+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

Date post: 28-Nov-2014
Category:
Upload: wellman
View: 610 times
Download: 3 times
Share this document with a friend
Description:
FAITHFULNESS AS A SOUL-MAKING THEODICY_________________A Thesis Presented to the Faculty of Criswell College_________________In Fulfillment of the Requirements for RES 603_________________by Jared C. Wellman April 23, 2011Copyright © 2011 Jared C. Wellman All rights reserved. Criswell College has permission to reproduce and disseminate this document in any form by any means for purposes chosen by the College, including, without limitation, preservation or instruction.APPROVAL
96
Transcript
Page 1: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy
Page 2: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

FAITHFULNESS AS A SOUL-MAKING THEODICY

_________________

A Thesis

Presented to

the Faculty of

Criswell College

_________________

In Fulfillment

of the Requirements for RES 603

_________________

by

Jared C. Wellman

April 23, 2011

Page 3: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

Copyright © 2011 Jared C. Wellman

All rights reserved. Criswell College has permission to reproduce and disseminate this

document in any form by any means for purposes chosen by the College, including,

without limitation, preservation or instruction.

Page 4: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

APPROVAL SHEET

FAITHFULNESS AS A SOUL-MAKING THEODICY

Jared C. Wellman

_______________________________________________________

[Barry Creamer, Associate Professor of Humanities]

_______________________________________________________

[Joe Wooddell, Associate Professor of Philosophy]

Date ________________________________

Page 5: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

ABSTRACT

FAITHFULNESS AS A SOUL-MAKING THEODICY

This thesis argues that the virtue of faithfulness is a satisfactory contribution to

the Soul-Making Theodicy. Faithfulness is best realized when it is directed to an ever-

faithful deity, who is also omnipotent and omnibenevolent. While John Hick is credited

with the Soul-Making Theodicy, many of his philosophical and theological tenets are

abandoned in order to develop a more Augustinian approach to the theodicy. Chapter 1

introduces the Soul-Making Theodicy and how it was developed in response to the

problem of God and evil.

Chapter 2 conveys various philosophical approaches to the problem of God

and evil. These approaches are Alvin Plantinga’s Free Will Defense, St. Augustine’s Evil

is a Privation of Good Theodicy, Gregory Boyd’s Trinitarian Warfare Theodicy, Gordon

Clark’s Deterministic Defense, and John Hick’s Soul-Making Theodicy. These are

offered after an explanation of the problem of evil as outlined by David Hume and

William Rowe, who are the leading advocates to the Logical and Evidential problems of

evil, respectively.

Chapter 3 offers a rendering of John Hick’s Soul-Making Theodicy that

questions his views on the Word of God, the image of God in man, and eschatology.

Chapter 4 discusses the necessity of virtue in man, and observes the four

cardinal virtues (temperance, courage, wisdom, and justice) and the three theological

Page 6: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

virtues (faith, hope, and love). Faithfulness is proposed as a unique virtue that helps

justify the problem of evil. Moreover, Augustine’s arguments concerning virtue are

detailed as well as a brief overview of the book of Habakkuk and how it expresses the

relationship between faithfulness and evil.

Chapter 5 observes two of the apologetic arguments for the existence of God—

the teleological and moral arguments. These arguments help support the notion that an

omnipotent and omnibenevolent God exists.

The Conclusion summarizes the overview of the argument proposed in this

thesis, suggesting an Irenaean in terms of the Word of God, Augustine in terms of the

image of God in man, and Clarkian in terms of free will, rendering of Hick’s Soul-

Making Theodicy.

The primary thrust of this work is to argue that the virtue of faithfulness is a

satisfactory soul-making property that helps justify the existence of evil in a world

created by an omnipotent and omnibenevolent God.

Jared Clent Wellman

Criswell College, 2011

Page 7: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

vii

TABLE OF CONTENTS

Page

LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . ix

PREFACE . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . x

Chapter

1. INTRODUCTION . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1

2. VARIOUS APPROACHES TO

QUESTION OF GOD AND EVIL . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 5

The Case Against God’s Existence . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 9

Alvin Plantinga’s Free Will Defense . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 13

St. Augustine’s Evil is a Privation of God . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 24

Gregory Boyd’s Trinitarian Warfare Theodicy . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 31

Gordon Clark’s Deterministic Approach . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 34

John Hick’s Soul-Making Theodicy . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 38

3. A RENDERING OF HICK’S SOUL-MAKING THEODICY . . . . . . . . 43

An Irenaean View of the Word of God . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 44

An Augustinian View of the Image of God . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 49

Hick’s Eschatological View of Universal Salvation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 58

4. FAITH AS A VIABLE SOUL-MAKING CHARACTERISTIC . . . . . . 63

The Four Cardinal Virtues . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 63

The Three Theological Virtues . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 64

Page 8: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

viii

The Virtue of Faithfulness . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 65

5. THE EXISTENCE OF AN OMNIPOTENT

AND OMNIBENEVOLENT GOD . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 70

The Teleological Argument . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 70

The Moral Argument . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 72

6. AN OVERVIEW OF A RENDERED

SOUL-MAKING THEODICY . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 76

BIBLIOGRAPHY . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 78

Page 9: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

ix

LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS

EPE The Evidential Problem of Evil

LPE The Logical Problem of Evil

NASB New American Standard Bible

NPNF Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers

Page 10: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

x

PREFACE

My interest with the problem of God and evil started many years ago during

my first philosophy course at the Criswell College. While I tarried to study philosophy, it

was this course that propelled me into new and exciting ways of viewing the world. Dr.

Joe Wooddell taught this class, and his passionate theological emphasis on what I once

feared changed the way that I viewed philosophy forever. This newfound zeal was

cultivated by the likes of Dr. R. Alan Streett and Dr. Barry Creamer, who taught me the

need for theological philosophy in a skeptical, unbelieving world, and that Christian

philosophy has a rational and reasonable place in the field. Throughout my continued

studies, it became evident that the problem of God and evil was one of the most

devastating attacks on Christianity, and I therefore wanted to provide satisfactory

contributions to the topic. With this said, I am thankful to all of my professors at the

Criswell College who helped me build a strong theological foundation by which I can

properly do philosophy.

I am also thankful to the three Southern Baptist Churches that I have had the

honor of serving in—First Baptist Church of Gun Barrel City in Gun Barrel City, Texas,

Powell Baptist Church in Powell, Texas, and the Carpenter’s Cross Baptist Church in

Flint, Texas. My student pastor at First Baptist Gun Barrel City—Denilio Gorena—was

a key individual who encouraged me to attend the Criswell College, and who taught me

everything he knew about preaching the Gospel. The loving people at Powell Baptist

Page 11: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

xi

Church felt led to invest in my education, which has been a true blessing in my academic

ministry, and the fellowship at Carpenter’s Cross Baptist Church has allowed me to

continue my graduate studies as I served them as their pastor.

I am most thankful to my wife Amanda, who has been the biggest supporter

throughout my ministerial and academic tenures. I simply would not be where I am if

she was not as loving, encouraging, and supportive as she is toward what the Lord has led

me to do. Her parents—Jim and Karen Vess—have also been encouraging to the both of

us as we pursue the Lord’s will in our lives.

Finally, I continue to be amazed by the grace of God in my life. The

psalmist’s declaration, “What is man that You take thought of him, and the son of man

that You care for him?” (Psalm 8:4) continually resounds in my heart as I have the

privilege of getting to know the Lord better each day. It is only by God’s love through

His Son Jesus Christ that I press on.

Jared C. Wellman

Chandler, Texas

April, 2011

Page 12: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

1

CHAPTER 1

Introduction

In Religion, Reason and Revelation, Gordon Clark wrote, “In the background

of every religious worldview there stands a frightening specter. An author may refrain

from mentioning it; he may hope that his public will forget to think about it; but no

position is complete and none can be unhesitatingly accepted until it makes a clear

pronouncement on the problem of evil.”1 John Stott furthers this thought in writing, “The

fact of suffering undoubtedly constitutes the single greatest challenge to the Christian

faith, and has been in every generation. Its distribution and degree appear to be entirely

random and therefore unfair. Sensitive spirits ask if it can possibly be reconciled with

God’s justice and love.”2

“At some time or another, everyone wonders about the existence of evil and

suffering in the world. Its presence has touched all, ravaged many, and perplexed

thinking men throughout the ages.”3 Evil comes in various forms. The two most

generally accepted forms are moral evil and natural evil. “Natural evils arise solely from

nature: earthquakes, pestilence, famine, drought, flooding, mudslides, and hurricanes.

Moral evils are due to the free choices of human beings and include, for example, war,

1 Gordon Clark, Religion, Reason, and Revelation (Hobbs: The Trinity Foundation, 1995), 194.

2 John R. W. Stott, The Cross of Christ (Downers Grove, Ill.: InterVarsity Press, 1986), 311.

3 Norman Geisler, The Roots of Evil (Grand Rapids: Zondervan, 1978), 11.

Page 13: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

2

poverty, and racism.”4 Both manifestations cause man to consider and give answer to the

reality and purpose of evil in this world. These considerations and answers are what

theologians and philosophers call theodicies—“[Answers] to the problem of evil that

attempt to justify the ways of God to man by explaining God’s reasons for allowing

evil.”5

Prima facie, the existence of evil seems to oppose the existence of an

omnibenevolent and omnipotent God. This is why some consider the question of God

and evil instead the problem of God and evil. “Any given argument becomes a problem

when its premises are perceived to be plausible or true and the conclusion opposes one’s

current position.”6 The question of evil therefore becomes a problem for the theist

because “of its very strong support for an atheistic conclusion.”7 The eighteenth-century

philosopher David Hume summarized this “problem” well in writing, “Is [God] willing to

prevent evil, but not able? Then He is impotent. Is He able, but not willing? Then He is

malevolent. Is He both willing and able? Whence then is evil?”8 Hume’s argument

echoes the early writings of Epicurus who wrote, “Either God wants to abolish evil, and

cannot; or he can, but does not want to; or he cannot and does not want to. If he wants to,

4 Kelly Clark, Richard Lints, and James K.A. Smith, 101 Key Terms in Philosophy and Their

Importance for Theology (Louisville: John Knox Press, 2004), 25.

5 Stephen Evans, Pocket Dictionary of Apologetics & Philosophy of Religion (Leicester:

InterVarsity Press, 2002), 114.

6 Michael Peterson, William Hasker, Bruce Reichenbach, and David Basinger, Philosophy of

Religion : Selected Readings (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007), 289.

7 Ibid.

8 David Hume, Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, ed. Nelson Pike (New York: Bobbs-

Merrill Co., Inc., 1970), pt. X, pp. 88, 91.

Page 14: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

3

but cannot, he is impotent. If he can, and does not want to, he is wicked. But, if God both

can and wants to abolish evil, then how comes evil in the world?”9

Throughout the last few centuries, many responses have been given to show

that Hume’s argument is not necessarily satisfactory. “Two of the more important

theodicies are the ‘soul-making theodicy,’ which argues that God allows evil so as to

make it possible for humans to develop certain desirable virtues, and the ‘free will

theodicy,’ which argues that God had to allow for the possibility of evil if he wished to

give humans (and angelic beings) free will.”10

Other theodicies include the Trinitarian

Warfare Theodicy, Evil is a Privation of Good Theodicy, and the Deterministic Theodicy.

This thesis advances a rendering of the “soul-making theodicy” and attempts to

answer the question as to whether or not it is it philosophically satisfying to suggest that

being faithful to an ever-faithful God is an adequate contribution to the problem of God

and evil. John Hick is credited with the concept of the Soul-Making Theodicy and

therefore his development of the argument will be evaluated. Its strengths and

weaknesses will be examined both philosophically and theologically. The theological

attribute known as faithfulness will be researched on both a theistic and humanistic level

in order to determine whether or not it is a worthwhile virtue that contributes to the soul-

making theodicy. A distinction will be made on how this virtue of faithfulness is best

realized when it appropriated to an omnipotent and omnibenevolent God who is ever-

9 Epicurus, as quoted in 2000 Years of Disbelief. Epicurus himself did not leave any written

form of this argument. It can be found in Christian theologian Lactantius's Treatise on the Anger of

God where Lactantius critiques the argument. Epicurus's argument as presented by Lactantius actually

argues that a god that is all-powerful and all-good does not exist and that the gods are distant and

uninvolved with man's concerns. The gods are neither our friends nor enemies.

(http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Problem_of_evil#Epicurus)

10

C. Stephen Evans, Pocket Dictionary of Apologetics & Philosophy of Religion (Downers

Grove: InterVarsity Press, 2002), 114.

Page 15: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

4

faithful. This will moreover be supported by a defense of the teleological and moral

arguments for the existence of God. The biblical book of Habakkuk will also be utilized

to enhance the discussion of biblical faithfulness. This thesis will be an applicative

contribution to everyone who has ever struggled with the problem of God and evil.

Page 16: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

5

CHAPTER 2

Various Responses to the Question of God and Evil

In the film Shutter Island, the following conversation takes place between the

warden and Teddy Daniels after a terrible storm ambushed the island:

Warden: Did you enjoy God's latest gift?

Teddy Daniels: What?

Warden: God's gift. Your violence.

[Daniels looks at him blankly]

Warden: When I came downstairs in my home, and I saw that tree in my living

room, it reached out for me... a divine hand. God loves violence.

Teddy Daniels: I... I hadn't noticed.

Warden: Sure you have. Why else would there be so much of it? It's in us. It's what

we are. We wage war, we burn sacrifices, and pillage and plunder and tear at the

flesh of our brothers. And why? Because God gave us violence to wage in his

honor.

Teddy Daniels: I thought God gave us moral order.

Warden: There's no moral order as pure as this storm. There's no moral order at all.

There's just this: can my violence conquer yours?11

This dialogue displays the various conclusions that can be made when dealing

with the question of evil and how it relates to God. The warden acknowledged God, but

said that He was evil. Daniels also acknowledged God, but said that He provided moral

order. The same variety of answers is seen in Albert Camus’ book The Plague, where the

reader is confronted with the problem of God and evil through the character Paneloux,

the priest of the village. As the community is overpowered by the plague, Paneloux is

forced to make a critical philosophical decision. He must either “have faith that God will

bring good out of the evil situation, or he must stand with Dr. Rieuc and Tarrou and

11

Quote derived from the 2010 film, Shutter Island as listed on the Internet Movie Database:

http://www.imdb.com/character/ch0094019/quotes

Page 17: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

6

condemn the evil situation as unbearable and unredeemable. To them, the situation

declares either that there is no God, and man is left to struggle in futility or that there is a

God, but He is the supreme, evil enemy of man.”12

Films and novels are just two of culture’s ways of relating the struggles and

confusion surrounding the question of God and evil. These dialogues furthermore

convey the notion that the question of God and evil is, as detailed earlier, more befittingly

considered a “problem.” As previously noted, “Any given argument becomes a problem

when its premises are perceived to be plausible or true and the conclusion opposes one’s

current position.” In this sense, the question of God and evil seemingly becomes a

problem for the theist because of its alleged strong support for an atheistic conclusion.

It is in this respect that many have developed an argument to deny the problem

as being such.13

Philosophers deem these arguments either defenses or theodicies.

“Theodicies are often distinguished from defenses, which argue that it is reasonable to

believe that God has reasons for allowing evil even if we do not know what those reasons

are.”14

It is not illogical in this respect, however, to accept and purport both a theodicy

and defense to answer the problem of God and evil.

It is important to note that there are two generally accepted assertions for the

problem of God and evil—the Logical Problem of Evil15

(LPE hereafter) and the

12

Norman Geisler, The Roots of Evil (Grand Rapids: Zondervan, 1978), 11.

13

Alvin Plantinga, for example, distinguishes the argument as the “sol-called problem of evil.”

Alvin Plantinga, God, Freedom, and Evil (New York: Harper & Row Publishers, 1974), 7.

14

C. Stephen Evans, Pocket Dictionary of Apologetics & Philosophy of Religion (Downers

Grove: InterVarsity Press, 2002), 114.

15

Also known as the deductive argument from evil.

Page 18: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

7

Evidential Problem of Evil16

(EPE hereafter). LPE asks, “Is the existence of God and

evil logically compatible?” “Some atheists have claimed that God and evil are logically

incompatible, just as Rufus is a dog and Rufus is not a dog are logically incompatible.

Exactly one must be true; they cannot both be true.”17

EPE, as developed by William

Rowe, “envisions a hypothetical case of natural evil not brought about by misuse of

human or angelic freedom.”18

Ed Hindson and Ergun Caner have illustrated this

argument in the following example: “Lightning causes a forest fire. An escaping fawn is

trapped by falling trees and, after much intense suffering, the fawn dies.”19

The argument

suggests that the fawn’s suffering is gratuitous, and that no greater good or justifiable

purpose was served.

Both LPE and EPE present a seemingly difficult problem for the theist. Since

LPE, however, “alleges that theism is inconsistent, it is properly defended simply by a

proof that it is not inconsistent.”20

Alvin Plantinga’s God, Freedom, and Evil is arguably

the most renowned work on providing a logically consistent defense against LPE.

Concerning EPE, several responses have been given which include Paul Draper’s

argument that the good that we know is not representative of all possible good, Stephen

Wykstra’s argument that things are not always as they appear, attacking EPE’s claim that

while the fawn’s death may have appeared gratuitous it doesn’t necessarily entail that it

16

Also known as the inductive argument from evil.

17

Ed Hindson and Ergun Caner, The Popular Encyclopedia of Apologetics (Eugene: Harvest

House Publishers, 2008), 211. 18

Ibid.

19

Ibid., 212.

20

Michael Peterson, William Hasker, Bruce Reichenbach, and David Basinger, Philosophy of

Religion : Selected Readings (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007), 290.

Page 19: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

8

was, and Michael Peterson’s argument that denies EPE’s second premise, which states

that “If God existed, then there would be no gratuitous evils.”21

Peterson argues that “It

is possible that God, in creating a world suitable for humans to achieve moral growth of

their own making, must create a world where evils sometimes happen that are never

directly ‘redeemed.’22

It is in this respect that a Soul-Making Theodicy is helpful. In the

proper understanding, a Soul-Making Theodicy contributes to both LPE and EPE,

especially when that soul-making property is faithfulness to an ever-faithful Deity. With

respect to LPE, the virtue of faithfulness in man is arguably a justifiable reason for many

accounts of evil. Regarding EPE, obtaining the virtue of faithfulness hinders its premise

that “if God exists, then there would be no gratuitous evils,” for it is not unreasonable to

suggest that gratuitous evils are a necessary by-product of God’s greater good in man,

even if it is not necessarily ascertainable.

