ways to assess, to undertake and to reinforce

    the links they are entwined in.

    The importance of a partnership to its members and the relationships between partners

    depend on many factors that can easily change, which makes frequent testing of the

    social bond essential (Zahavi, 1976:1). The testing not only assesses the bond and its

    reliability, it creates it. Rituals perform social links.

    Mixing together in the same story babblers, human beings and dogs is not solely a

    practice similar to the amateur’s. It is an embodied practice that, I would suggest following

    Haraway’s analysis, recreates similarities between scientific and mundane practices, an

    embodied practice that redefines work with animals as companionship. Primatologist

    Barbara Smuts explains that she has been struck by the frequent enactments of brief 

    greeting rituals, be it between the baboons she observed for years or between herself and

    her dog Bahati. Among baboons, both friends and non-friends greet one another all the

    time, “and,”   Haraway comments, “who they are is in constant becoming in these rituals”

    (2008:26).The way Smuts construes ritual greetings — or the way her baboons enact

    them — is very similar to the way Zahavi and his babblers understand them. Harawaywrites, “an embodied communication is more like a dance than a word. The flow of 

    entangled meaningful bodies in time — whether jerky and nervous or flaming and flowing,

    whether both partners move in harmony or painfully out of synch or something else

    altogether — is communication about relationship, the relationship itself, and the means of 

    reshaping relationship and so its enacters.” 

    Therefore, in dancing, babblers have literally embodied the meaning of their rituals. And

    they appear closer and closer to the baboons who taught Smuts how to dance — as we

    will see — when we read her writing: “With language, it is possible to lie and say we like

    someone when we don’t. However, (…) closely interacting bodies tend to tell thetruth”. “This is,”  Haraway continues, “a very interesting definition of truth” . She is not

    referring to “the tired philosophical and linguistic arguments about whether dogs can lie,

    and if so, lie about lying. The truth or honesty of nonlinguistic embodied communication

    depends on looking back and greeting significant others, again and again (…) Rather, this

    truth telling is about (…) holding in esteem, and regard open to those who look back 

    reciprocally.  ” (2008:27).

    With these words, I eventually found the question I could explore in laboratory practice.

    Might animals not only be seen seeing   by the ethologists who observe them — as Derrida

    put it — but also be asked about their response  to the asking? In other words, mightethologists think animals respond to them, might they take a position with regard to the

    situation that one proposes to them, and might they give an opinion about what is being

    asked? Eileen Crist (1997) is right when she says — anticipating Derrida’s criticism of 

  • 8/9/2019 Ethology Between Empathy, Standpoint and Perspectivism_ the Case of the Arabian Babblers _ Vinciane Despret

    15/21

    Descartes — that the difference between response and reaction is not simply a matter of 

    language : it structures the way we see animals as passive reacting beings — driven by

    instincts, motivations, evolutionary rules or genes — or as active beings who invent their 

    own life, create, give meanings to events, anticipate, and I would add, who co-invent the

    practice of knowledge about themselves.

    If I put it in another way, my question becomes more concrete: which kind of practices,

    theories, or ethologists could make that shift possible? Theories do not only affect what

    scientists think they should see, and therefore what they actually see: theories affect

    what they do, who they are, and therefore the way animals see their scientists seeing

    them; the way animals respond to their scientists[21]. Which kind of theories or practices

    could afford to take that into account?

    Not surprisingly, we may find some answers to this question in primatology. Hans

    Kummer, for example, explained that he had succeeded in habituating his Hamadryas

    baboons in Ethiopia — after months and months of unsuccessful approaches — only

    when he was able to ask, and to answer, this very question: how do these baboons judge

    us? How do they see us? Similarly, Thelma Rowell considers that habituation is not due

    to the work of the scientist, but rather to the way animals perceive the very practical role

    of their observer. She told me in an interview that, when she was working with blue

    monkeys, she noticed that the eagles — which usually eat blue monkeys — were around

    overhead, “but,”  she added, “if they look down, of course they have very good eyesight,

    they see a face looking up  (Rowell shows the gesture of looking up with binoculars),

    which is very off-putting if you are thinking of catching a monkey. And then, they went and 

    caught other monkeys, somewhere else. I think actually to the point is whether a reason

    why a monkey eventually got tamed was because in some sense they realized that, by 

    allowing us to be with them, they were being protected from the eagles.”   And then sheconcluded: “There is much more awareness than the people watching them are aware of.” 

