+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics...

Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics...

Date post: 06-Mar-2018
Category:
Upload: tranxuyen
View: 231 times
Download: 2 times
Share this document with a friend
62
Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics Reading: ...................................... 1 Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) ......................................... 1 8 The meanings of ‘linguistic patterns’: semantics .......... 2 8.1 Different types of structure for different types of meaning ................................................................................. 7 8.1.1 Ideational meaning .................................................. 9 8.1.2 Interpersonal meaning .......................................... 15 8.1.3 Textual meaning .................................................... 25 8.2 Compositional semantics ............................................ 30 References ........................................................................... 41 9 “And what would you say it’s made of?” — Trees and Rules ....................................................................................... 42 9.1 Syntactic rules and phrase structure grammars ....... 44 9.2 The connection between rules and meanings ............ 60 Reading and references ...................................................... 62
Transcript
Page 1: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

Introduction to LinguisticsReading:

Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9)

Introduction to Linguistics Reading: ...................................... 1Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) ......................................... 18 The meanings of ‘linguistic patterns’: semantics.......... 2

8.1 Different types of structure for different types ofmeaning ................................................................................. 7

8.1.1 Ideational meaning.................................................. 98.1.2 Interpersonal meaning .......................................... 158.1.3 Textual meaning .................................................... 25

8.2 Compositional semantics ............................................ 30References ........................................................................... 41

9 “And what would you say it’s made of?” — Trees andRules ....................................................................................... 42

9.1 Syntactic rules and phrase structure grammars....... 449.2 The connection between rules and meanings ............ 60Reading and references ...................................................... 62

Page 2: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

8 The meanings of ‘linguistic patterns’:semantics

WHAT WE ARE DOING THIS CHAPTER.

We have now seen a variety of linguistic patterns of varyingdegrees of complexity. We have also seen some of themaps/theories that have been developed in order to provideframeworks for these patterns: in particular, functional vs.formal and maximal vs. minimal bracketing in grammaticalstructure.

In this chapter we look more closely at the relation betweenkinds of patterns and kinds of meanings. Here again we willfind that there is considerable systematicity that we canusefully rely upon when thinking about language. We willsee that particular types of patterns in fact expressparticular kinds of meanings. We will see that it is primarilythis feature that allows language and language use tobecome as sophisticated as it is. Language really isessentially made up of patterns of patterns of patterns and itis this successive build up of ever more abstract ‘structures’that provides something capable of carrying the meaningsthat make up texts.

sentence

ideational

interpersonal

textualsentence

ideational

interpersonal

textual

Page 3: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

It is now time to bring our introduction to the basic stuff oflanguage—and its structuring into larger-scale patterns—into a much clearer relationship with meaning. We haveseen that grammatical structure and the interpretation ofgrammatical structure are intimately tied together. Whenwe have found ambiguous sentences, we can also findalternatives in the grammatical structure. Differinginterpretations of a sentence then generally go along withdifferent structures. It is only because we perceive thestructure differently that differing meanings are drawn fromit.

Structure as such is then very powerful, and it is absolutelynecessary for language to exist—particular aspects ofstructure that we have seen so far can be called designfeatures of language; if a system, a semiotic system such aslanguage, is to do its job, then it will need something likestructure present. But structure is still only a tool thatserves a purpose. And tools, especially long-lived tools likethose that have evolved for language and language use, takeon special features and attributes that increases theirsuitability for the tasks demanded of them. This is, in fact,the broadest and most general statement of a functionalapproach—i.e., that language forms have evolved to performparticular functions. Describing linguistic functions can thentell us much about the kinds of linguistic forms thatlanguages use. The particular kinds of structure and theparticular tasks they take on within language is then whatgives us the organising subject of this chapter.

The approaches to syntactic structures that we have seen sofar have been drawn from a variety of maps concerned withthe task of building phrases and clauses. We have seendistinctions between formal and functional ‘maps’, andwithin form we have seen the different emphases brought byrank-based accounts and immediate-constituency basedaccounts. All of these views are in fact concerned with aparticular level, or scale, of structure. But structures alsooccur at many other places in the linguistic system: both‘below’ the clause, where for example they organisesequences of sounds into larger combined units (such aswords), and ‘above’ the clause, where they provide texts with

Page 4: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

additional organisation beyond the mere sequentiality of thesentences or utterances out of which they are built. It is thenvery useful to distinguish more carefully and exactlybetween these kinds of structures so as to examine theirparticular properties more closely. We will see that anunderstanding of structure and kinds of structures is afundamental aspect of thinking usefully about languagewithin linguistics overall.