This chapter discusses five of the most well-known arguments against the

problem of God and evil—the LPE and EPE—and evaluates their strengths and

weaknesses. While there are many credible contributions to the question of God and evil,

a concentration is placed on the Soul-Making Theodicy as a satisfying contribution to the

subject. The arguments presented in the following are (1) Alvin Plantinga’s Free Will

Defense, (2) Augustine’s Evil is a Privation of Good Theodicy, (3) Gregory Boyd’s

Trinitarian Warfare Theodicy, (4) Gordon Clark’s Deterministic Defense, and (5) John

Hick’s Soul-Making Theodicy. David Hume and William Rowe’s formation of the

problem will first be detailed in order to enhance the understanding of these responses.

21

Ed Hindson and Ergun Caner, The Popular Encyclopedia of Apologetics (Eugene: Harvest

House Publishers, 2008), 213.

22

Ibid.

Page 20: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

9

The Case Against God’s Existence – David Hume and William Rowe

As already noted, David Hume is arguably the most renowned advocate for the

logical problem of evil. Hume outlined his argument in his book Dialogues Concerning

Natural Religion, which “is applauded as the most sophisticated and elegant

philosophical dialogue written in English.”23

There are three principal speakers in

Hume’s Dialogues: Demea, Cleanthes, and Philo. “Demea, something of a dogmatist,

defends the existence of God on a priori grounds and, in that regard, follows Leibniz.

Cleanthes believes that experience provides evidence for the existence of a deity who is

immensely powerful and benevolent. Philo, probably Hume’s protagonist, is a skeptic

who attempts to rebut arguments from reason and experience.”24

The following is an

excerpt from Hume’s Dialogues cataloguing evil:

But through these external insults, said Demea, from animals, from men, from all

the elements, which assault us form a frightful catalogue of woes, they are nothing

in comparison of those which arise within ourselves, from the distempered condition

of our mind and body. How many lie under the lingering torment of diseases? Hear

the pathetic enumeration of the great poet.

Intestine stone and ulcer, colic-pangs,

Demoniac frenzy, moping melancholy,

And moon-struck madness, pining atrophy,

Marasmus, and wide-wasting pestilence.

Dire was the tossing, deep the groans: Despair

Tended the sick, busiest from couch to couch.

And over them triumphant Death his dart

Shook: but delay’d to strike, though oft invok’d

With vows, as their chief good and final hope.

The disorders of the mind, continued Demea, though more secret, are not perhaps

less dismal and vexatious. Remorse, shame, anguish, rage disappointment, anxiety,

23

Michael Peterson, William Hasker, Bruce Reichenbach, and David Basinger, Philosophy of

Religion : Selected Readings (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007), 296.

24

Ibid.

Page 21: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

10

fear, dejection, despair—who has ever passed through life without cruel inroads

from these tormentors? How many have scarcely ever felt any better sensations?

Labor and poverty, so abhorred by everyone, are the certain lot of the far greater

number; and those few privileged persons who enjoy ease and opulence never reach

contentment or true felicity. All the goods of life united would not make a very

happy man, but all the ills united would make a wretch indeed; and any one of them

almost (and who can be free from every one), nay, often the absence of one good

(and who can possess all) is sufficient to render life ineligible.25

While this excerpt details tenets of natural evil, Plantinga recognizes the other

generally accepted category of evil—moral evil—in writing, “In addition to ‘natural’

evils such as earthquakes, tidal waves, and virulent diseases there are evils that result

from human stupidity, arrogance, and cruelty.”26

In God, Freedom, and Evil, Plantinga

shares a passage from Fyodor Dostoevski’s The Brothers Karamazov that describes this

type of evil in detail:

A Bulgarian I met lately in Moscow,” Ivan went on, seeming not to hear his

brother’s words, “told me about the crimes committed by Turks and Circassians in

all parts of Bulgaria through fear of a general rising of the Slavs. They burn villages,

murder, outrage women and children, they nail their prisoners by the ears to the

fences, leave them so till morning, and in the morning they hang them—all sorts of

things you can’t imagine. People talk sometimes of bestial cruelty, but that’s a great

injustice and insult to the beasts; a beast can never be so cruel as a man, so

artistically cruel. The tiger only tears and gnaws, that’s all he can do. He would

never think of nailing people by the ears, even if he were able to do it. These Turks

took a pleasure in torturing children, too; cutting the unborn child from the mother’s

womb, and tossing babies up in the air and catching them on the points of their

bayonets before their mother’s eyes. Doing it before the mother’s eyes was what

gave zest to the amusement. Here is another scene that I though very interesting.

Imagine a trembling mother with her baby in her arms, a circle of invading Turks

around her. They’ve planned a diversion; they pet the baby, laugh to make it laugh.

They succeed, the baby laughs. At that moment a Turk points a pistol four inches

from the baby’s face. The baby laughs with glee, holds out his little hands to the

25

David Hume, Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, ed. Nelson Pike (New York: Bobbs-

Merrill Co., Inc., 1970), pt. X, pp.84-85. Plantinga notes that the “great poet” referred to is John Milton,

and the quotation is from Paradise Lost, bk. XI. Alvin Plantinga, God, Freedom, and Evil (New York:

Harper & Row, 1974), 8 (footnote).

26

Alvin Plantinga, God, Freedom, and Evil (New York: Harper & Row, 1974), 8.

Page 22: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

11

pistol, and he pulls the trigger in the baby’s face and blows out its brains. Artistic,

wasn’t it? By the way, Turks are particularly fond of sweet things, they say.27

Hume’s Dialogues and Dostoevski’s The Brothers Karamazov both express

the real evil present in the world. Plantinga asserted the atheologian’s concerns regarding

this evil in writing, “If God is as benevolent as Christian theists claim, He must be just as

appalled as we are at all this evil. But if He is also as powerful as they claim, then

presumably He is in a position to do something about it. So why does He permit it? Why

doesn’t He arrange things so that these evils don’t occur? That should have been easy

enough for one as powerful as He.”28

Hume has related the question in this way: “Is he

willing to prevent evil, but not able? Then he is impotent. Is he able, but not willing?

Then he is malevolent. Is he both able and willing? Whence then is evil?”29

Hume

furthermore has written, “Why is there any misery at all in the world? Not by chance,

surely. From some cause, then. It is from the intention of the deity? But he is perfectly

benevolent. Is it contrary to his intention? But he is almighty. Nothing can shake the

solidity of this reasoning, so short, so clear, so decisive…”30

At this point, it is evident

that Hume insists on the question: “If God is perfectly benevolent and also omnipotent, or

almighty, why is there any evil in the world? Why does he permit it?”31

In a

propositional sense, the argument is stated as follows:

27

Fyodor Dostoevski, The Brothers Karamazon, trans. Constance Garnett (New York:

Random House, 1933), 245-246.

28

Alvin Plantinga, God, Freedom, and Evil (New York: Harper & Row, 1974), 9.

29

David Hume, Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, ed. Nelson Pike (New York: Bobbs-

Merrill Co., Inc., 1970), pt. X, pp. 88.

30

Ibid., 91.

31

Plantinga, God, Freedom, and Evil, 10.

Page 23: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

12

1. God is omnipotent and wholly good.

2. God is omnipotent, God can eliminate evil.

3. If God is wholly good, God would want to eliminate evil.

4. There is evil.

5. Therefore, God does not exist.32

This is the deductive, logical problem of evil. In this context, Hume

“maintains that the existence of evil per se is logically inconsistent with the existence of a

good, omnipotent, omniscient God.”33

The atheologian J. L. Mackie advanced Hume’s

argument. According to Mackie, “it is not possible both that God is omnipotent and that

he was unable to create a universe containing moral good but no moral evil.” He has

written,

I think, however, that a more telling criticism can be made by way of the traditional

problem of evil. Here it can be shown not that religious beliefs lack rational support,

but that they are positively irrational, that the several parts of the essential

theological doctrine are inconsistent with one another…34

While David Hume is arguably the most renowned advocate of LPE, William

Rowe has been cited as the same for EPE. An apologetic encyclopedia has noted, “The

evidential argument from evil has been most powerfully and succinctly stated by William

Rowe.”35

Rowe calls EPE “the form of the problem which holds that the variety and

profusion of evil in our world, although perhaps not logically inconsistent with the

existence of [God], provides, nevertheless, rational support for the belief that the theistic

32

Kelly James Clark, Richard Lints, and James K. A. Smith, 101 Key Terms in Philosophy and

their Importance for Theology (Louisville: Westminster John Knox Press, 2004), 25.

33

Bruce Reichenbach, Evil and a Good God (New York: Fordham University Press, 1982), 1.

34

J. L. Mackie, “Evil and Omnipotence,” Mind 64, No. 254 (1955), reprinted in Nelson Pike,

ed., God and Evil (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1964) p.46.

35

Ed Hindson and Ergun Caner, The Popular Encyclopedia of Apologetics (Eugene: Harvest

House Publishers, 2008), 212.

Page 24: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

13

God does not exist.”36

The philosopher Bruce Reichenbach has summarized Rowe’s

claim in this way: “the pain and suffering which occur in our world make it unlikely or

improbable that a God who is good, omnipotent, omniscient, loving, and personal

exists.”37

Interestingly, Hume—perhaps realizing the inconsistency in LPE—also

defended EPE in writing,

…[A]s [God’s] goodness is not antecedently established, but must be inferred from

the phenomena, there can be no grounds for such an inference, while there are so

many ills in the universe, and while these ills might so easily have been

remedied…The bad appearances…may be compatible with such attributes as you

suppose. But surely they can never prove these attributes…However consistent the

world may be…with the idea of such a Deity, it can never afford us an inference

concerning his existence. The consistency is not absolutely denied, only the

inference.38

Understanding Hume’s LPE and Rowe’s EPE, the five aforementioned theodicies and

defenses can now be properly detailed.

The Free Will Defense – Alvin Plantinga

Born in 1932, Alvin Plantinga is arguably the “leading contemporary

philosopher of religion and developer of Reformed Epistemology.”39

Plantinga has

“criticized evidentialism in philosophy of religion by arguing that religious beliefs in

some cases may be ‘properly basic.’”40

This view is supported by an epistemology that

“sees knowledge as consisting of true beliefs that are the result of properly functioning

36

William Rowe, Philosophy of Religion (Encino: Dickenson, 1978), 86.

37

Bruce Reichenbach, Evil and a Good God (New York: Fordham University Press, 1982), 25.

38

David Hume, Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion (New York: Hafner, 1948), 78, 73.

39

C. Stephen Evans, Pocket Dictionary of Apologetics & Philosophy of Religion (Downers

Grove: InterVarsity Press, 2002), 93. Evans also includes Nicholas Wolterstorff and William Alston.

40

Ibid.

Page 25: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

14

faculties, operating according to their ‘design plan’ in a way that is directed at truth, in

the kind of environment in which they were intended to function.”41

According to

Plantinga, belief in God may be “properly basic” and does not have to be based on

evidence. This is important because it is this interpretation of epistemology that breeds

Plantinga’s Free Will Defense against the problem of evil. While philosophers like

Hume, Mackie, and Rowe attempt to logically and evidentially disprove the existence of

God, Plantinga’s belief in God is properly basic, and therefore his arguments follow in

this fashion.

Plantinga’s Free Will Defense was inspired by J. L. Mackie’s “basic contention

that it is not possible both that God is omnipotent and that he was unable to create a

universe containing moral good but no moral evil.”42

In Plantinga’s argument, “God

actualizes a world that contains free creatures who sometimes choose good and

sometimes evil.”43

Plantinga claims to have shown that it is logically possible for God to

and evil to coexist.

Mackie detailed what he saw as a logical inconsistency with God and evil in

his piece “Evil and Omnipotence:”

I think, however, that a more telling criticism can be made by way of the traditional

problem of evil. Here it can be shown, not that religious beliefs lack rational

support, but that they are positively irrational, that the several parts of the essential

theological doctrine are inconsistent with one another.44

41

Ibid.

42

Michael Peterson, William Hasker, Bruce Reichenbach, and David Basinger, Philosophy of

Religion : Selected Readings (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007), 315.

43

John Mackie, “Evil and Omnipotence,” in The Philosophy of Religion, ed. Basil Mitchell

(London: Oxford University Press, 1971), 92.

44

Ibid.

Page 26: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

15

Mackie moreover wrote,

In its simplest form the problem is this: God is omnipotent; God is wholly good; yet

evil exists. There seems to be some contradiction between these three propositions,

so that if any two of them were true the third would be false. But at the same time

all three are essential parts of most theological positions; the theologian, it seems, at

once must adhere and cannot consistently adhere to all three.45

To this, Plantinga asks, “Is Mackie right? Does the theist contradict himself?”46

Plantinga

then proceeds to offer the Free Will Defense, in which he shows that, “using the concept

of free will in humans and angels, God and evil are logically compatible (that is, they

could both exist without incompatibility).”47

In short, Plantinga claimed the following:

If God creates human beings with true, morally significant free will (where humans

can freely decide to act in ways that really do advance goodness in the world, or

really do cause evil in the world against self, others, or world), and if God wants a

world in which there are significant amounts of (angel—or human—originated)

moral goodness, it’s possible that God cannot get that kind of world without

significant amounts of moral badness as well. After all, if people are left free by

God, then the morally significant states of the world will in large part be up to the

decisions of humans (and angels), not up to God.48

Plantinga seems to be arguing that evil is the result of God choosing to create a

world in which man is significantly free, and in this freedom, man is free to choose good

or evil. Therefore, it doesn’t necessarily follow that God is not omnipotent, for He

sovereignly chose to create a significantly free world that included the possibility of evil.

It moreover doesn’t follow that God is malevolent, for He is not the one performing the

evil, and a world with freedom still includes good, even if evil is possible. Concerning

45

Ibid., 92-93.

46

Michael Peterson, William Hasker, Bruce Reichenbach, and David Basinger, Philosophy of

Religion : Selected Readings (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007), 315.

47

Ed Hindson and Ergun Caner, The Popular Encyclopedia of Apologetics (Eugene: Harvest

House Publishers, 2008), 211. 48

Ibid., 212.

Page 27: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

16

this, Peter Kreeft and Ronald Tacelli have written, “Evil’s source is not God’s power but

man’s freedom. A world without human freedom is a world without humans, a world

without hate but also without love.”49

Plantinga’s argument suggests that God’s decision

to create man inherently included a true, moral, and significant free will. While this

freedom produces significant moral goodness, it also includes the possibility of evil, and

it is logically possible that God cannot get a world of significant amounts of goodness

without the possibility of significant amounts of badness. This is why Plantinga’s

argument is considered a defense as opposed to a theodicy, for he gives not a “why” to

the problem of evil, but a “how.”

Plantinga has written that the crucial question for the Free Will Defense is,

“Was it within God’s power to create any possible world He pleased?”50

He ultimately

argues that it wasn’t, and moreover calls the notion that He could have “Leibniz’

Lapse.”51

Mackie—perhaps unknowingly—purported the “Lapse” in writing,

If God has made men such that in their free choices they sometimes prefer what is

good and sometimes what is evil, why could he not have made men such that they

always freely choose the good? If there is no logical impossibility in a man’s freely

choosing the good on one, or on several occasions, there cannot be a logical

impossibility in his freely choosing the good on every occasion. God was not, then,

faced with a choice between making innocent automata and making beings who, in

acting freely, would sometimes go wrong; there was open to him the obviously

better possibility of making beings who would act freely but always go right.

Clearly, his failure to avail himself of this possibility is inconsistent with his being

both omnipotent and wholly good.52

49

Peter Kreeft and Ronald Tacelli, Pocket Handbook of Christian Apologetics (Downers

Grover: InterVarsity Press, 2003), 51.

50

Michael Peterson, William Hasker, Bruce Reichenbach, and David Basinger, Philosophy of

Religion : Selected Readings (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007), 330.

51

Ibid., 337. C. Stephen Evans notes that “Leibniz is usually credited with first using the

concept of a possible world.” C. Stephen Evans, Pocket Dictionary of Apologetics & Philosophy of

Religion (Downers Grove: InterVarsity Press, 2002), 94.

52

Ibid., 329.

Page 28: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

17

At this juncture, a sensible question is: what is a possible world? Plantinga

defines the idea in writing, “a possible world is a way things could have been; it is a state

of affairs of some kind.”53

C. Stephen Evans has written that it is a set of ways that the

“actual world could have been. In the actual world I have brown hair, but perhaps there

is a possible world in which I have blond hair.”54

According to Plantinga, God was not

free to create any possible world He pleased. This, however, does not diminish His

omnipotence because His creation of freedom is an exercise of His omnibenevolence.

That is, significant freedom is a good thing. He writes, “It was not within God’s power to

create a world in which [an individual] produces moral good but no moral evil. Every

world God can actualize is such that if [an individual] is significantly free in it, he takes

at least one wrong action.” Plantinga’s argument here is essentially the same as

suggesting that because there are things that God cannot do, it doesn’t necessarily entail

that He is less omnipotent. For example, Titus 1:2 states that “God cannot lie.” Not

having the ability to lie doesn’t diminish God’s omnipotence, however. Instead, it

enhances His character of being God. Plantinga’s argument claims that God’s actualizing

of a world that includes significant freedom is the best way to express His omnipotence

and omnibenevolence, even if that significant freedom holds the potential of breeding

evil.

Plantinga’s argument has been widely accepted among philosophers—theistic

and atheistic—and many have even abandoned LPE because of it. Ergun Caner and Ed

Hindson have noted, for example, that “Plantinga’s free will defense is brilliantly

53

Ibid., 330.

54

C. Stephen Evans, Pocket Dictionary of Apologetics & Philosophy of Religion (Downers

Grove: InterVarsity Press, 2002), 94.

