+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using...

Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using...

Date post: 24-Sep-2020
Category:
Upload: others
View: 0 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend
37
1 Individual Preference for Longshots Robin CHARK CHEW Soo Hong ZHONG Songfa * April 2018 Results from studies on risk taking behavior suggest that people tend to be risk seeking when making choices over lotteries that involve longshots: small probabilities of winning sizable payoffs. To investigate preferences over longshots systematically, we conduct an incentivized experiment using state lotteries in China each involving a single prize and fixed winning odds. This enables our construction of single-prize lotteries involving winning odds between 10 -5 and 10 -1 and winning prizes ranging from RMB10 (about USD1.60) to RMB10,000,000 across different expected payoffs. For lotteries with the lower expected payoffs of 1 and 10, subjects exhibit heterogeneous preference for longshot: some prefer the smallest winning probability while others favor intermediate winning probabilities. As the expected payoff increases to 100, subjects become predominantly risk averse, even for the lowest winning probability of 10 -5 . Our findings pose challenges for several non-expected utility models in the literature. Keywords: longshot risk, gambling, non-expected utility, prospect theory, rank dependent utility, betweenness, experiment JEL Code: C91, D81 * Chark: Faculty of Business, University of Macau, [email protected]. Chew: Department of Economics, National University of Singapore, [email protected]. Zhong: Department of Economics, National University of Singapore, [email protected]. We gratefully acknowledge financial support from the National University of Singapore.
Transcript
Page 1: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

1

Individual Preference for Longshots

Robin CHARK

CHEW Soo Hong

ZHONG Songfa*

April 2018

Results from studies on risk taking behavior suggest that people tend to be risk seeking when

making choices over lotteries that involve longshots: small probabilities of winning sizable

payoffs. To investigate preferences over longshots systematically, we conduct an incentivized

experiment using state lotteries in China each involving a single prize and fixed winning odds.

This enables our construction of single-prize lotteries involving winning odds between 10-5 and

10-1 and winning prizes ranging from RMB10 (about USD1.60) to RMB10,000,000 across

different expected payoffs. For lotteries with the lower expected payoffs of 1 and 10, subjects

exhibit heterogeneous preference for longshot: some prefer the smallest winning probability

while others favor intermediate winning probabilities. As the expected payoff increases to 100,

subjects become predominantly risk averse, even for the lowest winning probability of 10-5.

Our findings pose challenges for several non-expected utility models in the literature.

Keywords: longshot risk, gambling, non-expected utility, prospect theory, rank dependent

utility, betweenness, experiment

JEL Code: C91, D81

*Chark: Faculty of Business, University of Macau, [email protected]. Chew: Department of Economics,

National University of Singapore, [email protected]. Zhong: Department of Economics, National

University of Singapore, [email protected]. We gratefully acknowledge financial support from the

National University of Singapore.

Page 2: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

2

1. Introduction

Individuals exhibit risk seeking behavior when there is a small chance of winning a sizable

prize – this is apparent in gambling activities from casino games to racetrack betting. A stylized

observation that has emerged from racetrack betting is the favorite-longshot bias (Griffith,

1949). Bettors are inclined to overbet longshots (horses with a small chance of winning) and

underbet favorites (horses with a high probability of winning. This general observation is in

keeping with the fact that Lotto games, such as Hong Kong’s Mark Six and U.S.’s Powerball,

have reduced their winning odds over the years and this has been accompanied by

disproportionate increases in demand (Baucells and Yemen, 2017). These findings, however,

are generally drawn from aggregate data, and provide little systematic information about

individuals’ preference for longshots (Jullien and Salanié, 2000; Snowberg and Wolfers, 2010).

At the individual level, researchers have turned to hypothetical lotteries to avoid the possibility

of having to award sizable prizes. Overall, evidence from gambling data and hypothetical

experiments suggest that decision makers are risk seeking when facing small probabilities of

winning sizable gains. This behavior is regarded as one of the stylized observations in decision

making under risk (Tversky and Kahneman, 1992; Wakker, 2010).

Beyond aggregate data and hypothetical choice, we present the first experimental study

on individual preferences for longshots with extremely small probabilities and extremely large

prizes. Our longshot lotteries are constructed from three fixed-odds-fixed-outcome state lottery

products in China, namely, 1D, 3D, and 5D. Respectively, 1D, 3D, and 5D pay out a prize of

RMB10 with probability 10-1, RMB1,000 with probability 10-3, and RMB100,000 with

probability 10-5. For instance, we can create a lottery that pays RMB10,000,000 with winning

probability of 10-5 by purchasing 100 5D tickets all with the same winning number. The full

range of single-prize lotteries are constructed under one of three expected payoffs: RMB1, 10,

or 100, and have explicit winning odds of 10-1 to 10-5 and explicit prizes of RMB10 to

RMB10,000,000 (see Figure 1 below). This construction affords us a wide array of lotteries

with small probabilities of winning sizable prizes; and further allows us to finely characterize

the individuals’ preference over longshot risks. We conduct the experiment with a sample size

of 836 participants in China to make choices between pairs of lotteries that have the same

expected payoffs.

Page 3: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

3

Figure 1. Structure of lotteries used in our experiment

Note. Illustration of lotteries grouped under EV (expected value) = 1, EV = 10, and EV = 100 involving the

probabilities of 10-1, 10-2, 10-3, 10-4, and 10-5 and winning outcomes (in RMB) of 10, 102, 103, 104, 105, 106, and

107, using different combinations of 1D, 3D, and 5D tickets. Preferences for longshots can be investigated for a

given expected value, and for different expected value with either a fixed winning probability or a fixed winning

outcome.

We find strong support for longshot preference at expected payoffs of 1 and 10, but not

100. Moreover, we observe considerable heterogeneity in longshot preferences: monotonic

longshot preference that favor the smallest winning probability of 10-5, and single-peak

longshot preference that favor intermediate winning probabilities such as 10-3 and 10-1. As the

winning probability gets smaller at a specific expected payoff, risk attitude may not converge.

The intuition of favorite-longshot bias suggests that the smaller the winning probability, the

higher the value of the lottery. Yet, the decision maker may consider the winning probability

to be negligible at some point and end up favoring a lottery with an intermediate winning

probability.1 . In this regard, Kahneman and Tversky (1979) observe that “Because people are

limited in their ability to comprehend and evaluate extreme probabilities, highly unlikely events

are either ignored or overweighed…”

As expected payoffs increase from 1 to 100, we observe a general tendency to switch

from being risk seeking to risk averse in the following ways. First, the favored winning

probability tends to increase as the expected payoff increases. Second, this tendency to switch

remains regardless whether the winning probability or the winning outcome is fixed or when

1 Decades after Bernoulli’s original paper in 1728, Buffon (1777) suggests that the St. Petersburg paradox could

be resolved if people ignore small probabilities. Morgenstern (1979) suggests that expected utility was not

intended to model risk attitude for very small probabilities.

1.E-5

1.E-4

1.E-3

1.E-2

1.E-1

1.E+0

1.E+0 1.E+1 1.E+2 1.E+3 1.E+4 1.E+5 1.E+6 1.E+7

EV1

EV10

EV100

win

nin

g p

rob

abili

ty

1 101 102 103 104 105 106 107

10-5

10-4

10-3

10-2

10-1

1

winning outcome

Page 4: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

4

the same ratio of winning probabilities is maintained across pairs of lotteries with the same

winning outcomes. The latter switch in risk attitude corresponds to a form of common-ratio

Allais behaviour as illustrated in Kahneman and Tversky’s (1979): Subjects exhibit a

preference for a 90 percent chance of winning 3,000 over a 45 percent chance of winning 6,000,

but an ‘opposite’ preference for a 0.2 percent chance of winning 3,000 over a 0.1 percent

chance of winning 6,000.

Our observed behavioral patterns shed light on several non-expected utility models,

including rank-dependent utility (Quiggin, 1982) and betweenness-conforming models such as

weighted utility (Chew, 1983) and disappointment averse utility (Gul, 1991). Under these

models, preference over longshots depends on the interplay between the concavity of utility

function and the overweighting of winning probability. When the winning outcome is

sufficiently large, the tendency towards risk aversion from the concavity of the utility function

would dominate the tendency towards risk seeking from the overweighting of small probability.

This can lead to a preference for intermediate winning probabilities over the smallest winning

probability and a switch from being risk seeking to being risk averse as expected payoff

increases. In Section 4, we show that these models can exhibit the full range of longshot related

choice behavior using a concave utility function displaying eventually decreasing elasticity

coupled with their respective forms of overweighting of winning probabilities.

The paper proceeds as follows. Section 2 presents our experimental design. Properties

involving longshot preferences are defined in Section 3. Section 4 derives conditions under

which different utility models may exhibit specific preference properties. Section 5 presents

the experimental results in terms of observed choice patterns among lotteries with the same

expected payoffs and across different levels of expected payoffs. We discuss in Section 6 and

conclude in Section 7.

2. Experimental Design

We develop an experimental design using three kinds of single-prize fixed-odds state lotteries

in China known as 1D, 3D and 5D. A 1D ticket pays RMB10 if the buyer chooses a one-digit

number between 0 and 9 that matches a single winning number. Similarly, for 3D tickets, a

buyer chooses a three-digit number from 000 to 999 and wins RMB1,000 if the number matches

a single winning number. Likewise, a 5D ticket pays RMB100,000 if the buyer’s five-digit

number matches the winning number. The digit lottery tickets cost RMB2 each, and are on sale

daily, including weekends, through authorized outlets by two state-owned companies. The

China Welfare Lottery sells the 1D lottery and the China Sports Lottery sells both 3D and 5D

Page 5: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

5

lotteries. The winning numbers for each lottery are generated using Bingo blowers by

independent government agents and this process is telecast live daily at 8 p.m. Buyers may pick

their own numbers or have a computer generate random numbers at the sales outlet. Winning

tickets are cashed out at the lottery outlets.

Figure 1 in the Introduction presents the parametric structure of the single-prize lotteries

with different levels of winning probabilities and expected payoffs of 1, 10 and 100. We

construct lotteries with expected values 10 and 100 using different combinations of tickets. For

example, a lottery with 10-3 chance of winning 105 can come from 100 3D tickets with same

numbers while a lottery with 10-4 chance of winning 105 corresponds to ten 5D tickets with 10

different numbers.2 Notice that the combination of lotteries does not work for lotteries with

expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning

probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs of 1. We summarize the details of these lottery

products and how we generate the lotteries used in the experiment in Table A1 in Appendix B.

