+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture...

Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture...

Date post: 25-Sep-2020
Category:
Upload: others
View: 0 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend
22
What Should be Known Expected Utility Measure of Risk Stochastic dominance Information partitions Common knowledge Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1: Patrick Legros 1 / 22
Transcript
Page 1: Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1homepages.ulb.ac.be/~plegros/documents/classes/micro2/L1-Reviews.pdfGraduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1: Patrick Legros 1/22. What Should be KnownExpected

What Should be Known Expected Utility Measure of Risk Stochastic dominance Information partitions Common knowledge

Graduate Microeconomics IILecture 1:

Patrick Legros

1 / 22

Page 2: Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1homepages.ulb.ac.be/~plegros/documents/classes/micro2/L1-Reviews.pdfGraduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1: Patrick Legros 1/22. What Should be KnownExpected

What Should be Known Expected Utility Measure of Risk Stochastic dominance Information partitions Common knowledge

Outline

What Should be Known

Expected Utility

Measure of Risk

Stochastic dominance

Information partitions

Common knowledge

2 / 22

Page 3: Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1homepages.ulb.ac.be/~plegros/documents/classes/micro2/L1-Reviews.pdfGraduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1: Patrick Legros 1/22. What Should be KnownExpected

What Should be Known Expected Utility Measure of Risk Stochastic dominance Information partitions Common knowledge

What Should be Known

• Constrained optimization

• Kuhn et Tucker• Dynamic programming• Comparative Statics

• Information economics• Risk aversion• Stochastic dominance• Value of information

• Basics of game theory• Extensive forms• Equilibrium

3 / 22

Page 4: Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1homepages.ulb.ac.be/~plegros/documents/classes/micro2/L1-Reviews.pdfGraduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1: Patrick Legros 1/22. What Should be KnownExpected

What Should be Known Expected Utility Measure of Risk Stochastic dominance Information partitions Common knowledge

Some Reviews

1. Measures of risk

2. Stochastic dominance

3. Information partitions and common knowledge

4. No trade theorems

4 / 22

Page 5: Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1homepages.ulb.ac.be/~plegros/documents/classes/micro2/L1-Reviews.pdfGraduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1: Patrick Legros 1/22. What Should be KnownExpected

What Should be Known Expected Utility Measure of Risk Stochastic dominance Information partitions Common knowledge

Utility for Money

Start from preferences over lotteries L = (p1, · · · , pN).Impose two axioms.

• CONTINUITY :∀L, L′, L′′, the sets α ∈ [0, 1] : αL + (1− α)L′ L′′ andα ∈ [0, 1] : αL + (1− α)L′ L′′ are closed.

• INDEPENDENCE: ∀L, L′, L′′, ∀α ∈ (0, 1),[L < L′]⇔ [αL + (1− α)L′′ < αL′ + (1− α)L′′]

Theorem (von Neuman expected utility)

If < satisfies CONTINUITY and INDEPENDENCE, then it admitsan expected utility representation: ∃u1, · · · , uN s.t.

L < L′ ⇔N∑

i=1

piui >N∑

i=1

p′iui

5 / 22

Page 6: Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1homepages.ulb.ac.be/~plegros/documents/classes/micro2/L1-Reviews.pdfGraduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1: Patrick Legros 1/22. What Should be KnownExpected

What Should be Known Expected Utility Measure of Risk Stochastic dominance Information partitions Common knowledge

Example 1: Allais Paradox

Four (simple) lotteries: A =

(10 0.10 0.9

), B =

(15 0.090 0.91

),

C =

(10 10 0

), D =

(15 0.90 0.1

)

• Do you prefer A to B? Do you prefer C to D?