Page 29: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

18

conceived and successfully destroys Mackie’s LPE.”55

Others have written, “Alvin

Plantinga’s free will defense shows that the deductive argument from evil is fallacious.

Most atheists have conceded the success of Plantinga’s refutation of the deductive

argument from evil and have shifted their arguments.”56

Plantinga’s Free Will Defense is sound, but it has still been met with several

kinds of objections. For example, some philosophers say that causal determinism and

freedom are not really incompatible.57

Causal determinism “is the idea that every event

is necessitated by antecedent events and conditions together with the laws of nature.”58

Plantinga has responded to this objection in writing,

But if so, then God could have created free creatures who were free, and free to do

what is wrong, but nevertheless were causally determined to do only what is right.

Thus He could have created creatures who were free to do what was wrong, while

nevertheless preventing them from ever performing any wrong actions—simply by

seeing to it that they were causally determined to do only what is right. Of course

this contradicts the Free Will Defense, according to which there is inconsistency in

supposing that God determines free creatures to do only what is right.59

55

Michael Peterson, William Hasker, Bruce Reichenbach, and David Basinger, Philosophy of

Religion : Selected Readings (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007), 330.

56

Kelly James Clark, Richard Lints, and James K. A. Smith, 101 Key Terms in Philosophy and

their Importance for Theology (Louisville: Westminster John Knox Press, 2004), 25.

57

See, for example, A. Flew, “Divine Omnipotence and Human Freedom,” in New Essays in

Philosophical Theology, eds. A. Flew and A. MacIntyre (London: SCM, 1955), pp.150-153.

58

The online Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy:

http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/determinism-causal/

59

Michael Peterson, William Hasker, Bruce Reichenbach, and David Basinger, Philosophy of

Religion : Selected Readings, 328.

Page 30: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

19

He has moreover written that this objection is “utterly implausible. One might as well

claim that being in jail doesn’t really limit one’s freedom on the grounds that if one were

not in jail, he’d be free to come and go as he pleased.”60

A second, more formidable, objection suggests that, according to Plantinga, “it

is possible to do only what is right, even if one is free to do wrong.”61

Plantinga outlines

the objection,

It is possible, in that broadly logical sense, that there would be a world containing

free creatures who always do what is right. There is certainly no contradiction or

inconsistency in this idea. But God is omnipotent; his power has no nonlogical

limitations. So if it’s possible that there be a world containing creatures who are

free to do what is wrong but never in fact do so, then it follows that an omnipotent

God could create such a world. If so, however, the Free Will Defense must be

mistaken in its insistence upon the possibility that God is omnipotent but unable to

create a world containing moral good without permitting moral evil.62

J. L. Mackie purported this objection in writing,

If God has made men such that in their free choices they sometimes prefer what is

good and sometimes what is evil, why could he not have made men such that they

always freely choose the good? If there is no logical impossibility in his freely

choosing the good on every occasion. God was not, then, faced with a choice

between making innocent automata and making beings who, in acting freely, would

sometimes go wrong; there was open to him the obviously better possibility of

making beings who would act freely but always go right. Clearly, his failure to avail

himself of this possibility is inconsistent with his being both omnipotent and wholly

good.63

This objection essentially suggests that, according to the Free Will Defense, “it

is possible both that God is omnipotent and that He was unable to create a world

60

Ibid., 329. For further discussion of Plantinga’s defense of this objection see his book, God

and Other Minds, pp.132-135.

61

Ibid., 329.

62

Ibid., 329.

63

J. L. Mackie, ed. Basil Mitchell, The Philosophy of Religion (London: Oxford University

Press, 1971), 100-1.

Page 31: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

20

containing moral good without creating one containing moral evil.”64

The limitation on

God’s power to create is inconsistent with God’s omnipotence. Plantinga notes that for

Mackie, “surely it’s possible that there be a world containing perfectly virtuous

persons—persons who are significantly free but always do what is right. Surely there are

possible worlds that contain moral good but no moral evil.”65

Mackie argues that if God

is truly omnipotent, then it follows that He had the power to create any possible world

that He chose. “So,” Mackie argues, “it is not possible, contrary to the Free Will

Defense, both that God is omnipotent and that he could create a world containing moral

good only by creating one containing more evil.”66

If God is omnipotent, the only

limitations of His power are “logical limitations, in which case there are no possible

worlds He could not have created.”67

According to G. W. Leibniz—the founder of the possible worlds theory—this

world, the actual world, must be the best of all possible worlds. Plantinga details

Leibniz’ argument in writing,

Before God created anything at all, He was confronted with an enormous range of

choices; He could create or bring into actuality any of the myriads of different

possible worlds. Being perfectly good, He must have chosen to create the best world

He could; being omnipotent, He was able to create any possible world He pleased.

He must, therefore, have chosen the best of all possible worlds; and hence this

world, the one he did create, must be the best possible.68

64

Michael Peterson, William Hasker, Bruce Reichenbach, and David Basinger, Philosophy of

Religion : Selected Readings (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007), 329.

65

Ibid.

66

Ibid.

67

Ibid.

68

Ibid., 330.

Page 32: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

21

Interestingly, while Leibniz concluded that his theory supported the idea of an

omnipotent and omnibenevolent God, Mackie, by the same theory, concluded instead that

there is no omnipotent, wholly good God. For Mackie, this simply cannot be the best of

all possible worlds, evidentially and logically.

As noted earlier, this is what Plantinga has deemed “Leibniz’ Lapse.” In this

regard, Plantinga disagrees with both Leibniz and Mackie. “In the first place,” Plantinga

notes, “what is the reason for supposing that there is such a thing as the best of all

possible worlds? No matter how marvelous a world is, isn’t it possible that there be an

ever better [one]?”69

The unique characteristic and central to the Free Will Defense is the

claim that “God, though omnipotent, could not have actualized just any possible world he

pleased.”70

That is, the ability to not actualize any possible world does not diminish

God’s omnipotence, in the same way not being able to do anything He pleases (i.e., lie),

doesn’t diminish His omnipotence. Kreeft and Tacelli describe this argument well in the

following:

Even omnipotence could not have created a world in which there was genuine

human freedom and yet no possibility of sin, for our freedom includes the

possibility of sin within its own meaning. “All things are possible with God” indeed;

but a meaningless self-contradiction is not anything at all. One such meaningless

self-contradiction is a world in which there is real free choice—that is, the

possibility of freely choosing good or evil—and at the same time no possibility of

choosing evil. To ask why God didn’t create such a world is like asking why God

didn’t create colorless color or round squares. Thus, even an omnipotent God cannot

forcibly prevent sin without removing our freedom. This “cannot” does not mean

that his power meets some obstacle outside himself.71

69

Ibid.

70

Ibid.

71

Peter Kreeft and Ronald Tacelli, Pocket Handbook of Christian Apologetics (Downers

Grover: InterVarsity Press, 2003), 51-2.

Page 33: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

22

Kreeft has moreover noted, “The point to remember is that creating a world where there’s

free will and no possibility of sin is a self-contradiction—and that opens the door to

people choosing evil over God, with suffering being the result.”72

C. S. Lewis

summarizes this thought well in writing, “nonsense does not cease to be nonsense when

we add the words ‘God can’ before it.”73

A third objection examines the foundational idea of the possible world theory

and the seemingly deterministic tenets of the actualization of a world therein. As noted

earlier, Plantinga has defined a possible world as “a way things could have been; it is a

state of affairs of some kind.”74

It is obvious that Plantinga is not concerned necessarily

with the “best possible world,” because it seems that he is not convinced that one exists.

He again has written, “”what is the reason for supposing that there is such a thing as the

best of all possible worlds?”75

Instead, he is concerned with significant free will, and the

thought that it is not illogical to consider that God, in His omnipotence, actualized a

world that includes it. But if a possible world is defined as “a way things could have

been,” it seems reasonable to consider that these “ways” are somewhat predetermined.

As C. Stephen Evans has noted, a possible world is a set of “ways the actual world could

have been. In the actual world I have brown hair, but perhaps there is a possible world in

72

Lee Strobel, The Case for Faith (Grand Rapids: Zondervan, 2000), 38.

73

Peter Kreeft and Ronald Tacelli, Pocket Handbook of Christian Apologetics (Downers

Grover: InterVarsity Press, 2003), 52.

74

Michael Peterson, William Hasker, Bruce Reichenbach, and David Basinger, Philosophy of

Religion : Selected Readings (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007), 330.

75

Ibid.

Page 34: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

23

which I have blond hair.”76

For an argument that purports significant free will, it seems

at least initially plausible to consider that this free will is deterministically set. If in

possible world A for example, John Smith, while sitting at the ice cream parlor, chooses

chocolate ice cream over vanilla ice cream, and in possible world B chooses vanilla ice

cream over chocolate ice cream, it seems like this “set of ways that the world could have

been” are not necessarily free at all, but instead determined when the possible world

becomes actual. That is, when God in His omnipotence actualized one possible world

over another, even if that world included significant freedom, it seems reasonable to

suggest that the “set of ways” is somewhat determined.

A good example of this assertion is seen in Scripture in the prophecy that Judas

Iscariot would betray Jesus Christ. The psalmist wrote in Psalm 41:9, “Even my close

friend in whom I trusted, who ate my bread, has lifted up his heel against me.”77

This

verse is realized in Luke 22:21-22 when Jesus said, “But behold, the hand of the one

betraying Me is with Mine on the table. For indeed, the Son of Man is going as it has

been determined; but woe to that man by whom He is betrayed!” Luke 22:47-48 details

the events of the actual betrayal which says, “While He was still speaking, behold, a

crowd came, and the one called Judas, one of the twelve, was preceding them; and he

approached Jesus to kiss Him. But Jesus said to him, ‘Judas, are you betraying the Son of

Man with a kiss?’” It seems reasonable to argue here that in the world that was

actualized—our world—that Judas’ betrayal of Jesus was a “set way,” predetermined.

While Judas arguably had the free will to betray Jesus, the reality is that it was without

76

C. Stephen Evans, Pocket Dictionary of Apologetics & Philosophy of Religion (Downers

Grove: InterVarsity Press, 2002), 94.

77

All Scripture references are taken from the New American Standard Bible (NASB) unless

otherwise noted.

Page 35: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

24

question the “set way” of this possible world that has been actualized. Therefore, it is at

least initially plausible to consider that while Plantinga’s argument works in the context

of significant freedom, it seems to experience difficulty if this significant freedom is

attacked.

If this argument is valid, then it is not unreasonable to conclude that

Plantinga’s Free Will Defense may not necessarily be as sufficient as one might hope, for

“significant” free will, so to speak, would not exist. Instead, man would appear to have a

determined free will. This is a debate that will not be detailed here; however, Ravi

Zacharias has perhaps described the thought well in writing,

The sovereignty and responsibility issue [free will and determinism] should really

be seen as two opposite poles of the same position. Light, for example, is viewed

from some vantage points as particles. From other vantage points it is viewed as

waves. Scientists are aware that light could not be both particles and waves, so they

have coined a term for it, a kind of a construct, and they call it a “photon.” All they

have done is create a word and a category that accommodates both perspectives

which are real. I think you should view the sovereignty of God and the

responsibility of man as a kind of a precious stone with two facets to it. When it

catches the light from one direction, you see one color; when it catches the light

from the other direction you see the other color.78

Evil is a Privation of Good – St. Augustine

St. Augustine was a philosopher and theologian, and arguably “the most

famous and influential of the church fathers for the Western church.”79

He has been

listed as the “last major thinker of the ancient world and the first philosopher and

78

An excerpt from Ravi Zacharias’ International Ministries page on the question, “Does RZIM

have a position on Calvinism or Arminianism?"

http://www.rzim.org/usa/usfv/tabid/436/articleid/174/cbmoduleid/1561/default.aspx

79

C. Stephen Evans, Pocket Dictionary of Apologetics & Philosophy of Religion (Downers

Grove: InterVarsity Press, 2002), 14.

Page 36: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

25

theologian of the Middle Ages.”80

Ronald Nash has written of Augustine that “his work

is the bridge that links ancient philosophy and early Christian theology to the thought

patterns of the Middle Ages.”81

Augustine’s journey to Christianity was met with various intellectual obstacles.

For years, Augustine practiced Manicheanism. “Manicheanism is characterized by a

dualistic ontology that sees matter and the physical world as bad, in tension with the pure

world of spirit and light.”82

Augustine converted to skepticism during his time with

Ambrose in Rome in 383-384 C.E. Nash notes, “By [this time] Augustine had replaced

his Manichean worldview with the strange variety of skepticism that had taken control of

Plato’s Academy.”83

Augustine’s experiment with skepticism ended with his discovery

of the writings of Neo-Platonists such as Plotinus. “Neo-Platonists taught him how evil

could exist in a world that depended for its existence on one perfectly good God.

Following this lead, Augustine came to think of evil as the privation of goodness, much

as darkness is the absence of light.”84

Augustine found that after his exposure to these

writings that most of his intellectual objections to Christianity had disappeared. The only

obstacles that remained were moral; He had still yet to renounce his moral failings,

especially concerning his mistress. “In 386, in a villa outside of Rome, he underwent one

of the more dramatic conversions in the history of the Christian church. After hearing a

voice say, ‘Take up and read,’ Augustine recounts how he opened the Bible at random

80

Ronald Nash, Life’s Ultimate Questions (Grand Rapids: Zondervan, 1999), 140.

81

Ibid.

82

C. Stephen Evans, Pocket Dictionary of Apologetics & Philosophy of Religion (Downers

Grove: InterVarsity Press, 2002), 72.

83

Ronald Nash, Life’s Ultimate Questions, 142.

84

Ibid.

Page 37: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

26

and his finger landed on Paul’s words in Romans 13:13-14.”85

Augustine recounts this

experience in his Confessions:

I seized it [the New Testament] and opened it, and in silence I read the first passage

on which my eyes fell. “No orgies or drunkenness, no fighting or jealousy. Take up

the weapons of the Lord Jesus Christ; and stop giving attention to your sinful nature,

to satisfy its desires.” I had no wish to read more and no need to do so. For in an

instant, as I came to the end of the sentence, it was as though the light of faith

flooded into my heart and all the darkness of doubt was dispelled.86

Augustine’s acquaintance with Manicheanism led him to reflect on the

problem of evil. “Manicheanism explained the existence of good and evil as the

unavoidable product of a never-ending struggle between two coequal and co-eternal

deities, one good and the other evil. Evil exists because the good God (Light) is

powerless to defeat the evil God (Darkness).”87

As a Christian, Augustine eventually

came to see that this was an unsatisfactory answer to the problem of evil. In his

Confessions, Augustine—disclosing his newfound faith in Christ—decided that “there

[was] only one God, and he is both good and all-powerful. Everything God created was

good. But the creation contained degrees of goodness.”

It has been written of Augustine that he “was one of the first Christian writers

to attempt a comprehensive and systematic explanation of evil in a theistic universe.”88

His theodicy “weaved together several key themes” such as “that God, who alone is

supremely and immutably good, creates all other things; that all created things are good

in their nature; that evil is a privation or lack in created things but not a positive reality;

85

Ibid.

86

St. Augustine, ed., John Ryan, Confessions (New York: Doubleday, 1960), 8.

87

Ronald Nash, Life’s Ultimate Questions (Grand Rapids: Zondervan, 1999), 144.

88

Michael Peterson, William Hasker, Bruce Reichenbach, and David Basinger, Philosophy of

Religion : Selected Readings (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007), 292.

Page 38: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

27

that moral evil in humans results from a deficiency in the will; and that all things that we

call evil from our finite perspective are actually part of the higher order and harmony in

God’s economy.”89

Ultimately, Augustine’s understanding of God’s good creation was

that he endowed certain creatures with free will.90

Evil was a result of these creatures

misusing their free will. That is, “Evil entered the world through sin as humans exercised

their free will.”91

Augustine details his understanding of evil in his Confessions,

And it was made clear to me that all things are good even if they are corrupted.

They could not be corrupted if they were supremely good; but unless they were

good they could not be corrupted. If they were supremely good, they would be

incorruptible; if they were not good at all, there would be nothing in them to be

corrupted. For corruption harms; but unless it could diminish goodness, it could not

harm. Either, then, corruption does not harm—which cannot be—or, as is certain,

all that is corrupted is thereby deprived of good. But if they are deprived of all good,

they will cease to be. For if they are at all and cannot be at all corrupted, they will

become better, because they will remain incorruptible.92

Augustine’s argument here is that foundationally, everything is good. He moreover

writes,

Now what can be more monstrous than to maintain that by losing all good they have

become better? If, then, they are deprived of all good, they will cease to exist. So

long as they are, therefore, they are good. Therefore, whatsoever is, is good. Evil,

then, the origin of which I had been seeking, has no substance at all; for if it were a

substance, it would be good. For either it would be an incorruptible substance and

so a supreme good, or a corruptible substance, which could not be corrupted unless

it were good. I understood, therefore, and it was made clear to me that thou madest

all things good, nor is there any substance at all not made by thee. And because all

89

Ibid.

90

Meaning humans and angels. Ron Nash has noted that Augustine’s notion of free will had

limits. Ronald Nash, Life’s Ultimate Questions (Grand Rapids: Zondervan, 1999), 145.

91

Ed Hindson and Ergun Caner, The Popular Encyclopedia of Apologetics (Eugene: Harvest

House Publishers, 2008), 91.

92

Michael Peterson, William Hasker, Bruce Reichenbach, and David Basinger, Philosophy of

Religion : Selected Readings (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007), 292.

Page 39: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

28

that thou madest is not equal, each by itself is good, and the sum of all of them is

very good, for our God made all things very good.93

It is clear that Augustine’s answer to the problem of God and evil was that evil

is a privation of good. That is, evil is not necessarily a “thing,” like a hole in the ground

is not a “thing;” The word “hole” is used to describe the absence of dirt. Likewise, for

Augustine, evil is the absence of good. It moreover needs good to exist. “Evil is

dependent upon a prior good in the sense that it is a kind of parasite or corruption of a

prior good. A parasite can never survive unless there is a separate and healthy organism

upon which it can prey, from which it can draw sustenance.”94

Ronald Nash describes

the theory by the illustration of darkness and light in writing, “Is light or darkness the

more fundamental reality? It is a mistake to think that darkness is a power or a force that

coexists with light. Darkness is the privation of light. Light is a positive force or power;

darkness is nothing, it is nonbeing.”95

While Augustine’s theodicy is arguably sound, it has, like Plantinga’s Free

Will Defense, been met with a handful of objections. Gordon Clark, for example, has

gone as far as to suggest that although “Augustine, admittedly, was a great Christian and

a great philosopher… here he was at his worst. Deficient causes, if there are such things,

do not explain why a good God does not abolish sin and guarantee that men always

choose the highest good.”96

F.D.E. Schleiermacher furthermore criticized Augustine’s

theodicy in suggesting that it is logically contradictory to claim that a perfectly created

93

Ibid.

