+ All Categories
Home > Documents > ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working...

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working...

Date post: 13-Oct-2020
Category:
Upload: others
View: 0 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend
35
Transcript
Page 1: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should
Page 2: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

IMF WORKING PAPERThis is a working paper and the author would welcome anycomments on the present text. Citations should refer to anunpublished manuscript, mentioning the author and the dateof issuance by the International Monetary Fund. The viewsexpressed are those of the author and do not necessarilyrepresent those of the Fund.

WP/88/18 INTERNATIONAL MONETARY FUND

Fiscal Affairs Department

The Case for Earmarked Taxes: Theory and an Example

Prepared by Ranjit S. Teja *

Authorized for Distribution by Peter S. Heller

February 18, 1988

Abstract

The earmarking (or setting aside) of revenues from various taxesfor specific types of expenditure is a much maligned fiscal practice.The paper examines a number of theoretical arguments and institutionalcircumstances under which earmarking (even widespread earmarking) may bewelfare enhancing. The paper also questions the criticism thatearmarking seriously erodes budgetary efficiency, and draws on theexperience of Colombia to demonstrate that the worst fears of critics donot necessarily come to pass.

JEL Classification numbers:3220,3230

* I am indebted to Thanos Catsambas, Peter Heller, A. Premchand,S. Ramachandran, and Jaime Vázquez for helpful comments and discussion.

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution

Page 3: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

11

Contents Page

I. Introduction 1

II. The Theoretical Rationale for Earmarked Taxes 2

1. Lindahl's theory 22. The public choice perspective 53. The benefits principle of taxation and the

economics of user charges 9A. Bureaucracy versus the legislature 105. Earmarking and intertemporal horsetrading 106. Other arguments 127. Summary 13

III. The Case Against Earmarking 14

IV. Earmarking in Practice 15

V. Concluding Remarks 20

Text Table1. Colombia: Earmarked Taxes, 1978 17

References 21

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution

Page 4: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

ill

jummary

Earmarking revenues for specific uses is frequently criticized asan unnecessary constraint in the efficient provision of publicly suppliedgoods and services. Detractors of earmarking portray such provisionsas a cause of budget inflexibility and, ultimately, not amounting to muchmore than a bald attempt by special interest groups to protect favoredexpenditures. This paper attempts to redress the balance, emphasizingthe welfare—enhancing aspects of earmarking and drawing attention to thepossibility that earmarking may be more a mechanism for escaping (ratherthan a cause of) economic and budgetary inefficiencies.

Although one can think of a number of positive arguments explain-ing the existence of earmarking, the normative case for earmarked taxesrests fundamentally on the assumption that individuals and groups insociety have differing preferences for public and private goods andservices. Earmarking allows individuals to express their preferencesfor public goods with tax dollars—in much the same way they expresstheir preferences for potatoes with outlays earmarked to the productionof potatoes—and to resolve their differences in socially desirableways. The analysis also emphasizes the rule-enforcing aspects of ear-marking clauses when there is conflict of interest between bureaucraciesand legislatures or when moral hazard forces legislatures to foregosocially beneficial expenditures. Where exclusion in public consumptionis feasible, earmarking can be seen as an application of the "benefitsprinciple of taxation" with taxes paid by beneficiaries earmarked tothe provision of that public good. In this case, an earmarked tax ismuch like a user charge and differs only in its mode of collection.

The paper also describes the experience of Colombia and argues that,despite shortcomings, the system has not carried earmarking to the pointthat it imposes significant constraints on efficient budgeting and bud-get flexibility. In fact, it is suggested that earmarking was set upas a defense against poor budgeting and expenditure control practices.

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution

Page 5: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

This page intentionally left blank

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution

Page 6: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

I. Introduction

The earmarking of taxes refers to the designation of funds—eitherfrom a single tax base or from a wider pool of revenues—to a particularend use. Typical examples include the earmarking of revenues fromproperty taxes for education, gasoline taxes for highway construction,and payroll taxes for social security payments. This may be contrastedwith general fund finance where expenditures are financed from consolidatedreceipts. For a number of reasons, the practice has been condemned aswasteful and inefficient. At the bottom of much of this criticism isthe homely analogy with households constrained to spending the receiptsfrom each source of income for specific items of consumption: whicheconomist has not experienced a twinge, of shame when earmarking incomefrom a spouse's new job toward the down payment on a house, or convertingwindfall profits into a vacation budget? Nevertheless, earmarkingprovisions are a pervasive fiscal phenomenon in both developed anddeveloping economies and are even written into the constitutions of somecountries.

Section II of this paper assesses the theoretical case forearmarking and also provides a positive analysis of its widespreadexistence. "Theoretical" refers to the conventional analysis of welfareeconomics and public choice theory. This may be distinguished from the"practical" aspects of public administration and budgeting. Readersfrom the latter tradition—particularly those familiar with the extremeforms of earmarking found in parts of Latin America and Africa—are aptto receive the arguments in this section with, at best, courteouscynicism. At the risk of some oversimplification, this may beattributed to an underlying tendency to view the task of budgeting andadministration from the point of view of the representative household,or, what amounts to the same thing, from the perspective of the benev-olent social planner. This attitude prevents a proper appreciation ofwhat emerges in Section II as the true role of earmarking in publicfinance: that of a mechanism for the resolution of differing andconflicting preferences in society. In reading Section II, it is alsoimportant to bear in mind two sets of distinctions: (a) normativeversus positive analysis; and (b) arguments supporting earmarking forspecific expenditures versus full-scale earmarking for all publicexpenditure.

Standard examples of earmarked taxes—the gasoline tax earmarkedfor highway construction or maintenance and the social security tax—have fostered the view that they are basically a means of taxing onlythose who directly benefit from a certain expenditure. (The obverse ofthis phenomemenon is incredulity at seeing taxes on liquor earmarked foreducation rather than for the rehabilitation of alcoholics.) It isremarkable then that the theoretical literature on earmarked taxes dealsalmost exclusively with "pure" public goods (i.e., characterized by the.impossibility or inefficiency of excluding any member of a communityonce a good has been supplied), a context in which viewing earmarkedtaxes as "benefit taxes" is ambiguous (but, as we shall see, not

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution

Page 7: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

— 9 —

entirely meaningless). The economic rationale—and the politicalmotives—for earmarking taxes are more subtle than suggested by thebenefits theory of taxation. However, once impure public goods areconsidered (goods with externalities, local public goods, etc.), thebenefits theory of taxation moves center stage as a normativecriterion. In that case an earmarked tax is essentially a user chargeand differs only in its mode of collection.

