+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Inference is carried out by inference rules, which allow one formula to be

Inference is carried out by inference rules, which allow one formula to be

Date post: 11-Jan-2016
Category:
Upload: kuri
View: 45 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend
Description:
Inference is a process of building a proof of a sentence, or put it differently inference is an implementation of the entailment relation between sentences. Inference is carried out by inference rules, which allow one formula to be - PowerPoint PPT Presentation
26
Inference is a process of building a proof of a sentence, or put it differently inference is an implementation of the entailment relation between sentences. Inference is carried out by inference rules, which allow one formula to be inferred from a set of other formulas. For example, A |-- B meaning that B can be derived from A. An inference procedure is sound if and only if (iff) its inference rules are sound. In turn, an inference rule is sound iff its conclusion is true whenever the rule's premises are true.
Transcript
Page 1: Inference is carried out by  inference rules,  which allow one formula to be

Inference is a process of building a proof of a sentence, or put it differently inference is an implementation of the entailment relation between sentences.

Inference is carried out by inference rules, which allow one formula to be

inferred from a set of other formulas. For example, A |-- B meaning that

B can be derived from A.

An inference procedure is sound if and only if (iff) its inference rules are sound. In turn, an inference rule is sound iff its conclusion is true whenever the rule's premises are true.

Page 2: Inference is carried out by  inference rules,  which allow one formula to be

PL inference rules

Modus ponens: if sentence A and implication A => B hold, then B also holds, i.e. (A, A => B) |-- B.

Example: Let A means “lights are off”,

A => B means “if lights are off, then there is no one

in the office”

B means “there is no one in the office” AND-elimination: if conjunction A1 & A2 & ... & An holds, then any of

its conjuncts also holds, i.e. A1 & A2 & ... & An |-- Ai. AND-introduction: if a list of sentences holds, then their conjunction

also holds, i.e. A1, A2,...,An |-- (A1 & A2 & ... & An). OR-introduction: If Ai holds, then any disjunction containing Ai also

holds, i.e. Ai |-- (A1 v ... v Ai v ... v An). Double-negation elimination: states that a formula can be either true

or false, i.e. (not (not A)) |-- A

Page 3: Inference is carried out by  inference rules,  which allow one formula to be

PL inference rules (cont.)

Unit resolution: (A v B), not B |-- A. Note that (A v B) is equivalent to (not B => A), i.e. unit resolution is a modification of modus ponens.

Resolution: (A v B), (not B v C) |-- (A v C). Note that

(A v B) is equivalent to (not A => B),

(not B v C) is equivalent to (B => C)

By eliminating the intermediate

conclusion, we get (not A => C).

The soundness of each one of these rules can be checked by means of the

truth table method. Once the soundness of a rule has been established, it

can be used for building proofs. Proofs are sequences of applications of

inference rules, starting with sentences initially contained in the KB.

Page 4: Inference is carried out by  inference rules,  which allow one formula to be

Example (adapted from Dean,Allen & Aloimonos "Artificial Intelligence: theory and practice")

Bob, Lisa, Jim and Mary got their dormitory rooms according to the results

of a housing lottery. Determine how they were ranked with respect to each

other, if the following is known:

1. Lisa is not next to Bob in the ranking.

2. Jim is ranked immediately ahead of a biology major.

3. Bob is ranked immediately ahead of Jim.

4. Either Lisa or Mary is a biology major.

5. Either Lisa or Mary is ranked first.

We must start with deciding how to represent the problem in PL. Let the

following two be the only types of propositions that we will use:

X-ahead-of-Y meaning “X is immediately ahead of Y”

X-bio-major meaning “X is a biology major”

Page 5: Inference is carried out by  inference rules,  which allow one formula to be

Statements representing the initial KB:

1. (not Lisa-ahead-of-Bob & not Bob-ahead-of-Lisa)

2. ((Jim-ahead-of-Mary & Mary-bio-major) V (Jim-ahead-of-Bob & Bob-bio-major) V

V (Jim-ahead-of-Lisa & Lisa-bio-major))