Overall, we include four lotteries with expected payoffs of 1, ten lotteries with expected payoffs

of 10, and ten lotteries with expected payoffs of 100. The preference relation is elicited by

pairwise comparison among lotteries with the same expected payoffs. This leads to a total of

96 binary choice comparisons: six at expected payoff 1, 45 at expected payoff 10, and 45 at

expected payoff 100. We also include four comparisons in which one choice stochastically

dominates the other to test for subjects’ engagement or attentiveness. (see Table A2 in

Appendix B for details).

In order to incentivize choices, ten percent of the subjects were randomly selected to be

compensated by receiving their chosen lottery from a randomly selected choice out of 100

choices made. The lottery was randomly chosen in the following ways. We add the subject’s

birthday (year, month, and date—eight numbers in total) to obtain its trailing digit. If this digit

is the same as the trailing digit from the sum of the winning number in the 3D Welfare lottery

on Feb 28, 2013, the subject will receive the additional compensation. Each randomly chooses

a number between 1 and 100, which determines the specific decision to be received whether it

is a sure amount of money or a lottery, in which case the subject will receive the corresponding

combination of lottery tickets purchased from a state lottery store. The theoretical and empirical

validity of this random lottery incentive has been a subject of debate (see, e.g., Starmer and

Sugden, 1991; Wakker, 2007; Freeman, Halevy, and Kneeland, 2015, for related discussions).

2 These combinations of different lottery tickets do not lead to compound lotteries (Halevy, 2007; Dean and

Ortoleva, 2014; Gillen, Snowberg, and Yariv, 2015), as the uncertainty is resolved in one stage. Moreover, after

they are explained how combinations work, to reduce complexity, subjects only see the winning probabilities and

winning outcomes when making choices.

Page 6: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

6

We adopt this incentive method in our current study because it is relatively simple and it offers

an efficient way to elicit subjects’ preferences thereby enabling the analysis of choice behavior

at the individual level.

The experiment is conducted in an internet-based setting. Running experiments online

has become increasingly common in experimental economics research. For example, Von

Gaudecker et al. (2008) compare laboratory and internet-based experiments, and show that the

observed differences arise more from sample selection rather than the mode of implementation.

Moreover, they find virtually no difference between the behavior of students in the lab and that

of young highly educated subjects in the internet-based experiments. Running an internet-based

experiment is convenient for collecting large samples, which could be helpful when conducting

individual level analysis. In our experiment, each choice is displayed separately on each screen,

as shown in Appendix D. We randomize the order of appearance of the 100 binary comparisons

as well as the order of appearance within each comparison. At the end of the experiment,

subjects answer questions about their demographics.

The potential subjects are Beijing-based university students (N = 1,282) whom we

recruited earlier for a large study. These subjects have previously received compensation from

participating in our experiments in both classroom and online settings, they are likely to have

greater trust in receiving their compensations for participating in our study. Email invitations

were sent and followed by two reminders over a two-month period. We ended up with a sample

of 836 subjects (50.0 percent females; average age = 21.8) with a response rate of 65 percent.

On average, subjects spent 19.3 minutes in the experiment. Each subject received RMB20 for

participating in the experiment. For reference, the students’ average monthly expenses were

about RMB1,200 based on survey data.

3. Properties involving Longshot Preferences

In our design, subjects choose between pairs of equal-mean lotteries (m/q, q) and (m/r, r) with

q > r, where (x, p) denotes a single-prize lottery paying x with probability p and paying 0 with

probability 1 – p. Receiving an amount x with certainty is denoted by [x]. We refer to a

preference for (m/q, q) over (m/r, r), denoted by (m/q, q) ≻ (m/r, r), as being risk averse, and

the opposite preference for (m/r, r) over (m/q, q), denoted by (m/q, q) ≺ (m/r, r), as being risk

seeking. We refer to a preference for [m] over (m/q, q) as risk averse towards (m/q, q), and a

preference for (m/q, q) over [m] as risk seeking towards (m/q, q).

Page 7: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

7

First, we are interested in the way risk attitudes may vary when the winning probability

p shrinks while the expected payoff is maintained at m. This idea is related to the favorite

longshot bias at an individual level in which the decision maker will increasingly value (m/p, p)

as p decreases towards 0 (Chew and Tan, 2005). We state this property formally below.

Property M. A decision maker exhibits monotonic longshot preference at m over (0, q] if

(m/q, q) ≻ [m] and (m/p, p) ≻ (m/p’, p’) with 0 < p < p’ < q.

In our experimental setting, should the decision maker be risk seeking towards a lottery

with 10-1 winning probability, the monotonic longshot preference property implies a preference

for the lottery with 10-5 winning probability over the lottery with 10-3 winning probability,

which is in turn preferred to the lottery with 10-1 winning probability, when all three lotteries

have the same expected payoff. Alternatively, the decision maker may have a favored winning

probability of p* at expected payoff m in being increasingly risk seeking as the winning

probability decreases from q to p*, and then switch to being increasingly risk averse as the

winning probability further decreases from p*. We state this single-peak property below.

Property SP. A decision maker exhibits single-peak longshot preference at m over (0, q] if

(m/q, q) ≻ [m] and there is a favored winning probability p* such that (m/p, p) ≻ (m/p’, p’) for

p* < p < p’ < q and (m/p’, p’) ≻ (m/p, p) for 0 < p < p’ < p*.

In the limit, as p* tends towards 0, single-peak longshot preference becomes monotonic

longshot preference, which relates to favorite longshot bias at the individual level. In our

experiment, single-peak longshot preference over (0, 10-1] is compatible with four choice

patterns: (i) one with 10-1 as the favored winning probability: (m/10-5, 10-5) ≺ (m/10-3, 10-3) ≺

(m/10-1, 10-1); (ii) two with 10-3 as the favored winning probability: (m/10-5, 10-5) ≺

(m/10-1, 1-1) ≺ (m/10-3, 10-3) and (m/10-1, 10-1) ≺ (m/10-5, 10-5) ≺ (m/10-3, 10-3); and (iii) one

with 10-5 as the favored winning probability: (m/10-1, 10-1) ≺ (m/10-3, 10-3) ≺ (m/10-5, 10-5).

Notice that case (iii) is observationally indistinguishable from monotonic longshot preference

over (0, 10-1].

Page 8: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

8

We say that a decision maker exhibits longshot preference at m over (0, q] if her

preference is either monotonic or single-peaked. We next investigate the potential tendency

towards risk aversion when the stake in terms of expected payoff increases. We examine this

tendency in three ways: (i) when the winning probability is fixed; (ii) when the winning

outcome is fixed; and (iii) when winning outcomes of pairs of lotteries are fixed so that the

ratio of winning probabilities remain the same. We state these tendencies formally as properties

below.

Property SA (Scale aversion). (i) The decision maker exhibits outcome scale aversion at

probability q if there is an m* such that (m/q, q) ≻ [m] for m < m* and (m/q, q) ≺ [m] for

m > m*. (ii) The decision maker exhibits probability scale aversion at outcome x if there is an

m* such that (x, m/x) ≻ [m] for m < m* and (x, m/x) ≺ [m] for m > m*. (iii) The decision maker

exhibits common-ratio scale aversion at outcomes H > L if there is an m* such that (H, m/H)

≻ (L, m/L) for m < m* and (H, m/H) ≺ (L, m/L) for m > m*.

Relatedly, the intuition behind scale aversion suggests that the favored winning

probability itself would increase as the expected payoff increases. In our setting, a decision

maker who is risk seeking towards lottery (103, 10-3) may become risk averse towards lottery

(105, 10-3) due to outcome scale aversion, or become risk averse towards lottery (103, 10-1)

arising from probability scale aversion. On the other hand, a decision maker who is risk seeking

towards (m/q, q) would need to remain risk seeking towards (m’/q, q) for m’ > m. For example,

if the decision maker is risk seeking towards (103, 10-1), the decision maker will also be risk

seeking towards lottery (103, 10-3) as well as lottery (10, 10-1). Notice that pure risk aversion

or pure risk seeking for our three levels of expected payoffs is observationally indistinguishable

from outcome scale aversion or probability scale aversion.

From the definition of common-ratio scale aversion above, comparing risk attitude

towards two pairs of equal-mean lotteries with the same ratio L/H of winning probabilities, i.e.,

(L, m/L) and (H, m/H) versus (L, m’/L) and (H, m’/H) with m’ > m yields four possible choice

patterns: (i) risk seeking for both pairs; (ii) risk averse for both pairs; (iii) risk seeking for the

lower expected payoff comparison and risk averse for the higher expected payoff comparison;

(iv) risk averse for the lower expected payoff comparison and risk seeking for the higher

expected payoff comparison. Expected utility is compatible with the first two patterns but not

the third pattern, commonly known as the common-ratio Allais paradox, and the fourth pattern

referred to as reverse Allais behavior. For example, being risk seeking between (103, 10-3) and

(105, 10-5) coupled with being risk averse between (103, 10-1) and (105, 10-2) represents an

instance of common-ratio Allais behaviour.

Page 9: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

9

4. Implications of Utility Models In this section, we investigate the conditions under which different utility models can exhibit

the various properties of longshot preference. It is known that the expected utility model (EU)

cannot exhibit Allais behavior arising from common-ratio scale aversion, and also cannot

exhibit preference for longshots when concave utility function is imposed. We consider several

commonly used non-expected utility models in the literature including rank-dependent utility

(RDU – Quiggin, 1982) and two forms of betweenness utility: weighted utility (WU – Chew,

1983) and disappointment aversion utility (DAU – Gul, 1991).