    However, the clearest example in primatology is given by the analysis Donna Haraway

    offers on the work of Barbara Smuts — not so surprisingly if one remembers Haraway’s

    response to Derrida’s lack of acknowledgement of the few scientists who have been able

    to meet the gaze of animals. Smuts tells us that when she began her first fieldwork with

    baboons, she did exactly what she has been taught to do in order to habituate her animals

    to her presence: according to the conventions of objective knowledge, she was advised to

    be as neutral as possible, to be “like a rock, to be unavailable, so that eventually the

    baboons would go on about their business in nature as if data-collecting humankind werenot present ”. Haraway remarks that, in these kind of situations, scientists “could query but 

    not be queried ”: “ people could ask if baboons are or are not social subjects, or ask 

    anything else for that matter, without any ontological risk either to themselves, except 

    maybe being bitten by an angry baboon or contracting a dire parasitic infection, or to their 

    culture’s dominant epistemologies about what are named nature and culture.” Progress in

    habituation was painfully slow: the baboons frequently looked at Smuts, and the more she

    ignored their looks, the less satisfied they seemed. Ignoring social cues is far from neutral

    social behavior: “I imagine the baboons as seeing somebody off-category, not 

    something,”   Haraway writes, “and asking if that being were or were not educable to the

    standard of a polite guest” . (2008:24-25)

    So the question that weighed most heavily in the field was probably not “Are the baboons

    social subjects?” but rather “Is the human being a social subject?”. And the answer was

    http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftn21

  • 8/9/2019 Ethology Between Empathy, Standpoint and Perspectivism_ the Case of the Arabian Babblers _ Vinciane Despret

    16/21

    probably “No”. Do people have a face? The baboons would have had some doubts about

    it. The monkeys inquired whether the woman was a good social subject, whom one could

    understand and with whom one could have a relationship. Smuts therefore had to learn to

    be polite, in the ethical, political, and epistemological senses of the world. She learned to

    respond, to acknowledge, to look back, perhaps to greet. She learned to respect and to

    make this respect the core of her practice, the condition of learning. And, as she tells us,

    her own being was transformed: “I… in the process of gaining their trust, changed almost 

    everything about me, including the way I walked and sat, the way I held my body and the

    way I used my eyes and voice. I was learning a whole new way of being in the world —

    the way of baboons”. She explains that, having learned the way baboons express their 

    emotions or intentions, she could respond to them and be understood. As a result, the

    baboons started to give her very deliberate dirty looks, which made her move away. This

    signaled a profound change: Smuts was not treated like an object (to avoid), but was

    recognized as a subject, a reliable subject with whom baboons could communicate, who

    would move away when told to do so, and with whom things could be clearly established.

    Of course, this is primatology: a practice that deals with animals who can resist to a

    certain extent and who may have good reasons to resist this will to be “no-one” that would

    prevent any interaction. Baboons may have supposed we could do better than that in

    social matters — and we should acknowledge their perplexity in regard to us, and their 

    lack of fear of “baboonomorphism”.

    Might we, however, imagine that if babblers have become so interesting, this might be

    partly due to the fact that Zahavi takes into account the opinion babblers may have about

    the questions scientists address to them? In that case, in some way, Zahavi and the

    babblers may be said to be responding to each other, and to be acting according to the

    questioning and the response of the other. They would be making each other moreresponsive: Zahavi’s anthropological-like practice — meeting, feeding, “biographing” and

    calling his babblers — could for example explain the fact that babblers act so interestingly.

    They do more things. In other words, Zahavi’s practice with “his” babblers, if we draw the

    contrast with Jon’s babblers, gives those birds a greater chance to be interesting[22].

    I do not have any clear evidence of that, and it might look like generous but candid

    speculation.

     Among the hypotheses, we could first consider the peculiarity of Zahavi’s practice and

    suggest that Zahavi is undertaking with his babblers a hermeneutic approach grounded in

    common rationality; a kind of “If I were him/her” way of thinking. This of course might alsobe suspected of heavy anthropomorphism: instead of putting himself in the babblers’

    shoes, Zahavi would actually be asking the birds to wear human shoes. The perspective

    would not be the babblers’ one, but would only reflect a human situated standpoint [23].