94

Ronald Nash, Life’s Ultimate Questions (Grand Rapids: Zondervan, 1999), 145.

95

Ibid.

96

Gordon Clark, Religion, Reason, and Revelation (Hobbs: The Trinity Foundation, 1995),

196.

Page 40: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

29

world went wrong because it implies that evil created itself out of nothing, which is a

logical contradiction. “If the world was perfect and there was no knowledge of good and

evil, how could Adam and Eve have the freedom to disobey God if goodness and evil

were as yet unknown? The disobedience of Adam and Eve and the angels implies that

there already was knowledge of good and evil. Augustine’s interpretation of the tree of

knowledge therefore is questionable.”97

Another objection suggests that if evil is a lack of goodness or perfection rather

than a substance in itself, how does one know what perfection is? In order, for example,

to distinguish between what is good in man and what is bad one would need to

understand what perfect human nature is.

Other objections combat Augustine’s foundational assumption that evil is a

privation of good. First, in a theological sense, the prophet Isaiah—writing on behalf of

the Lord—wrote, “I am the Lord, and there is no other, the One forming light and

creating darkness, causing well-being and creating calamity; I am the Lord who does all

these” (Isaiah 45:6-7). In this verse, it seems reasonable to suggest that first, darkness is

actually a “thing” that has been created by God, and second, that God is more involved

with evil—at least natural evil—than Augustine would like to think. It is important to

note here that the context of this verse claims that God’s involvement with “calamity” is

so that “men may know from the rising to the setting of the sun that there is no one

besides [Him]” (Isaiah 45:6). That is, God seems to give His own theodicy. This

contextual consideration derives from the two Hebrew words used in this passage, ra’

(calamity) and bara’ (to create), which suggest that evil is more than a mere absence or

97

http://instruct.westvalley.edu/lafave/evil_and_theodicies_tutor2u.html

Page 41: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

30

parasite of good, but an actual thing.98

Second, an observation notes that Augustine

argued that evil is both the privation of good and also the parasite of good. To deem evil

a parasite seems to attribute to it characteristics that can only be attributed to something

that is real, not simply the absence of something else. In this case, it would at least seem

initially illogical to deem evil both the privation of good, and also the parasite of good.

In this case, it would be both nothing and something at the same time and in the same

sense, which contradicts the law of non-contradiction. This law states that “A cannot be

both B and non-B at the same time and in the same sense.”99

A final—and perhaps philosophically weak—objection concerns Augustine’s

use of Scripture. Throughout the course of Augustine’s theodicy, he quotes a handful of

verses to support his arguments, one of which comes from Isaiah 5:20 which states, “Woe

to those who call evil good, and good evil; who put darkness for light, and light for

darkness; who put bitter for sweet, and sweet for bitter.” Augustine uses this verse in his

philosophical analysis of the problem of evil, suggesting that calling man evil is worthy

of rightly falling under judgment; “Therefore, if anyone says that simply to be a man is

evil, or that to be a wicked man is good, he rightly falls under the prophetic judgment:

‘Woe to him who calls evil good and good evil.’”100

In its context, however, this verse

seems to be rather suggesting a condemnation against the reversal of immorality which

98

The book of Jonah contains many uses of the Hebrew ra’ as does Amos 3:6. Both passages

allude to significant acts of natural evil. The Hebrew bara’ is a strong word for “creating,” and is the same

word used in Genesis 1:1 to describe God’s creating of the earth. A question can be asked here as to

whether or not God simply allowed for the possibility of evil, or actually created evil. Again, this context

arguably suggests that if the latter is true, that He did so for His glory. This would coincide with the evil

represented during Christ’s death on the cross. Isaiah 53:10 says that “it pleased the Lord to bruise Him; He

has put Him to grief.”

99

Ronald Nash, Life’s Ultimate Questions (Grand Rapids: Zondervan, 1999), 194.

100

Michael Peterson, William Hasker, Bruce Reichenbach, and David Basinger, Philosophy of

Religion : Selected Readings (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007), 295.

Page 42: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

31

dominated Judah at this time. The nation had “confused all moral distinctions.”101

Augustine interpreted the verse ontologically, suggesting that it refers to “finding fault

with God’s work, because man is an entity of God’s creation.” He wrote of it, “It means

that we are praising the defects in this particular man because he is a wicked person.

Thus, every entity, even if it is a defective one, in so far as it is an entity, is good. In so

far as it is defective, it is evil.”102

While Augustine interpreted the verse ontologically, it

instead seems to be a reference to morality.

Trinitarian Warfare Theodicy – Gregory Boyd

Gregory Boyd is senior pastor of Woodland Hills Church in St. Paul,

Minnesota, and president of Christus Victor Ministries. He is perhaps best known for his

open theism primer, The God of the Possible.

In order to understand Boyd’s Trinitarian Warfare Theodicy, one must grasp

the argument of his first book—Trinity and Process: A Critical Evaluation and

Reconstruction of Hartshorne’s Di-Polar Theism Towards a Trinitarian Metaphysics—a

monograph version of his 1988 Princeton Seminary doctoral dissertation. Boyd’s preface

reads,

This work is, in essence, an attempt to work out a trinitarian-process metaphysic…It

is our conviction that the fundamental vision of the process worldview, especially as

espoused by Charles Hartshorne, is correct. But it is our conviction as well that the

scriptural and traditional understanding of God as triune and antecedently actual

within Godself is true, and is, in fact, a foundational doctrine of the Christian faith.

101

John MacArthur, The MacArthur Study Bible, New King James Version (Nashville: Thomas

Nelson Publishing), 962. Excerpt from the footnote on Isaiah 5:20.

102

Michael Peterson, William Hasker, Bruce Reichenbach, and David Basinger, Philosophy of

Religion : Selected Readings (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007), 295.

Page 43: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

32

But, we contend, these two views, when understood within a proper framework, do

not conflict.103

Boyd Luter and Kelly Hunter have noted of Boyd’s thesis, “Simply put, Boyd is

constructing a ‘best of both worlds’ approach, drawing from process and orthodox

Trinitarian thought.”104

While Boyd purports a process theology in origin, it is important to note that

he is more accurately an open theist. Process theology is “an approach to theology

inspired by the philosophical thought of Alfred North Whitehead and Charles Hartshorne,

[which] rejects the classical picture of God as immutable and transcendent in favor of a

God who is partly evolving with and in relation to the created world.”105

Open theism

claims “that some of the traditional attributes ascribed to God by classical theism should

be either rejected or reinterpreted.”106

Advocates of open theism “reject the claim that

God is timelessly eternal, and believe that though God’s essential character is immutable,

God changes in some ways so as to respond appropriately to a changed creation.”107

The

difference is slight, but rests—at least in the context of the problem of evil—in God’s

immutability. The most controversial tenet of this theology is arguably the belief that

God’s foreknowledge is limited because of the limitations He gave Himself in giving

humans free will.

103

Luter, A. Boyd and Hunter, Emily K., “Review: Satan and the Problem of Evil:

Constructing a Trinitarian Warfare Theodicy” (2003), 159. Faculty Publications and Presentations. Paper

257. http://digitalcommons.liberty.edu/Its_fac_pubs/257

104

Ibid.

105

C. Stephen Evans, Pocket Dictionary of Apologetics & Philosophy of Religion (Downers

Grove: InterVaristy Press, 2002), 97.

106

Ibid., 85.

107

Ibid.

Page 44: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

33

The thrust of Boyd’s theodicy is outlined in the following:

Boyd [purports] six Trinitarian warfare theses that comprise the framework of his

theodicy. These are: (1) love must be freely chosen; (2) love entails risk; (3) love

and freedom entail that we are responsible for one another; (4) the power to

influence for the worse is proportionate to the power to influence for the better; (5)

within limits, freedom must be irrevocable; and (6) this limitation is not infinite, for

our capacity to choose freely is not endless.108

“Boyd asserts that these six theses add up to a compelling explanation for the knotty

problem of how evil exists in a world created by a good God.”109

Boyd’s theodicy is an unusually difficult argument to “assign strengths and

weaknesses; such evaluation depends almost entirely on one’s entry viewpoint.”110

Luter

and Hunter have conveyed this difficulty well in writing,

On the one hand, if readers share Boyd’s semi-process/openness presuppositions,

his ambitious theodicy will come off as strong and of great significance. Again, if

readers are in his camp or do not notice his unproven assumptions of God’s self-

limiting ultra-immanence and man’s minimized sinfulness, they likely will end up

exactly where he is trying to take them. In a word, if the eccentric premises of open

theism make sense to readers, the construction of Boyd’s logic probably will as

well. On the other hand, if readers don’t accept Boyd’s foundational stance, the

superstructure built on it, while flashy, is ultimately a virtual house of cards.111

With this said, the most emphatic objection to Boyd’s theodicy is that he sacrifices the

legitimate omnipotence of God, which naturally appeases the atheologian in his LPE.

108

Luter, A. Boyd and Hunter, Emily K., “Review: Satan and the Problem of Evil:

Constructing a Trinitarian Warfare Theodicy” (2003), 160. Faculty Publications and Presentations. Paper

257. http://digitalcommons.liberty.edu/Its_fac_pubs/257

109

Ibid.

110

Ibid.

111

Ibid.

Page 45: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

34

A Deterministic Approach – Gordon Clark

“Gordon Clark was born in Philadelphia and received his Ph.D. in philosophy

in 1929. He taught at Wheaton College, Reformed Episcopal Seminary, and Covenant

College and was chairman of the Philosophy Department at Butler University for twenty-

eight years. His teaching career spanned sixty years.”112

Clark is most remembered for his rational presuppositionalism, which is a

philosophy that stresses reason as the means of determining truth. “Mind is given

authority over senses, the a priori over the a posteriori.”113

Norman Geisler has written

of Clark and his philosophy,

Clark has provided a great service to Christian apologetics by stressing the laws of

logic on which all rational arguments are based. The law of noncontradiction is

absolutely necessary to the affirmation and confirmation of all truth claims.

However, logic is only a set of formal principles. It tells what could be true; not

what is true. To know what is really true, sooner or later one must touch base with

the external world.114

Clark’s theodicy was founded on his rationalism. For Clark, “The Bible

[presents] God as omnipotent, and only on this basis can a Christian view of evil be

worked out.” Clark did not consider free will and the omnipotence of God logically

compatible. He has written, “free will is not only futile but false.”115

Clark has moreover

112

Norman Geisler, Baker Encyclopedia of Christian Apologetics (Grand Rapids: BakerBooks,

1999), 150.

113

Ibid., 633.

114

Ibid., 153.

115

Gordon Clark, Religion, Reason, and Revelation (Hobbs: The Trinity Foundation, 1995),

206.

Page 46: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

35

written that “free will cannot resolve the difficulty” of the problem of God and evil, and

that one must therefore “turn to the opposite theory of determinism.”116

Clark admits that at first, “determinism, instead of alleviating the situation,

seems to accentuate the problem of evil by maintaining the inevitability of every event;

and not only the inevitability, but also the further and more embarrassing point that it is

God himself who determines or decrees every action.”117

This accentuation, however, is

alleviated in Clark’s discussion of God’s will. He writes,

The term will is ambiguous. The Ten Commandments are God’s perceptive will.

They command men to do this and to refrain from that. They state what ought to be

done; but they neither state nor cause what is done. God’s decretive will, however,

as contrasted with his precepts, causes every event. It would be conducive to clarity

if the term will were not applied to the precepts. Call the requirements of morality

commands, precepts, or laws; and reserve the term will for the divine decree. These

are two different things, and what looks like an opposition between them is not a

self-contradiction.118

Clark cites the biblical event of Jesus’ crucifixion to illustrate his argument:

“The Jews ought not to have demanded Christ’s crucifixion. It was contrary to the moral

law. But God had decreed Christ’s death from the foundation of the world. It may seem

strange at first that God would decree an immoral act, but the Bible shows that he did.”119

Clark moreover argues that to suggest that,

If God did not arrange it this way, then there must be an independent factor in the

universe. And if there is such, one consequence and perhaps two follow. First, the

doctrine of creation must be abandoned. A creation ex nihilo would be completely in

God’s control. Independent forces cannot be created forces, and created forces

cannot be independent. Then, second, if the universe is not God’s creation, his

116

Ibid. Clark’s use of “must” here is later followed up in writing, “Is there not a third

possibility? Could it not be that some events or choices are determined and some are not? Such a third

possibility, however, could contribute nothing to this discussion” (p. 207).

117

Ibid. Of course, Clark is being sarcastic here.

118

Ibid., 222.

119

Ibid., 223

Page 47: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

36

knowledge of it—past and future—cannot depend on what he intends to do, but on

his observation of how it works. In such a case, how could we be sure that God’s

observations are accurate? How could we be sure that these independent forces will

not later show an unsuspected twist that will falsify God’s predictions? And, finally,

on this view God’s knowledge would be empirical, rather than an integral part of his

essence, and thus he would be a dependent knower.120

For Clark, these objections are “insurmountable. We can consistently believe in creation,

omnipotence, omniscience, and the divine decree. But we cannot retain sanity and

combine any one of these with free will.”121

That is, to suggest that man has a significant

free will is to suggest that God is not God.

Like the aforementioned theodicies, Clark’s deterministic approach has been

met with objections. The most common objection toward Clark’s theodicy is likely the

thought that it is not illogical to decree that God is omnipotent and that free will exists, as

noted by Augustine and Plantinga. Moreover, skeptics have argued that while Clark’s

theodicy may solve the omnipotence portion of LPE, that it is weak in the context of

God’s omnibenevolence, which is also part of the problem. EPE advocates argue that

Clark’s theodicy portrays a wicked God, but Clark argues just the opposite. “We are

unconscious of our limitations,” writes Clark. That is, it is not necessarily outside of the

realm of logic to suggest that while it may appear that God is evil because evil exists (or

because He created it), He assuredly is not. For Clark, it’s not that God merely “allows”

evil; He created it. Apart from the weaknesses, a major strength in Clark’s theodicy is his

exegesis of Scripture. He utilizes passages that reference Jesus’ crucifixion, Judas’

betrayal, and Pilate’s decision not to release Jesus. Clark does an excellent job including

theological considerations in his philosophical theories:

120

Ibid.

121

Ibid., 210.

Page 48: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

37

Aside from the peculiarity of assigning a semi-sovereignty to God and to man a

semi-free will, the crux of the conflict lies in choices that cannot be split in half.

Could Judas have chosen not to betray Christ? If he could have chosen not to betray

Christ, his moral responsibility is established, says the Arminian; but says the

Calvinist, prophecy in such a case could have proved false. Or, again, could Pilate

have decided to release Jesus? Are we prepared to say that God could not make sure

of the necessary events in his plan of redemption? Besides, the Bible explicitly says,

“Herod and Pontius Pilate, with the Gentiles and the people of Israel, were gathered

together ‘to do whatever your hand and your purpose determined before to be

done.’” Here in these individual choices moral responsibility is potted against the

success of God’s eternal plan of redemption. There is therefore no use in supposing

some choices free and others determined. The Scriptures say that this one choice

was determined ahead of time, and the whole theological and philosophical issue is

found complete in this one choice.122

Clark’s theodicy is not as prevalent in today’s conversations as Augustine’s

and Plantinga’s, to name a couple. This much is seen in the lack of information about

him in many of the leading philosophical and apologetic encyclopedias. This is perhaps

because Clark is often ridiculed for his allegedly irrational rational presuppositionalism,

and perhaps on this front, rightly so. However, it is not unreasonable to suggest that

Clark’s deterministic theodicy is any less logical or valuable than Plantinga’s, or even

Augustine’s. Clark’s theodicy is arguably more bible-centered than many of the other

theodicies that have been offered. His exegeses of the Scriptures can, and have, been

questioned, but Clark’s greatest strength is that his philosophy was birthed from the

Scriptures where other commonly accepted philosophies are not. Scripture gets

honorable mention in many theodicies, but it receives first place in Clark’s. It is safe to

suggest that Clark was a philosopher because he was a Christian.

122

Ibid., 207.

Page 49: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

38

The Soul-Making Theodicy – John Hick

John Hick is heralded as “one of the most important philosophers of religion of

the late twentieth century. His literary output and influence has been a strong force

against orthodox Christianity at several crucial junctures.”123

One of these “crucial

junctures” is the question of the problem of evil.

John Hick has been credited with developing the Soul-Making Theodicy. Hick

graciously notes, however, that his argument was inspired by the church father Irenaeus.

“The major theme [of Hick’s theodicy] is not one of causal genesis, but of progress and

development. Rather than view the present condition of the world as fallen from a kind of

perfection, Hick views the world as a necessary stage in the evolution of a relatively

immature creation into a more mature state. God seeks to bring forth mature moral and

spiritual beings who are capable of freely exercising faith in him and love toward their

fellows.”124

Hick introduces his theodicy in the following:

Can a world in which sadistic cruelty often has its way, in which selfish

lovelessness is so rife, in which there are debilitating diseases, crippling accidents,

bodily and mental decay, insanity, and all manner of natural disasters be regarded as

the expression of infinite creative goodness? Certainly all this could never by itself

lead anyone to believe in the existence of a limitlessly powerful God. And yet even

in a world which contains these things innumerable men and women have believed

and do believe in the reality of an infinite creative goodness, which they call God.

The theodicy project starts at this point, with an already operating belief in God,

embodied in human living, and attempts to show that this belief is not rendered

irrational by the fact of evil. It attempts to explain how it is that the universe,

assumed to be created and ultimately ruled by a limitlessly good and limitlessly

powerful Being, is as it is, including all the pain and suffering and all the

wickedness and folly that that we find around us and within us. The theodicy project

is thus an exercise in metaphysical construction in the sense that it consists in the

123

Norman Geisler, Baker Encyclopedia of Christian Apologetics (Grand Rapids: BakerBooks,

1999), 316.