For a lottery (m/p, p) paying outcome m/p with probability p, its RDU is given by

w(p)u(m/p), where u is a continuous and increasing utility function and w is a continuous and

increasing probability weighting function which maps [0, 1] to [0,1] such that w(0) = 0 and

w(1) = 1. We list below several forms of wfunctions in the literature:

pc/[pc+(1 – p)c]1/c Tversky and Kahneman (1992)

pd/[pd+(1 – p)d] Goldstein and Einhorn (1987)

exp{–[–ln p]} Prelec (1998)

To model longshot related preference properties in conjunction with a concave utility function,

the probability weighting function is initially concave and overweights small probabilities.3

DAU and WU both belong to the class of preferences satisfying the betweenness axiom

which represents an important weakening of the independence axiom. In our setting of single-

prize lotteries, the DAU of (x, p) is given by pu(x)/(p + λ(1-p)). This coincides with RDU using

the Goldstein-Einhorn (1987) probability weighting function with = 1/and d (see

Abdellaoui and Bleichrodt, 2007). It follows that DAU exhibits longshot related preference

properties which are similar to RDU. The WU of a single-prize lottery (m/p, p) is given by

ps(m/p)u(x)/[ps(m/p) + 1 – p], where s is a continuous and positive valued salience function

defined over outcomes. The winning probability is overweighted, when s is increasing. In

contrast with RDU, the degree of overweighting of the winning probability increases with the

magnitude of the winning outcome when s is an increasing function.

Under the models discussed, the preference for single-prize longshots depends on the

interplay between the concavity of the utility of large winning prize and overweighting of small

winning probability. Table 1 displays the conditions under which these two utility models can

3 The special case where d = 1 reduces to the form of probability weighting function in Rachlin, Raineri, and

Cross (1991) given by (1 + (1 – p)/p)–1 with being interpreted in terms of hyperbolic discounting of the

odds (1 – p)/p against yourself winning. See Section 7.2 of Wakker (2010) for a comprehensive review of different

forms of probability weighting functions.

Page 10: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

10

exhibit the various longshot related preference properties using a concave u function with

eventually declining elasticity coupled with appropriate conditions. Specifically, RDU and

WU can each exhibit monotonic as well as single-peak longshot preference in which the

favored winning probability is increasing with expected payoff, along with scale aversion in

both outcome and probability.

The limiting case of a power utility function with constant elasticity merits special

attention. In this case, RDU can exhibit single-peak longshot preference but the corresponding

favored winning probability is independent of the expected payoff. While it implies constant

relative risk aversion and is compatible with probability scale aversion, yet it is not compatible

with outcome scale aversion. By comparison, WU can exhibit the full range of longshot related

preference properties except for outcome scale aversion given that s is an increasing function.

The derivation of the conditions summarized in Table 1 are provided in the appendix A.

Table 1. Conditions on utility models to exhibit longshot preference related properties

Property

RDU WU

Eventually

decreasing

u-elasticity

Constant

u-elasticity

Eventually

decreasing

u-elasticity

Constant

u-elasticity

Monotonic longshot Y N Y Y

Single-peak longshot Y Ya Y Y

Outcome scale aversion Y N Y Nb

Probability scale aversion Y Y Y Y

Common-ratio scale aversion Y Y Y Y

Note. a. favored winning probability is fixed. b. Incompatible with an increasing s function.

5. Results

In this section, we report the observed choice behavior among lotteries with the same expected

payoffs of 1, 10, and 100 as well as comparisons of risk attitudes elicited at different expected

payoffs. Table 2 presents the aggregate proportions of risk seeking choice at the three levels of

expected payoffs. At expected payoff 1, subjects are generally risk seeking, except for being

risk averse between 10-3 and 10-5. In particular, the winning probability of 10-3 seems favored

since (103, 10-3) tends to be chosen over [1], (10, 10-1), and (105, 10-5). At expected payoff 10,

subjects are generally risk seeking relative to receiving the expected payoff with certainty and

risk averse between pairs of lotteries. At expected payoff 100, subjects are predominantly risk

averse.

Page 11: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

11

Table 2. Proportion of risk seeking choice at each level of expected payoff.

Winning probability Proportion of risk seeking choice (%)

Higher Lower EV = 1 EV = 10 EV = 100

1 10-1 75.8 60.2 19.6

1 10-2 - 55.0 18.5

1 10-3 80.3 55.3 16.0

1 10-4 - 52.8 14.5

1 10-5 79.8 51.9 14.5

10-1 10-2 - 33.3 24.7

10-1 10-3 61.5 35.2 17.6

10-1 10-4 - 31.3 19.3

10-1 10-5 63.3 32.3 17.8

10-2 10-3 - 29.7 28.6

10-2 10-4 - 27.5 24.5

10-2 10-5 - 28.5 24.5

10-3 10-4 - 37.8 38.0

10-3 10-5 40.3 39.1 32.8

10-4 10-5 - 43.8 41.1

Note. Column 1 (2) presents the winning probability for the lottery with the higher (lower) probability. Columns

3, 4, and 5 display the proportions of risk seeking choice under the three levels of expected payoffs of EV = 1,

EV = 10, and EV = 100 respectively.

At the aggregate level, observe that subjects tend to be risk seeking for lotteries with

smaller expected payoffs and switch to being risk averse as expected payoff increases. This

leads us to organize our results in two ways: First, when expected payoff is fixed, we examine

the extent to which subjects may possess monotonic or single-peak longshot preference.

Second, we study subjects’ switching behavior from being risk seeking to being risk averse as

expected payoff increases.

5.1. Preference within the same expected payoff

For each of expected payoffs of 1, 10, and 100, Figure 2 displays the corresponding frequencies

of different choice patterns: single-peak longshot behavior at 10-5, 10-3 and 10-1, purely risk

averse choice behavior, and other transitive patterns classified as “transitive-others” alongside

those exhibiting intransitive choice. To facilitate comparisons with the observed choice

frequencies, we present the corresponding chance rate for each type of choice pattern.4 At

4 To compare across three levels of expected payoffs, we focus on choice patterns involving probabilities 1, 10-1,

10-3, and 10-5, and denote the transitive choice patterns in an ascending order (e.g., 1053 refers to 10-3 ≻ 10-5 ≻ 1

≻ 10-1) (see Table A3 in Appendix B for the list). For each level of expected payoff, more than 80% of the subjects

exhibit transitive choice patterns (see Appendix C for detailed discussions on intransitive choice patterns). Of

twenty four transitive choice patterns, thirteen are single-peak, including seven over (0, 10-1], four over (0, 10-3],

and two over (0, 10-5]. Six are purely risk averse—1350, 1530, 3150, 3510, 5130, and 5310. For the remaining

five patterns under “Others”, 10-3 is worse than 10-1 as well as 10-5. We test whether the observed frequency is

significantly different from the chance rate in Table A4 in Appendix B.

Page 12: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

12

expected payoff 1, 65.6 percent of the subjects exhibit single-peak longshot preference patterns

while only 12.3 percent are purely risk averse. Among those with single-peak preferences, the

observed frequency is higher than the corresponding chance rate for each favored winning

probability at 10-5, 10-3 and 10-1 (proportion test, p < 0.001). At expected payoff 10, 44.0

percent exhibit single-peak preferences while 29.7 percent are purely risk averse. Among those

with single-peak preferences, the observed frequency is higher than the corresponding chance

rate for each of the favored winning probabilities of 10-5 and 10-1 (proportion test, p < 0.001).

At expected payoff 100, a substantial majority of 68.3 percent are purely risk averse while only

13.8 percent have single-peak preferences. Among those with single-peak preferences, the

observed frequency remains significantly higher than the corresponding chance rate only for

the favored winning probability of 10-1 (proportion test, p < 0.001).5

Summarizing, we have the following overall observation of longshot preferences

involving equal-mean comparisons.

Observation 1. Subjects exhibit significant incidences of both single-peak longshot preference

and monotonic longshot preference for lower expected payoffs, and they exhibit less longshot

preference as expected payoffs increase.

Figure 2. Frequencies of individual longshot preferences

Note. This figure plots the frequencies of individual longshot preferences including single-peak at 10-5, 10-3, and

10-1 (delineated with thickened borders), purely risk averse choice, other transitive choice, and intransitive

choice across expected payoffs (EV) of 1, 10, and 100, compared to the chance rate.

5 We include an additional analysis with 10-2, and 10-4 lotteries. Observe that the proportions of subjects with

transitive preference is 38.16% for EV10 and 54.78% for EV100. This supports the observed low frequency of

intransitivity relative to the chance rate of 97.8%. Observe also that the proportions of risk averse subjects are

20.57% for EV10 and 48.33% for EV100. These are consistent with the switch from being risk seeking to being

risk averse as expected payoff increases. Proportions which are too small to be displayed in Figure 2 are presented

in Table A5 in the Appendix.

0%

10%

20%

30%

40%

50%

60%

70%

80%

90%

100%

EV=1 EV=10 EV=100 Chance rate

Perc

enta

ge

Peak at 10^-5

Peak at 10^-3

Peak at 10^-1

Risk averse

Others transitive

Intransitive

10-3

10-5

10-1

Page 13: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

13

5.2. Preferences across expected payoffs

This subsection investigates the following longshot properties as the expected payoff increases

(i) migration pattern of favored winning probabilities; (ii) outcome scale aversion and

probability scale aversion; and (iii) common-ratio scale aversion.

Figure 3. Migration of favored winning probabilities across expected payoffs

Note. Panel A shows the migration pattern of subjects migrating from being risk averse, denoted by “Peak at 1”,

or having single-peak longshot preference at 10-1, 10-3, or 10-5 at expected payoffs of 1 to being risk averse, or

have single-peak longshot preference at 10-1, 10-3, or 10-5 at expected payoffs of 10. Panel B and Panel C show

the corresponding migration patterns from expected payoffs of 10 to expected payoffs of 100, and from expected

payoffs of 1 to expected payoffs of 100, respectively.

Migration pattern of favored winning probabilities. To investigate the migration pattern of

favored winning probabilities as the expected payoff increases, we examine the behaviors for

those subjects who either are purely risk averse or have single-peak longshot preferences.

Figure 3 presents the migration pattern across expected payoffs of 1 and 10 (Panel A), across

expected payoffs of 10 and 100 (Panel B), and across expected payoffs of 1 and 100 (Panel C).

More specifically, of 165 subjects who favor 10-3 at expected payoff 1, only about one third

0%

50%

100%

Peak at 1Peak at 10-1

Peak at 10-3

Peak at 10-5

0%

50%

100%

Peak at 1Peak at 10-1

Peak at 10-3

Peak at 10-5

0%

50%

100%

Peak at 1Peak at 10-1

Peak at 10-3

Peak at 10-5

Per

cen

tage

C

B

A

Per

cen

tage

Per

cen

tage

Page 14: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

14

continue to do so at expected payoff 10. A strong majority switch to the higher winning

probability of 10-1 or become risk averse. Of 86 subjects favoring 10-1 at expected payoff 1,

majority of them become risk averse at expected payoff 10. By contrast, for the 99 subjects

who are risk averse at expected payoff 1, almost all of them remain risk averse at expected

payoff 10. Similar patterns are observed between expected payoffs 10 and 100, as well as

between expected payoffs 1 and 100. Overall, we observe that the favored winning probabilities

increase as expected payoffs increase (see Table A6 in Online Appendix B for details).