3. Bob-ahead-of-Jim

4. Mary-bio-major V Lisa-bio-major

5. ((Mary-ahead-of-Bob & Bob-ahead-of-Lisa & Lisa-ahead-of-Jim) V

V (Mary-ahead-of-Bob & Bob-ahead-of-Jim & Jim-ahead-of-Lisa) V

V (Mary-ahead-of-Lisa & Lisa-ahead-of-Bob & Bob-ahead-of-Jim) V

V (Mary-ahead-of-Lisa & Lisa-ahead-of-Jim & Jim-ahead-of-Bob) V

V (Mary-ahead-of-Jim & Jim-ahead-of-Lisa & Lisa-ahead-of-Bob) V

V (Mary-ahead-of-Jim & Jim-ahead-of-Bob & Bob-ahead-of-Lisa) V

V (Lisa-ahead-of-Bob & Bob-ahead-of-Jim & Jim-ahead-of-Mary) V

V (Lisa-ahead-of-Bob & Bob-ahead-of-Mary & Mary-ahead-of-Jim) V

V (Lisa-ahead-of-Mary & Mary-ahead-of-Jim & Jim-ahead-of-Bob) V

V (Lisa-ahead-of-Mary & Mary-ahead-of-Bob & Bob-ahead-of-Jim) V

V (Lisa-ahead-of-Jim & Jim-ahead-of-Bob & Bob-ahead-of-Mary) V

V (Lisa-ahead-of-Jim & Jim-ahead-of-Mary & Mary-ahead-of-Bob))

Page 6: Inference is carried out by  inference rules,  which allow one formula to be

Example (contd.)

In addition to the explicit knowledge encoded by the five sentences above, the

following background (or common-sense) knowledge is needed to solve the

problem:

BGRule1: A student can be immediately ahead of at most one other student.

Cons1: Bob-ahead-of-Jim ==> not Bob-ahead-of-Lisa

Cons2: Bob-ahead-of-Jim ==> not Lisa-ahead-of-Jim

BGRule2: If X is immediately ahead of Y, then Y cannot be immediately ahead

of X.

Cons3: Bob-ahead-of-Jim ==> not Jim-ahead-of-Bob

Page 7: Inference is carried out by  inference rules,  which allow one formula to be

Example (contd.)

By sentence 3, Cons3 and MP, we can infer

6. not Jim-ahead-of-Bob

By sentences 5 and 6, and the Unit Resolution rule, we can infer

7. ((Mary-ahead-of-Bob & Bob-ahead-of-Lisa & Lisa-ahead-of-Jim) V

V (Mary-ahead-of-Bob & Bob-ahead-of-Jim & Jim-ahead-of-Lisa) V

V (Mary-ahead-of-Lisa & Lisa-ahead-of-Bob & Bob-ahead-of-Jim) V

V (Mary-ahead-of-Jim & Jim-ahead-of-Lisa & Lisa-ahead-of-Bob) V

V (Lisa-ahead-of-Bob & Bob-ahead-of-Jim & Jim-ahead-of-Mary) V

V (Lisa-ahead-of-Bob & Bob-ahead-of-Mary & Mary-ahead-of-Jim) V

V (Lisa-ahead-of-Mary & Mary-ahead-of-Bob & Bob-ahead-of-Jim) V

V (Lisa-ahead-of-Jim & Jim-ahead-of-Mary & Mary-ahead-of-Bob))

Page 8: Inference is carried out by  inference rules,  which allow one formula to be

Example (contd.)

By sentence 3, Cons2 of BGRule1, and MP, we can infer

8. not Lisa-ahead-of-Jim

By sentences 7 and 8, and the Unit Resolution rule (in several steps) , we can infer

9. ((Mary-ahead-of-Bob & Bob-ahead-of-Jim & Jim-ahead-of-Lisa) V

V (Mary-ahead-of-Lisa & Lisa-ahead-of-Bob & Bob-ahead-of-Jim) V

V (Mary-ahead-of-Jim & Jim-ahead-of-Lisa & Lisa-ahead-of-Bob) V

V (Lisa-ahead-of-Bob & Bob-ahead-of-Jim & Jim-ahead-of-Mary) V

V (Lisa-ahead-of-Bob & Bob-ahead-of-Mary & Mary-ahead-of-Jim) V

V (Lisa-ahead-of-Mary & Mary-ahead-of-Bob & Bob-ahead-of-Jim))

Page 9: Inference is carried out by  inference rules,  which allow one formula to be

Example (contd.)