124

Michael Peterson, William Hasker, Bruce Reichenbach, and David Basinger, Philosophy of

Religion : Selected Readings (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007), 341.

Page 50: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

39

formation and criticism of large-scale hypotheses concerning the nature and process

of the universe.125

For Hick, Christian thought includes “a certain range of variety, and in the area

of theodicy offers two broad types of approach.”126

These approaches are the

Augustinian approach, which “hinges upon the fall, and has in turn brought about the

disharmony of nature”127

and the Irenaean approach which “hinges upon the creation of

humankind through the evolutionary process as an immature creature living in a

challenging and therefore person-making world.”128

Hick makes it clear that he finds the

Augustinian approach unsatisfactory. “But even if it should be sound,” Hick argues, “I

suggest that the argument wins only a Pyrrhic victory, since the logical possibility that it

would establish is one which, for very many people today, is fatally lacking in

plausibility.”129

Hick’s Soul-Making Theodicy argues that God allows suffering so that human

souls might grow or develop towards maturation. It has also been defined as the

argument that “God allows evil so as to make it possible for humans to develop certain

desirable virtues.”130

Its roots are Irenaean because Irenaeus “[built] a framework of

thought within which a theodicy became possible which does not depend upon the idea of

the fall, and which is consonant with modern knowledge concerning the origins of the

125

Ibid.

126

Ibid., 342.

127

Ibid.

128

Ibid.

129

Ibid.

130

C. Stephen Evans, Pocket Dictionary of Apologetics & Philosophy of Religion (Downers

Grove: InterVarsity Press, 2002), 114.

Page 51: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

40

human race.”131

It is important to note that while the roots of the Soul-Making Theodicy

are Irenaean, Hick rightfully notes that “this theodicy cannot, as such, be attributed to

Irenaeus.”132

This is because although Hick adopted Irenaeus’ theology concerning the

fall, much of the arguments surrounding his theodicy are simply not Irenaean. Hick

regards Irenaeus as the “patron saint” of his Soul-Making Theodicy. Hick expresses this

Irenaean inspired theodicy in the following:

The central theme out of which this Irenaean type of theodicy has arisen is the two-

stage conception of the creation of humankind, first in the “image” and then in the

“likeness” of God. Re-expressing this in modern terms, the first stage was the

gradual production of homo sapiens, through the long evolutionary process, as

intelligent ethical and religious animals. The human being is an animal, one of the

varied forms of earthly life and continuous as such with the whole realm of animal

existence. But the human being is uniquely intelligent, having evolved a large and

immensely complex brain. Further, the human being is ethical—that is, a gregarious

as well as an intelligent animal, able to realize and respond to the complex demands

of social life. And the human being is a religious animal, with an innate tendency to

experience the world in terms of the presence and activity of supernatural beings

and powers. This then is early homo sapiens, the intelligent social animal capable of

awareness of the divine.133

Hick argues for a two-stage process which includes the “image” and the

“likeness” of man. This specific quote concerns the “image,” and argues that instead of

being created in the perfect image of God, as Augustinian theology suggests, “the life of

this being must have been a constant struggle against a hostile environment, and capable

of savage violence against one’s fellow human beings.”134

Hick further suggests that

131

Michael Peterson, William Hasker, Bruce Reichenbach, and David Basinger, Philosophy of

Religion : Selected Readings, 343.

132

Ibid.

133

Ibid.

134

Ibid.

Page 52: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

41

“this being’s concepts of the divine were primitive and often bloodthirsty.”135

Thus

existence “‘in the image of God’ was a potentiality for knowledge of and relationship

with one’s Maker rather than such knowledge and relationship as a fully realized

state.”136

Hick is arguing, generally, that people were created as spiritually and morally

immature creatures. Moreover, this spiritual and morally immature creation is the

beginning of a long process of further growth and development. For Hick, this process

“constitutes the second stage of God’s creative work [in which] the intelligent, ethical,

and religious animal is being brought through one’s own free responses into what

Irenaeus called the divine ‘likeness.’”137

That is, the human animal is being created into

a child of God, and wasn’t necessarily created as a child of God. This is distinct from

Irenaeus who believed that “God created Adam and Eve as children, frail and open to

Satan’s seducing.”138

For Irenaeus, “Humanity was a child; and its mind was not yet

fully mature; and thus humanity was easily led astray by the deceiver.”139

Hick is

convinced “that there never was a fall from an original righteousness and grace.”140

Hick’s theodicy has been heralded as one of the more philosophically

convincing arguments for the problem of evil, but it has still been met with objections.

First, some have argued that there are some evils that do not seem to contribute to the

135

Ibid.

136

Ibid.

137

Ibid.

138

Ed Hindson and Ergun Caner, The Popular Encyclopedia of Apologetics (Eugene: Harvest

House Publishers, 2008), 275.

139

McGrath, Demonstration of the Apostolic Preaching, 12. 93

140

Michael Peterson, William Hasker, Bruce Reichenbach, and David Basinger, Philosophy of

Religion : Selected Readings, 344.

Page 53: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

42

process of soul-making. Rowe’s development of EPE and the consideration of gratuitous

evils arguably suggest, for example, that there are evils that seem to incur the opposite

effect of soul-making. A second objection suggests that many individuals live lives of

luxury and virtually never experience evils that can potentially promote soul-making

properties. The wealthy and powerful are, in this objection, rarely, if ever, confronted

with evil in order to produce soul-making effects. Finally, and perhaps the most

formidable objection raised suggests that there are better ways to attain soul-making

properties than by experiencing evil, and this therefore renders the soul-making theodicy

unjustifiable. Many of these objections are acknowledged in the following chapter, in

which a rendering of Hick’s Soul Making Theodicy is offered. Suffice it to say here that

while Hick offers a considerably logical theodicy, it is in many ways an unsatisfactory

approach to conservative Christianity. The rendering offered in the next chapter adapts

the theodicy into a more biblical approach to the question of God and evil, while

maintaining a philosophically sound contribution.

Page 54: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

43

CHAPTER 3

A Rendering of John Hick’s Soul-Making Theodicy

Irenaeus was a missionary, pastor, and apologist, who studied at the feet of

Polycarp. He was moreover the “preeminent ante-Nicene father, for he, more than any

other [in his] time, promulgated the soundness of the orthodox faith as the apostolic

tradition in the face of late-second-century Gnosticism.”141

As previously noted, although Irenaeus inspired the Soul-Making Theodicy, it

is not necessarily Irenaean. He is best considered its “patron saint.” This inspiration

stems from the thought that Irenaeus “[built] a framework of thought within which a

theodicy became possible which does not depend upon the idea of the fall, and which is

consonant with modern knowledge concerning the origins of the human race.”142

That is,

Irenaeus is credited with the thought that man is an “immature creature living in a

challenging and therefore person-making world.”143

This is distinct from Augustine,

who argued that the creation of man “hinges upon the fall, and has in turn brought about

the disharmony of nature”144

141

Ed Hindson and Ergun Caner, The Popular Encyclopedia of Apologetics (Eugene: Harvest

House Publishers, 2008), 274.

142

Michael Peterson, William Hasker, Bruce Reichenbach, and David Basinger, Philosophy of

Religion : Selected Readings (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007), 343.

143

Ibid., 342.

144

Ibid.

Page 55: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

44

Hick’s theodicy extends beyond what Irenaeus would have purported. He has

written, in fact, that his theodicy “cannot, as such, be attributed to Irenaeus.”145

In fact, at

the end of their respective lives, Irenaeus and Hick likely did not agree on much. Hick,

for example, had a fairly weak view concerning Scripture, while Irenaeus held an

extremely high view of it. Hick moreover advocated such theological thoughts as

universal salvation, the reincarnation of man, a mythical interpretation of the incarnation

of Christ, and an evolutionary interpretation of the image of God in man. Many of these

differences will be outlined in the following in order to support an Irenaean rendering of

Hick’s Soul-Making Theodicy.146

The Word of God

In his book, A Hill on Which to Die, Paul Pressler asked, “Why would a person

give up personal comfort and ease to become involved in a distasteful and bitter conflict

that would impact his entire life?”147

He answered, “Some people have difficulty

accepting the fact that a person might simply have convictions which are so strong that he

must stand for them.”148

For Pressler, these convictions are “the complete, absolute, total

accuracy and integrity of the revelation that God has given us in His Book—the

Bible.”149

He concluded, “Believing this, I had no option but to stand for what I know to

be the truth.”150

145

Ibid., 343.

146

Only the differences that directly affect Hick’s theodicy will be detailed, which are his

convictions concerning the Bible, the image of God in man, and his eschatological conviction, which is

universal salvation.

147

Paul Pressler, A Hill on Which to Die (Nashville: B&H Publishing, 1999), ix.

148

Ibid.

Page 56: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

45

Pressler’s convictions of Scripture—that it is complete, absolute, totally

accurate, integral, and revelatory—historically surmise one of Christianity’s most

controversial issues. This is to say that the interpretation of the inspiration of Scripture

has been a subject of debate amongst Christians for centuries.

David Dockery, in his work Christian Scripture, lists five historical theories of

inspiration that have developed as a result of these centuries-long debates. These are the

dictation, illumination, encounter, dynamic, and plenary-verbal theories of inspiration.151

To briefly define these theories, “the dictation theory places the emphasis upon God’s

actual dictation of His Word to the human writers;”152

In the illumination theory, “human

authors were enabled to express themselves with eloquent language to produce a certain

emotional response from the readers or hearers. Inspiration is the illumination of the

authors beyond their normal abilities;”153

“[The Encounter Theory] states that in regard to

its composition, the Bible differs little from other books. Yet, the Bible is unique because

of the Spirit’s ability to use it as a means of revelation to specific individuals or

communities;”154

The dynamic theory attempts “a combination of divine and human

elements in the process of inspiration;”155

Finally, “[The plenary-verbal theory’s]

approach is careful to see the Spirit’s influence both upon the writers and, primarily, upon

149

Ibid., 160.

150

Ibid.

151

David Dockery. Christian Scripture. (Nashville: Broadman & Holman, 1995), Noted on

pages 51-55. 152

Ibid.

153

Ibid., 52.

154

Ibid., 53.

155

Ibid., 54.

Page 57: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

46

the writings. It also seeks to view inspiration as extending to all portions of Holy

Scripture, even beyond the direction of thoughts to the selection of words.”156

Dockery

wrote concerning these theories, “Many of [these] are attempts to deal seriously with the

two-sided character of the Scripture—[God and man].”157

Irenaeus and Hick certainly

argued their own respective theories concerning this “two-sided character of Scripture.”

Regarding Irenaeus’ view of Scripture, Caner and Hindson have noted that,

Irenaeus held an extremely high view of Scripture, for he believed that the

Septuagint had been interpreted by the inspiration of God. He was also the earliest

Christian writer to list the four canonical Gospels. Furthermore, Irenaeus upheld all

the Pauline writings as authoritative, because he derived apostolic succession from

them. Finally, he employed other apostolic writings (as well as tradition) to build his

case against Gnosticism’s falsehood.158

Hick summarized his personal view of Scripture in writing,

For most educated inhabitants of the modern world regard the biblical story of

Adam and Eve, and their temptation by the devil, as myth rather than as history.

Further, they reject as incredible the idea that earthquake and flood, disease, decay,

and death are consequences either of a human fall, or of a prior fall of angelic

beings who are now exerting an evil influence upon the earth. They see all this as

part of a pre-scientific world view, along with the stories of the world having been

created in six days and of the sun standing still for twenty-four hours at Joshua’s

command. One cannot, strictly speaking, disprove any of these ancient biblical

myths and sagas, or refute their confident elaboration in the medieval Christian

picture of the universe. But those of us for whom the resulting theodicy, even if

logically possible, is radically implausible, must look elsewhere for light on the

problem of evil.159

These quotes evidence the notion that although Hick considered his theodicy Irenaean in

origin, he disagreed with him concerning the inspiration and value of Scripture. Irenaeus

156

Ibid., 55.

157

Ibid., 51.

158

Ed Hindson and Ergun Caner, The Popular Encyclopedia of Apologetics (Eugene: Harvest

House Publishers, 2008), 275.

159

Michael Peterson, William Hasker, Bruce Reichenbach, and David Basinger, Philosophy of

Religion : Selected Readings (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007), 342-3.

Page 58: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

47

viewed Scripture with authority, and Hick considered most of it as myth. This is

important because Hick’s theodicy rests heavily on the notion that Adam and Eve were

merely mythical characters. Irenaeus, on the other hand, likely considered the two actual,

historical figures. C. Stephen Evans has written that “Irenaeus is known for his argument

that Christ came to actualize all those perfections that God had intended humans to have

but that were lost through the sin of Adam and Eve.”160

This suggests a literal

interpretation of the individual’s existence. This thesis purports the plenary-verbal theory

of inspiration of Scripture, which is closer to what Irenaeus would have advocated.

Historically, many theologians have noted some wonderful discourse on the

Word of God. The most notable is perhaps W.A. Criswell. In his book, Why I Preach

That the Bible is Literally True, he noted, “The Bible is the Word of God, not merely

contains it.”161

In the book, he consistently asks, “Why do I believe that the Bible is

literally true?” Some of his answers include: (1) Because of the testimony of Jesus

Christ, (2) because of the internal witness of the Holy Scriptures, (3) because of the

fulfillment of prophecy, (4) and because of the confirmation of archeology.162

Criswell

also addressed any doubters and discussed questions such as, “Is the Bible Full of Errors

and Contradictions?” and “Is the Bible an Immoral Book?” Criswell’s conclusion to

these questions is one that has withstood time, translating to an inspiration that has been

etched into the pulpits of many churches; Criswell wrote, “I believe that the Bible is

literally true because it partakes of the nature of God, who is eternal, who is the same

160

C. Stephen Evans, Pocket Dictionary of Apologetics & Philosophy of Religion (Downers

Grove: InterVarsity Press, 2002), 62.

161

W.A. Criswell. Why I Preach That the Bible is Literally True (Nashville: Broadman Press,

1973), 33.

162

These general answers are seen in the chapter titles.

Page 59: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

48

yesterday, today, and forever.”163

This is an important point because a mythical

interpretation of the events renders a weak view of God, which arguably leads to a

weakness in one’s theodicy regarding the omnipotence of God. Criswell advocated an

important thought in that a literal interpretation of Scripture upholds the nature of God as

eternal, the same yesterday, today, and forever.

Arthur Pink has said, “The Bible is an inexhaustible mine of wealth: it is the El

Dorado of heavenly treasure. It has veins of ore which will never ‘give out’ and pockets

of gold which no pick can empty. It is like a spring of water which never runs dry.”164

Pink’s quote speaks not only of the wealth of Scripture, but of its veracity. The battle for

biblical authority has waged for many years, and will, in all likelihood, continue to wage.

It is important for Christian philosophers to fight for a literal interpretation of Scripture.

This should always be a “hill on which to die,” or Christian philosophy will be able to do

nothing less than “bemoan the fate of millions of lost persons around the globe who

remain oblivious to the message of Christ due to the inroads of universalism, liberation

theology, and anemic evangelism which rests on a shifting foundation of historical-

critical hypothesizing.”165

Hick’s view concerning Scripture arguably hinders his

theodicy insofar as it ventures away from the biblical description of omnipotence. A

skeptic could easily attack this claim, suggesting that his rendering of omnipotence

hinders his theodicy.

163

W.A. Criswell. Why I Preach That the Bible is Literally True (Nashville: Broadman Press,

1973), 101.

164

Arthur Pink. The Divine Inspiration of the Bible (Grand Rapids: Baker Book House, 1971),

23.

165

The Proceedings of the Conference on Biblical Inerrancy, 1987 (Nashville: Broadman

Press, 1987), 93.

Page 60: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

49

Evolution and the Image of God in Man

Another difference between Irenaeus and Hick is their interpretation of the

image of God in man. Irenaeus lived before evolution became a theory and his theology

never seemed to suggest this interpretation of creation. With this said, Irenaeus’ theology

is distinct in that he argued a theory that didn’t necessarily depend on the fall, which, as

noted earlier, suggests man as an “immature creature living in a challenging and therefore

person-making world.”166

Unlike Augustine who argued that man fell from perfection,

Irenaeus suggested man as more of working towards perfection, and the existence of evil

doesn’t necessarily depend upon the fall. Augustine believed that it did.167

“Irenaeus

believed God created Adam and Eve as children, frail and open to Satan’s seducing:

‘Humanity was a child; and its mind was not yet fully mature; and thus humanity was

easily led astray by the deceiver.’”168

Irenaeus advocated this thought in writing,

Things which have recently come into being cannot be eternal; and, not being

eternal, they fall short of perfection for that very reason. And being newly created

they are therefore childish and immature, and not yet fully prepared for an adult way

of life. And so, just as a mother is able to offer food to an infant, but the infant is not

yet able to receive food unsuited to its age, in the same way, God, for his part, could

have offered perfection to humanity at the beginning, but humanity was not capable

of receiving it. It was nothing more than an infant.169

This is essentially the starting point for Hick’s theodicy, but Hick advanced

Irenaeus’ conviction to the scientific theory of evolution. Hick wrote, “Re-expressing

this in modern terms, the first stage was the gradual production of homo sapiens, through

166

Michael Peterson, William Hasker, Bruce Reichenbach, and David Basinger, Philosophy of

Religion : Selected Readings (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007), 342.

167

The fall refers to both angels and man.

168

Ed Hindson and Ergun Caner, The Popular Encyclopedia of Apologetics (Eugene: Harvest

House Publishers, 2008), 275.

169

Ibid., 275-6.