• Most often: B A and C D

Violation of expected utility

A = 0.1 ∗ C + 0.9 ∗ 0

B = 0.1 ∗ D + 0.9 ∗ 0

B A ⇔ D C

6 / 22

Page 7: Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1homepages.ulb.ac.be/~plegros/documents/classes/micro2/L1-Reviews.pdfGraduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1: Patrick Legros 1/22. What Should be KnownExpected

What Should be Known Expected Utility Measure of Risk Stochastic dominance Information partitions Common knowledge

Example 1: Allais Paradox

Four (simple) lotteries: A =

(10 0.10 0.9

), B =

(15 0.090 0.91

),

C =

(10 10 0

), D =

(15 0.90 0.1

)

• Do you prefer A to B? Do you prefer C to D?

• Most often: B A and C D

Violation of expected utility

A = 0.1 ∗ C + 0.9 ∗ 0

B = 0.1 ∗ D + 0.9 ∗ 0

B A ⇔ D C

7 / 22

Page 8: Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1homepages.ulb.ac.be/~plegros/documents/classes/micro2/L1-Reviews.pdfGraduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1: Patrick Legros 1/22. What Should be KnownExpected

What Should be Known Expected Utility Measure of Risk Stochastic dominance Information partitions Common knowledge

Example 2: Mean-VarianceOr Beware of Seemingly “Natural” Utility Functions• Businessman who never heard of Bernoulli nor von Neumann

Morgenstern nor expected utility. Thinks that it is a good ideato get a high expected profit but he thinks that someadjustment has to be made for risk.

• He may think, if he had some rudimentary statistics in hisyouth, the variance is a good measure of risk. He may thendecide to assign the following utility to a lottery f (x) withmean E and variance V :

W (f ) = E − aV

where a can be taken as a measure of “risk aversion.”

• However, there is no function u(x) independent of f so thatU(f ) =

∑u(x)f (x). This means that the decision rule of our

businessman violates some axioms of expected utility and leadto some “weird” decisions.

8 / 22

Page 9: Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1homepages.ulb.ac.be/~plegros/documents/classes/micro2/L1-Reviews.pdfGraduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1: Patrick Legros 1/22. What Should be KnownExpected

What Should be Known Expected Utility Measure of Risk Stochastic dominance Information partitions Common knowledge

Example 2: Mean-VarianceOr Beware of Seemingly “Natural” Utility Functions• Businessman who never heard of Bernoulli nor von Neumann

Morgenstern nor expected utility. Thinks that it is a good ideato get a high expected profit but he thinks that someadjustment has to be made for risk.

• He may think, if he had some rudimentary statistics in hisyouth, the variance is a good measure of risk. He may thendecide to assign the following utility to a lottery f (x) withmean E and variance V :

W (f ) = E − aV

where a can be taken as a measure of “risk aversion.”• However, there is no function u(x) independent of f so that

U(f ) =∑

u(x)f (x). This means that the decision rule of ourbusinessman violates some axioms of expected utility and leadto some “weird” decisions.

9 / 22

Page 10: Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1homepages.ulb.ac.be/~plegros/documents/classes/micro2/L1-Reviews.pdfGraduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1: Patrick Legros 1/22. What Should be KnownExpected

What Should be Known Expected Utility Measure of Risk Stochastic dominance Information partitions Common knowledge

• For instance, consider the two lotteries, lottery f1: get 1 withproba 0.1 and get −99 with proba 0.9lottery f2: get 1 with proba 0.2 and −99 with proba 0.8suppose a = 0.1, then U(f1) = −179 > U(f2) = −239

• If instead, we start from the utility for money, u(x) = x − ax2

where 0 ≤ a ≤ 1/(2M) and −∞ ≤ x ≤ M then,

U(f ) =∑

xf (x)− a∑

x2f (x)

=∑

xf (x)− a(∑

xf (x))2 − a∑

(x −∑

xf (x))2f (x)

= E − aE 2 − aV

10 / 22

Page 11: Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1homepages.ulb.ac.be/~plegros/documents/classes/micro2/L1-Reviews.pdfGraduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1: Patrick Legros 1/22. What Should be KnownExpected