By sentences 6 and 2, and the Unit resolution rule, we can infer

10. (Jim-ahead-of-Mary & Mary-bio-major) V (Jim-ahead-of-Lisa & Lisa-bio-major)

By sentence 1 and the AND Elimination rule, we can infer

11. not Lisa-ahead-of-Bob

By sentences 9 and 11, and the Unit Resolution rule, we can infer

12. (Mary-ahead-of-Bob & Bob-ahead-of-Jim & Jim-ahead-of-Lisa) V

V (Lisa-ahead-of-Mary & Mary-ahead-of-Bob & Bob-ahead-of-Jim)

Notice that the second disjunct in 12 contradicts sentence 10 (Jim is ranked

immediately ahead of a biology major, therefore cannot be the last one in the ranking).

To arrive at the correct conclusion, we must eliminate this disjunct from sentence 12.

Page 10: Inference is carried out by  inference rules,  which allow one formula to be

Example (contd.)

Let us apply the following transformation on sentence 10.

(Jim-ahead-of-Mary & Mary-bio-major) V (Jim-ahead-of-Lisa & Lisa-bio-major) (A & B) v (C & D) (A v C) & (A v D) & (B v C) & (B v D) (the validity of this equivalence can be proved by the truth tables method)

By the AND-elimination rule, we can infer (A v C), i.e.

13. Jim-ahead-of-Mary V Jim-ahead-of-Lisa

Unfortunately, it is not possible to logically prove that 13 contradicts the second disjunct in sentence 12. The only way to complete the proof is to change the representation so that it suits our purposes. For that, we can add 2 more propositions in our language:

Nobody-ahead-of-X X-ahead-of-Nobody

Now we can derive the following consequent from BGRule1:

Cons4: Jim-ahead-of-Mary V Jim-ahead-of-Lisa not Jim-ahead-of-Nobody

Page 11: Inference is carried out by  inference rules,  which allow one formula to be

Example (contd.)

12 now becomes:

12. (Nobody-ahead-of-Mary & Mary-ahead-of-Bob & Bob-ahead-of-Jim &

& Jim-ahead-of-Lisa & Lisa-ahead-of-Nobody) V

V (Nobody-ahead-of-Lisa & Lisa-ahead-of-Mary & Mary-ahead-of-Bob &

& Bob-ahead-of-Jim & Jim-ahead-of-Nobody)

13. (Jim-ahead-of-Mary V Jim-ahead-of-Lisa) & not Jim-ahead-of-Nobody

By 13, Cons4 and MP, we can infer

14. not Jim-ahead-of-Nobody

By 12, 14 and the Unit Resolution Rule, we now can infer

15. Nobody-ahead-of-Mary & Mary-ahead-of-Bob & Bob-ahead-of-Jim &

& Jim-ahead-of-Lisa & Lisa-ahead-of-Nobody

Page 12: Inference is carried out by  inference rules,  which allow one formula to be

Complexity of propositional inference

1. Propositional inference is complete, i.e. any valid formula can be proved by means of the truth tables method.

2. However, the truth table may have as much as 2^N rows, where N is the number of propositional variables in the KB. Building such a table takes exponential time, i.e. the problem of proving the validity of a PL formula is NP-complete.

3. Inference rules in PL are monotonic. That is,

if KB1 |-- A, then KB1 U KB2 |-- A

Here, KB2 can be contradictory to KB1, which makes monotonicity of PL rules a major representation problem.

4. Inference rules in PL are local, i.e. they depend only on their premises (this is a consequent of the monotonicity property). This, in turn, makes the inference procedure much better than exponential, because only a small number of propositions are involved in each inference.