It will thus be most fruitful to taxonomize the theoreticalrationale for earmarked taxes according to the public goods charac-teristics of the commodity or service in question. Section II.1 andII.2 examine alternative perspectives for dealing with "pure" publicgoods; this may loosely be thought of as the "pure theory of earmarkedtaxation." Section II.3 covers the economics of user charges and thepotential choice between earmarking and user charges. The part playedby earmarking as a rule-enforcing device is examined in Sections II.4and II.5. Finally, Section II.6 presents some additional considerationsnot formally modeled in the literature.

Section III briefly examines the case against earmarking from theperspective of efficient budgeting and administration. Section IVutilizes the framework developed in the previous two sections to assessthe practice of earmarking in Colombia. The paper concludes with someobservations on the circumstances under which earmarking may berecommended.

II. The Theoretical Rationale for Earmarked Taxes

1. Lindahl's theory

Decisions on the provision of public goods may be taken either inthe context of a vigorous democracy with an active legislature or,alternatively, by executive decree. Here, we adopt the former per-spective and, in this context, begin by disposing of the questionableanalogy with the household that earmarks earnings from different sourcesfor various end uses. This analogy would have been appropriate if itwere indeed true that legislatures make decisions the way individualsdo. An earmarking provision is then an unnecessary constraint in theutility-maximization problem of allocating the last dollar to yieldequal marginal utility in every direction. But it is a fact of lifethat a legislature i s a forum where conflicting preferences areexpressed and resolved. Moreover, a legislature, in principle, does notmake expenditure decisions without simultaneously determining revenuerequirements.

Both these features that distinguish fiscal decision-making fromthat of the individual household were elegantly captured in the writingsof Knut Wickseil and, subsequently, Eric Lindahl over sixty years ago.A by-product of that analysis was a welfare theoretical case for

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution

Page 8: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

- 3 -

earmarked taxation based on the Pareto criterion. The main point isthat the alternative to earmarked taxes—general fund financing—willresult in non-Pareto efficient outcomes.

Following Johansen's (1963) exposition, consider an economy withtwo pure public goods, G and S, and a composite private good X. Let Y^and Yg be the incomes of two types of individuals—A and B—and X^ andXg their consumption of the private good X. Let h denote A1 s "taxshare" in the financing of total expenditures (G+S), so that B's shareis (1-h). Under general fund financing, both public goods are financedby the revenues derived from these lump-sum taxes. Given utilityfunctions UA(XA,G,S) and Ug(Xg,G,S), each agent maximizes utilitysubject to the corresponding budget constraint:

(1)

(2)

yielding the following first-order conditions:

(3)

(A)

(5)

(6)

The system of equations consists of six equations but only fiveunknowns (G,S,X¿,Xg, and h) and hence is overdetermined. In otherwords, no tax share h is capable of meeting all the requirements forefficiency.

One way to arrive at a determinate solution is to assume thatpreferences are identical. Then equations (3) and (5) are duplicated sothat we are really left with five equations in five unknowns. But thistrivializes the whole problem, robbing fiscal analysis of one of itsdistinguishing features.

Suppose instead chat expenditures on G and S are met from twoseparate "earmarked" funds. Thus, expenditure on G is met by payment ofgG by A and (l-g)G by B; likewise, for S, A pays sS while B pays (1-s)S. Agents now maximize utility functions subject to the new budgetconstraints

(I1)

(21)

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution

Page 9: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

- A -

which yields a new set of first order equations

(31)

(4')

(5')

(6')

The system now consists of six equations and six variables andhence can be solved for the optimal values of G, S, XA, Xß, g, and s.

Note that rearranging (3')-(6') yields

(7)

The terms on the left are the sums of A and B's marginal rates ofsubstitution for each public good. The marginal rates of transformationof G and S for X are, by construction, unity. The earmarking solution,then, is equivalent to Samuelson's well known condition for the Paretoefficient allocation of public goods and, indeed is necessary for Paretoefficiency: both individuals can be made better off by moving fromgeneral fund financing to earmarking.

This case for earmarking has been couched in terms of numbers ofequations and unknowns. However, recalling that the problem is resolvedwhen preferences are identical, it should be clear that the role ofearmarking lies in facilitating the mutual accommodation of differingpreferences in the economy. Note also that since tax shares are derivedfrom individuals' marginal rates of substitution in utility, the taxshares may be viewed as a form of "benefits taxation." Although every-one consumes the same level of public goods, agents pay for this inaccordance with their marginal utility (benefit).

Although the Lindahl theory espouses widespread earmarking for eachpublic good, the accounts can always be consolidated once a consensushas been reached. This prevents the myopia that may arise, as apractical matter, when there are a myriad of special funds in thebudget. Also, the analysis presumes that agents continually reassesstaxes and expenditures through time.

As students of public economics well know, a fundamental short-coming of Lindahl's analysis is the assumption that agents in theeconomy will truthfully reveal their preferences. Equations (3')-(6')state that an individual's tax burden for any particular good is deter-mined by his marginal rate of substitution vis-à-vis private goods.Owing to nonexcludability in consumption inherent in pure public goods,an agent has every incentive to understate the marginal benefit derived

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution

Page 10: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

— s —

from an additional unit of the public good. Although economists havedevised clever (sometimes bizarre) mechanisms for the truthfulrevelation of preferences that approximate the Lindahl equilibrium, theimplementation of Lindahl's solution remains a complex and difficultissue. /̂

2. The public choice perspective

While a mainstream theorist is apt to view earmarking as a con-straint on expenditure, the public choice school stands this propositionon its head and argues, instead, that it is general fund financing thatimposes constraints on voters' choices. General fund finance involvesthe acceptance of a budget that effectively requires consumers topurchase (through payment of taxes) a bundle of complex andheterogeneous products. This forces the public to consume goods in aless than optimal mix. As Buchanan has put it, "...any requirement thatone stick of butter be purchased with each loaf of bread would surelyproduce inefficiency in choice..." Public choice theory—like Lindahl'stheory—explains the existence of earmarking and draws normativeconclusions from its potential role in facilitating individualpreferences. The main difference lies in the fact that Lindahl's theoryis predicated on complete consensus, whereas public choice theoryrecognizes the existence of majority voting.