Figure 4. Switching towards risk aversion as the expected payoff increases

Note. This figure displays the percentages of different scale averse choice patterns across the three levels of

expected payoffs: SSS (risk seeking at all three levels of expected payoffs), SSA (risk seeking at expected payoffs

of 1 and 10, and risk averse at expected payoff 100), SAA (risk seeking at expected payoff 1, and risk averse at

expected payoffs of 10 and 100), and AAA (risk averse at all three levels of expected payoffs), and “Others” (the

other four patterns), when fixing the winning probability as 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5, as well as fixing the winning

outcome as 103 and 105, respectively.

Outcome scale aversion and probability scale aversion. To examine the property of outcome

scale aversion, we examine risk attitudes relative to expected payoffs while fixing the winning

probability across the three levels of expected payoffs successively. In parallel, to examine the

property of probability scale aversion, the winning outcome is fixed at 103 and 105 as the winning

probability varies between 10-5 and 10-1. In each case, there are eight possible choice patterns

given that there are three comparisons between a lottery and receiving its expected payoff with

certainty. Of these, four are compatible with the tendency of a switch from being risk seeking

to being risk averse as the expected payoff increases: (i) risk seeking across all three levels of

expected payoffs; (ii) risk seeking at expected payoffs of 1 and 10, and risk averse at expected

payoff 100; (iii) risk seeking at expected payoff 1, and risk averse at expected payoffs of 10

and 100; and (iv) risk averse across all three levels of expected payoffs. The four remaining

0%

10%

20%

30%

40%

50%

60%

70%

80%

90%

100%

P=10^-1 P=10^-3 P=10^-5 X=10^3 X=10^5

Perc

etan

ge

SSS

SSA

SAA

AAA

Others

p = 10-1 p = 10-3 p = 10-5 x = 103 x = 105

Page 15: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

15

patterns, grouped under “Others”, allow for the opposite tendency to switch from being risk

averse to being risk seeking as expected payoff increases. The proportion of each choice pattern

is summarized in Figure 4, which is derived from Table A7 in Appendix B. We see that the

bulk of our subjects tend to switch from being risk seeking to being risk averse as expected

payoff increases—57.9 percent (with p = 10-1), 63.4 percent (with p = 10-3), 65.5 percent (with

p = 10-5), 61.5 percent (with x = 103), and 64.4 percent (with x = 105).

Common-ratio scale aversion. We examine common-ratio Allais behavior (relating to

common-ratio scale aversion as defined in section 3) and their corresponding frequencies for

14 instances (see Table 3 for details). The observed incidence of Allais choice pattern ranges

from 13.6 percent to 27.4 percent.6 We investigate whether the observed patterns of EU

violations are systematic using Conlisk’s (1989) test which takes expected utility as the null

hypothesis, and compares the frequencies of Allais and reverse Allais behavior. Taking the 14

comparisons in Table 3 together, we find Allais violations to be more pronounced than reverse

Allais behavior (Z = 27.17, p < 0.001). For these 14 comparisons, the proportion of each Allais

pattern is significant at p < 0.003, suggesting that violations of expected utility are pervasive

for longshot lotteries.

We further test for the possible presence of a certainty effect (Kahneman and Tversky,

1979) by comparing the incidence of Allais behavior in the presence of a sure outcome with its

incidence without a sure outcome. Across the expected payoffs of 100 and 10, we find that the

incidence of 20.1% for Allais behaviour involving 100 as sure outcome (Items 3 – 6) is

significantly higher (D = 1.93, p < 0.03) than the incidence of 16.4% for Allais behavior not

involving sure outcomes (Items 8 – 13). Focusing instead on expected payoffs of 10 and 1, we

find that the incidence of 16.4% for Allais behaviour involving 10 as sure outcome (Items 1

and 2) is not significantly different (D = -1.19, p > 0.1) from the incidence of 18.5% for Allais

behavior not involving sure outcomes (Item 7).

6 This is in line with what is reported in the literature based generally on moderate probabilities (i.e., Conlisk,

1989; Cubitt, Starmer and Sugden, 1998; List and Haigh, 2005; Huck and Muller, 2012; Nebout and Dubois,

2014). For instance, Conlisk (1989) observes that the proportion of individual-level Allais pattern is 43.6 percent

for his basic treatment and 10.8 percent for his three-step treatment. List and Haigh (2005) find the proportion of

such patterns to be 43 percent among student subjects and only 13 percent among professional traders. More

recently, with a sample of 1424, Huck and Muller (2012) report the proportion of Allais behavior to be 49.4

percent in a high hypothetical-payoff treatment, 19.6 percent in a low hypothetical-payoff treatment, and 25.6

percent in a low real-payoff treatment

Page 16: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

16

Table 3. Incidence of common-ratio Allais choice behavior

Item High EV Low EV Allais Reverse

Allais

1 [10] vs (103,10-2) (10,10-1) vs (103,10-3) 15.6% 9.1%

2 [10] vs (105,10-4) (10,10-1) vs (105,10-5) 17.1% 6.6%

3 [102] vs (103,10-1) (102,10-1) vs (103,10-2) 20.7% 7.1%

4 [102] vs (104,10-2) (102,10-1) vs (104,10-3) 20.9% 4.3%

5 [102] vs (105,10-3) (102,10-1) vs (105,10-4) 18.3% 3.0%

6 [102] vs (106,10-4) (102,10-1) vs (106,10-5) 20.3% 2.5%

7 (103,10-2) vs (105,10-4) (103,10-3) vs (105,10-5) 18.5% 5.7%

8 (103,10-1) vs (104,10-2) (103,10-2) vs (104,10-3) 15.0% 10.0%

9 (103,10-1) vs (105,10-3) (103,10-2) vs (105,10-4) 15.7% 5.7%

10 (103,10-1) vs (106,10-4) (103,10-2) vs (106,10-5) 15.1% 6.0%

11 (104,10-2) vs (105,10-3) (104,10-3) vs (105,10-4) 18.5% 9.3%

12 (104,10-2) vs (106,10-4) (104,10-3) vs (106,10-5) 20.7% 6.1%

13 (105,10-3) vs (106,10-4) (105,10-4) vs (106,10-5) 13.6% 7.9%

14 (103,10-1) vs (105,10-3) (103,10-3) vs (105,10-5) 27.4% 4.7%

Note. The first column numbers the common-ratio Allais cases. The next two columns present the pairs of high

expected payoff and low expected payoff lotteries. The last two columns display the corresponding rates of Allais

and reverse Allais behavior. The first six common-ratio comparisons each involve a sure outcome for the high

expected payoff lottery while the remaining eight comparisons all do not involve any sure outcomes.

Summarizing, we have the following overall observation.

Observation 2. Subjects switch from being risk seeking to being risk averse as expected payoff

increases. (A) For subjects exhibiting single-peak longshot preference, the favored winning

probability tends to increase with an increase in the expected payoff; (B) Subjects exhibit

outcome scale aversion and probability scale aversion in switching from being risk seeking to

being risk averse as the expected payoff increases when either the winning outcome or the

winning probability is fixed; (C) Subjects exhibit systematic equal-mean common-ratio Allais

behavior for small probabilities.

6. Discussion

Theoretical Implications. The two observations summarized above help discriminate among

possible specifications of the different utility models in choice under risk. Using a concave

utility function with decreasing elasticity, both RDU and WU can account for the main

observations of our experiment through different approaches to overweighting of the winning

probability. RDU overweighs directly with a probability weighting function which is initially

concave. For WU, the higher the winning outcome, the more WU overweighs the winning

probability given an increasing salience function defined on outcomes. In the limiting case of

Page 17: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

17

a power utility function with constant elasticity, these two models differ in their implications.

Here, RDU is compatible with outcome scale aversion but not with probability scale aversion.

While RDU can exhibit single-peak longshot preference, the favored winning odds being fixed

does not accord well with the migratory pattern. By contrast, WU can exhibit a fuller range of

longshot preference behavior; however, WU is not compatible with outcome scale aversion

when the salience function is increasing.

Preference for longshots in gambling. Our results shed light on the understanding of gambling

behavior and the working of gaming markets. Since Griffith (1949), one of the most well-

known phenomena in betting market is the favorite longshot bias in which the expected return

from betting on favorites exceeds the expected return from betting on longshots (see Sobel and

Ryan, 2008 for a recent review). Despite its extensive occurrence in the literature, there are

some exceptions. For example, Busche and Hall (1988) find no evidence for favorite longshot

bias using data from racetracks in Hong Kong. Subsequently, Busche (1994) identifies a

reverse favorite longshot bias in Japanese and Hong Kong racetrack markets, which have much

more sizable betting volumes than those in US and Europe. Moreover, there is no known

evidence for favorite longshot bias in Asian markets. Taken together, these findings point to a

potential cultural difference in preference towards longshots, which is of interest for future

studies.

To account for the phenomenon of favorite-longshot bias, researchers have offered

theoretical accounts based on asymmetric information (Ali, 1977; Shin, 1991), heterogeneity

in bettors’ behavior (Hurley and McDonough, 1995; Ottaviani and Sørensen 2006),

misperception of winning probability and probability weighting (Griffith, 1949; Jullien and

Salanié, 2000; Snowberg and Wolfers, 2010), and bettors being generally risk seeking (Quandt,

1996; Golec and Tamarkin, 1998). Barseghyan, Molinari, and O'Donoghue (2013) note that

the estimation of winning odds relies on aggregate data, and cannot differentiate between

estimating the winning probability versus weighting the winning probability. In our

experimental setting, using fixed-odds-fixed-outcome lotteries enables a focus on nonlinear

probability weighting rather than an estimation of probability in accounting for the observed

choice behavior.