Some kinds of structures are very strict, others are moreflexible or ‘contingent’—i.e., depending on particular detailsof how they unfold, or develop, in time. The strictness of thestructures usually goes together with the ‘size’ of thelinguistic units considered. When we look at ‘smaller’ unitssuch as sentences, we can say that a sequence of words suchas:

running train late the is

is a sufficiently gross violation of the structures of Englishgrammar that it is not possible—it is structurally notEnglish. It is in some serious and fundamental way deficientand will not, under normal circumstances (i.e., excludingspeech errors, brain damage, language learning situationsand the like) occur. This tighter notion of structure will giveus a good place to begin below.

But when we turn to ‘larger’ untis such as texts such acategorial two-way decision of possible/impossible isproblematic. For larger units it is very unusual forstructures to be so binding that the unit can be rejected as‘impossible’ on purely structural grounds. As we saw in theexamples of conversational interaction in Chapter 4 (Section4.3) before and will return to later in the course, interactionconsists of a very particular kind of ‘structure’: that ofadjacency pairs and interactional sequences. In this ‘domain’of structure, there is no sense in which we could say that ananswer must follow a question in a Question-Answeradjacency pair in order for the interaction to be ‘legal’ or‘well-formed’ or an example of an English interaction. Thereis no sense, that is, in which we can say that a dialogueextract such as:

A: Are you going to the party tonight?B: Nice weather we’re having.

Page 5: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

is ‘not English’ because it appears to violate the Question-Answer pattern.

The term used in conversation analysis for such ‘violations’of structure is to say that the second item of the pair isnoticeably absent. That is, might have been predicted tooccur but, in fact, does not. We cannot say that such asequence is ‘wrong’ or impossible, but we can say that it willhave particular, specifiable and systemic consequences. Thehearer is explicitly invited to make certain inferences. Thenotion of structure is then just as important at these largerscale instances of language as it is at the smaller-scale ofgrammar. If structure were not present then we would not beable to recognise the cases where a turn is noticeably absent.Clearly, however, the use that we make of structure at thislevel or scale is different from that within sentences.

Because it is the smaller linguistic units, as we have seen,that often have the strictest structural properties, it is hereagain we will begin our discussion of the connection betweenforms of meaning and forms of structure. The richest kindsof structure that we can find are those that have developedfor, and are employed by, grammar. and so it is here we findmost of the basic components that we need to talk aboutstructure more generally.

Grammatical structures are there so that language usershave a flexible means of expressing their meanings. Thebasic properties of structure—particularly recursion—alwayslet syntax expand as necessary to carry the meaningsrequired of it. If what we want to say fits into a simplesentence fine; but when we need to pick out carefully someparticular object (like the person that we met last Friday atthe second party in town that we went to after midnight),grammar and the syntax of relative clauses and modificationwill get us there.

But the demands made on syntax—the ‘loads’ placed on it ifwe take as a metaphor the description of physical structuresillustrated in the quotation below—can push the structureswe see in real texts into a range of shapes that stretch ourabilities to recognise them to their limits. You will alreadyhave encountered many such problematic cases inattempting to apply phrase structure to naturally occurring

Page 6: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

Structure is “any assemblage ofmaterials which is intended to sustainloads.” J. E. Gordan, Structures: or whythings don’t fall down. Penguin. 1978.p17.

sentences. And in fact this thenbecomes an important methodologicaldecision within linguistics—one ofthose choices between maps and‘cartographic’ principles thatdistinguishes one approach to

linguistics from another. Some schools of linguistics attemptto follow the different shapes of syntactic trees no matterhow far they are pushed around by meaning, other schools oflinguistics employ a range of techniques that do not alwaysfollow the contortions of syntax. The first approach gives usincreasingly complicated phrase structures; the second givesus simpler phrase structures but more complex componentsof the model elsewhere.

This can usefully be seen as a continuum of approaches—ranging from the strictly formal to the strictly functional.Both extremes have severe problems as maps of language:we need both and a lot of the discussion between differentapproaches revolves around just how much information toput where. The less functional information that is availablein a map, the more complex a formal structure needs tobecome; the less formal information that is available in amap, the more difficult it becomes to explain the fine detailsof syntax and grammar.