What Should be Known Expected Utility Measure of Risk Stochastic dominance Information partitions Common knowledge

Example 3: “Bernoulli Utility”Utility for money u(x + s) where s is initial wealth. If preferenceordering over lotteries is independent of s, then

u(x + s) = a(s)u(x) + b(s)

then

u′(x + s) = au′(x)

u′(x + s) = a′u(x) + b′

⇒a′u(x)− au′(x) + b′ = 0

Then,

• a′ = 0⇒ u(x) = b′

a x + C1 (risk neutral)

• a′ 6= 0⇒ u(x)− aa′u′(x) + b′

a′ = 0 ⇒ u(x) = C2e−a′ax− b′

a′

or u(x) = C3e−αx

11 / 22

Page 12: Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1homepages.ulb.ac.be/~plegros/documents/classes/micro2/L1-Reviews.pdfGraduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1: Patrick Legros 1/22. What Should be KnownExpected

What Should be Known Expected Utility Measure of Risk Stochastic dominance Information partitions Common knowledge

Risk aversion

The Bernoulli utility ui incorporates the preferences for risk. Let xbe a random payoff. The certainty equivalent is the sure payoff cx

such that Eu(x) = u(cx)

• Risk loving: u is convex; hence cx > E x

• Risk averse: u is concave; hence cx < E x

• Risk premium: ρx = E x − cx

Intuition: a risk averse agent would be ready to pay for insurance

12 / 22

Page 13: Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1homepages.ulb.ac.be/~plegros/documents/classes/micro2/L1-Reviews.pdfGraduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1: Patrick Legros 1/22. What Should be KnownExpected

What Should be Known Expected Utility Measure of Risk Stochastic dominance Information partitions Common knowledge

Deriving risk premium for small risks

y is a small risk with E y = 0,E y 2 = 1. Let σ be a scaling factor;

• Write the absolute risk premium p when initial wealth is xwhen face the risk σy as u(x − p) = Eu(x + σy). Taylorseries expansion:

u(x)− pu′(x) = E [u(x) + σu′(x)y + (1/2)σ2u′′(x)y 2]

= u(x) + (1/2)σ2u′′(x)

So

p ≈ −u′′(x)

u′(x)

σ2

2

• Relative risk premium: u(x − ρx) = Eu(x + σyx). Seriesexpansion yields

ρ = −u”(x)x

u′(x)

σ2

2

13 / 22

Page 14: Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1homepages.ulb.ac.be/~plegros/documents/classes/micro2/L1-Reviews.pdfGraduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1: Patrick Legros 1/22. What Should be KnownExpected

What Should be Known Expected Utility Measure of Risk Stochastic dominance Information partitions Common knowledge

Measure of Risk Aversion

The coefficient of absolute risk aversion is −u”(x)u′(x) .

The coefficient of relative risk aversion is −u”(x)xu′(x) Usually (stylized

fact?) we think of the absolute risk aversion as declining in wealth(condition on the third derivative on u). Evidence?

• Constant relative risk aversion - u(x) = x1−ρ

1−ρ (CES), ρ ≥ 0.

Note that ρ = −u”(x)xu′(x) .

• Special cases: risk neutrality ( ρ = 0); log utility (ρ = 1)

14 / 22

Page 15: Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1homepages.ulb.ac.be/~plegros/documents/classes/micro2/L1-Reviews.pdfGraduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1: Patrick Legros 1/22. What Should be KnownExpected

What Should be Known Expected Utility Measure of Risk Stochastic dominance Information partitions Common knowledge

How risk averse?

Equity premium puzzle

• (Mehra and Prescott 1985): equity premium ρ ≈ var [y ][Ey ]2 R

where R = −[E y ][u”(E y)]/u′(E y) is the index of relative riskaversion evaluated at the mean return. In data,var [y ]/[E y ]2 ≈ 0.056% .