    In addition, since Zahavi calls the babblers, “invites them” and offers presents to them, I

    could suggest that each encounter in the field actually looks like a request: “Come and

    show me what you can do” — as if babblers were actively being requested to cooperate

    — when Zahavi says that babblers give help to the experimenter, isn’t he himself 

    suggesting this hypothesis?

    However, these two hypotheses miss something that Smuts did not miss: she was able

    to acknowledge the hard work the baboons did to obtain from her a response to them.

    With my two hypotheses, babblers are not seriously involved in the change. How can we

    formulate that from the babblers’ perspective? A consideration of the theoretical

    http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftn22http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftn23

  • 8/9/2019 Ethology Between Empathy, Standpoint and Perspectivism_ the Case of the Arabian Babblers _ Vinciane Despret

    17/21

    framework could help us to find a more polite way to assess both the perspective of the

    babblers and their active interest in the research. This framework may be construed as

    being, in some way, similar to the device that made Alex, the parrot, talk; it meets the

    animal’s interest.

    The hypothesis could be formulated in two ways. First let us take the babblers’

    perspective. Because babblers are so fond of exhibition, and because scientists, thanks

    to Zahavi’s signal theory, are looking for babblers to exhibit, babblers are “requested” to do

    what they do “well” and what they feel at ease in doing. Babblers, then, might be more

    sensitive to being seen and to seeing who is seeing them, since scientists are responsive

    to what they do. That is why the birds come so easily when Zahavi calls them. It is as if 

    he is saying to them “Come, babblers, and show me”. Of course, there are crumbs of 

    bread. Saying that makes me think that the behaviorist’s animals are still the only animals

    we deal with. Behaviorists made us forget that to give is  a relationship per se, and I think

    that, sadly, they succeeded in making starving animals (artificially starving animals) the

    norm — as if animals were only interested in food. Might the babblers be construing

    Zahavi’s offer as a greeting? Do they greet the scientist? I do not have the answers to

    these questions, but I strongly affirm that Zahavi is clearly greeting his babblers. And he

    does that with a present, with his body when he tends his hand, with his gaze, with his

    voice. And babblers do understand that the question of prestige is not at stake between

    them — if one remembers that they eagerly accept food from their scientists after having

    resisted a congener’s offer.

    Let us now take the second perspective, that of Zahavi. I might suggest that because

    Zahavi is so interested in display, because his theory is almost entirely grounded in

    exhibition, he has had many more chances to assume that the babblers were responding

    to the scientist who was interacting with them. I have noticed, in my own recent research(Despret & Porcher, 2007) with farm breeders, that animals taken to participate in

    contests or exhibitions are very responsive, and that breeders are as acutely sensitive to

    the way animals may be self-conscious as they are prone to credit their animals with a

    clear consciousness of what is at stake: “When cows go to contest, they know they are

    beautiful” , they “pose for the camera and know exactly that they are seen” ,“they are

     proud” ,… . The same may be said about trainers and their dogs. And the same happiness

    transpires.

    This hypothesis delights me particularly. Not so much because it talks about happiness,

    rather because it gives a new meaning, a new constructivist and non-relativist translation,to that famous and rather tired assertion: the behavior of animals is the product of the

    observer’s vision.

    Bibliography

    Boivin, Xavier. 2003. “The human-animal relationship, stockmanship and extensive sheep

    production”. In P. Goddard, editor, Improving sheep welfare on extensively managed 

    flocks: economics, husbandry and welfare. Proceedings of a workshop held in Aberdeen;

     Aberdeen, Scotland: 11-19.

    Coghland, Andy. 2006. « Animal welfare: See things from their perspective ».  New 

    scientist , sept. 23. 2006: 6-7.

    Crist, Elen. 1999. Images of Animals. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Crist, Elen.1997. « From questions to stimuli, from answers to reactions: The case of 

    Clever Hans »,Semiotica, 113-1/2: 1-42.

  • 8/9/2019 Ethology Between Empathy, Standpoint and Perspectivism_ the Case of the Arabian Babblers _ Vinciane Despret

    18/21

  • 8/9/2019 Ethology Between Empathy, Standpoint and Perspectivism_ the Case of the Arabian Babblers _ Vinciane Despret

    19/21

    Darwin’s puzzle. Oxford: Oxford University Press..

    [1]  See the work of Irene Pepperberg (1995).