We have already seen this concretely in the maps we haveexamined in previous chapters.

Understanding syntax is an important prerequisite foruncovering how language is doing its job of carryingmeanings. But it is also very useful to combine this withother characterisations describing language. In Chapter 2,for example, we saw the distinct kinds of meanings that wecan pick apart in the sentences of texts: the ideational,interpersonal and textual meanings. These different kinds ofmeanings all bring differing kinds of ‘communicativepressure’ to bear on the basic structural ‘stuff’ of sentences.We pick this relationship apart more below.

We also drew attention in Chapter 2 to the close relationshipthat can be seen between these distinct kinds of meaningand distinct aspects of social situations—introducing theterms of field, mode and tenor. One way of seeing this

Page 7: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

connection that we will focus on here is again in terms ofpatterns. When particular structures are selected repeatedly,or within particular limited degrees of variation, thenreaders and hearers can attribute meaning to this. And sopatterns of meaning in the grammar can be combined intolarger patterns of patterns that indicate social andcontextual meanings. It is only because the relationships areso systematic and relatively stable that language users canrely on their language making sense to others sharing (togreater or lesser degrees) their social situation(s).

8.1 Different types of structure for different types of meaning

We have raised the possibility of a connection between thekinds of meanings raised by the three metafunctions andtheir expression in grammatical structures. To recap, weshould recall that ideational meaning is to do with

representing the world,interpersonal meaning isto do with enacting andsignalling socialrelationships, and textualmeanings are concernedwith building ourutterances into larger-scale textual units thathang together in order toachieve particular

communicative purposes.

Although all three of these kinds of meanings are regularlyexamined in different kinds of linguistics, it is rare to findthem all given equal treatment, especially in introductions.These is why most introductions that you may come acrossfocus almost exclusively on one or two of them and seldomrelate them to one another. We will try to give the threemetafunctions a more equal treatment: An alternativeapproach that is often seen and which you will encounter inthe readings chooses instead to place the textual andinterpersonal metafunctions ‘outside’ ‘core’ linguistics in anarea called pragmatics. This naturally influences both thekinds of questions that you can ask and the kinds of answersthat you get. For the perspective taken in this introduction,

In 1995 she wrote her first novel.

THEME MOOD

CIRCUMSTANCES, PROCESS, PARTICIPANTS

In 1995 she wrote her first novel.

THEME MOOD

CIRCUMSTANCES, PROCESS, PARTICIPANTS

Page 8: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

Ideational: logic and phrasestructure grammar

Interpersonal: Interaction andconversation analysis

Textual: text linguistics

it is seen as particularly limiting because our concern is toengage with texts rather than isolated utterances or sounds.We try to present an integrative view of the areas oflinguistics which brings these aspects together rather thanleaving them within different components—but, as said, youwill encounter all of these possibilities in your readings: anindication of the correspon-dences between the types ofmeaning talked about with ‘metafunctions’ and some othercomponents of linguistics is shown to the left.

The different kinds of meaningare significant, though, not onlyfor describing meaning, but alsofor describing linguistic form—this is because the differenttypes of meaning prefer to beexpressed in different kinds oflinguistic structures. We saw

indications of this above whenever we, for example, used ourexpectations about clause functions to look for particularconstituents in clauses we were analysing. Knowing aboutthe different kinds of meaning can then help us further whenwe need to understand more generally what parts ofsentences and texts are serving what purposes. The differentkinds of meanings in fact require different forms ofexpression: that is, their inherent properties do not let themall be expressed in the same ways.

A suggestive metaphor might be trying to build an igloo withsquare bricks—naturally the fact that an igloo is typicallymeant to be round will bring certain ‘pressures’ to bear onthe appropriate forms of the materials that you use toconstruct it. And similarly, if building a rectangular-shapedhouse, specially rounded bricks (or blocks of ice) may not bethe best choice! Form can very usefully follow function.

The three kinds of meaning—textual, interpersonal andideational—regularly go together with three different kindsof linguistic form or structuring—pulse, prosody andconstituency. We introduce each of these in turn, startingwith constituency since this is the one that has received themost attention in linguistics generally and that you haveseen with phrase structure. This is the area which has seen

Page 9: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

the most significant advances in the last 100 years—theother areas of meaning are all relatively new and, althoughthey are essential to understand how texts work, for manylinguists they still seem experimental or ‘non-core’. Bringingthese aspects of form and meaning into the picture is part ofthe essential link between linguistic form and socialinterpretation that makes a socially-oriented linguisticspossible.