Our findings of a greater incidence of single-peak longshot preference over monotonic

longshot preference suggests a limit to the favorite-longshot bias phenomenon. This may

conceivably be reflected in the design of racetrack betting in terms of the number of horses in

a typical race and the range of winning odds available. The presence of 1D, 3D, and 5D lottery

tickets in China also reveals heterogeneity in the demand for lottery products in terms of

Page 18: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

18

favorite winning probabilities. Interestingly, based on a report on sales of lottery products in

China from Caitong Consultancy, a lottery research institute of sina.com, the 2015 annual sales

for 3D lottery tickets is RMB20.5 billion compared to RMB3.2 billion for 5D lottery tickets,

suggesting that many lottery purchasers do not favor 10-5. Moreover, while the rules for

Powerball in the U.S. have been gradually changed towards drastically smaller winning odds,

the odds for the jackpot were increased slightly to 1: 175,223,509, with a decrease in the

number of red balls from 39 to 35 in 2012. This development corroborates the idea of a limit

to the reach of the favorite-longshot bias, with lottery commissions settling for a less extreme

longshot probability of winning the jackpot. Relatedly, the strong incidence of longshot

preference at expected payoffs of 1 and 10 but not 100 corroborates a general observation about

lottery ticket pricing. Lottery tickets tend to be priced low; scaling up the price together with

their prizes may not pay.

Preference for longshots in other markets. In financial markets, it has been suggested that a

positively skewed security can be “overpriced” and earn a negative average excess return (see,

e.g., Kraus and Litzenberger, 1976). Moreover, the preference for skewed securities may be

related to a number of financial phenomena such as the low long-term average return on IPO

stock and the low average return on distressed stocks (Barberis and Huang, 2008). In the

insurance market, it has been commonly suggested that the demand for insurance could be

driven by the overweighting of small probabilities of large losses. Kunreuther and Pauly (2003)

argue that people often ignore extremely small probabilities, leading to underpurchasing of

insurance for disasters. Relatedly, McClelland, Schulze, and Coursey (1993) propose that some

people fully ignore small probabilities while other people overweight them. The literature

further suggests that people tend to be more pessimistic as stakes increase (see, e.g., Etchart-

Vincent, 2004; Barseghyan, Molinari, and O'Donoghue, 2013). It is natural to ask whether we

may observe the counterparts in these settings, especially when the losses are extremely large

(Kahneman and Tversky, 1979; Barberis, 2013). Would we find single-peak preference in

insuring longshot hazards? Is there a stake-size effect in attitude towards longshot in financial

markets? Further research towards addressing these questions may help shed light on the

understanding of investment behavior and the design of insurance policies.

Page 19: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

19

7. Conclusion

Using state lotteries in China, we conduct an incentivized experiment, and arrive at two

observations. First, for lotteries with lower expected payoffs, subjects exhibit heterogeneous

preference for longshots: some prefer the smallest winning probability while others favor

intermediate winning probabilities. Second, subjects tend to switch from being risk seeking at

low expected payoff to being risk averse at high expected payoff. These two observations

contrast with the existing literature that people tend to be risk seeking when facing longshots,

and that there is a further tendency within this group to favor bets with smaller winning

probabilities for the same expected payoff. Overall, our study suggests that the tendency

towards risk aversion from the overall concavity of the utility function over sizable outcomes

can dominate eventually the tendency towards risk seeking from the overweighting of small

probability.

References

Abdellaoui, M., & Bleichrodt, H. (2007). “Eliciting Gul’s theory of disappointment aversion

by the tradeoff method.” Journal of Economic Psychology, 28(6): 631-645.

Ali, MM. "Probability and utility estimates for racetrack bettors." The Journal of Political

Economy (1977): 803-815.

Barberis, N, and M Huang (2008). "Stocks as Lotteries: The Implications of Probability

Weighting for Security Prices." American Economic Review 98.5: 2066-2100.

Barseghyan, L, F Molinari, and T O'Donoghue (2013). "The nature of risk preferences:

Evidence from insurance choices." American Economic Review 103.6: 2499-2529.

Baucells, M, and G Yemen (2017). "Powerball: Somebody's Gotta Win!." Darden Case No.

UVA-QA-0857.

Buffon, G-L L (1777) “Essai d’arithmétique morale.” in Supplément à l’historie naturelle IV,

reproduced in Unautre Buffon, Hermann (1977): 47-59.

Busche, K. and CD Hall (1988). “An exception to the risk preference anomaly”. Journal of

Business, pp.337-346.

Busche, K (1994). “Efficient Market Results in an Asian Setting.” In Efficiency of Racetrack

Betting Markets, eds. Hausch D, V Lo, and WT. Ziemba, pp. 615-616 New York:

Academic Press.

Chew SH (1983). "A generalization of the quasilinear mean with applications to the

measurement of income inequality and decision theory resolving the Allais paradox."

Econometrica: 1065-1092.

Chew SH (1989). "Axiomatic utility theories with the betweenness property." Annals of

operations Research 19.1: 273-298.

Chew SH, and G Tan (2005). "The market for sweepstakes." Review of Economic Studies 72:

1009-1029.

Conlisk, J (1989). "Three variants on the Allais example." American Economic Review: 392-

407.

Cubitt, RP, C Starmer, and R Sugden. "On the validity of the random lottery incentive system."

Experimental Economics 1 (1998): 115-131.

Dean, M., and P Ortoleva (2015). “Is it all connected? a testing ground for unified theories of

behavioral economics phenomena.” Working Paper.

Page 20: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

20

Dekel, E (1986). "An axiomatic characterization of preferences under uncertainty: Weakening

the independence axiom." Journal of Economic Theory 40: 304-318.

Etchart-Vincent, N (2004). "Is probability weighting sensitive to the magnitude of

consequences? An experimental investigation on losses." Journal of Risk and

Uncertainty 28: 217-235.

Freeman, D, Y Halevy, and T Kneeland (2015). “Eliciting Risk Preferences Using Choice

Lists”, working paper.

Gillen, B., E Snowberg, and L Yariv (2015). “Experimenting with measurement error:

techniques with applications to the Caltech cohort study” (No. w21517). National

Bureau of Economic Research.

Goldstein, WM., and HJ Einhorn (1987). "Expression theory and the preference reversal

phenomena." Psychological Review 94.2: 236.

Golec, J and M Tamarkin (1998). "Bettors love skewness, not risk, at the horse track." Journal

of Political Economy 106: 205-225.

Griffith, RM (1949). "Odds adjustments by American horse-race bettors." American Journal

of Psychology 62: 290—294.

Gul, F (1991). "A theory of disappointment aversion." Econometrica: 667-686.

Huck, S and W Müller (2012). "Allais for all: Revisiting the paradox in a large representative

sample." Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 44.3: 261-293.

Halevy, Y. (2007). “Ellsberg revisited: An experimental study.” Econometrica, 75(2), 503-536.

Hurley, W and L McDonough. "A note on the Hayek hypothesis and the favourite-longshot

bias in parimutuel betting." American Economic Review (1995): 949-955.

Jullien, B and B Salanié. "Estimating preferences under risk: The case of racetrack bettors."

Journal of Political Economy 108 (2000): 503-530.

Kahneman, D and A Tversky (1979). "Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk."

Econometrica: 263-291.

Kraus, A and RH Litzenberger (1976). "Skewness preference and the valuation of risk assets."

Journal of Finance 31: 1085-1100.

Kunreuther, H and M Pauly (2005). "Terrorism Losses and All Perils Insurance." Journal of

Insurance Regulation 23.4: 3.

List, JA and MS Haigh (2005). "A simple test of expected utility theory using professional

traders." Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 102.3: 945-948.

McClelland, GH., WD. Schulze, and DL Coursey (1993). "Insurance for low-probability

hazards: A bimodal response to unlikely events." Journal of risk and uncertainty 7.1:

95-116.

Morgenstern, O (1979). “Some reflections on utility”. Expected utility hypotheses and the

Allais Paradox. Allais and O Hagen (eds.), Dordrecht, Holland: Reidel.

Nebout, A., & Dubois, D. (2014). When Allais meets Ulysses: Dynamic axioms and the

common ratio effect. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 48(1), 19-49.

Ottaviani, M and PN Sørensen. "The strategy of professional forecasting." Journal of Financial

Economics 81 (2006): 441-466

Ottaviani, M and PN Sørensen (2008). "The favourite-longshot bias: an overview of the main

explanations." Handbook of Sports and Lottery Markets (eds. Hausch and Ziemba),

North-Holland/Elsevier: 83-102.

Prelec, D (1998). "The probability weighting function." Econometrica: 497-527.

Quandt, RE. "Betting and equilibrium." Quarterly Journal of Economics 101 (1986): 201-207.

Quiggin, J (1982). "A theory of anticipated utility." Journal of Economic Behavior and

Organization 3: 323-343.

Rachlin, H, A Raineri, and D Cross (1991). “Subjective probability and delay”. J Exp Anal

Behav. 55: 233–244.

Page 21: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

21

Shin, HS. "Optimal betting odds against insider traders." Economic Journal 101, (1991): 1179-

1185.

Starmer, C and R Sugden (1991). "Does the random-lottery incentive system elicit true

preferences? An experimental investigation." American Economic Review: 971-978.

Snowberg, E and J Wolfers. Explaining the favourite-longshot bias: Is it risk-love or

misperceptions? Journal of Political Economy 118.4 (2010). 723-746.

Topkis, DM (1998). Supermodularity and Complementarity, Princeton

Tversky, A and D Kahneman (1992). "Advances in prospect theory: Cumulative representation

of uncertainty." Journal of Risk and uncertainty 5: 297-323.

Von Gaudecker, HM, AV Soest, and E Wengstrom (2011). "Heterogeneity in risky choice

behavior in a broad population." American Economic Review 101: 664-694.

Wakker PP (2007). "Message to referees who want to embark on yet another discussion of the

random-lottery incentive system for individual choice".

http://people.few.eur.nl/wakker/miscella/debates/randomlinc.htm.

Wakker, PP (2010). Prospect theory: For risk and ambiguity. Cambridge.

Page 22: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

22

Appendix A. Derivations for Claims in Table 1

This appendix provides details and derivations of the conditions on the class of u functions

with decreasing elasticity shared between RDU and WU and on the w and s functions for the

respective models to exhibit monotonic versus single-peak losngshot preference and scale

aversion in outcome and in probability as illustrated in Table 1. The case of a power u function

with constant elasticity is treated separately for both models.