• Historical data for 1889-1978 (Shiller 1989, Kocherlakota1996), average return S&P is 7% while short-term risk freerate is 1%. Fro 1963-1995, figures are resp. 7,72% and3,14%, hence ρ approx4, 5%, requiring R ≥ 40

In the lab

• Often risk aversion over small amount of money

• Rabin (2000): risk aversion in the small leads to impossibleresults in the large

15 / 22

Page 16: Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1homepages.ulb.ac.be/~plegros/documents/classes/micro2/L1-Reviews.pdfGraduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1: Patrick Legros 1/22. What Should be KnownExpected

What Should be Known Expected Utility Measure of Risk Stochastic dominance Information partitions Common knowledge

“Suppose we knew a risk-averse person turns down 50-50 lose$100/gain $105 for any lifetime wealth level less than $350,000,but we knew nothing about the degree of his risk aversion forwealth levels above $350,000. Then we know that from an initialwealth level of $340,000 the person will turn down a 50-50 bet oflosing $4,000 and gaining $635,670.”

If mu is the marginal utility then sinceu(w + 105)− u(w) < u(w)− u(w − 100),

mu(w + 105) < [u(w + 105− u(w)]/105

<100

105[u(w)− u(w − 100)]/100

<100

105mu(w − 100)

Hence mu falls at a faster rate than that of a geometrical sequence.

• Rubinstein (Nobel symposium 2001): assumes that there is asingle preference relation over set of lotteries; but could havepreferences depend on w .

16 / 22

Page 17: Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1homepages.ulb.ac.be/~plegros/documents/classes/micro2/L1-Reviews.pdfGraduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1: Patrick Legros 1/22. What Should be KnownExpected

What Should be Known Expected Utility Measure of Risk Stochastic dominance Information partitions Common knowledge

Stochastic dominance

How can we say that a lottery is riskier than another? Statementmust be true for all or only some utility functions?

• (Rotschild-Stiglitz) Take mass from middle and spread it atthe tails; mean-preserving risk.

• (FOSD) unambiguous higher returns;F 1 G ⇔ ∀x ,F (x) ≤ G (x) (< on a set of positive measure)FOSD ⇔ ∀φ increasing,EFφ ≥ EGφ

• (SOSD) unambiguous lowerrisk;F 2 G ⇔ ∀y ,

∫ y0 F (x)dx) ≤

∫ y0 G (x)dx (< on a set of

positive measure.SOSD ⇔ ∀u concave,EF u ≥ EG u

• (Lorentz) Inequality measure; φ(F (y)) =R y

0 xf (x)dx

EF x . AssumingEF x = EG x , F is more unequal than G ifF (y1) = G (y2)⇒ φ(F (y1)) ≥ φ(G (y2))

17 / 22

Page 18: Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1homepages.ulb.ac.be/~plegros/documents/classes/micro2/L1-Reviews.pdfGraduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1: Patrick Legros 1/22. What Should be KnownExpected

What Should be Known Expected Utility Measure of Risk Stochastic dominance Information partitions Common knowledge

Blackwell theorema ∈ A action, θ ∈ Θ states, p dist. on θ, u(a, θ) utility function.An environment is t = (u,A).Optimization: maxa∈A Epu(a, θ)⇒ a(p, t)Signal x1 or x2, πi (x |θ) conditional of signal x given θ. Posterior is

pi (θ|x i ) =πi (x |θ) · p(θ)

πi (x i )

Optimal action as a function of signal received and indirect utilityS i (x i ; t)

• x1 is more informative than x2 if S1(x1; t) ≥ S2(x2; t) for allt.