An insightful distinction between earmarked taxation and generalfund finance can be illustrated as follows. Under the former, theequilibrium quantity of each public good is determined by a separatevote along with a specified tax, or set of taxes, to finance thatexpenditure. The opportunity cost to the voter of an additionalbattleship then is higher taxes rather than reduced expenditures onother public goods. General fund financing, on the other hand, ischaracterized by separate voting on the size of the budget (tax bills)and the composition of expenditures (expenditure bills). Given thegovernment s separately determined budget constraint, the opportunitycost of an extra battleship is no longer higher taxes but insteadreduced expenditure on other public goods. This separation of taxdecisions and expenditure decisions lies at the heart of the publicchoice school's normative case for earmarked taxes.

One strand of this approach—initiated in Buchanan's (1963) seminalpaper—argues that the voter who might have approved a tax increase ifit were earmarked to, say, environmental protection would oppose itunder general fund finance because he or she may expect the increment tobe allocated to an unfavored expenditure such as defense. Earmarkedtaxation then permits a more satisfactory expression of individualpreferences. While Buchanan's analysis is basically an exercise inpositive economics, it has distinct normative overtones.

7̂ For a good review of preference revelation mechanisms, see Mueller(1979).

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution

Page 11: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

- 6 -

A second strand—developed in Browning (1975)—draws attention tothe possibility of perverse outcomes under general fund financing thatmay argue for the institution of widespread earmarking. The constraintsimposed by the separation of tax decisions and expenditure decisions aresufficiently serious that there is little basis for predicting theoutcome under general fund financing. It may well turn out that a lowerquantity of a public good will be supplied even if every voter'spreference for that good increased.

Both these points can be demonstrated using a simple geometricaldevice developed by Browning (1975). Consider a community of threevoters (A, B, and C) consuming two public goods (G and S), and acomposite private good (X). .To abstract from distributional issues, itis assumed that tax shares g1 and s1, i = A,B,C, are exogenously given,as is the market price (marginal cost), px, of the private good and thatall goods are produced at constant marginal cost. The budget constraintof any agent is:

(8)

where Y1 is agent i's fixed income. Each agent maximizes the utilityfunction U1(X,G,S) subject to the budget constraint (8).

The budget plane defined by equation (8) is depicted in Figure 1 asBjiBnBo, while the utility function (not drawn in) can be visualized as asequence of nested bowls tilted against the origin. The optimalconsumption bundle is given by the point where a bowl is tangent to.thebudget plane. This can be mapped on the (G,S) plane as the point E1.Other bowls that slice the budget plane trace out concentric circles(more generally, ellipses) around E1, where outer circles represent alower level of utility as they correspond to bowls nearer the origin.Thus any one circle (or utility contour) is much like an indifferencecurve but utility declines as one moves away from the innermost circlessurrounding E1.

Two more preliminaries must be set aside before turning to Buchananand Browning's analyses. First, how is the budget decided underearmarking? Assume, as in Figure 2, that voter A is the median voter onboth the issue of G and S to be supplied to the public. I/ Under simplemajority voting, the decisions on G and S are made separately, say,first G and then S. A will immediately gravitate to the point E and inso doing will implicitly accede to being taxed first by an amount g Gand then (when choosing S) by an amount s S". This is precisely what is

_!/ Note that the three voters' optima are such that, relative to A, Cprefers more S, while B prefers less S. This makes A the median voteron the amount of S to be supplied. Likewise, A is also the median voteron the equilibrium quantity of G.

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution

Page 12: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

- 6a -

Figure 1

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution

Page 13: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

- 6b -

Figure 2

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution

Page 14: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

- 7 -

referred to as "earmarking": the practice of taking a decision on eachpublic good, together with a decision on taxes to finance thatexpenditure, separately from other public goods.

Second, how are the size and the composition of the budget decidedupon under general fund finance? The size of the budget is the value ofG plus S. For any point (G,S), it is the length along the axesresulting from drawing in the relative price of G and S (the ratio ofmarginal costs—assumed here, for simplicity, to equal unity). Next,for any given budget size, say MN in Figure 3, an agent maximizesutility by choosing a point where an indifference contour is tangent toit. Consideration of a sequence of budget sizes yields, for each agent,a locus of points describing the preferred composition of the budget forevery budget size. These loci are depicted, for simplicity, as straightlines in Figure 3.

In Figure 4, A is assumed to have the median preference as regardsboth budget composition and budget size. In this special case, thegeneral fund financing and earmarking solutions are identical. On theother hand, in Figure 5, A has the median preference with regard tobudget mix, but B has the median preference for budget size. In thiscase, the general fund financing solution is given by the point K, alongthe median budget size MN, where A 1s preferences (regarding budgetcomposition) dominate.

With these preliminaries in hand, we can now turn to the pointraised by Buchanan (1963). Buchanan compared earmarking with the casewhere an exogenous "budgetary authority" sets the budget mix whilevote-s can only choose the size of the budget. In Figure 6, thebudgetary authority imposes the mix OR. Given this budget mix, votersmust select the overall size of the budget by choosing a point alongOR. Each voter's utility is maximized by picking a point along OR wherean indifference contour is tangent to it. In the example presented inFigure 6, voter A happens to be the median voter on the size of thebudget. Note that the bureaucracy's choice will definitely lower A 1swelfare, since A is the median voter on the issues of both budget sizeand budget mix. In the configuration assumed in Figure 6, it alsohappens to lower everyone's welfare (since the indifference contourspassing through the earmarking solution E are smaller than thosepassing through the general fund financing solution).

While the condemnation of general fund finance is stark in thisexample, the result is obviously not general. In particular, it isarbitrary to assume an exogenous selection of the budget mix (oralternatively, of the size of the budget). As we have already seen,public choice under general fund finance can be generalized to anendogenous selection of both budget size and budget mix. Whenever onevoter does not possess the median preference on the issue of both budget

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution

Page 15: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

- 8 -

composition and budget size as in Figure 5 (i.e., when the earmarkingand general fund financing solutions are different), then at least oneof the parties will be worse off by a move to earmarking.