Page 13: Inference is carried out by  inference rules,  which allow one formula to be

Wang’s algorithm for proving the validity of a formula

Let the KB be represented as a “sequent” of the form:

Premise1, Premise2, ... , PremiseN ===>s

===>s Conclusion1, Conclusion2, ... , ConclusionM

Wang’s algorithm transforms such sequents by means of seven rules, two of

which are termination rules. Other five rules either eliminate a connective

(thus shortening the sequent), or eliminate the implication.

The following example will be used to illustrate Wang’s algorithm.

Fact1: If Bob failed to enroll in CS462, then Bob will not graduate this Spring.

Fact2: If Bob will not graduate this Spring, then Bob will miss a great job.

Fact3: Bob will not miss a great job.

Question: Did Bob fail to enroll in CS462?

Page 14: Inference is carried out by  inference rules,  which allow one formula to be

Representing the example in formal terms

First, we must decide on the representation. Assume that:

P means “Bob failed to enroll in CS462” ,

Q means “Bob will not graduate this Spring” , and

R means “Bob will miss a great job”.

The problem is now described by means of the following PL formulas:

Fact 1: P --> Q

Fact 2: Q --> R

Fact 3: not R

Question: P or not P

Here fact1, fact2, and fact3 are called premises.

Page 15: Inference is carried out by  inference rules,  which allow one formula to be

The question answered by using a truth table

Propositional Premises Possible

variables Conclusions

P Q R P --> Q Q --> R not R P not P

F F F T T T F T

T F F F T T T F

F T F T F T F T

T T F T F T T F

F F T T T F F T

T F T F T F T F

F T T T T F F T

T T T T T F T F

Page 16: Inference is carried out by  inference rules,  which allow one formula to be

Wang’s algorithm: transformation rules

Wang’s algorithm takes a KB represented as a set of sequents and applies

rules R1 through R5 to transform the sequents into simpler ones. Rules R6

and R7 are termination rules which check if the proof has been found.

Bob’s example. The KB initially contains the following sequent:

P --> Q, Q --> R, not R ===>s not P

Here P --> Q, Q --> R, not R, not P are referred to as top-level formulas.

Transformation rules: R1 (“not on the left / not on the right” rule). If one of the top level

formulas of the sequent has the form not X, then this rule says to drop the negation and move X to the other side of the sequent arrow. If not X is on the left of ===>s, the transformation is called “not on the left; otherwise, it is called “not on the right”.

Page 17: Inference is carried out by  inference rules,  which allow one formula to be

R2 (“& on the left / v on the right” rule). If a top-level formula on the left of the arrow has the form X & Y, or a top-level formula on the right of the arrow has the form X v Y, then the connective (&, v) can be replaced by a comma.

R3 (“v on the left” rule). If a top-level formula on the left has a form X v Y, then replace the sequent with two new sequents: X ===> s ...... and Y ===>s ......

R4 (“& on the right” rule). If a top-level formula on the right has a form X & Y, then replace the sequent with two new sequents: ....... ===>s X and ....... ===>s Y

R5 (“implication elimination” rule). Any formula of the form X --> Y is replaced by not X v Y.

R6 (“valid sequent” rule). If a top-level formula X occurs on both sides of the sequent, then the sequent is considered proved. Such a sequent is called an axiom. If the original sequent has been split into sequents, then all of these sequents must be proved in order for the original sequent to be proved.

R7 (“invalid sequent” rule). If all of the formulas in a given sequent are propositional symbols (i.e. no future transformations are possible) and the sequent is not an axiom, then the sequent is invalid. If an invalid sequent is found, the algorithm terminates, and the original sequent is proved not to follow logically from the premises.

Page 18: Inference is carried out by  inference rules,  which allow one formula to be

Bob’s example continued

Sequent: P --> Q, Q --> R, not R ===>s not P

Apply R5 twice, to P --> Q and to Q --> R Sequent: (not P v Q), (not Q v R), not R ===>s not P

Apply R1 to (not R) Sequent: (not P v Q), (not Q v R) ===>s not P, R

Apply R3 to (not P v Q), resulting in splitting the current sequent

into two new sequents. Sequents: not P, (not Q v R) ===>s not P, R

Q, (not Q v R) ===>s not P, R

Note that the first sequent is an axiom according to R6 (not P is on

both sides of the sequent arrow). To prove that not P follows from

the premises, however, we still need to prove the second sequent.