    [2]  Bernd Heinrich (2001) writes that his mentor advised him not to work with ravens,

    because they are, as he said, too clever for scientists: ravens screw up their data— as

    soon you have a theory about them, they behave otherwise 2001). About “recalcitrant”

    objects as being what scientists working with living beings should search for, see bothworks of Isabelle Stengers (1993) and Bruno Latour (1999).

    [3]  So, what the cat’s curves (raising and falling) let us discern is not the cat’s power of 

    deliberation about a given task (as assumed by psychologists likeThorndike), but the

    power of deliberation about the demands about this given task. See below.

    [4]  See Ian Parker (2000) and his survey of Milgram’s subjects forty years later. Why did

    they do that — giving electric shocks to other persons, in a so-called (and fake) test

    improving learningship?

    [5]  The title of her book When species meet , sums up Haraway’s approach to human

    relationships with animals. She talks of “becoming worldly” through “becoming with” other species, saying that humans are transformed in their encounters with members of other 

    species, as well as are animals with humans.

    [6]  See Haraway (ibid)  who says that in animal’s welfare researches, objective answers

    can only be found if one is curious and one cares, p.337, note 27.

    [7]  But see Crespi for another and more convincing counterevidence. In 1942, Crespi

    reported that rats for which the quantity of reward has just been increased run faster than

    do rats having always received the large quantity food reward. He talked about “elation” for 

    this positive contrast and about “deception” for a negative one (less food reward).

    [8]  See Eileen Crist (2000) for a very an illuminating contrast.

    [9]  « Stockmanship and Farm animal Welfare », p. 9 of the manuscript.

    [10]  See Derrida’s critics about two kinds of representations, one set from those who

    observe animals but are never seeing themselves being seen, and even if they were

    inadvertently, did not take that into account — “they never meet their gaze”— and the

    other set who engages animals only as literary or mythological figures. What I am doing

    here, in someway, follows and tries to continue Haraway comments on Derrida (2008:20-

    21): « For those readings I and my people are permanently his debt. But with his cat,

    Derrida failed a simple obligation of companion species; he did not become curious about 

    what a cat might actually be doing, feeling, thinking, or perhaps making available to him in

    looking back at him that morning ». Nor was he curious of the work of some

    primatologists who actually met the gaze of their animals, and « in response undone and 

    redone themselves and their sciences  ».

    [11] We are here reminded Pemberton’s (quoted by Haraway, 2008: 59) suggesting that

    « we cannot understand how scientists discipline their experimental organisms without

    understanding how these organisms also discipline scientists, forcing them to care ».

    [12]  My Psychological thesis (1991) was about altruistic behaviors in birds. So, I had

    some ideas about what one could expect from “average” altruistic birds.

    [13] Interestingly, Zahavi’s style (and the stories he tells) is exactly the same in his

    scientific papers (from 1975) and in his book. Even in seminar Zahavi was considered as

    an eccentric, sometimes making his colleagues very nervous, sometimes enjoying them

    (like Thelma Rowell who told me that when Zahavi was attending at a meeting as orator 

    http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftnref11http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftnref6http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftnref4http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftnref10http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftnref3http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftnref5http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftnref7http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftnref9http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftnref2http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftnref13http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftnref8http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftnref12http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftnref1

  • 8/9/2019 Ethology Between Empathy, Standpoint and Perspectivism_ the Case of the Arabian Babblers _ Vinciane Despret

    20/21

    Tweet   0   2Curtir    0

    she would not miss it, it was always amusing).

    [14]  In his earlier papers, Zahavi did not talk about prestige but about « status »: status,

    he explained, was different from hierarchy and was gained through altruistic actions. The

    term prestige appeared in the 1997 book. We may find some very similar intuitions about

    ravens in the work of Bernd Heinrich.

    [15] Thelma Rowell makes similar hypothesis about fighting in sheep. « I think, she says,

    that one of the functions of the fighting is coordination, or the result of fighting is

    coordination. The females take a keen interest to the fight. When you are doing this ( T.R.

    hits her hands loudly) it makes a lovely loud noise. And if somebody is fighting here, the

    ewes will come running to watch. And so I said, all right, let us say that it is not a fight,

    this is a display. How could a sheep make a loud noise by himself? It is a sound one-hand

    clapping, you can’t do it, but with 2 of them, you make a spectacular noise and the visual

    display. And it is very exiting to the ewes, and they all coming and eat together, and then,

    it’s all over” (My interview, June 2003).