It is worth noting here that neither earmarking nor general fundfinance will meet the Samuelsonian criterion for optimality (except bychance), since the tax shares are assumed to be given. However, anexamination of Figure 7 reveals that both earmarking and general fundfinance are constrained Pareto efficient (constrained, of course, bygiven tax shares). To see this, consider the utility contours passingthrough the point E (the earmarking solution) and point K (the generalfund financing solution). Any point outside the envelope of thesecontours leaves all three worse off; any movement within the envelopeleaves at least one of the three worse off. The moral is that thechoice between earmarking and general fund finance ultimately depends onthe choice of a social welfare function and there are no easygeneralizations. The model is thus useful for predicting support forearmarking provisions but not for drawing normative conclusions.

Turning now to Browning's point about perverse outcomes undergeneral fund financing, suppose that starting from the equilibriumposition (62,82) in Figure 8, all three voters' preference for Gincreases. This is shown as a rightward shift in each of E ,HE , and Eto E* H,E' , and E' . Although A remains the median voter on budgetcomposition, A rather than B now determines the actual size of thebudget. In Figure 8, the new equilibrium amount of G publicly suppliedfalls, despite a unanimous increase in preference for G—a paradoxicaloutcome that could not occur under earmarked taxes. The paradox arisesfrom the dependence on the preferences of the median voter. The issuesunder earmarking and general fund finance are different—under thelatter, one separately chooses budget size and budget composition. Themedian voter associated with the distinct issues of budget size andbudget composition may change, which influences the outcome. No suchcomplication affects decision-making under earmarking.

The public choice approach is frequently received with skepticism.Goode (1984), for example, draws attention to its irrelevance in countriesthat lack provision for citizen participation. A much strongercriticism of its normative aspects—even in circumstances where they maybe valid as in Figure 5—is the underlying assumption that voterscontinuously (or even once in a while) re-evaluate their position onearmarking. A widely noted tendency (see, for example, Deran (1965)) isfor earmarking provisions to become embedded in the state's financialstructure and not to be re-evaluated as conditions change. In practice,the level of public goods supplied will depend entirely on the amount ofearmarked revenues and costs, regardless of whether that level hasbecome excessive or deficient. While the usual example cited in thisregard is exaggeratedly horrifying (the continued presence in two U.S.states during the mid 1960s of taxes earmarked for Confederatepensions), most would agree that rigidity in earmarking provisions is

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution

Page 16: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

- 8a -

Figure 3

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution

Page 17: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

8b

Figure 4

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution

Page 18: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

- 8c -

Figure 5

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution

Page 19: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

- 8d -

Figure 6

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution

Page 20: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

8e

Figure 7

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution

Page 21: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

- 8f -

Figure 8

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution

Page 22: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

- 9 -

the ultimate flaw in the concept. The moral, then, is that suchprovisions should be mandatorily reviewed at regular intervals whenevertheir introduction becomes inevitable.

3. The benefits principle of taxation and the economics ofuser charges

Frequently, the use of earmarked taxation is justified by invokingthe "benefits principle of taxation," which argues that taxes should beborne by those who most benefit from the associated expenditure. Thenotion is appealing to economists because it parallels the marketmechanism for private goods. The analogy makes most sense when animpure public good is characterized by excludability in consumption.Then it becomes possible to finance the activity with a user charge.Although user charges are in a sense "earmarked" to their associatedactivity, the implementation of a user charge is not equivalent to anearmarked tax in terms of efficiency and equity. When the implemen-tation of user charges is judged to be administratively infeasible ortoo costly, an earmarked tax can be used as a second-best instrument offinance (e.g., a gasoline tax as a proxy for charges on highwayusers). In this case, it is essential that the base of the earmarkedtax bear some relation to the level of public consumption.

The simple economics of user charges sheds some light on theprinciples that determine the extent of revenues to be earmarked.Consider the provision of an excludable public good characterized bypositive externalities. In Figure 9, the marginal social benefit (MSB)from a unit of consumption exceeds the corresponding private benefit(MRS). The marginal cost of production (MCP) is, for simplicity,assumed to be constant at p^. The optimal level of consumption forsociety is q*, for which consumers are willing to pay only P2« Then q*,can be publicly provided by a user charge of p2> together with a perunit subsidy of (pi - PO ) • The subsidy will have to come from thegovernment's general fund rather than from direct consumers. Financingshould come entirely from general funds only if social benefits are solarge as to imply a user charge so low that it would barely cover theadded costs of collection.

It is possible that owing to price distortions in the economy thefinancial cost of implementing user charges may diverge from the socialopportunity cost of employing these resources elsewhere. The oppor-tunity cost of using experienced managers and accountants may beextremely high in developing countries. It may make sense in such acircumstance to earmark revenues from an easily administered tax basethat varies positively with the level of public good consumption, forexample, gasoline tax revenues for highway construction and mainten-ance. Ideally, earmarked revenues should total Poq*» while theremainder, (p, - Po)*}" *s financed by general revenues unrelated to thelevel of consumption of the good. In fact, this is precisely howexpenditure on road construction and maintenance is financed in a number

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution

Page 23: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

- 10 -

of countries. Eklund (1972) reports that, for a cross section ofcountries with earmarking provisions, an average of 63 percent of allroad expenditure was financed out of the general fund.

A. Bureaucracy versus the legislature

A somewhat more institutional ist perspective on earmarking may begained by pursuing in greater detail—as Niskanen (1971) has—thequestion of who precisely supplies public goods and services. Whiledemand for public goods is expressed and resolved in the legislature,public goods are generally supplied by bureaucracies. According to oneview, the distinguishing characteristic of a bureaucracy is the absenceof external control on efficiency and weak internal incentives. Weakexternal control results from the ambiguous nature of a bureaucracy'soutput \_l and the dependence of the legislature on the bureaucracy forinformation. Weak internal incentives to produce efficiently are aconsequence of an absence of financial incentives for managers and alack of competition in the market for their final output. The effect ofthis constellation of circumstances is to make bureaucrats pursue goalsother than efficiency, such as larger staff establishments, prestige,and patronage. As most of these are positively related to the size ofthe budget, Niskanen analyzed the behavior of bureaucracies in terms ofthe budget-maximizing bureaucrat, who is in a bilateral monopolyposition with the legislature.