Rank-dependent Utility (RDU)

To derive the condition for properties relating to longshot preference over probabilities

between (0, q], consider the following maximization problem for RDU:

𝑚𝑎𝑥𝑝∈(0,𝑞]

𝑤(𝑝)𝑢(𝑚/𝑝). (1)

Monotonic longshot preference. It is straightforward to verify that the maximand in (1) is

strictly decreasing if the utility elasticity u(m/p) given by (m/p)u’(m/p)/u(m/p) always exceeds

the probability weighting elasticity w(p) given by pw’(p)/w(p). For example, the elasticity

of a power utility function x may be uniformly greater than the elasticity of a piecewise linear

= a + bp, which increases from 0 to b/(a + b).

Single-peak longshot preference. The first-order condition for (1) is given by the equality

between the probability weighting elasticity w(p) and the utility elasticity u(m/p). This yields

a sufficient condition for the solution p* to be unique over (0, q]: w(p) is decreasing in p and

u(m/p) is increasing in p, corresponding to u(y) being decreasing in y, e.g., an exponential

utility. To obtain a comparative statics condition so that the favored winning probability p*

increases as expected payoff m increases, we apply Topkis’ (1998) theorem which requires the

cross partial derivative of the maximand w(p)u(m/p) to be positive. This corresponds to

requiring 𝜕

𝜕𝑝u(m/p) to be positive which is part of the sufficient condition for the first-order

condition already assumed. Note that a number of wfunctions in the literature, e.g., Goldstein

and Einhorn (1987) and Tversky and Kahneman (1992), have decreasing elasticity for p near

0. By contrast, the w function in Prelec (1998) has increasing elasticity for the usual case of the

parameter being less than 1 when w overweights small probabilities.

Scale Aversion. Consider the difference u(px)/u(x) – w(p). With utility elasticity u(x) being

decreasing so that u(px)/u(x) is increasing in x, it follows that RDU exhibits outcome scale

aversion as long as u(px)/u(x) exceeds w(p) for a sufficiently large x. RDU also exhibits

probability scale aversion as long as u(px)/u(x) > w(p) as p increases. This would be the case

Page 23: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

23

for the more usual reverse S-shape wfunction which lies below the identity line for moderate

probabilities.

Power uitility. The case of a power u function x with constant utility elasticity which also

corresponds to constant relative risk aversion merits further attention. This specification can

exhibit monotonic longshot preference as long as the probability weighting elasticity wis

bounded from above by the utility elasticity . While it can exhibit single-peak longshot

preference at w(p*) = the favored winning probability p* does not depend on expected

payoff. In relation to scale aversion in outcome and in probability, the relevant comparison

between u(px) and w(p)u(x) yields (p – w(p))x. It follows that this specification can exhibit

probability scale aversion at the same probability at which p exceeds w(p) regardless of the

outcome x. Moreover, this specification cannot exhibit outcome scale aversion – once it is risk

seeking at some probability for some winning outcome, it would remain risk seeking at that

probability regardless of the magnitude of the outcome. Interestingly, the condition of utility

elasticity xu’(x)/u(x) being decreasing which underpins outcome scale aversion does not appear

to be directly related to the property of increasing relative risk aversion which corresponds to

xu”(x)/u’(x) being increasing.

Weighted Utility (WU)

Consider the maximization problem below:

𝑚𝑎𝑥𝑝∈(0,𝑞]

𝑝𝑠(𝑚/𝑝)𝑢(𝑚/𝑝)/[𝑝𝑠(𝑚/𝑝) + 1 – 𝑝]. (2)

Monotonic longshot preference. Should the maximand in (2) be increasing over (0, q], WU

would exhibit monotonic longshot preference. This is shown in Chew and Tan (2005) for WU

under constant absolute risk aversion with a negative exponential u function and an increasing

exponential s function. More generally, monotonic longshot preference corresponds to the

maximand in (2) being decreasing in p over (0, q]. This yields the following condition:

u’(m/p, p)/u(m/p, p) > [1 – (m/p – m)s’(m/p)/s(m/p)]/[ms(m/p)+y – m],

for p over (0, q]. For the above inequality to be satisfied, it is sufficient that the inequality

below holds once it holds at some outcome m/p with respect to expected payoff m.

s’(m/p)/s(m/p) 1/(m/p – m). (3)

Single-peak longshot preference. The first-order condition to (2) is given by:

p/(1 – p) = [1 – s(m/p) – u(m/p)]/[s(m/p)u(m/p) – 1], (4)

Page 24: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

24

where s(y) = ys’(y)/s(y) is the elasticity of the salience function s. Since p/(1 – p) is increasing

in p, a sufficient condition for the solution p* to be optimal is for RHS of (4) to be decreasing

over (0, q]. It follows that p* increases in m since this term is increasing in m. We further note

that the condition on RHS of (4) being decreasing for p near 0 holds if s(m/p) and the product

s(m/p)u(m/p) are both increasing in p while the numerator and the denominator are both

positive. We can verify that this condition holds for u = ln(1+x) with u(x) = x/[(1+x)ln(1+x)]

and s = 1 + bx with s(x) = bx/(1 + bx).

Scale Aversion. Consider the difference between the utility ratio and the decision weight given

by:

u(px)/u(x) – ps(x)/[ps(x) + 1 – p]. (5)

Under the condition of decreasing utility elasticity, it is apparent that WU can exhibit scale

aversion at probability p as long as both u and s are bounded. In this case, u(px)/u(x) tends to 1

while the ratio ps(x)/[ps(x) + 1 – p] tends to [1+(1 – p)/ps*]-1 < 1, where s* is the limit of s(x)

as x increases. To see that WU can exhibit scale aversion with fixed outcome x, observe that

(5) becomes positive as p increases towards 1 as long as the slope of the right-hand term of (5)

at p = 1 given by u(x)/u’(x) exceeds s(x). This latter inequality is easily satisfied with a bounded

utility function. We can verify that WU also exhibits both outcome and probability scale

aversion when its u function is a negative exponential function and its weight function s is a

power function.

Power utility. As with RDU, we discuss the case of a power u function with elasticity

separately. From the preceding discussion, it follows that WU can exhibit both monotonic

given that condition (3) does not involve the utility function. It can also exhibit single-peak

longshot preference since the decreasingness of RHS of (4) is not affected by utility elasticity

being constant. In terms of scale aversion, the relevant comparison yields p – s(x)/[ps(x) +1 –

p]. It follows that WU can exhibit probability scale aversion with a judicious choice of its

salience function s, e.g., the form of s = 1 + bx considered above. However, WU with a power

u function cannot exhibit outcome scale aversion when s is an increasing function.

Page 25: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

25

Appendix B: Supplementary Tables

Table A1. Lotteries used in the experiment.

Outcome

x

EV = 1 EV = 10 EV = 100

p Lottery p Lottery p Lottery

1 1 Cash - - - -

10 10-1 1D 1 Cash - -

102 - - 10-1 Same 1D 1 Cash

103 10-3 3D 10-2 Different 3D 10-1 Different 3D

2 x 103 - - 5 x 10-3 5 same 3D - -

5 x 103 - - 2 x 10-3 2 same 3D - -

104 - - 10-3 Same 3D 10-2 10 x 10 3D

2 x 104 - - - - 5 x 10-3 50 same 3D

5 x 104 - - - - 2 x 10-3 20 same 3D

105 10-5 5D 10-4 Different 5D 10-3 Same 3D

2 x 105 - - 5 x 10-5 5 same 5D - -

5 x 105 - - 2 x 10-5 2 same 5D - -

106 - - 10-5 Same 5D 10-4 10 x 10 5D

2 x 106 - - - - 5 x 10-5 50 same 5D

5 x 106 - - - - 2 x 10-5 20 same 5D

107 - - - - 10-5 Same 5D Note. Besides the lotteries listed in Figure 1, this table lists an additional eight lotteries involving winning

probabilities of 2 x 10-3, 5 x 10-3, 2 x 10-5, and 5 x 10-5. The choice frequencies of the additional lotteries under

the three levels of expected payoffs – EV = 1, EV =2, and EV =3 – appear similar to those corresponding to the

adjacent lotteries. Column 1 displays the winning outcome. Columns 2, 4, and 6 display the winning probabilities

under the three expected payoffs respectively. Columns 3, 5, and 7 display our implementation of the individual

lotteries using different combinations of 1D, 3D, and 5D tickets for the three expected payoffs respectively.

Page 26: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

26

Table A2. Comparisons involving stochastic dominance

1A 1/100,000 chance receiving RMB100,000 and 99,999/100,000 chance of receiving 0.

1B 1/100,000 chance receiving RMB10,000 and 99,999/100,000 chance of receiving 0.

2A 1/10,000 chance receiving RMB100,000 and 9,999/10,000 chance of receiving 0.

2B 1/100,000 chance receiving RMB100,000 and 99,999/100,000 chance of receiving 0

3A 50/1,000 chance receiving RMB980,500/1,000 chance of receiving RMB98,and

450/1,000 chance of receiving 0

3B 50/1,000 chance receiving RMB9,800,500/1,000 chance of receiving RMB980,and

450/1,000 chance of receiving 0

4A 10/100,000 chance receiving RMB1,000,000, 5000/100,000 chance of receiving

RMB1,000,and 94,990/100,000 chance of receiving 0.

4B 5/100,000 chance receiving RMB1,000,000, 5000/100,000 chance of receiving

RMB1,000,and 94995/100,000 chance of receiving 0 Yuan

Note. The table presents four pairs of lotteries in which one option dominates the other option in terms of first

order stochastic dominance. One product, 2D, paying RMB98 rather than RMB100 at 1 percent chance, is used

in constructing four binary comparisons to detect violations of stochastic dominance in this table.