Page 19: Inference is carried out by  inference rules,  which allow one formula to be

Bob’s example (cont.)

Sequent: Q, (not Q v R) ===>s not P, R

Apply R3 to (not Q v R) Sequents: Q, not Q ===>s not P, R

Q, R ===>s not P, R

Here the second sequent is an axiom according to R6.

Apply R1 to (not Q) to the first sequent Sequent: Q ===>s not P, R, Q

According to R6, the resulting sequent is an axiom. All sequents

resulting from different splits of the original sequent were proved,

therefore not P follows from the premises P --> Q, Q --> R, not R .

Page 20: Inference is carried out by  inference rules,  which allow one formula to be

Characterization of Wang’s algorithm

1. Wang’s algorithm is complete, i.e. it will always prove a formula if it is valid. The length of the proof depends on the order in which rules are applied.

2. Wang’s algorithm is NP-complete in the worst case. However, in the average case its performance in better compared to that of the truth tables method.

3. Wang’s algorithm is sound, i.e. it will prove only formulas entailed by the KB.

Note: Wang’s algorithm was originally published in Wang, H. “Towards mechanical mathematics”, in IBM Journal of Research and Development, vol.4, 1960.

Page 21: Inference is carried out by  inference rules,  which allow one formula to be

The wumpus example continued

The KB describing the WW contains the following types of sentences:

– Sentences representing the agent’s percepts. These are propositions of the form:

not S [1,1] : There is no stench in square [1,1]

B [2,1] : There is a breeze in square [2,1]

not W [1,1] : There is no wumpus in square [1,1], etc.

– Sentences representing the background knowledge (i.e. the rules of the game). These are formulas of the form:

R1: not S [1,1] --> not W [1,1] & not W [1,2] & not W [2,1]

. . . .

R16: not S [4,4] --> not W [4,4] & not W [3,4] & not W [4,3]

There are 16 rules of this type (one for each square).

Rj: S [1,2] --> W [1,3] v W[1,2] v W [2,2] v W [1,1]

. . . .

There are 16 rules of this type.

Page 22: Inference is carried out by  inference rules,  which allow one formula to be

WW knowledge base (cont.)

Rk: not B [1,1] --> not P [2,1] & not P [1,2]

. . . .

16 rules of this type

Rn: B [1,1] --> P [2,1] v P [1,2]

. . . .

16 rules of this type

Rp: not G [1,1] --> not G [1,1]

. . . .

16 rules of this type

Rs: G[1,1] --> G[1,1]

. . . .

16 rules of this type

Also, 32 rules are needed to handle the percept “Bump”, and 32 more

to handle the percept “Scream”. Total number of rules dealing with

percepts: 160.

Page 23: Inference is carried out by  inference rules,  which allow one formula to be

WW knowledge base: limitations of PL

Rules describing the agent’s actions and rules representing “common-sense knowledge”, such as “Don’t go forward, if the wumpus is in front of you”. This rule will be represented by 64 sentences (16 squares * 4 orientations).

If we want to incorporate the time into the representation, then each group of 64 sentences must be provided for each time segment. Assume that the problem is expected to take 100 time segments. Then, 6400 sentences are needed to represent only the rule “Don’t go forward, if the wumpus is in front of you”. Note: there are still many other rules of this type which will require thousands of sentences to be formally described.

The third group of sentences in the agent’s KB are the entailed sentences.

Note: using truth tables for identifying the entailed sentences is infeasible

not only because of the large number of propositional variables, but

also because of the huge number of formulas that will eventually be

tested for validity.

Page 24: Inference is carried out by  inference rules,  which allow one formula to be

The WW: solving one fragment of the agent’s problem by means of the Wang’s algorithm.

Consider the situation on Figure 6.15 (AIMA), and assume that we want to prove

W [1,3] with the Wang’s algorithm.