Page 61: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

50

the long evolutionary process, as intelligent ethical and religious animals.”170

This

thought is furthermore expressed in the following quote from Hick:

But early homo sapiens is not the Adam and Eve of Augustinian theology, living in

perfect harmony with self, with nature, and with God. On the contrary, the life of

this being must have been a constant struggle against a hostile environment, and

capable of savage violence against one’s fellow human beings, particularly outside

one’s own immediate group; and this being’s concepts of the divine were primitive

and often bloodthirsty. Thus existence “in the image of God” was a potentiality for

knowledge of a relationship with one’s Maker rather than such knowledge and

relationship as a fully realized state. In other words, people were created as

spiritually and morally immature creatures, at the beginning of a long process of

further growth and development, which constitutes the second stage of God’s

creative work. In this second stage, of which we are a part of the intelligent, ethical,

and religious animal is being brought through one’s own free responses into what

Irenaeus called the divine “likeness.” The human animal is being created into a child

of God.171

As evidenced in this quote, Hick took Irenaeus’ interpretation of the image of

God and advanced it to the theory of evolution. The center of this difference is

discovered in Hick’s theory that man is a “human animal” that is “being created into a

child of God” by a “long evolutionary process,” as opposed to being a man who, though

created imperfect, was created as a child of God, as Irenaeus suggested. Both the image

of God in man and the theory of evolution are detailed in the following, and an

interpretation is offered for the rendered Soul-Making Theodicy.

The Image of God in Man

The image of God in man is a rare and controversial topic among Christians.

The thought that man is unique from other animals is a thought-provoking concept that

captures the minds of theologians and scientists alike.

170

Michael Peterson, William Hasker, Bruce Reichenbach, and David Basinger, Philosophy of

Religion : Selected Readings (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007), 343.

171

Ibid.

Page 62: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

51

Interestingly, the World Resources Institute has observed that, “scientists have

a better understanding of how many stars there are in the galaxy than how many species

there are on Earth. Estimates of global species diversity have varied from 2 Million to

100 million, with a best estimate of somewhere near 10 million, and only 1.4 million

have actually been named.”172

Of these estimated 10 million species, the Bible states that

God placed a unique description on mankind only. Genesis speaks only of man being

created in God’s image, with His likeness. Scripture portrays no other creature having

this characterization.

The idea of the image of God is developed primarily from Genesis 1:26, which

utilizes the words, “image” and “likeness.” In Hebrew, these words are tselem and

demuth.173

“Both terms, obviously, refer to a relation between man and his Creator.”174

In the Hebrew Old Testament, tselem and demuth are a rare find. In fact, the notion that

man is created in God’s image is rarely stated, which makes Hick’s theodicy fairly

unique. G.C. Berkouwer has observed, “If we examine the Biblical witness regarding

man, we soon discover that it never gives us any kind of systematic theory about man as

the image of God. It is indeed rather striking that the term is not used often at all, and

that it is far less ‘central’ in the Bible than it has been in the history of Christian

thought.”175

Berkouwer was correct in his observation. The church is quick to note that

man is created in the image of God, but rarely defines its meaning. The Evangelical

Lutheran Church in America, for example, has stated, “Human beings have a unique

172

http://www.wri.org/publication/content/8202

173

English transliteration.

174

G.C. Berkouwer, Man: The Image of God (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1962), 69.

175

Ibid., 67.

Page 63: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

52

position in the order of creation. As males and females created in God’s image, we are

given the capacity and freedom to know and respond to our Creator.”176

The Baptist

Faith and Message reads, “The sacredness of human personality is evident in that God

created man in His own image, and in that Christ died for man.”177

While these are

biblical statements, they do not define the meaning of the Image of God. Berkouwer was

right; the idea is far less “central”178

in the Bible than it is in Christian thought.

This lack of centrality has led many scholars to investigate Scripture, hoping to

find a specific meaning of the idea. In his work, In the Image of God, William Baker

generalized the various conclusions of these scholars into five categories. He writes,

“Christians have offered various suggestions as to precisely what the image consists of.

[They] can be categorized as an inner quality, as a relationship between God and

humanity, as dominion over nature, as a representation of God, or as sonship.”179

Each

view falls under a more general category. Millard Erickson considers these

generalizations the substantive view, which believes that man has a spiritual or physical

commonality with God, the relational view which argues that one must be in a

relationship with God in order to possess the image of God, and the functional view

which argues that the image of God is imprinted on us in function rather than in form or

relationship.180

176

http://archive.elca.org/communication/brief.html

177

Baptist Faith and Message, Article III, Man, 11 1998

178

Not that it fails in importance, only that it is rare in occurrence.

179

William Baker, In the Image of God (Chicago: Moody, 1991), 36.

180

Millard Erickson, Christian Theology (Grand Rapids: Baker, 1994), 520-530.

Page 64: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

53

Having noted difficulties with many of the leading views, an attempt at

advocacy must be made. Millard Erickson has discerned, “The existence of a wide

diversity of interpretations is an indication that there are no direct statements in Scripture

to resolve the [image of God] issue.”181

This thesis advances the representation view of

the image of God, which is closer to Augustine’s convictions than Irenaeus’. This does

not sacrifice the credibility of a Soul-Making Theodicy because, while this rendering

doesn’t hinge on the weakened understanding of the image of God in man, it still submits

that God, in His omnipotence and omnibenevolence, considered it satisfactory to allow

man the opportunity to grow in character. This suggested interpretation of the image of

God in man best defends sin’s impact and Scripture’s total representation of the image.

Of its many tenets, the Representation view sees Christ as the perfect image of God.

G.C. Berkouwer wrote, “The whole Scriptural witness makes clear that our understanding

of the image of God can be sound only when in unbreakable relation to the witness

regarding Jesus Christ, who is called the image of God.”182

Scriptural Support

In his epistle to the Colossians, Paul wrote that Christ “is the image of the

invisible God” (Col 1:15a). Verse 15 parallels183

verse 19 which says, “For it pleased the

Father that in Him all the fullness should dwell.” The “invisible God” that Christ bears

image of is none other than the “Father” of verse 19. Essentially, Christ is looking to the

181

Ibid., 531-2.

182

G.C. Berkouwer, Man: The Image of God (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1962), 107.

183

In its Greek chiastic structure.

Page 65: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

54

Father, imitating Him. The Father is looking back to Christ declaring, “I am pleased that

in You all fullness dwells.”

To conclude, man is substantively like God,184

but the complete185

image of

God can only be restored when man imitates Jesus Christ. This requires an incorruptible

and undefiled relationship that can only be revealed by His saving grace and perfected186

upon entering His kingdom.

Evolution

As previously noted, Hick also asserted a unique view on evolution. He

argued that God used the process, and continues to use the process, to develop man’s

character. While this theology—theistic evolution—differed from that of Irenaeus’, it

has been more accepted in recent days.

On October 23, 1996, while speaking to the Pontifical Academy of Sciences at

the Vatican, Pope John Paul II stated, “[evolution] has been proven true; we always

celebrate natures factuality, and we look forward to interesting discussions of theological

implications.”187

This comment may come as a surprise to the modern day Protestant;

however, it is important to note that John Paul II was only reiterating what Pope Pius XII

had stated nearly fifty years earlier: “In his encyclical ‘Humani Generis’ (1950) my

184

The tripartite make-up.

185

Meaning, as close as possible in a fallen world.

186

Meaning, a restored image that is not corrupted by sin. This can only be fulfilled in heaven.

187

Michael Peterson, William Hasker, Bruce Reichenbach, and David Basinger, Philosophy of

Religion (New York: Oxford Press, 2007), 555.

Page 66: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

55

predecessor Pius XII had already stated that there was no opposition between evolution

and the doctrine of faith about man and his vocation.”188

Pope Pius XII wrote,

The Teaching Authority of the Church does not forbid that, in conformity with the

present state of human sciences and sacred theology, research and discussions, on

the part of men experienced in both fields, take place with regard to the doctrine of

evolution, in as far as it inquires into the origin of the human body as coming from

pre-existent and living matter –for the Catholic faith obliges us to hold that souls are

immediately created by God.189

This is an important quote because, according to the Catechism of the Catholic Church,

the church’s interpretation of Scripture is authoritative. Article II, Section 85 of the

Catechism reads, “The task of giving an authentic interpretation of the Word of God,

whether in its written form or in the form of Tradition,190

has been entrusted to the living

teaching office of the Church alone. This means that the task of interpretation has been

entrusted to the bishop.”191

This is to say that both Pope Pius and John Paul’s statements

regarding evolution are understood as the official Catholic, and therefore church’s, stance

on God’s creation of man.

The late Stephen Gould harmoniously wrote, “Sincere Christians must now

accept evolution, not merely as a plausible possibility, but also as an effectively proven

fact.”192

Gould illustrates this statement with the following story,

188

Ibid., 554.

189

Ibid., 553.

190

Tradition here is best described in Article II, Section 78 of the Catechism: This living

transmission, accomplished in the Holy Spirit, is called Tradition, since it is distinct from Sacred Scripture,

though closely connected to it. Through Tradition, "the Church, in her doctrine, life and worship,

perpetuates and transmits to every generation all that she herself is, all that she believes. The sayings of the

holy Fathers are a witness to the life-giving presence of this Tradition, showing how its riches are poured

out in the practice and life of the Church, in her belief and her prayer."

191

http://www.vatican.va/archive/catechism.htm. Emphasis added.

192

Michael Peterson, William Hasker, Bruce Reichenbach, and David Basinger, Philosophy of

Religion (New York: Oxford Press, 2007), 555.

Page 67: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

56

I am often asked whether I ever encounter creationism as a live issue among my

Harvard undergraduate students. I reply that only once, in thirty years of teaching,

did I experience such an incident. A very sincere and serious freshman student

came to my office with a question that had clearly been troubling him deeply. He

said to me, “I am a devout Christian and have never had any reason to doubt

evolution, an idea that seems both exciting and well documented. But my

roommate, a proselytizing evangelical, has been insisting with enormous vigor that I

cannot be both a real Christian and an evolutionist. So tell me, can a person believe

both in God and in evolution?” Again, I gulped hard, did my intellectual duty, and

reassured him that evolution was both true and entirely compatible with Christian

belief – a position that I hold sincerely, but still an odd situation for a Jewish

agnostic.193

There are at least two important questions concerning evolution and

Christianity. These questions are: “Can an individual be both a real Christian and an

evolutionist?” and “Is there any real reason for the Christian to doubt evolution?” For

Stephen Gould, the answers are “yes” and “no.” Alvin Plantinga surprisingly echoes

Gould. The Soul-Making Theodicy rendering offered here, however, suggests the

answers of “yes” and “yes.”

Concerning the first question, while a theology including Christianity and

evolution is arguably incorrect, this is not grounds for the termination or neglection of

salvation. Jesus is the way by which man must be saved. The Scriptures state that Jesus

is “the way, the truth, and the life” and that “no one comes to the Father but through

[Him]” (John 14:6). An incorrect understanding of creation therefore does not remove or

rebuke legitimate salvation.

Concerning the second question, the theodicy offered here suggests that not

only is there a real reason for the Christian to doubt the theory of evolution, there are real

reasons. The Creeds that define Christianity, for example, arguably restrict evolution

193

Ibid., 550. Emphasis added.

Page 68: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

57

from being considered as compatible with the faith,194

and more importantly, a correct

exegetical understanding of the Genesis account on the creation of man arguably forbids

the theory of evolution as being compatible with Christianity.195

Plantinga has noted that “it is not incompatible for theism and evolution to co-

exist,” which is not philosophically unsatisfactory, however, the thought that Christianity

and evolution are not incompatible arguably is, because it includes the notion of a

religion that exegetically restricts it, if not creedally. Christianity, in its correct

rendering, does not reasonably allow for the theistic evolution of man. The Scriptures

and the Christian Creeds arguably discourage the idea.

194

Plantinga has stated that “Christianity is to be understood by the great creeds of the church

(which includes, but is not limited too): The Apostles Creed, the Nicene Creed, the Belgic Confession, the

Westminster Confession, and the Baptist Faith & Message” (Criswell College ETS lectures). This is to say

that Plantinga argues that these creeds should not, in any way, interfere with the argument of compatibility,

for they define part of the premise. Of the Creeds mentioned, three of them speak directly on the creation

of man. These are, The Belgic Confession, The Westminster Confession, and the Baptist Faith and

Message. Article 14 of The Belgic Confession is entitled The Creation and Fall of Man, and states, “We

believe that God created man from the dust of the earth and made and formed him in his image and

likeness.”194

Chapter IV of The Westminster Confession states, “After God had made all other creatures, he

created man, male and female, with reasonable and immortal souls, endued with knowledge, righteousness,

and true holiness after his own image.”194

Article III of The Baptist Faith & Message 2000 states, “Man is

the special creation of God, made in His own image.” Each creed surmises the same claim, that God

“created man in His own image.” The question then is raised concerning the interpretation of this claim. Generally speaking, the Creeds can be interpreted in one of two ways. First, it can be taken that God

created man “from the dust of the earth,” which is to say, specially, or, not by evolution. Or second, it can

be taken that “after God made all other creatures, he created man,” and that this creation of man was by the

modification of genetic mutation, governed by God. The problem with this second interpretation is that

none of these “great Creeds of the church” suggest the idea of theistic evolution. 195

Genesis 2:7 seems to be the most straightforward verse regarding God’s creation of man.

In interpreting this verse, Kenneth Gangel and Stephen Bramer have written, “This verse says that God

formed the man from the dust of the ground. The Hebrew verb for “formed” is commonly used of the work

of a potter with clay (e.g., Job 33:6; Isa. 45:9; Jer. 18:6). It conveys the idea of molding and shaping with

careful, loving care. It is a new word for Genesis. The Hebrew words used in the first account to describe

the creation of man and animals include “make” (asah) and “create” (bara) (Gen. 1:26-27). Here God acts

as the potter taking clay or soil and forming man. [Furthermore], man is a combination of dust and

divinity. Genesis 2:7 goes on to say that the Lord God breathed into his nostrils the breath of life, and man

became a living being. It was God who gave man a life unique to mankind. Animals had life too, but man

had a portion of deity within him because he was made ‘in the image of God.’” (Kenneth Gangel and

Stephen Bramer, Holman Old Testament Commentary (Nashville: B&H Publishers, 2002), 26-27.)

Page 69: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

58

It is important to remember that in Christian philosophy, the Bible must always

remain the standard by which all truth is measured. When one strays from this,

philosophy has the potential of becoming a religion in and of itself, and moreover, a

religion without a standard of accountability. Brian Leftow summarized this thought well

in writing, “I am a philosopher because I am a Christian.”196

Universal Salvation

It is safe to argue that Hick disagreed with Irenaeus concerning the veracity of

Scripture and the image of God in man, but he also disagreed with his patron saint’s

eschatology. Hick noted, quite accurately, that any viable theodicy must include an

eschatological statement: “I…do not see how any coherent theodicy can avoid

dependence upon an eschatology.”197

Hick purports the eschatological concept known as

universal salvation which is seen in his belief that “the reality of a limitlessly loving and

powerful deity must incorporate some kind of eschatology according to which God holds

in being the creatures whom God has made for fellowship with himself, beyond bodily

death, and brings them into the eternal fellowship which God has intended for them.”198

Concerning this, he has moreover written,

If the justification of evil within the creative process lies in the limitless and eternal

good of the end state to which it leads, then the completeness of the justification

must depend upon the completeness, or universality, of the salvation achieved. Only

if it includes the entire human race can it justify the sins and sufferings of the entire

human race throughout all history. But, having given human beings cognitive

freedom, which in turn makes possible moral freedom, can the Creator bring it

196

Thomas Morris ed., God and the Philosophers (New York: Oxford Press, 1995), quote

located on the back cover.

197

Michael Peterson, William Hasker, Bruce Reichenbach, and David Basinger, Philosophy of

Religion (New York: Oxford Press, 2007), 352.

198

Ibid.

Page 70: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

59

about that in the end all his human creatures freely turn to God in love and trust?

The issue is a very difficult one; but I believe that it is in fact possible to reconcile a

full affirmation of human freedom with a belief in the ultimate universal success of

God’s creative work. We have to accept that creaturely freedom always occurs

within the limits of a basic nature that we did not ourselves choose; for this is

entailed by the fact of having been created. If then a real though limited freedom

does not preclude our being endowed with a certain nature, it does not preclude our

being endowed with a basic Godward bias, so that, quoting from another side of St.

Augustine’s thought, “our hearts are restless until they find their rest in Thee.”199

If

this is so, it can be predicted that sooner or later, in our own time and in our own

way, we shall all freely come to God; and universal salvation can be affirmed, not as

a logical necessity but as the contingent but predictable outcome of the process of

the universe, interpreted theistically.200

Hick attempts to complete his Soul-Making Theodicy by suggesting that

ultimately, every soul will be perfectly made complete in salvation. He opposes the idea

of a “heaven and hell” eschatology, or even the idea of “annihilationism.”201

Ultimately,

for his Soul-Making Theodicy to work, every soul must experience God’s ultimate love

in eternity, which is the very reason for the existence of evil. Philosophically, this is not

necessarily unsound, but theologically, the thought experiences some difficulties. The

evident descriptions of Hell in the Scriptures initially provide satisfactory objections;

however, these are arguably philosophically and theologically negotiable depending on

one’s interpretation.

Hick argues that if the existence of evil is justified by the end—and for Hick

that end is eternity with God—then that end must be realized. If it is not realized by

every person, then Hick argues that the Soul-Making Theodicy fails. The theodicy

offered in this thesis does include a viable eschatological suggestion, but that suggestion

199

The Confessions of St. Augustine, trans. F. J. Sheed (New York: Sheed and Ward, 1942),

Bk. 1, chap. 1, p. 3.

200

Michael Peterson, William Hasker, Bruce Reichenbach, and David Basinger, Philosophy of

Religion (New York: Oxford Press, 2007), 353.

201

Ibid.

Page 71: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

60

includes the notion that some souls will not experience eternity with God. It is not

necessarily unsatisfactory to suggest that because every soul doesn’t experience the

fullness of soul-making (i.e., salvation), that the entire argument fails. Hick’s argument

seemingly becomes unsound because he sacrifices freedom, a tenet that is dear to his

argument, to purport universal salvation. Moreover, surely it is not unsatisfactory to

suggest that while soul-making characteristics are offered to all, and that many will

obtain them, that not everyone will experience the totality and conclusion of this offer.