    [16]  This theory is called the « Handicap Principle theory ». (Zahavi,1975). Zahavi

    explains that, for example, you may find the rule of honesty in the encounter between a

    predator and its prey when the latter apparently seems to warn its congeneres. « Why 

    does a gazelle reveal itself to a predator that might not spot it? Why does it waste time

    and energy jumping up and down (stotting) instead of running away as fast as it can? The

    gazelle is signaling to the predator that it has seen it; by « wasting » time and by jumping 

    high in the air rather than bounding away, it demonstrates in a reliable way that it is able to

    outrun the wolf. The wolf, upon learning that it has lost its chance to surprise its prey, and 

    that this gazelle in in tip-top physical shape (…) may decide to look for more promising 

     prey   ». (Zahavi and Zahavi, 1997:xvi).

    [17]  But see Marion Thomas for a more radical criticism.[18]  See Crist, who talks about a descriptive style characterized as « frequency-laden »,

    (1999:148).

    [19] Of course, I would not deny that Zahavi’s model is sometimes as despotic — as it

    aims to explain all behaviors or all strange behaviors— as others are. But this model seem

    to work case by case, taking each time other paths, other motivations, other experiences,

    in sum, other « details ».

    [20]  If babblers are actually as subtle as human observers all suspect, the « no

    differences » hypothesis between group might deserve a full anthology of explanations.

    [21]  See for a first formulation of that in Despret (2006) « Sheep do have Opinions« .[22] See about giving a chance Latour, B. (2002).

    [23] It was one of the suspicion that lead my first analysis, for example, when I heard

    Zahavi telling me that babblers had to solve the same problem than pioneers of first

    Kibbutz: how to solve the dilemma between the necessity of cooperation and the need to

    compete? Competing to cooperate (and to enhance each own status) would have been the

    solution for the kibbutz, he then said. But the world has changed and has enlarged, and

    people are not satisfied anymore with local prestige.

    Partager:

    Ce contenu a été publié dans Papers  par Vinciane. Mettez-le en favori avec son

    Share

    http://twitter.com/intent/tweet?text=Ethology%20between%20Empathy%2C%20Standpoint%20and%20Perspectivism%3A%20the%20case%20of%20the%20Arabian%20babblers%20-%20http%3A%2F%2Fwww.vincianedespret.be%2F2010%2F04%2Fethology-between-empathy-standpoint-and-perspectivism-the-case-of-the-arabian-babblers%2F%20http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftnref15http://www.vincianedespret.be/author/vinciane/http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftnref18http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftnref22http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftnref21http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftnref19http://www.vincianedespret.be/2010/04/sheep-do-have-opinions/http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftnref16http://www.facebook.com/share.php?u=http%3A%2F%2Fwww.vincianedespret.be%2F2010%2F04%2Fethology-between-empathy-standpoint-and-perspectivism-the-case-of-the-arabian-babblers%2F&t=Ethology%20between%20Empathy%2C%20Standpoint%20and%20Perspectivism%3A%20the%20case%20of%20the%20Arabian%20babblershttp://www.vincianedespret.be/category/papers/http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftnref20http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftnref14https://mail.google.com/mail/?view=cm&fs=1&to&su=Ethology%20between%20Empathy%2C%20Standpoint%20and%20Perspectivism%3A%20the%20case%20of%20the%20Arabian%20babblers&body=http%3A%2F%2Fwww.vincianedespret.be%2F2010%2F04%2Fethology-between-empathy-standpoint-and-perspectivism-the-case-of-the-arabian-babblers%2F&ui=2&tf=1&shva=1http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftnref23http://www.blogger.com/post-create.g?blogID=2851373267162470404#_ftnref17

  • 8/9/2019 Ethology Between Empathy, Standpoint and Perspectivism_ the Case of the Arabian Babblers _ Vinciane Despret

    21/21

    permalien [http://www.vincianedespret.be/2010/04/ethology-between-empathy-

    standpoint-and-perspectivism-the-case-of-the-arabian-babblers/] .

    http://www.vincianedespret.be/2010/04/ethology-between-empathy-standpoint-and-perspectivism-the-case-of-the-arabian-babblers/

Recommended