Current sequent:

not S [1,1], not B [1,1], S [1,2], not B [1,2], not S [2,1], B [2,1],

not S [1,1] --> not W [1,1] & not W [1,2] & not W [2,1],

not S [2,1] --> not W [1,1] & not W [2,1] & not W [2,2] & not W [3,1],

S [1,2] --> W [1,3] v W [1,2] v W [2,2] v W [1,1] ===>s W [1,3] Applying R1 to all negated single propositions on the left results in

Current sequent:

S [1,2], B [2,1], not S [1,1] --> not W [1,1] & not W [1,2] & not W [2,1],

not S [2,1] --> not W [1,1] & not W [2,1] & not W [2,2] & not W [3,1],

S [1,2] --> W [1,3] v W [1,2] v W [2,2] v W [1,1] ===>s W [1,3], S [1,1],

B [1,1], B [1,2], S [2,1]

Page 25: Inference is carried out by  inference rules,  which allow one formula to be

Applying R5 to the first two implications on the left in combination with R2, and only R5 to the third implication results in

Current sequent:

S [1,2], B [2,1], S [1,1] v not W [1,1], S [1,1] v not W [1,2], S [1,1] v not W [2,1],

S [2,1] v not W [1,1], S [2,1] v not W [2,1], S [2,1] v not W [2,2],

S [2,1] v not W [3,1], not S [1,2] v W [1,3] v W [1,2] v W [2,2] v W [1,1] ===>s

W [1,3], S [1,1], B [1,1], B [1,2], S [2,1] Applying R3 to the last disjunct will result in

Current sequents:

S [1,2], B [2,1], S [1,1] v not W [1,1], S [1,1] v not W [1,2], S [1,1] v not W [2,1],

S [2,1] v not W [1,1], S [2,1] v not W [2,1], S [2,1] v not W [2,2],

S [2,1] v not W [3,1], not S [1,2] ===>s W [1,3], S [1,1], B [1,1], B [1,2], S [2,1]

Moving not S [1,2] on the right by using R1 will prove that this is an axiom.

S [1,2], B [2,1], S [1,1] v not W [1,1], S [1,1] v not W [1,2], S [1,1] v not W [2,1],

S [2,1] v not W [1,1], S [2,1] v not W [2,1], S [2,1] v not W [2,2],

S [2,1] v not W [3,1], W [1,3] ===>s W [1,3], S [1,1], B [1,1], B [1,2], S [2,1]

proves that this is an axiom

Page 26: Inference is carried out by  inference rules,  which allow one formula to be

S [1,2], B [2,1], S [1,1] v not W [1,1], S [1,1] v not W [1,2], S [1,1] v not W [2,1],

S [2,1] v not W [1,1], S [2,1] v not W [2,1], S [2,1] v not W [2,2],

S [2,1] v not W [3,1], W [1,2] ===>s W [1,3], S [1,1], B [1,1], B [1,2], S [2,1]

Applying R3 to the underlined disjunct will create two new sequents, the first of which is an axiom because S [1,1] will be on both sides of the arrow, and the second after applying R1 (moving not W [1,2] to the right) will be proven because W [1,2] will be on both sides.

S [1,2], B [2,1], S [1,1] v not W [1,1], S [1,1] v not W [1,2], S [1,1] v not W [2,1],

S [2,1] v not W [1,1], S [2,1] v not W [2,1], S [2,1] v not W [2,2],

S [2,1] v not W [3,1], W [2,2] ===>s W [1,3], S [1,1], B [1,1], B [1,2], S [2,1]

Same as above to prove that the two resulting sequents are axioms.

S [1,2], B [2,1], S [1,1] v not W [1,1], S [1,1] v not W [1,2], S [1,1] v not W [2,1],

S [2,1] v not W [1,1], S [2,1] v not W [2,1], S [2,1] v not W [2,2],

S [2,1] v not W [3,1], W [1,1] ===>s W [1,3], S [1,1], B [1,1], B [1,2], S [2,1]

Same as above to prove that the two resulting sequents are axioms.

All sequents proven, therefore W [1,3] follows from the initial premises.


Recommended