Specifically, the theodicy offered here argues a rendering of the Soul-Making

Theodicy that suggests a contribution to the problem of evil, not necessarily the solution

of it. The foundational solution is best seen, arguably, in Gordon Clark’s theodicy.

While Hick argues that his Soul-Making Theodicy is a justifiable conclusive solution to

the problem of God and evil, the theodicy offered in this thesis proposes an Ireneaen (in

terms of Scripture), Augustinian (in terms of the image of God), and Clarkian (in terms of

God’s involvement with evil) approach to the problem of evil, that suggests that God

oversees evil in order that man may be edified for His glory. Soul-making is not

extended to the origins of the evolutionary process, or to the ends of universal salvation,

but instead to the beginning of God’s sovereignty of the fall, and to the end of eternity

with Christ. The eschatological claim here suggests that while some will never

experience the fullness of what a soul can become in Christ, that those who will will be

better for it. That is, the experiences on earth—particularly evil and the decision to

follow Christ—will not be forgotten once the soul enters into eternity. This is notably

true if that soul-making property is faithfulness, and especially true if that faithfulness is

directed to an omnipotent, omnibenevolent Deity who is ever-faithful to mankind.

Page 72: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

61

An Eschatological Approach – The Second Coming

Hick is correct in writing, “I…do not see how any coherent theodicy can avoid

dependence upon an eschatology.”202

The eschatological suggestion offered in this

thesis’ rendering of Hick’s Soul-Making Theodicy argues that all evil will be justified on

the day of Christ’s return, upon the establishment of His millennial Kingdom on earth,

and in the rest of eternity with God. Revelation 19:11-16 best details this event:

And I saw heaven opened, and behold, a white horse, and He who sat on it is

called Faithful and True, and in righteousness He judges and wages war. His eyes

are a flame of fire, and on His head are many diadems; and He has a name written

on Him which no one knows except Himself. He is clothed with a robe dipped in

blood, and His name is called The Word of God. And the armies which are in

heaven, clothed in fine linen, white and clean, were following Him on white horses.

From His mouth comes a sharp sword, so that with it He may strike down the

nations, and He will rule them with a rod of iron; and He treads the wine press of

the fierce wrath of God, the Almighty. And on His robe and on His thigh He has a

name written, "KING OF KINGS, AND LORD OF LORDS."

Tim Lahye has written of this event that it is,

…the most thrilling event in all of human history. It will be that moment in time

when our Lord Jesus Christ returns to this earth in power and great glory to set up

His kingdom that will last 1000 years, the final event prior to the new heavens and

the new earth in eternity. From a prophetic standpoint, it will be the culmination of

all prophecy. At least 325 prophecies of Christ’s second coming guarantee it will

take place, and this event will usher in the most ideal conditions on earth since the

Garden of Eden.203

The notion of the justification of evil on the day of the second coming of Jesus

Christ supports the aforementioned characteristic of faithfulness. As Lahaye noted, this

is arguably one of the main Scriptural truths for the Christian. If Christ is not faithful in

His return, then evil has no justification, but if Christ does remain faithful in His return,

202

Ibid., 352.

203

Tim Lahaye and Thomas Ice, Charting the End Times (Eugene: Harvest House Publishers,

2001), 65.

Page 73: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

62

then the soul will be made complete when it is perfected in unity with Him in a Kingdom

that includes no evil, in which man remembers his earthly life that built his soul toward

this new era. The Apostle Paul has written that if “Christ has not been raised…faith is

worthless” (1 Corinthians 15:17). This statement can be attributed to the second coming

and the faithfulness of God. If Christ is not faithful in His promised return, then the soul-

making process is “worthless.” This is moreover a philosophically satisfying argument,

which will be seen in the following discussion concerning the soul-making characteristic

known as faithfulness.

Page 74: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

63

CHAPTER 4

Faithfulness as a Viable Soul-Making Characteristic

While the general notion of Hick’s Soul-Making Theodicy is valuable, it

experiences both philosophical and theological difficulties, especially in what is

considered conservative theology. Hick argues a mythical-scriptural, evolutionary,

universal-salvific theodicy that is not advocated in this thesis. Instead, a literal-scriptural,

Augustinian imago Dei, exclusive-salvific rendering of Hick’s theodicy is suggested.

This is shown to arguably be both philosophically and theologically consistent. In this

chapter, this Soul-Making Theodicy rendering will be enhanced by the theological virtue

known as faithfulness.

The Four Cardinal Virtues

A virtue is a “disposition or character trait that is itself an excellence or good

or that tends to lead to what is good, with moral virtues being those excellences that

foster human flourishing.”204

The value of virtue is something that has permeated society

for ages. C. Stephen Evans has written,

In ancient and medieval philosophy ethical thinking centered on the virtues—what

they are, how they are related and how they are to be achieved. The medievals

accepted the cardinal virtues of the ancient world (wisdom, justice, courage,

temperance) and added to them the three principal Christian virtues (faith, hope and

love). Both ancient and medieval thinkers tied their account of the virtues as leading

to human flourishing to accounts of human nature. Recent ethical theory has seen a

rediscovery of the importance of the virtues and the development of virtue theory,

204

C. Stephen Evans, Pocket Dictionary of Apologetics & Philosophy of Religion (Downers

Grove: InterVarsity Press, 2002), 121.

Page 75: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

64

which holds that concepts of the virtues are basic to ethics and not reducible to claims

about moral duties or what is impersonally valuable.205

Christian tradition suggests four “cardinal virtues,” which were arguably first

developed by Plato in Protagoras.206

These virtues are justice, prudence, temperance,

and fortitude. The term “cardinal” comes from the Latin word for “hinge,” which

suggests that the moral life must hinge upon these virtues. These virtues were eventually

adopted, and adapted, by Ambrose, Augustine, and Aquinas. The virtues are also

identified in the classes of Plato’s city in his work, The Republic: Temperance was

associated with the farmers and craftsmen; fortitude was assigned to the warrior class;

prudence was reserved for the rulers; justice was the transcendent virtue which governed

the other three. According to most philosophies, these virtues hold an important place in

society, and therefore affect the problem of God and evil.

Theological Virtues

Scripture conveys three theological virtues. These are faith, hope, and love.

These virtues are communicated in Paul’s first letter to the Corinthians: “But now faith,

hope, love, abide these three; but the greatest of these is love” (1 Corinthians 13:13).

Paul moreover communicates the Christian emphasis upon character and virtue in his

letter to the Galatians: “But the fruit of the Spirit is love, joy, peace, patience, kindness,

goodness, faithfulness, gentleness, self-control” (Galatians 5:22-23). Ron Nash has

written that “A major function of the Christian ethic is the development of character and

virtue. Any person could on occasion appear to obey God’s moral law while inwardly

205

Ibid.

206

See Protagoras 330b

Page 76: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

65

surrendering to evil motives. It is important that believers attain the appropriate virtues,

that is, a disposition to behave in a moral way, a loving way.”207

The Virtue of Faithfulness

The pursuit of virtue has been an important philosophical concept since its

origins in Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle. Most agree that obtaining a quality that makes

one a better person is a good thing, and most furthermore agree that the four cardinal

virtues represent four of the greatest qualities an individual can achieve. The theological

virtues—faith, hope, and love—have also been widely accepted among philosophers as

worthwhile virtues. This thesis argues that the value of obtaining virtuous characteristics

helps justify the existence of evil.

Although faith is primarily considered a theological virtue, it is not

unreasonable to suggest that the virtue is valuable outside of that context. That is,

faithfulness toward fellow-man, to self, and to other areas of life is a good thing. With

this said, it is important to understand that this virtue is best expressed and totally

fulfilled when it exists in a theological context and is expressed in the realm of

Christianity. This is essentially what Augustine argued.

“While Augustine is well aware of the prominence of the four cardinal virtues

in Greek ethical thinking, he offers a corrective from his perspective as a Christian

thinker. Unless the cardinal virtues of unbelievers result from their desire to love and

honor God, the best of pagan virtues will be reduced to ‘splendid vices.’”208

For

207

Ronald Nash, Life’s Ultimate Questions (Grand Rapids: Zondervan, 1999), 162.

208

Ibid., (Augustine, The City of God 19.25, in The Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers (NPNF).

This multivolume nineteenth-century work was reprinted in 1956 by the Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing Co.,

Grand Rapids.)

Page 77: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

66

Augustine, an unbeliever’s search for virtue is motivated by his selfish pride. Augustine

offers an insight on the relationship between the four cardinal virtues and Christian love:

Temperance is love keeping itself entire and uncorrupt for God; fortitude is love

bearing everything readily for the sake of God; justice is love serving God only, and

therefore ruling well all else, as subject to man; prudence is love making a right

distinction between what helps it toward God and what might hinder it.209

Bigham and Mollegen advance Augustine’s claim in writing that, “The four pagan virtues

are transformed into Christian virtues only when faith (that by which we love God not yet

seen) and hope (that by which we love what we have not yet reached) and love (which

remains when faith has become sight, and hope has been realized) undergird them.”210

Faith has been observed as “that attitude of trust in God, including beliefs

about God and his goodness, that is essential to a right relationship with God.”211

Hebrews 11:1 is likely the most oft quoted verse in Scripture concerning faith. It reads,

“Now faith is the assurance of things hoped for, the conviction of things not seen.” This

observation and this verse express the notion of faithfulness toward God, and inherently,

express the notion that God is also faithful. The motivating reason to be faithful to God

is because He is faithful in return. Moreover, if God is omnipotent and omnibenevolent,

as LPE suggests, then it is not unreasonable to suggest that God is always faithful, even

in man’s unfaithfulness. Therefore, it is not unreasonable to suggest that while

faithfulness is a good virtue, it is best realized when it is directed towards an ever-faithful

deity—God. In this understanding, it is moreover not unreasonable to suggest that

growing in faithfulness toward God is a justifiable reason for the existence of evil, both

209

Augustine, On the Morals of the Catholic Church. 19-25.

210

Bigham and Mollegen, “The Christian Ethic,” 377.

211

C. Stephen Evans, Pocket Dictionary of Apologetics & Philosophy of Religion (Downers

Grove: InterVarsity Press, 2002), 43.

Page 78: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

67

moral and natural. This also provides a rare response to EPE and gratuitous evils, for

faith is best tested when the reasons of said evil are unknown. This furthermore echoes

the Clarkian influence purported in this Soul-Making Theodicy rendering because it

places the ultimate emphasis upon the glory of God. Augustine summarizes this in his

well-known saying, “Love [God] and do as what thou wilt…let the root of love be within,

of this root can nothing spring but what is good.”212

“Augustine meant that if we truly

love God, what we will then desire to do and choose to do will be what will please the

just and holy God.”213

Faithfulness in Scripture

A rendered Soul-Making Theology based on a theological virtue would not be

of much value—at least practically and in Christendom—unless it was actually expressed

and supported by the Bible. With this said the prophet Habakkuk expresses the virtue of

faithfulness in his dialogue with God as recorded in his Old Testament book.

The book of Habakkuk is a conversation between the prophet and God

concerning evil. The book begins with Habakkuk crying out, “How long, O Lord, will I

call for help, and You will not hear?” (Habakkuk 1:2) Habakkuk essentially declares that

the Lord is disguised, that evil is intensified, and that the law is therefore paralyzed

(Habakkuk 1:1-4). God responds in an unusual way. He tells Habakkuk to “Look among

the nations…because I am doing something” (Habakkuk 1:5). This “something” was the

raising up of the Chaldeans, those “fierce and impetuous people,” who are “dreaded and

feared,” who “come for violence…[mocking] at kings…[laughing] at every fortress…

212

Epistle of St. John, Homily 7.8; On Nature and Grace 70 (84), and On Christian Doctrine

1.28. (42).

213

Ronald Nash, Life’s Ultimate Questions (Grand Rapids: Zondervan, 1999), 163.

Page 79: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

68

[heaping] up rubble” (Habakkuk 1:6-10). Habakkuk was naturally confused at such a

declaration. How could an omnipotent and omnibenevolent God conceive—and

dictate—such evil? He responded, “Your eyes are too pure to approve evil, and You can

not look on wickedness with favor. Why do You look with favor on those who deal

treacherously?” (Habakkuk 1:13). Habakkuk’s final statement in his second response,

however, is of the upmost importance—“I will keep watch to see what He will speak to

me, and how I may reply when I am reproved” (Habakkuk 2:1). God was orchestrating

an evil event in order that Habakkuk—and Judah—could obtain the virtuous

characteristic of faithfulness, and the process was evidentially beginning in the prophet.

God’s response to Habakkuk’s second cry suggests the Clarkian theodicy as

well as the virtue of faithfulness and why it is best expressed when directed toward God.

The Lord expresses first that “the righteous will live by faith” (Habakkuk 2:4). This is a

direct reference to the virtue purported in this Soul-Making rendering. God moreover

tells Habakkuk that “the earth will be filled with the knowledge of the glory of the Lord,

as the waters cover the sea” (Habakkuk 2:14). This is another reference to faithfulness,

suggesting the need to be faithful to God’s promises. God lastly encourages Habakkuk,

informing Him that He is indeed omnipotent: “the Lord is in His holy temple. Let all the

earth be silent before Him” (Habakkuk 2:20). Habakkuk responds by declaring a psalm

to God, stating that he will “wait quietly for the day of distress,” a far cry from his initial

plead of “How long, O Lord” (Habakkuk 3:16). Habakkuk ends his psalm and his

dialogue with the Lord by proclaiming that,

Though the fig tree should not blossom and there be no fruit on the vines, though

the yield of the olive should fail and the fields produce no food, though the flock

should be cut off from the fold and there be no cattle in the stalls, Yet I will exult in

the Lord, I will rejoice in the God of my salvation (Habakkuk 3:17-18).

Page 80: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

69

This is a vivid example of the kind of faithfulness purported in this rendered Soul-

Making Theodicy—faithfulness to an ever-faithful, omnipotent God, who desires the best

for man.

This is an example of a biblical event in which an individual obtained the

virtue of faithfulness, and moreover an illustration of how this faithfulness is best

expressed when it is directed towards an ever-faithful Deity. In essence, this Soul-

Making rendering suggests that one of the highest soul-making characteristics available is

faithfulness towards God’s faithfulness. This is not an unreasonable contribution to the

problem of God and evil.

Page 81: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

70

CHAPTER 5

The Existence of an Omnipotent and Omnibenevolent God

LPE and EPE argue on the premise that God is omnipotent and

omnibenevolent. This is based on the theological claims derived from the Scriptures.

Because LPE and EPE argue that the existence of evil thwarts the notion that God is

omnipotent and omnibenevolent, it is important to review two of the leading

philosophical arguments that help support these claims—the Teleological and Moral

arguments for the existence of God. This is also important because the rendered Soul-

Making Theodicy argued in this thesis also depends on the notion of an omnipotent and

omnibenevolent God. When paired with the virtue of faithfulness, these characteristics

become vital because sometimes the reasons for evil are not necessarily ascertainable.

Both the Teleological and Moral arguments philosophically purport the existence of an

omnipotent and omnibenevolent God.

Teleological Argument

The teleological argument is “an argument for the existence of God that takes

as its starting point the purposive character of the universe.”214

This argument is often

referred to as the “argument from design.” Its name is developed from the Greek word

telos meaning “end” or “purpose.” The teleological argument is therefore the study of

the purpose of the universe.

214

C. Stephen Evans, Pocket Dictionary of Apologetics & Philosophy of Religion (Downers

Grove: InterVarsity Press, 2002), 113.

Page 82: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

71

The teleological argument has its origins in the ancient Greeks, such as Plato

and Aristotle, who argued for the existence of God based on their observations of the

stars. Thomas Aquinas used this argument as one of his five ways of proving the

existence of God.215

In 1802 William Paley “published what is probably the most famous

articulation of the argument.”216

The analogy is detailed in the following:

In crossing a heath, suppose I pitched my foot against a stone, and were asked how

the stone came to be there; I might possibly answer, that, for anything I knew to the

contrary, it had lain there forever: nor would it perhaps be very easy to show the

absurdity of this answer. But suppose I had found a watch upon the ground, and it

should be inquired how the watch happened to be in that place; I should hardly think

of the answer I had before given, that for anything I knew, the watch might have

always been there. (...) There must have existed, at some time, and at some place or

other, an artificer or artificers, who formed [the watch] for the purpose which we

find it actually to answer; who comprehended its construction, and designed its use.

(...) Every indication of contrivance, every manifestation of design, which existed in

the watch, exists in the works of nature; with the difference, on the side of nature, of

being greater or more, and that in a degree which exceeds all computation.217

Paley’s analogy “tries to show that when we observe nature, whether on a tiny level (like

cells or proteins) or on a grand scale (like whole organisms or even the universe), we can

see precision and intentionality, a purpose, a plan. And from that observation we can

infer that there must be an intelligence behind it all.”218

Concerning the design of the universe, a scientist has written,

There are no facts yet wrested from the intriguing mysteries of this strange,

onrushing cosmos which can in any degree disprove the existence and intelligent

activities of an unconditioned, personal God. On the contrary, when as careful

215

Thomas Aquinas, Great Books of the Western World, vol. 19, Summa Theologica (Chicago:

Encyclopedia Britannica, 1952), 14.

216

Doug Powell, Holman Quicksource Guide to Christian Apologetics (Nashville: Holman,

2006), 51.

217

William Paley, Natural Theology(London: J. Faulder, 1809, 12th

edition), 1-8; (Ann Arbor,

MI: University of Michigan Humanities Text Initiative, 1998), 1-8, online at

http://www.hti.umich.edu/cgi/p/pd-modeng/pd-modeng-idx?type=header&id=paleynatur.

218

Doug Powell, Holman Quicksource Guide to Christian Apologetics, 50.