Page 27: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

27

Table A3. Frequencies of the twenty four transitive choice patterns

Small-probability

risk attitude

Transitive

choice patterns

Favored winning

probability

Frequencies in %

EV = 1 EV = 10 EV = 100

0 5 3 1 10-1 8.7*** 9.7*** 1.70

5 0 3 1 10-1 1.40 3.8*** 0.60

SP over 5 3 0 1 10-1 1.10 5.4*** 5.3***

(0, 10-1] 0 1 5 3 10-3 21.1*** 7.8*** 0.50

0 5 1 3 10-3 3.5*** 2.9*** 0.60

5 0 1 3 10-3 0.40 0.40 0.10

Monotonic 0 1 3 5 10-5 23.6*** 11.6*** 3.2***

1 0 5 3 10-3 2.6** 0.008 0.50

SP over 1 5 0 3 10-3 0.10 0.20 0.00

(0, 10-3] 5 1 0 3 10-3 0.10 0.00 0.00

1 0 3 5 10-5 2.8*** 0.014 0.70

SP over 3 1 0 5 10-5 0.00 0.00 0.10

(0, 10-5] 1 3 0 5 10-5 0.20 0.00 0.50

5 3 1 0 1 8.6*** 20.3*** 47.2***

Purely 3 5 1 0 1 1.30 5.7*** 14.0***

Risk 5 1 3 0 1 0.50 1.00 2.8***

Averse 1 5 3 0 1 0.50 0.00 0.50

1 3 5 0 1 1.20 2.20 2.8***

3 1 5 0 1 0.20 0.50 1.00

0 3 5 1 - 3.0*** 4.2*** 0.60

3 5 0 1 - 0.70 2.3* 1.70

Others 3 0 5 1 - 0.60 1.00 0.50

0 3 1 5 - 2.3* 0.016 0.80

3 0 1 5 - 0.20 0.20 0.00

Total 84.4*** 82.9*** 86.7*** Note. The table presents the frequencies of the twenty four transitive choice patterns. They include thirteen single-

peak (SP) choice patterns, six purely risk averse choice patterns, and five choice patterns under “Others”. Each

choice pattern lists the four options in ascending order of preference, e.g., 1053 means that (103, 10-3) ≻ (105, 10-

5) ≻ [1] ≻ (10, 10-1). Against a chance rate of 1.6 percent (1 out of 64 possible patterns), the per cell threshold

frequencies for the three levels of significance *10%, **5%, ***1% are 2.3 percent, 2.5 percent, and 2.8 percent,

respectively.

Page 28: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

28

Table A4. Frequencies of longshot preferring and risk averse choice patterns

Small-Probability

Risk Attitude

Chance

Rate

Frequency (%)

EV = 1 EV = 10 EV = 100

Single-peak over (0, 10-1] 7/64 59.5*** 41.6*** 12.0

Single-Peak@10-1 3/64 11.2*** 19.0*** 7.6***

Single-Peak@10-3 3/64 25.0*** 11.0*** 1.2

Single-Peak@10-5 1/64 23.3*** 11.6*** 3.2**

Single-peak over (0, 10-3] 4/64 5.7 2.5 1.2

Single-Peak@10-3 3/64 2.9 1.1 0.5

Single-Peak@10-5 1/64 2.8* 1.4 0.7

Single-peak over (0, 10-5] 2/64 0.2 0.0 0.6

Purely risk averse 6/64 12.3*** 29.7*** 68.3***

Others 5/64 6.8 9.2 3.6

Total Transitive 24/64 84.6 82.9 86.7 Note. The table summarizes the frequencies of single-peak and purely risk averse choice patterns in Table A4

along with “Others” under the three levels of expected payoffs (EV =1, EV =2, and EV = 100). We test whether

the observed frequency is significantly higher than the chance rate at three levels of significance—10 percent, 5

percent, and 1 percent—indicated by *, **, and *** using the proportion tests.

Table A5. Frequencies of choice patterns including 10-2 and 10-4

Chance EV10 EV100

Pattern N Percent N Percent N Percent

Risk Aversion 120 0.37% 172 20.57% 404 48.33%

Single-Peak@10-1 5 0.02% 76 9.09% 27 3.23%

Single-Peak@10-2 30 0.09% 11 1.32% 7 0.84%

Single-Peak@10-3 100 0.31% 5 0.60% 2 0.24%

Single-Peak@10-4 120 0.37% 6 0.72% 3 0.36%

Single-Peak@10-5 120 0.37% 0 0.00% 0 0.00%

Others 225 0.69% 49 5.86% 15 1.79%

transitive 720 2.20% 319 38.16% 458 54.78% Note. The table summarizes the frequencies of single-peaked and purely risk-averse choice patterns, from 10-1 to

10-5. With 6 lotteries, there are 15 binary choices leading to 32768 (= 215) possibilities. Among them, 720 (= 6!)

patterns are transitive, resulting in a chance rate of 2.2%.

Page 29: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

29

Table A6. Migration of favored winning probabilities across expected payoffs

Panel A: Expected payoffs 1 and 10 Expected payoff 10 1 10-1 10-3 10-5 Total

Exp

ecte

d

payo

ff 1

1 95 4 0 0 99

10-1 57 26 2 1 86

10-3 18 79 53 15 165

10-5 4 14 37 86 141

Total 174 123 92 102 491

Panel B: Expected payoffs 10 and 100 Expected payoff 100 1 10-1 10-3 10-5 Total

Exp

ecte

d

payo

ff 1

0 1 231 4 0 2 237

10-1 127 20 1 0 148

10-3 43 20 7 4 74

10-5 29 4 3 29 65

Total 430 48 11 35 524

Panel C: Expected payoffs 1 and 100 Expected payoff 10 1 10-1 10-3 10-5 Total

Exp

ecte

d

payo

ff 1

1 96 0 0 1 97

10-1 83 7 0 0 90

10-3 161 34 5 2 202

10-5 96 12 7 32 147

Total 436 53 12 35 536 Note. Panel A shows the counts for subjects who migrate from being either risk averse, denoted by “1”, or having

single-peak longshot preference at 10-1, 10-3, or 10-5 at expected payoff of 1 to being either risk averse, or having

single-peak longshot preference at 10-1, 10-3, or 10-5 at expected payoff of 10. Panel B (resp: Panel C) shows the

corresponding migration counts for subjects from expected payoff of 10 (resp: 1) to expected payoff of 100.

Pearson's chi-squared tests are highly significant (p < 0.001).

Table A7. Proportion (%) of scale-averse behavior as expected payoff increases Panel A: Fixed winning probability

Probability SSS SSA SAA AAA Others

10-1 16.9 37.3 20.6 17.8 7.4

10-3 14.8 37.9 25.7 18.1 2.3

10-5 13.6 37.2 28.3 19.0 1.8

Panel B: Fixed winning outcome

Outcome SSS SSA SAA AAA Others

103 16.9 37.1 24.4 18.9 3.8

105 14.1 37.6 26.8 18.9 2.6

Note. Panel A presents the percentage of choice patterns across the three levels of expected payoffs keeping the

winning probability constant. Panel B presents the percentage of choice patterns across the three levels of expected

payoffs keeping the winning outcome constant. SSS (risk seeking at all three levels of expected payoffs), SSA

(risk seeking at expected payoffs of 1 and 10, and risk averse at expected payoffs of 100), SAA (risk seeking at

expected payoffs of 1, and risk averse at expected payoffs of 10 and 100), and AAA (risk averse at all three levels

of expected payoffs).

Page 30: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

30

Table A8. Frequencies of single-peak and risk averse choice patterns

Small-Probability

Risk Attitude

Chance With Violation (%) Without Violation (%)

Rate EV = 1 EV = 10 EV = 100 EV = 1 EV = 10 EV = 100

Single-peak over

(0, 10-1] 7/64 58.4 40.7 14.4

60.5 42.3 9.6

Single-Peak@10-1 3/64 9.6 14.1 8.3 12.9 23.7 6.7

Single-Peak@10-3 3/64 21.5 11.5 1.4 28.2 10.5 0.9

Single-Peak@10-5 1/64 27.2 15.1 4.5 19.4 8.1 1.9

Single-peak over

(0, 10-3] 4/64 6.5 2.9 1.4

4.8 2.1 0.9

Single-Peak@10-3 3/64 2.6 1.4 0.7 3.1 0.7 0.2

Single-Peak@10-5 1/64 3.8 1.4 0.7 1.7 1.4 0.7

Single-peak over

(0, 10-5] 2/64 0.2 0.0 1.0

0.2 0.0 0.2

Purely risk averse 6/64 9.3 24.6 60.5 15.3 34.7 78.2

Others 5/64 7.4 10.3 4.3 6.2 8.1 2.8

Total Transitive 24/64 81.8 78.5 81.5 87.1 87.3 91.8

Note. The table summarizes the frequencies of single-peak and purely risk averse choice patterns in Table A4

along with “Others” for those with and without violations of first-order stochastic dominance.

Page 31: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

31

Table A9. Effect of violation of stochastic dominance on choice across expected payoffs

Note. Panel A presents the mean and standard deviation of the incidence (in %) of choice patterns across the three

levels of EVs keeping the winning probability constant for those with and without violations of first-order

stochastic dominance. Panel B presents the mean and standard deviation (in %) of the incidence of choice patterns

across the three levels of EVs keeping the winning outcome constant for those with and without violations. SSS

(risk seeking at all three EVs), SSA (risk seeking at EV = 1 and EV = 10, and risk averse at EV = 100), SAA (risk

seeking at EV = 1, and risk averse at EV = 10 and EV = 100), and AAA (risk averse at all three EVs). Using

multinomial logistic regression, we find that no-violation subjects tend to exhibit more AAA and less SSS,

suggesting that they are generally more risk averse (10-1, p < 0.103; 10-3, p < 0.001; 10-5, p < 0.001; 103, p <

0.039; 105, p < 0.002). The overall single-switch behaviors for both groups appear similar.

Panel A: Fixed winning probability

Probability Choice

Pattern

With Violation Without Violation

Mean Std. Dev. Mean Std. Dev.

10-1

AAA 15.6 1.8 20.1 2.0

SAA 19.4 1.9 21.8 2.0

SSA 37.1 2.4 37.6 2.4

SSS 19.4 1.9 14.4 1.7

Others 8.6 1.4 6.2 1.2

10-3

AAA 14.8 1.7 21.3 2.0

SAA 25.1 2.1 26.3 2.2

SSA 37.3 2.4 40.9 2.4

SSS 18.9 1.9 10.8 1.5

Others 3.8 0.9 0.7 0.4

10-5

AAA 15.1 1.8 23.0 2.1

SAA 25.8 2.1 30.9 2.3

SSA 37.6 2.4 36.8 2.4

SSS 18.7 1.9 8.6 1.4

Others 2.9 0.8 0.7 0.4

Panel B: Fixed winning outcome

Outcome Choice

Pattern

With Violation Without Violation

Mean Std. Dev. Mean Std. Dev.