This approach to bureaucratic behavior can be used to rationalizethe legislative tactic of earmarking revenues for specific end uses.Numerous expenditures exist that are clearly in the public interest, butwhich bureaucracies may have little interest in pursuing adequately. Agood example is expenditure on operations and maintenance of publicstructures and capital. The prestige-maximizing bureaucrat generallyprefers to see his department's allocation go to new and high-profileinvestment and construction projects rather than to something as mundaneas maintaining an old road or irrigation ditch. While it is true thatbureaucratic reputation may depreciate along with public structures, theprocess is long and managers are rarely stationary targets. As propermaintenance of the capital stock is in many countries an urgent issue,the legislature (or the executive branch) may force the bureaucracy'shand on the matter by earmarking funds for maintenance expenditures.

5. Earmarking and intertemporal horsetrading

Earmarked revenues can also serve to enforce long-term dealsbetween legislators, and in the process be welfare enhancing. Considerthe case of the U.S. Hazardous Substance Response Fund (or "Superfund"),which obtains revenue from excise taxes on petroleum and chemicals and

_!/ For example, the Ministry of Defense produces an amalgalm ofsoldiers, guns, ships, and aircraft from which the final output ofinterest to the consumer—defense services—must be inferred.

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution

Page 24: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

- 10a -

Figure 9

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution

Page 25: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

- 11 -

uses the proceeds to help clean up environmental damage caused by theirproduction and disposal. I./ While taxing the chemical industry as awhole can be rationalized as a crude approximation to the "polluter-must-pay" principle, one can still question the validity of earmarkingthe proceeds to a special fund. Why should such revenues not beassigned too—and expenditures be met from—the general fund?

Consider now the following explanation. The ex ante probability ofdiscovering a toxic waste dump is roughly the same across the country.However, ex post, a legislator from Nevada has no incentive to approvecleanup expenditures in New York (because it is a pure income transfer),unless the legislator from New York can assure reciprocal support in theevent of a similar disaster in Nevada at some future date. Butlegislators from New York cannot bind their successors to suchpromises. A way out of this impasse is to earmark revenues for aspecial fund whose expenditures do not require legislative approval.Such a one-time agreement enforces mutual promises through time and, inthis instance, permits the introduction of a welfare-enhancing publicactivi ty.

It is interesting to note that the Superfund may not be used toclean up oil spills (even in the unlikely event that the perpetratorcannot be identified). This can be explained by the fact that theex ante probability of an oil spill is not uniform across states. Onlycoastal states are concerned, and legislators from the interior of theUnited States will naturally oppose a long-term commitment (i.e., anearmarked fund) for such purposes.

The role of earmarking in enforcing commitments between legislatorscan be extended to a number of situations. Eklund (1969), for instance,points out that in fractionalistic societies with unstable majoritycoalitions, earmarking may be the only way in which new expenditure

l/ Jankowski (1984) has suggested that the Superfund is essentially aPigovian tax. This is not correct because the supporting taxes are notintended to influence the current flow of pollution, but rather to cleanup the stock of past environmental damage perpetrated by unknown orinsolvent parties. Moreover, a single instrument such as the Pigoviantax on the level of effluence would be socially inoptimal for dealingwith two issues (the cleanup of existing toxic waste and the appropriatelevel of future effluence).

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution

Page 26: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

- 12 -

decisions can be agreed upon. In the absence of such a provision,society will tend toward the status quo, in the process forgoing publicprojects with a high return to society. _!/

While the rule enforcing aspect of earmarking enhances welfare inthese cases, the opposite may also occur in practice. Special interestgroups may want to earmark specific taxes as a means of limiting theirtax burden. The petroleum industry, for example, may lobby for ear-marking any gasoline tax for highway maintenance, if they suspect thatthere is limited scope for expansion of this activity. Similarly,firearms manufacturers would attempt to earmark taxes levied on theirindustry for a complementary activity such as maintenance of wildlife.

6. Other arguments

One justification for earmarking taxes concerns the deleteriouseffects of erratic financing. Revenue flows can be very unstable overthe life of large public sector projects, resulting in costly idling ofheavy machinery over extended periods of time for want of timely andadequate funding. Earmarking receipts from a stable revenue base is ameans of protecting socially important projects from the exigencies of abudgetary crunch and can, over time, be an important cost-saving devicefor the public sector. In terms of Figure 9, the cost schedule MCP islowered when steady finance is made available through earmarked taxes.While earmarking serves as a constraint on budgetary flexibility, it isnevertheless argued that the inflexibility in the overall size of thebudget is welfare enhancing because there are offsetting savings incosts. It is precisely this sort of consideration that has prompted theWorld Bank to attach earmarking clauses to project finance in severaldeveloping countries.

Another justification for earmarking taxes is that in a number ofdeveloping countries, where democratic institutions are weak andmistrust of the government is high, earmarked taxation can improve taxcompliance. If the public can be assured that taxes will be spent intheir locality rather than, say, used to indulge a strongman's penchantfor military expansion, they will be more willing to comply withexisting taxes. In this case, earmarking substitutes for lack ofrepresentative power in the executive and legislative branches ofgovernment.

I/ Legislators are not the only class that may resort to earmarkingin such a circumstance. Wilkie (1974) and Premchand (1983) suggestthat, in a number of Latin American countries, earmarking was motivatedby the executive branch of government, which wanted to bypass theproblem posed by legislative logrolling and unstable coalitions.

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution

Page 27: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

- 13 -

Third, earmarked taxes and user charges can play an important partin promoting economic stability. Consider for example the case of adeveloping country that is reliant on export taxes. An exogenousdecline in export proceeds would not only adversely affect the exportsector but also entail cutbacks in development spending. If spendingwas not reduced accordingly, the alternatives—given monetary policies—are, of course, a deterioration in the balance of payments andinflation. To the extent that the tax bases underlying earmarked fundsare more stable than trade taxes—user charges for roads and water maybe expected to be so—macroeconomic stability may be enhanced by usingcertain earmarked taxes.

Fourth, many countries have in recent years been unable to musterthe political will to make painful (but necessary) fiscal adjustments inthe face of serious external shocks. In a number of cases, the brunt offiscal adjustment has been borne entirely by capital and infrastructuralexpenditure with minimal reduction of current expenditures. While thedistinction between current and development expenditure should not beexaggerated—underfunding of the recurrent costs of development expen-diture is a long-standing problem in developing countries—there is atendency to cut back on vital infrastructural and maintenance expen-ditures rather than on public sector employment and wages. An ear-marking clause, designed to protect vital projects and expenditures,would strengthen the government's hand in reducing less sociallyproductive components of public expenditure.