• x1 is sufficient for x2 if there exists a matrix B such that

1.∑

x2 b(x2, x1) = 1 for all x1

2. π2(·|θ) = B · π1(·|θ); hence π2(·|θ) =∑

x1 b(x2, x1)π1(x1|θ)

Theorem (Blackwell, Cremer) x1 is more informative than x2 if and onlyif x1 is sufficient for x2

18 / 22

Page 19: Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1homepages.ulb.ac.be/~plegros/documents/classes/micro2/L1-Reviews.pdfGraduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1: Patrick Legros 1/22. What Should be KnownExpected

What Should be Known Expected Utility Measure of Risk Stochastic dominance Information partitions Common knowledge

Information partitions

(Hintikka 1962) Information structure is a pair (Ω,P), Ω set ofstates and P : Ω→ 2Ω describes the individual information (ifstate is ω agent can exclude all states not in P(ω).Basic Properties

P-1 ω ∈ P(ω)

P-2 If ω′ ∈ P(ω)⇒ P(ω′) ⊆ P(ω)

P-3 If ω′ ∈ P(ω)⇒ P(ω′) ⊇ P(ω)

Ex (awareness) Identify first digit but notice second digit only if itis the same; P(33) = 33 but P(23) = 13, 23, 33 violates P-3Ex (measurement error) States from 00 to 99, mistake of 1 atmost. P(n) = n − 1, n, n + 1, violates P-2.

Proposition An information structure is partitional if and only if itsatisfies P-1,P-2,P-3.

19 / 22

Page 20: Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1homepages.ulb.ac.be/~plegros/documents/classes/micro2/L1-Reviews.pdfGraduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1: Patrick Legros 1/22. What Should be KnownExpected

What Should be Known Expected Utility Measure of Risk Stochastic dominance Information partitions Common knowledge

Knowledge

E is known at ω if P(ω) ⊆ E“Knowledge” of E at state ω induces a set-theoretical definition of“to know” E .

K (E ) = ω|P(ω) ⊆ E

Note that K (E ) is an event, and can define K (K (E )),−K (E ) = Ω− K (E )etc.Definition implies

K-0 E ⊆ F ⇒ K (E ) ⊆ K (F ): K (E ∩ F ) = K (E ) ∩ K (F );K (Ω) = Ω

K-1, axiom of knowledge K (E ) ⊆ E

K-2, axiom of transparency K (E ) ⊆ K (K (E ))

K-3, axiom of wisdom −K (E ) ⊆ K (−K (E ))

20 / 22

Page 21: Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1homepages.ulb.ac.be/~plegros/documents/classes/micro2/L1-Reviews.pdfGraduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1: Patrick Legros 1/22. What Should be KnownExpected

What Should be Known Expected Utility Measure of Risk Stochastic dominance Information partitions Common knowledge

Common knowledge

Let K1,K2 be two knowledge operators for agents 1 and 2. Then,

Common Knowledge E is common knowledge between 1 and 2 inthe state ω if ω is a member of all sets of the typeK1(E ),K2(E ),K1(K2(E )),K2(K1(E )), · · ·

P1 = ω1, ω2, ω3, ω4, ω5, ω6, ω7, ω8P2 = ω1, ω2, ω3, ω4, ω5, ω6, ω7ω8

• E = ω1, ω2, ω3, ω4. Then E is not common knowledge atany ω.

• F = ω1, ω2, ω3, ω4, ω5. Then F is common knowledge inany state ωi , i = 1, · · · , 5

21 / 22

Page 22: Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1homepages.ulb.ac.be/~plegros/documents/classes/micro2/L1-Reviews.pdfGraduate Microeconomics II Lecture 1: Patrick Legros 1/22. What Should be KnownExpected

What Should be Known Expected Utility Measure of Risk Stochastic dominance Information partitions Common knowledge

No trade theorem

Consider two agents who:

• have the same prior beliefs on Ω

• have different information structures P1 and P2

• have a mutual understanding of the information structures

Question Is it possible that they have CK at some ω that agent 1believes that the expectation of a lottery L is strictly above α andthat agent 2 believes that the expectation of L is strictly below α?

If yes: exchange is acceptable to both agents. If no, no tradepossible. No if partitional information structures

22 / 22


Recommended