1,000

AAA 15.6 1.8 20.6 2.0

SAA 23.4 2.1 25.4 2.1

SSA 36.6 2.4 37.6 2.4

SSS 20.6 2.0 13.2 1.7

Others 3.8 0.9 3.3 0.9

100,000

AAA 15.6 1.8 22.2 2.0

SAA 24.9 2.1 28.7 2.2

SSA 38.0 2.4 37.1 2.4

SSS 18.2 1.9 10.0 1.5

Others 3.3 0. 9 1.9 0.7

Page 32: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

32

Table A10. Effect of violation of stochastic dominance on Allais behavior

Allais Behavior With violation Without violation

Mean Std. Dev. Mean Std. Dev.

EV = 1 vs. EV =10 17.5 24.1 16.3 23.5

EV = 10 vs. EV = 100 21.0 17.8 14.9 16.6

EV = 1 vs. EV = 100 29.9 45.8 249 43.3

Note. The table lists the mean and standard deviation (in %) of the incidence of Allais behavior for those with

violations (columns 2 and 3), those with violations (columns 4 and 5). The overall proportions of Allais behavior

for these two groups appear similar. While subjects without violations exhibit a significantly lower incidence of

Allais behavior for EV = 10 vs EV = 100 than those with violations, we do not observe a significant difference

between EV = 1 and EV = 10, and between EV = 1 and EV = 100.

Page 33: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

33

Appendix C. Intransitive Choice and Violation of Dominance

This appendix examines the incidence of intransitive choice and violation of first order

stochastic dominance observed in the data. At all three levels of expected payoffs, subjects

exhibit high rates of transitive choice—84.4 percent for expected payoff 1, 82.9 percent for

expected payoff 10, and 86.7 percent for expected payoff 100—exceeding the chance rate of

24/64 in each case (p < 0.001) with 61.5 percent exhibiting transitivity across all three levels

of expected payoffs. This suggests that subjects’ choices are mostly transitive even when the

winning probabilities are extremely small at 10-3 and 10-5 regardless of the level of expected

payoff.

We relate the observed intransitive choices to violation of stochastic dominance in

terms of four binary choices in which one lottery stochastically dominates another (Table A2).

In terms of stochastic dominance, 50 percent of our subjects show no violation, 31 percent have

one violation, 15 percent have two violations, 4 percent have three violations, and the

remaining 1 percent have four violations. Subjects are divided into two groups—one without

violations and another with at least one violation. For those without violations of dominance,

the proportion of transitive patterns is between 87.1 percent and 91.9 percent, which is

significantly higher than those with violations of dominance (between 78.5 percent and 81.8

percent) (p < 0.001). The association between violation of stochastic dominance and preference

intransitivity suggests that the observed intransitive choice may be linked to inattention or lack

of effort in participating in our experiment.

We further make use of the observed degree of violation, which may reflect the

subjects’ level of attentiveness and effort in participating in our experiment, to test whether this

factor influences the observed choice behavior. The proportion of longshot preference at (0,

10-1] is similar for those with violations of dominance and those without violations of

dominance (58.4 percent versus 60.5 percent for expected payoffs of 1; 40.7 percent versus

42.3 percent for expected payoffs of 10; 14.4 percent versus 9.6 percent for expected payoffs

of 100). Overall, those without violations of dominance are more risk averse than those with

violations (9.3 percent versus 15.3 percent for expected payoffs of 1; 24.6 percent versus 34.7

percent for expected payoffs of 10; 60.5 percent versus 78.2 percent for expected payoffs of

100).

For scale aversion, the proportion of risk aversion across the three levels of expected

payoffs for those without violations of dominance is between 21 percent and 23 percent for

either fixed winning probability or fixed winning outcome, which is significantly larger than

those with violations of dominance (about 15 percent) (p < 0.001), while the proportion of risk

Page 34: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

34

seeking across the three levels of expected payoffs for those without violations of dominance

is between 10 percent and 15 percent, which is significantly smaller than those with violations

of dominance (between 18 percent and 21 percent) (p < 0.001). The overall proportions of

Allais behavior for these two groups appear similar. While subjects without violations exhibit

a significantly lower incidence of Allais behavior for expected payoffs across 10 and 100

relative to those with violations (p < 0.001), we do not observe a significant difference in the

incidence of Allais behavior for expected payoffs across 1 and 10 (p > 0.584), and for expected

payoffs across 1 and 100 (p > 0.104). We report the details in Tables A7, A8, and A9. In sum,

while there are some observed differences for subjects who are more prone to violations of

stochastic dominance, the qualitative features of the observed longshot preference behavior,

the switching behavior in risk attitudes across expected payoffs, and the equal-mean common-

ratio Allais behavior remain robust.

Page 35: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

35

Appendix D: Experimental Instructions

Thank you for participating in this study on decision making. Please read the following

instructions carefully before you make any decisions.

Tasks: In this study, you will make a number of binary choices as illustrated in the following

two examples.

Example 1. Which of the following two options will you choose?

A. 1/1000 chance of receiving 2000 Yuan, 999/1000 chance of receiving 0 Yuan

B. 1/100,000 chance of receiving 200,000 Yuan, 99,000/100,00 of receiving 0 Yuan

Choosing A means that you have 1/1000 chance of receiving 2000 Yuan and 999/1000 chance

of receiving 0 Yuan. Choosing B means that you have 1/100,000 chance of receiving 200,000

Yuan and 99,000/100,000 chance of receiving 0 Yuan.

Example 2. Which of the following two options will you choose?

A. 1/1000 chance of receiving 100,000 Yuan, 999/1000 chance of receiving 0 Yuan

B. receiving 100 Yuan for sure

Choosing A means that you have 1/1000 chance of receiving 100,000 Yuan and 999/1000

chance of receiving 0 Yuan. Choosing B means that you receive 100 Yuan for sure.

In each round, you choose between two options, and there are 100 rounds in total. The

probability and amount of money may be different in each round. We will use lotteries with

different combinations of probability and amount of money.

Details of Rules for the Lottery: Three types of lotteries are used in this study, i.e., “Array 3”

and “Array 5” of China Sports Lottery, and “3D” of China Welfare Lottery. You may refer to

the detailed rules of these three lotteries. Below is a brief introduction of these three types of

lotteries.

Array 3. Buyers can choose a three-digit number from 000 to 999. If the number chosen by the

buyer is the winning number (same digits in the same order), the buyer of the lottery wins 1000

Yuan. That is, the probability of winning 1000 Yuan is 1/1000 for a randomly chosen number.

For example, if the winning number is 543 and you have ten lotteries with the number 543, you

will receive 10,000 Yuan. That is, you have 1/1000 chance to win 10,000 Yuan with ten

lotteries of the same number.

Array 5. Buyers can choose a five-digit number from 00000 to 99999. If the number chosen by

the buyer is the winning number (same digits in the same order), the buyer of the lottery wins

100,000 Yuan. That is, the probability of winning 100,000 Yuan is 1/100,000 for a randomly

chosen number.

Page 36: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

36

For example, if the winning number is 54321 and you have ten lotteries with the number

54321, you will receive 1000,000 Yuan. That is, you have 1/100,000 chance to win 1000,000

Yuan with ten lotteries of the same number.

3D. 3D is similar to Array 3. Buyers can bet on a three-digit number from 000 to 999. If the

number chosen by the buyer is the winning number (same digits in the same order), the buyer

of the lottery wins 1000 Yuan. That is, the probability of winning 1000 Yuan is 1/1000 for a

randomly chosen number. Lottery 3D has another two ways of betting.

“2D” Betting: Buyers can bet on the first two digits, last two digits, or the first and last digit

of a three-digit number from 000 to 999. The chosen two digits should have the same order and

be in the same position as the winning number. The winning amount is 98 Yuan for each ticket.

“1D” Betting: Buyers can bet on the ones, tens, and hundreds of a three-digit number from 000

to 999. The chosen digit should have the same order and be in the same position as the winning

number. The winning amount is 10 Yuan for each ticket.

Detailed rules for “Array 3” in China Sports Lottery:

http://www.lottery.gov.cn/news/10006630.shtml

Detailed rules for “Array 5” in China Sports Lottery:

http://www.lottery.gov.cn/news/10006657.shtml

Detailed rules for “3D” in China Welfare Lottery:

http://www.bwlc.net/help/3d.jsp

We will implement the corresponding probability and the amount by combining

different types of lotteries. In Option A of Example 1, you have 1/1000 chance of receiving

2000 Yuan with two “Array 3” lotteries with the same number. In Option A of Example 2, you

have 1/1000 chance of receiving 100,000 Yuan with 100 “Array 3” with the same number.

In a similar manner, you will get lottery combinations with different probabilities of winning

various amounts. In this experiment, all the numbers of the lotteries are generated randomly by

a computer. We will buy these lotteries from lottery stores.

Payment: Every participant in the experiment will get 20 Yuan as a base payment. You have a

ten percent chance of receiving an additional payment, which is randomly chosen in the

following way. We will add your birthday (year, month, and date—eight numbers in total) to

get a one-digit number (0-9). If this number is the same as the sum of the “3D” Welfare lottery

on Feb 28, 2013, you will receive the additional payment. That is, you have approximately a

ten percent chance of receiving an additional payment.

The amount of the additional payment is decided in the following way. You will be asked to

randomly choose one number between 1 and 100, which determines one decision out of your

Page 37: Individual Preference for Longshots€¦ · expected payoffs of 1, and we are limited to using 10-1, 10-3, and 10-5 as the winning probabilities for lotteries with expected payoffs

37

100 decisions. Your payment will depend on the decision you made on that particular round.

If your choice on that round is a certain amount of money, you will get that amount of money.

If your choice on that round is a lottery, then your payment is through the lottery.

Time for payment: The payment will be implemented around March to April, 2013. The

specific date will be announced later.

Summary for Rules:

1. You will be asked to decide between two options in each of the 100 rounds.

2. The probabilities and amounts of money in each decision can be realized by different

combinations of lotteries.

3. Each participant will get 20 Yuan as a base payment.

4. Ten percent of participants will be randomly chosen to receive additional payment; the

payment will be based on one randomly chosen decision out of the 100 decisions made.

If you have any questions about this experiment, please feel free to email us at

[email protected]. If you are clear about the instructions, you may start and make your

decisions now.

Sample Screen of Choice.

Note. The translation of the sample screen is as follows. Page 2 of 107 Pages: 1. In the following two options,

which one will you choose? *1/10,000 chance of receiving 100,000 Yuan, 9,999/10,000 chance of receiving 0;

*1/50,000 chance of receiving 500,000 Yuan, 49,999/50,000 receiving 0 Yuan.


Recommended