7. Summary

The normative case for earmarked taxes rests fundamentally on theassumption that groups and individuals in society have differentpreferences. Earmarking provides voters an opportunity to reveal theirpreferences for public goods with their tax dollars. This is similar tothe mechanism in private markets where individuals reveal theirpreference for potatoes with outlays earmarked for the production ofpotatoes. _!/ Earmarking may be loosely thought of as an application ofthe benefits principle of taxation since, as in private markets, taxesare paid according to perceived benefits. This is readily seen in caseswhere excludability in consumption is feasible, but is difficult toimplement when it is not.

The analogy with private markets also breaks down when we descendinto the real world of majority voting in legislatures. However, we didderive the important lesson in Section II.2 that one cannot, in general,make a welfare comparison between earmarking and general fund financesince there are gainers and losers under both regimes; public choicetheory provides only a positive analysis of earmarking. The possibility

_!/ Whether or not the underlying distribution of income is "just" is,of course, a separate issue.

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution

Page 28: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

- 14 -

of perverse outcomes under general fund financing—such as a decline inthe provision of a public good even when there is a unanimous increasein public preference for that good—is one argument against that system.

The role of earmarking as a rule-enforcing device was also noted inthe context of conflict of interest with the bureaucracy as well as infacilitating a welfare-enhancing provision of public goods acrosstime. Finally, it was noted that earmarking may improve both thecomposition of public expenditure and the stability of the budgetdeficit in developing countries.

With the exception of Lindahl's theory, most normative argumentssupport earmarking for specific goods and services rather than advocatefull-scale earmarking for all public expenditures. As a practicalmatter too, it is important to examine instances of earmarkingindividually, since our positive analysis revealed that it may arisefrom a number of welfare-reducing causes such as rent seeking or taxavoidance by special interest groups.

Ill. The Case Against Earmarking

The case against earmarking is best summarized by Deran (1965):

(a) Earmarking hampers effective budgetary control.(b) Earmarking leads to a misallocation of funds, giving excess

revenues to some functions while others are undersupported.(c) Earmarking imparts inflexibility to the revenue structure,

with the result that legislatures are hard put to make suitableadjustments when conditions change.

(d) Earmarking provisions often remain in force long after theneed for which they were established has vanished.

(e) By removing a portion of fiscal action from periodic reviewand control, earmarking infringes on the policymaking powers of stateexecutives and legislatures.

Such criticisms derive from a particular outlook on publicfinance: that of the benevolent social planner attempting to maximize awell-defined social welfare function. However, the essence of thetheoretical arguments for earmarking derived from a completely differentview of society: one where voters with differing preferences attempt toarrive at a consensus (or at least a simple majority) to supportalternative public expenditures. Thus any evaluation of earmarkingshould include a judgment about the appropriate model of social choice.

Even if one accepts the benevolent social planner approach, otherdifficulties remain. The arguments against earmarking implicitly assumethat the alternative of general fund finance will eliminate the problemsassociated with earmarking. Points (b)-(e) imply, for instance, thatexpenditures under general fund financing are indeed periodicallyreviewed and adjusted to ensure that no program is under- or over-

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution

Page 29: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

- 15 -

provided for. The empirical basis for such an assertion is highlyquestionable. Most budgeting under general fund financing occursincrementally rather than by a procedure that evaluates each tax andexpenditure afresh from year to year. Clearly then, any rejection ofearmarking should verify whether the public sector is indeed capable ofdelivering a superior result without earmarking.

Finally, the extent to which earmarking leads to rigidity in thebudget should be ascertained. Many, like Premchand (1983), would arguethat it is not earmarking per se, but rather its prevalence that is thekey issue. Although widespread earmarking may induce rigidities in thebudget, there are ways to reduce this effect. For example, adjustmentscan be made to the base or the tax rate of an earmarked pool ofrevenues. Alternatively, an activity can be jointly financed by bothearmarked and general fund revenues, the latter providing the latitudenecessary to make discretionary changes at the margin.

More fundamentally, one can question whether it is really worthmaking such a fuss about budget rigidity. Earmarked taxes are anapplication of the benefits principle of taxation and may be associatedwith higher revenues. As pointed out by Bird (1984), "it makes littlesense to criticize earmarking for budgetary rigidity, since withoutearmarking, there would be less of a budget to be rigid about."

IV. Earmarking in Practice

No attempt is made here to provide an empirical overview of theextent of earmarking in the world economy or any class of countries.Instead, we limit ourselves to the more modest objective of describingthe experience of just one country—Colombia—chosen to illustrate boththe beneficial role that can be played by earmarking as well as some ofthe pitfalls.

The complex nature of the issue makes it very difficult to judgewhether a particular regime of earmarking has been a success or afailure. The strategy adopted here involves weighing the potentialbenefits of earmarking derived in Section II against the costsattributed to it by its detractors. A proper evaluation of the benefitsrequires that each instance of earmarking be considered, to use asensible bureaucratic cliché, "on a case-by-case basis." A properevaluation of the costs requires consideration of the effects ofearmarking on budget formulation and overall fiscal policy. The latterrequires some judgment whether the extent of earmarking has reached thepoint where there is little room for maneuver in adjusting fiscalpolicies to changing circumstances.

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution

Page 30: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

- 16 -

Earmarking is extensive in Colombia. I/ A conservative estimate—which excludes a number of smaller earmarked taxes, as well as theretained profits of public enterprises—indicates that earmarked taxesaccounted for about 45 percent of total tax revenue in 1978. Table 1provides a partial listing of major taxes and the expenditures for whichthey were earmarked. In fact, the practice of earmarking is a greatdeal more complex than suggested by this table, as there are numerousinstances of convoluted two-tier and three-tier earmarking, where anagency receiving the proceeds of a tax is required to earmark a certainfraction of the receipts for another agency or enterprise.