Page 83: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

72

scientists we analyze and synthesize the data of scientists we analyze and synthesize

the data of the natural world, even by analogical inference, we are observing only

the phenomena of the operations of that unseen Being who cannot be found by mere

scientific seeking, but who can and did manifest Himself in human form. For

science is indeed “watching God work.”219

The apologist Doug Powell has noted,

Naturalism can only account for so much; at a certain point its explanatory power

fails. But it is not this failure that points to an intelligent designer (the so-called

“God of the gaps” theory). The precision of the universe, the nature of information,

and the observation that random and undirected forces cannot account for the

complexity of living things all lead to a transcendent, personal, intelligent

designer.220

The teleological argument is a reasonable philosophical argument that suggests that the

universe conveys meaning and purpose, which therefore leads one to consider that there

must be an intelligent, and perhaps omnipotent, deity behind it all. The scientist Allan

Sandage has notably written,

The world is too complicated in all its parts and interconnections to be due to

chance alone. I am convinced that the existence of life with all its order in each of

its organisms is simply too well put together. Each part of a living thing depends on

all its other parts to function. How does each part know? How is each part specified

at conception? The more one learns of biochemistry the more unbelievable it

becomes unless there is some type of organizing principle—an architect for

believers.221

The Moral Argument

The moral argument for God’s existence suggests that “God must exist as the

ground of the moral order (or some aspect of that order, such as moral obligations) or as

219

Merritt Stanley Congdon, “The Lesson of the Rosebush,” in The Evidence of God in an

Expanding Universe, ed. John Clover Monsma (New York: Putnam, 1958), 35-36.

220

Doug Powell, Holman Quicksource Guide to Christian Apologetics (Nashville: Holman,

2006), 68.

221

Allan Sandage, “A Scientist Reflects on Religious Belief,” available online at Leadership

U., http://www.leaderu.com/truth/1truth15.html.

Page 84: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

73

the explanation of certain moral facts.”222

Someone has asked, “Are right and wrong

objective realities with claims on all people at all times, or are they subjective realities

only—matters of opinion? Was Adolph Hitler evil or did he simply have a different

opinion about things?”223

The moral argument tries to show that moral values are indeed

objective, and that these values must therefore come from a moral law giver who is a

“transcendent, personal being for whom human actions and motives are not a matter of

indifference.”224

The moral argument is in direct opposition to the theory of relativism

which “holds that societies and/or individuals decide what is right and wrong and that

those values vary from culture to culture or person to person. There are no objective,

universal moral truths—just conventions for behavior that are created by people for

people and that are subject to change.”225

In defending moral law, Caner and Hindson have noted three valuable

observations: (1) denying moral law is self-defeating; (2) without moral law, moral

disagreements would be senseless; (3) without moral law, moral judgments would be

meaningless. These observations help purport the veracity of the Moral argument.

Denying Moral Law is Self-Defeating

Moral relativists claim that in matters of morality, there are no objective truths

or values. To claim that all moral truths are relative, however, is self-defeating. “A

statement is self-defeating when what is being affirmed fails to meet its own

222

C. Stephen Evans, Pocket Dictionary of Apologetics & Philosophy of Religion (Downers

Grove: InterVaristy Press, 2002), 77.

223

Ibid., 71.

224

Ibid., 72.

225

Ibid.

Page 85: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

74

requirements. The statement ‘All truth is relative’ is itself an absolute claim for truth.”226

Therefore, it is not unreasonable to suggest that moral law—and arguably a moral law

giver—exists.

Without Moral Law, Moral Disagreements Would Be Senseless

Without moral law, moral disagreements are a senseless exercise. Most

arguments consist of moral truth claims such as “You’re wrong!” or “That’s not fair!”

However, these types of statements lose value if there is no objective moral code. C.S.

Lewis points out that what is interesting about these kinds of remarks is that “the man

who makes them is not merely saying that the other man’s behavior does not please him.

He is appealing to some kind of standard of behavior which he expects the other man to

know about.”227

Caner and Hindson appropriately note,

Interestingly enough, when it comes to a dispute on morals, the disagreeing party

does not attack the standard to which he is making his appeal. Rather, he tries to

show how his position does not violate or is an exception to the standard. Thus, true

moral disagreements are not possible without an absolute moral standard. Without

absolutes, all moral disagreements would be reduced to matters of personal opinion

or taste.228

The Apostle Paul also advocated the moral law in writing,

For when Gentiles who do not have the Law do instinctively the things of the Law,

these not having the Law, are a law to themselves, in that they show the work of the

Law written in their hearts, their conscience bearing witness and their thoughts

alternately accusing or else defending them (Romans 2:14-15).

226

Ed Hindson and Ergun Caner, The Popular Encyclopedia of Apologetics (Eugene: Harvest

House Publishers, 2008), 354.

227

Ibid., 355.

228

Ibid.

Page 86: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

75

Without Moral Law, Moral Judgments Would Be Meaningless

“Without moral law, not only would moral disagreements be senseless, but

also moral judgments would be meaningless.”229

A philosopher has suggested,

concerning this, that the statement “Torturing babies is wrong,” for example would

become mere opinion as opposed to universally, objectively wrong. Without a universal

moral law, it becomes impossible to claim any difference between the lives of Adolph

Hitler and Mother Teresa, and no one could “express the truth that terrorism, murder,

rape, and slavery are wrong, and that honesty, truthfulness, and benevolence are right.”

Without objective morality, all moral claims become mere matters of opinion. All of

these statements suggest that it is not unreasonable to suggest that because an objective

moral law exists, that there therefore must be a moral law giver, and that moral law giver

is arguably omnibenevolent.

The teleological and moral arguments for the existence of God arguably

convey the notion that an omnipotent and omnibenevolent God exists. If this is the case,

and it is, then it is not unsatisfactory to argue that a rational theodicy must exist that

defends these claims. For centuries, philosophers have offered these theodicies, some of

which have satisfactorily contributed to what is known as the problem of God and evil.

229

Ibid.

Page 87: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

76

CONCLUSION

An Overview of a Rendered Soul-Making Theodicy

John Hick provides a valuable contribution to the problem of God and evil in

his Soul-Making Theodicy, but the argument experiences philosophical and theological

difficulties. These difficulties have been outlined throughout the course of this thesis.

With this said, it is difficult to achieve an argument for LPE and EPE that doesn’t

experience objections. The problem of God and evil will always be a topic of question

and controversy, but this doesn’t mean that satisfactory contributions are not possible.

The theodicy purported in this thesis argues not necessarily for a solution to the problem

of God and evil, but for a satisfactory contribution to the justification of its existence.

The theodicy is soul-making insofar as it suggests that God desires to grow man in the

knowledge of His grace and truth. This God is both omnipotent and omnibenevolent in

the highest interpretation of the terms. He created man in His image, but that image was

disrupted by sin, which is something that He foresaw. This does not diminish His

omnipotence, for He sovereignly predestined creation to fall. It moreover does not

diminish His goodness, for He oversees evil for the greatest good, which will ultimately

be realized in eternity. This is to say that if an omnipotent and omnibenevolent God

exists, it is not unreasonable to suggest that He has a higher knowledge and purpose than

mankind, and this knowledge and purpose cannot be fully ascertained in this limited

world. The virtue of faithfulness, while a stand-alone worthy characteristic and soul-

Page 88: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

77

making property, is best realized when it is expressed toward an ever-faithful deity. That

is, if an omnipotent, omnibenevolent, and ever-faithful God exists, then learning to be

faithful to that God is a justifiable reason for the existence of evil in this world, for God is

utilizing the evil in His own sovereign way for His own greater good, which is not

logically inconsistent with the meaning of the terms. One may call this rendering the

Augustinian Soul-Making Theodicy, although it includes Clarkian influence in terms of

freedom. One objection that can be offered against this soul-making rendering is an

attack on the omnipotence of God, who arguably could have provided a different kind of

method in developing the soul as opposed to allowing evil. This objection is contested,

however, when one understands omnipotence in the purest of interpretations, and

moreover, in a proper understanding of the eschatological context that an individual who

follows Christ will exist in for eternity. These soul-making properties will not be lost as

man enjoys eternity with the “lamb” who was “foreknown before the foundation of the

world” (1 Peter 1:19-20).

Page 89: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

78

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Books

Albright, William and David Freedman, ed. Habakkuk : A New Translation with

Introduction and Commentary. New York: Doubleday, 2001.

Aquinas, Thomas. Selected Writings. London New York: Penguin Books, 1998.

Augustine. The confessions of St. Augustine. Garden City, N.Y: Doubleday, 1960.

Baker, David, ed. Looking into the Future: Evangelical Studies In Eschatology. Grand

Rapids, Michigan: Baker Academic, 2001.

Barber, Cyril. The Faithfulness of God : Devotional Studies in I Chronicles. Santa Ana,

CA: Promise Pub, 2002.

Beisner, E. Psalms of Promise : Celebrating The Majesty And Faithfulness of God.

Phillipsburg, N.J: P&R Pub, 1994.

Blocher, Henri. Evil and the Cross. Downers Grove, Ill: InterVarsity Press, 1994.

Boyd, Gregory. Satan and the Problem of Evil : Constructing a Trinitarian Warfare

Theodicy. Downers Grove, Ill: InterVarsity Press, 2001.

Carson, D. How long, O Lord? : Reflections on Suffering and Evil. Grand Rapids,

Michigan: Baker Academic, 2006.

Clark, Gordon. Religion, Reason, and Revelation. Hobbs, New Mexico: Trinity

Foundation, 1995.

Clark, Kelly. 101 Key Terms In Philosophy And Their Importance For Theology.

Louisville, Kentucky: Westminster John Knox Press, 2004.

Colson, Charles. Developing A Christian Worldview Of The Problem Of Evil. Wheaton,

Illinois: Tyndale House, 2001.

Cooper, Barry. The Political Theory of Eric Voegelin. Lewiston N.Y: E. Mellen Press,

1986.

Page 90: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

79

Cooper, David, ed., Epistemology : The Classic Readings. Oxford, UK Malden, Mass:

Blackwell Publishers, 1999.

Copan, Paul and William Lane Craig, ed. Passionate Conviction : Contemporary

Discourses On Christian Apologetics. Nashville, Tenn: B & H Academic,

2007.

Crenshaw, James, ed. Theodicy in the Old Testament. Philadelphia London: Fortress

Press SPCK, 1983.

Criswell, W. Why I Preach That The Bible Is Literally True. Nashville, Tenn: Broadman

& Holman, 1999.

Curtler, Hugh. Ethical Argument : Critical Thinking In Ethics. New York: Paragon

House, 1993.

Davis, Stephen, ed., Encountering Evil: Live Options In Theodicy. Atlanta: J. Knox

Press, 1981.

Dostoyevsky, Fyodor. The Brothers Karamazov. New York: Bantam Books, 1981.

Erickson, Millard. Christian Theology. Grand Rapids: Baker Book House, 1998.

Evans, C. Pocket Dictionary Of Apologetics & Philosophy Of Religion. Downers Grove,

Illinois: InterVarsity Press, 2002.

Feinberg, John. The many faces of evil : theological systems and the problems of evil.

Wheaton, Ill: Crossway Books, 2004.

Flew, Antony. There is a God : How The World's Most Notorious Atheist Changed His

Mind. New York: HarperOne, 2007.

Geisler, Norman and Chad Meister. Reasons for Faith : Making A Case For The

Christian Faith : Essays In Honor Of Bob Passantino And Gretchen

Passantino Coburn. Wheaton, Ill: Crossway Books, 2007.

Geisler, Norman. Baker Encyclopedia Of Christian Apologetics. Grand Rapids,

Michigan: Baker Books, 1999.

__________. The Roots Of Evil. Grand Rapids, Michigan: Zondervan Pub. House,

1978.

Haak, Robert. Habakkuk. Leiden New York: E.J. Brill, 1992.

Page 91: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

80

Hauerwas, Stanley. Christians Among The Virtues : Theological Conversations With

Ancient And Modern Ethics. Notre Dame, Ind: University of Notre Dame

Press, 1997.

Hebblethwaite, Brian. Evil, Suffering, And Religion. New York: Hawthorn Books, 1976.

Helm, Paul and Carl Trueman, ed. The Trustworthiness Of God : Perspectives On The

Nature Of Scripture. Grand Rapids, Mich: Eerdmans Pub, 2002.

Hick, John. Evil And The God Of Love. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2010.

__________. Faith And Knowledge : A Modern Introduction To The Problem Of

Religious Knowledge. Eugene, Or: Wipf & Stock, 2009.

__________. Philosophy of Religion. Englewood Cliffs, N.J: Prentice Hall, 1990.

Hiebert, Theodore. God of My Victory : The Ancient Hymn In Habakkuk 3. Atlanta, Ga:

Scholars Press, 1986.

Hindson, Ed and Ergun Caner,The Popular Encyclopedia Of Apologetics. Eugene, Or:

Harvest House Publishers, 2008.

Hitchens, Christopher. Is Christianity Good For The World. Moscow, Idaho: Canon

Press, 2008.

Hume, David. Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, The Posthumous Essays, Of The

Immortality Of The Soul, And Of Suicide, From An Enquiry Concerning

Human Understanding Of Miracles. Indianapolis: Hackett Pub, 1998.

Inwagen, Peter Van. Christian Faith And The Problem Of Evil. Grand Rapids, Mich:

W.B. Eerdmans Pub, 2004.

__________. The Problem Of Evil : The Gifford Lectures Delivered In The University

Of St. Andrews In 2003. Oxford New York: Clarendon Press Oxford

University Press, 2006.

Jones, David. Faith Tried And Triumphant. Grand Rapids, Mich: Baker Book House,

1987.

__________. From Fear To Faith : Studies In The Book Of Habakkuk. Grand Rapids:

Baker Book, 1982.

Keller, Timothy. The Reason For God : Belief In An Age Of Skepticism. New York:

Dutton, 2008.

Page 92: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

81

Kreeft, Peter. Pocket Handbook Of Christian Apologetics. Downers Grove, Ill:

InterVarsity Press, 2003.

LaHaye, Tim. Charting the End Times. Eugene, OR: Harvest House Publishers, 2001.

Legg, John. When We Don't Understand... : God's ways with Jonah and Habakkuk.

Darlington, Co.Durham: Evangelical Press, 1992.

Leibniz, Gottfried. Theodicy : Essays On The Goodness Of God, The Freedom Of Man,

and The Origin Of Evil. Charleston, S.C: BiblioBazaar, 2007.

Lemos, Noah. An Introduction To The Theory Of Knowledge. Cambridge, UK New York:

Cambridge University Press, 2007.

MacIntyre, Alasdair. After Virtue : A Study In Moral Theory. Notre Dame, Ind:

University of Notre Dame Press, 2007.

Mackie, J. The Miracle Of Theism : Arguments For And Against The Existence Of God.

Oxford Oxfordshire New York: Clarendon Press Oxford University Press, 1982.

Mathis, Terry. Against John Hick : An Examination Of His Philosophy Of Religion.

Lanham, MD: University Press of America, 1985.

McComiskey, Thomas, ed. The Minor Prophets : An Exegetical And Expository

Commentary. Grand Rapids, Mich: Baker Book House, 1992.

Meilaender, Gilbert. Faith and Faithfulness : Basic Themes In Christian Ethics. S.l: Univ

Of Notre Dame Press, 1992.

Moreland, James. Philosophical Foundations For A Christian Worldview. Downers

Grove, Ill: InterVarsity Press, 2003.

Morris, Thomas, ed. God and the Philosophers : The Reconciliation Of Faith And

Reason. New York: Oxford University Press, 1995.

Nash, Ronald. Life's ultimate Questions : An Introduction To Philosophy. Grand Rapids,

MI: Zondervan Publishing House, 1999.

Oliphint, K. Reasons [for faith] : Philosophy In The Service Of Theology. Phillipsburg,

N.J: P&R Pub, 2006.

Packer, J. Evangelism and the SOVEREIGNTY of God. Downers Grove, Ill: InterVarsity

Press, 2008.

Page 93: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

82

Peterson, Michael, William Hasker, Bruce Reichenbach, and David Basinger, Philosophy

of Religion : Selected Readings. New York: Oxford University Press, 2007.

Peterson, Michael. Evil and the Christian God. Grand Rapids, Mich: Baker Book House,

1982.

Phillips, D. The Problem Of Evil & The Problem Of God. Minneapolis: Fortress Press,

2005.

Plantinga, Alvin. God, Freedom, and Evil. New York, New York: Harper & Row

Publishers, 1974.

__________. Warranted Christian Belief. New York: Oxford University Press, 2000.

Plato. Protagoras and Meno. London: Penguin Books, 2005.

Powell, Doug. Holman QuickSource Guide To Christian Apologetics. Nashville, Tenn:

Holman Reference, 2006.

Prior, David. The Message Of Joel, Micah, And Habakkuk : Listening To The Voice Of

God. Downers Grove, Ill: InterVarsity Press, 1999.

Reichenbach, Bruce. Evil and a Good God. New York: Fordham University Press, 1982.

Rowe, William. Philosophy of Religion : An Introduction. Belmont, Calif:

Wadsworth/Thomson, 2007.

Stackhouse, John. Can God be Trusted? : Faith And The Challenge Of Evil. Downers

Grove, Ill: IVP Books, 2009.

Stott, John. The Cross of Christ. Downers Grove, Ill: IVP Books, 2006.

Strobel, Lee. The Case For Faith : A Journalist Investigates The Toughest Objections To

Christianity. Grand Rapids, Mich: ZondervanPublishingHouse, 2000.

Surin, Kenneth. Theology and the Problem Of Evil. Oxford, UK New York, NY, USA:

Blackwell, 1986.

Timmons, Mark. Moral Theory : An Introduction. Lanham, Md: Rowman & Littlefield

Publishers, 2002.

Wright, N. Evil and the Justice of God. Downers Grove, Ill: IVP Books, 2006.

Page 94: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

83

Journals

The Criswell Theological Review

Liberty University Faculty Publications and Presentations

Bible

New American Standard Bible

New King James Version Bible

Creeds and Confessionals

Baptist Faith and Message 2000

Catechism of the Catholic Church

The Apostles Creed

The Belgic Confession

The Nicene Creed

The Westminster Confession

Internet Sources

Christian Apologetics and Research Ministry – www.carm.org

Evangelical Lutheran Church in America – www.elca.org

Internet Movie Database – www.imdb.com

Leadership University – www.leaderu.com

Ravi Zacharias International Ministries – www.rzim.org

The Online Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy – plato.stanford.edu

The University of Michigan – www.umich.edu

The Vatican – www.vatican.va

Page 95: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

84

West Valley College – www.westvalley.edu

World Resources Institute – www.wri.org

Page 96: Faithfulness as a Soul-Making Theodicy

Recommended