Coffee taxes. The largest class of earmarked taxes in Colombia arecoffee taxes. A number of taxes are levied on coffee exports and aconsiderable percentage of the proceeds are earmarked for the NationalCoffee Fund. The organizations of growers comprising the Coffee Fundutilize these resources to finance various activities. Some of theseexpenditures can be justified on grounds of benefits taxation. Forexample, in 1978, the Coffee Fund spent 7 percent of its earmarkedreceipts on direct benefits to growers by providing important agri-cultural inputs as well as infrastructure in the form of aquaducts,health, and education in coffee producing areas; in the same year,60 percent was retained by the Fund as part of its price stabilizationactivities. Other expenditures have no rationale at all: the Fundspent 33 percent of its receipts in 1978 to subsidize domestic coffeeconsumption, a questionable use of resources for a developing country.

Overall, given the Fund's surplus and the fact that a considerableportion of expenditure makes little developmental sense, one could arguethat the earmarking of coffee taxes is somewhat excessive. Although theGovernment has already effectively de-earmarked some revenue by forcingthe Fund to invest a part of its surplus in government securities,matters could be improved by reducing the amount earmarked for theCoffee Fund.

Payroll taxes. A second major group of earmarked revenues are payrolltaxes, which are mostly assigned to various social securityinstitutions. The benefits rationale underlying earmarking is quiteclear in these cases. Likewise, a benefits rationale partly applies tothe Colombian Family Welfare Institute (ICBF). Among the activitiesfinanced by a separate 2 percent payroll tax is the provision of childcare services for working couples. However, it is probable that theearmarking provision was also motivated by a previous Government'sdesire to ensure ICBF1s survival in the future by endowing it with agenerous and reliable source of revenue.

Earmarked revenues also accrue to a non-social security institution,without any apparent rationale. The Compensation Funds receive theproceeds of a 4 percent payroll tax that is supposed to be earmarked

I/ This section draws heavily on Bird (1984).

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution

Page 31: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

Table

Tax

Coffee taxesAd valorem export tax

Retention tax

"Pastlla" tax

Payroll taxesVarious taxes, different

rates

Three taxes, total rate13 percent

4 percent tax

2 percent tax

2 percent tax

Taxes earmarked for healthBeer tax

Liquor taxes

Gambling taxes

Other earmarked taxesTobacco taxes

Gasoline taxes

Hotel tax

Import tax

Valorization taxes

Property tax surcharge

Earmarked transfersTax allowance

Sales tax transfer

Total Earmarked TaxesTotal Tax Revenue

- 17 -

1. Colombia: Earmarked Taxes, 1978

(In millions of pesos)

Destination Amount

National Coffee Fund, small portion 2,176further earmarked for DepartmentalCommittees of Coffee Growers

National Coffee Fund 15,650

National Coffee Fund, small portion 370further earmarked for DepartmentalCommittees of Coffee Growers

National Insurance Fund (CAJANAL) and 1,749Communications Workers Social SecurityFund (CAPRECOM)

Colombian Social Security 11,343Institute (ISS)

Compensation Funds 2,060

National Apprenticeship Service (SENA) 1,030

Colombian Family Welfare Institute (ICBF) 1,479

Sectional Health Serwlces (SSS) 513

SSS 680

SSS, through welfare agencies (85 percent 862to schools for the blind; 15 percent toNational Federation for the Blind

Sectional Sports Commissions; 241portion further earmarked

National Road Fund, portion further ear- 5,431marked for National Fund for NeighborhoodRoads; departmental roads; traffic departments

Colombian Tourist Company (COLTURISMO) 178

Export Promotion Fund (PROEXPO) 4,593

To valorization offices, for public works 994

Regional Corporations 369

Departments and national territories 9,900and Special District of Bogotá; 74 per-cent dedicated to education and 26 per-cent dedicated to health

30 percent of sales tax receipts granted 1,551to departments and municipalities; a largepercentage Is dedicated to education

61,169132,269

Source: Bird, Richard M., Intergovernmental Finance in Colombia, Final Report of theMission on Intergovernmental Finance (Cambridge: Harvard Law School, 1984), Table 5-1;and Colombia: Recent Economic Developments, 1984.

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution

Page 32: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

- 18 -

toward payment of a family subsidy to the workers of participatingfirms. However, about half the proceeds have instead been financing theconstruction of luxury resorts run by the Funds. To the extent thatmost contributors are unable to utilize these subsidized facilities,this otherwise productive and easily administered tax has no benefitsaspect.

Earmarking for health. Although some sources, such as taxes on beer andliquor, do have some tenuous links with ill health, a good deal offinancing for health (from taxes on gambling) has no benefitsrationale. Because "vice taxes" are heavily and successfully taxed inmany countries without resort to earmarking provisions, it is unlikelythat they have increased total revenues in Colombia. Consequently, thetrue role of earmarking lies in assuring the health sector a minimumlevel of resources. It is difficult to judge a situation like thisbecause there is no way of knowing whether the alternative would involvewasteful forms of military expenditure or more efficient developmentexpenditure. The main challenge lies more in verifying whether revenuesearmarked for specific programs (such as schools for the blind) areappropriate.

Other earmarked taxes. Except for taxes on tobacco, which are earmarkedfor sports and cultural institutions, most other taxes can be rationalizedon grounds of benefits with varying degrees of plausibility. Thestrongest case may be made for the valorization tax levied on propertyvalues benefiting from public works. Bird (1984) approvingly notesthat :

"...it has been more successful in Colombia, particularly in someColombian cities, than almost anywhere in the world. In thevarious studies that have been made of the valorization tax, it hasbeen suggested that a principal reason why that tax is acceptableis precisely that those who have to pay it perceive a relationshipbetween the tax and the benefits that they expect to receive fromthe public works that it finances."

The weakest case is that of an import surcharge earmarked for theexport promotion council, PROEXPO. _!/ The argument that exportersshould be subsidized by importers, because "exporters earn the foreignexchange that permit imports," is artificial. Most likely, thearrangement simply reflects the political power of exporters at the timePROEXPO was set up, and the Government's belief that an indirect tax inthe form of an import surcharge would slip through the legislature muchmore readily than, say, higher income taxes.

I./ This case is not far removed from the suggestion of the U.S. autoindustry some years ago to dedicate tariff revenues to "improvingproductivity" in the auto industry.

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution

Page 33: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

- 19 -

Earmarked transfers. Transfers from higher levels of government oftenreflect a revenue-sharing scheme between different levels of governmentand, as such, should not be considered a form of earmarking. However,in Colombia, the law enjoins regional governments that receive suchfunds to devote 74 percent of the transfer to current expenditure forprimary education and 26 percent to current health expenditure.Presumably, the intent of the provision is to insulate and increasetotal public expenditure on these functions. A recent empiricalanalysis by Slack and Bird (1983) suggests that such tied transfershave, in fact, had the opposite effect: regions effectively used thetransfers to replace locally financed health and education expenditure.This highlights the importance of carefully designing earmarking schemesthat are intended to promote (or protect) particular expenditures. Thepromotion of health and education expenditure may have been betterserved by an open-ended matching grant. _!/

What can be concluded from this somewhat elliptic summary ofearmarking in Colombia? It would be difficult to argue that earmarkingis so excessive that it imposes significant constraints on efficientbudgeting and budget flexibility. In fact, Bird (1983) asserts that itis the other way around, that earmarking is largely a reflection of poorbudgeting and expenditure control practices:

"The structure and operation of the present budgetary andexpenditure system in Colombia are such as to make it extremelydifficult to spend resources efficiently. Indeed, the cumber-someness and unreliability of this system are among the principalreasons for the marked growth of the decentralized sector and ofearmarked revenues that have characterized the Colombian publicsector in recent years.... Until such changes are made, it issimply Utopian to expect anyone to give up the hard-won defensivepositions that have been erected in such forms as earmarkedrevenues and autonomous organizations, in large part as bulwarksagainst the perceived inefficiency of the present expendituresystem."

Although earmarking in Colombia may be viewed partly as a flightfrom inefficiency, this is not to suggest that the system of earmarkingdoes not need substantial reform. It was noted that some earmarkedrevenues were excessive, as in the case of earmarked coffee taxes thatsubsidize domestic coffee consumption. In such instances, a largerfraction could be retained in the general fund. Another example involvesthe earmarking of 10 percent of expenditures for the judiciary. Moregenerally, there is clearly a need to review periodically all earmarkingprovisions and to verify whether funding for each activity adequatelyreflects changing circumstances and priorities.

I/ A matching grant provides x pesos for each peso raised locally.An open-ended grant does not set a ceiling on the size of the transfer.

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution

Page 34: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

- 20 -

V. Concluding Remarks

Having examined the case for earmarking, as well as some of thedifficulties associated with its implementation, we conclude with somethoughts on the circumstances under which earmarking can be recommended.

Since the primary function of earmarking lies in facilitating theexpression and resolution of differing preferences, earmarking has itsgreatest potential in pluralistic societies with strong democraticinstitutions. However, even in democracies with a broad consensus onmost issues, the legislature may need to guard itself from encroachmentby the military; an earmarking device that protects important social andeconomic expenditures can play a useful role in this respect.

It often happens that the only way a legislature can agree uponsupporting a vital social activity is by decentralizing it and removingit from routine legislative consideration. A good example of this isthe U.S. Superfund. Earmarking should be permitted when the alternativewould be to forgo an activity that may broadly be deemed in the nationalinterest.

The usefulness of earmarking is not limited to societies withactive legislatures. It was noted earlier that earmarking rules may beneeded to force a bureaucracy into activities that it has few incentivesto pursue, such as, expenditure on operations and maintenance. Morefundamentally, an earmarked tax can also be recommended when it is abenefits tax or a substitute for a user charge. Benefit taxation is notonly appealing in terms of equity but is likely to meet with greaterpublic compliance. This argument would apply to a great many activitieswhere the beneficiaries are readily identified, for example, localservices such as fire protection or small public works projects.Earmarking for such purposes does not preclude supplementary financingfrom general revenues, insofar as the government may also haveredistributive motives. In fact, supplementary financing from generalfunds allows policymakers to make discretionary changes at the margin,thus reducing the rigidities associated with earmarking.

The circumstances sketched above are far from exhaustive but doconvey the general flavor of the case for earmarking. At the risk ofstating the obvious, one should bear in mind that earmarking provisionsmay become obsolete and counterproductive as times change; hence theyshould be mandatorily reviewed at regular intervals of about fiveyears. Also, the extent of earmarking should be limited to allowgovernments some latitude in adjusting to various shocks and exigenciesas they arise.

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution

Page 35: ©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution€¦ · IMF WORKING PAPER This is a working paper and the author would welcome any comments on the present text. Citations should

- 21 -

References

Bird, R.M., "Budgeting and Expenditure Control in Colombia," PublicBudgeting and Finance (Autumn 1982).

, Intergovernmental Finance in Colombia! Final Report of theMission on Intergovernmental Finance, (Harvard University LawSchool, 1984), pp. 87-115.

Browning, E.K., "Collective Choice and General Fund Financing," Journalof Political Economy (April 1975).

Buchanan, J.M., "The Economics of Earmarked Taxes," Journal ofPolitical Economy, (October 1963).

Deran, E., "Earmarking and Expenditures: A Survey and a New Test,"National Tax Journal, (December 1965).

Eklund, P., "Taxation and Earmarking," (mimeo, World Bank, 1969).

, "A Theory of Earmarking Appraised," National Tax Journal,(June 1972).

Goode, R., "Government Finance in Developing Countries," (Washington:The Brookings Institution, 1984), pp. 11-13.

Jankowski, J.E., Jr., "The Practice and Prevalence of Earmarking,"(National Tax Association, Tax Institute of America Proceedings,1984).

Johansen, L. , "Some Notes on the Lindahl Theory of Determination ofPublic Expenditures," International Economic Review (September1963).

Mueller, D.C., Public Choice (Cambridge University Press, 1979),pp. 68-89.

Niskanen, W.A., Jr., Bureaucracy and Representative Government(Aldine Atherton, 1971).

Premchand, A., Government Budgeting and Expenditure Controls:Theory and Practice (Washington: International Monetary Fund,1983), pp. 158-60.

Slack, N.E., and R.M. Bird, "Local Response to IntergovernmentalFiscal Transfers: The Case of Colombia," Public Finance(No. 3, 1983).

Wilkie, J.W., "The Budgetary Dilemma in the Economic Developmentof Mexico, Bolivia, and Costa Rica" in Fiscal Policy forIndustrialization and Development in Latin America, ed. byD.T. Geithman (University of Florida Press, 1974).

©International Monetary Fund. Not for Redistribution


Recommended