8.1.1 Ideational meaning

Ideational meaning is the kind of meaning expressed in ourdivision of texts into Processes, Participants andCircumstances—and this very division is much more readilytalked about in terms of the ‘building blocks’ offered bysyntactic constituents. This is just the kind of division thatideational meanings make, dividing the world up into doersand actions, qualities and states, and it is the role of thiskind of meaning to impose some regularity on the fluid worldaround us. For this reason, the kind of linguistic structurethat is most relevant for ideational meaning isconstituency structure.

Because of this, it is often relatively straightforward to findthe portions of a syntactic tree that correspond to theideational elements in a sentence. This makes it easier toavoid mixing Participants, Circumstances and Processestogether in loose chains that would hide the realinterrelationships between them. Consider again thefollowing sentence:

A fast car with twin cams sped by the children on the grassy lane

This sentence has three prepositional phrases in it and sooffers plenty of possibilities for ambiguities in structure andinterpretation as we saw previously. It also invites a numberof ‘mis-analyses’ that would in fact not be accuratestatements of the structure of the sentence. One of thesemis-analyses we have discussed above: that is, it is notpossible to link the ‘with twin cams’ to the verb phrase; itmust be a part of the initial noun phrase. Another is moresubtle: that is the role of the word ‘by’—a possibleconsideration is whether this is to be linked to the verb or

Page 10: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

not. This latter possibility we can see by analogy withsentences such as:

Yesterday he called up his mother.

The mouse ate up the cheese.

The ‘up’ in both of these sentences is not the simplepreposition of a prepositional phrase that we have seen inour syntactic rules so far; they are instead parts of phrasalverbs. A phrasal verb is made up of more than a single wordand often includes an additional word looking like apreposition, which we can call a particle. This is alsoanother example of how we cannot consider sentences assimple strings of words; the structure of sentences involvingphrasal verbs is very different to that of sentences withoutthem. And, as a consequence, these structures allow theirwords to be moved around very differently. It is normallypossible, as we have seen and will see again below, to move aprepositional phrase that expresses a Circumstance to thebeginning of a sentence in order to become the Theme.Attempting this trick with these two sentences produceshighly deviant sentences however:1

*Up his mother he called yesterday.

*Up the cheese the mouse ate.

This is an indication that the underlying structure is not ofthe simple kinds we have seen above. Applying our testsprobes for identifying constituents and dependenciesbetween constituents also leads to some curious results. Forexample, conjunction should make us doubt whether theconstituent that we just moved to the front is, in fact, aconstituent at all.

*The mouse ate up the cheese and up the bread.

1 Remember that linguists indicate that a sentence or other grammatical unit is not acceptableby marking it with a star at the beginning. Sentences that are not absolutely unacceptable butare instead somewhat dubious are marked with question marks. Note also that this clearlyshows that the expression “to sleep in a bed” does not involve a phrasal verb: “in this bed heslept yesterday” is a perfectly well-formed sentence, if rather limited in the contexts in whichit could appear.

Page 11: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

Returning to our car with twin cams sentence, we can nowask again about the word ‘by’. Can we move it to the Themeposition? Can we combine it with another similar phrase?

• By the children a fast car with twin cams sped on the grassylane.

• A fast car with twin cams sped by the children and by thetourists on the grassy lane.

These are both acceptable sentences and so we can concludewith some confidence that the ‘by’ is not associated with theverb but is a normal preposition associated with thechildren.

There are then still two possible interpretations of oursentence. Each of these has its own tree structure, which canbe contrasted as follows. In the first tree, it is the childrenwho are on the grassy lane, since the PP ‘on the grassy lane’is part of the NP ‘the children on the grassy lane’

A fast car with twin cams sped by the children on the grassy lane

A fast car with twin cams

PP

prep

noun noun

NPadj noun

NP

det

NP

the children on lane

PP

prep

noun

NP

noun

NP

det

NP

grassy

adj

the

det

by

PP

prep

VP

S

sped

verb

Page 12: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

In this second tree, it is the car that is speeding on thegrassy lane, since the PP ‘on the grassy lane’ is now part ofthe VP describing the speeding. Both readings are possiblefor this sentence and deciding which situation applies—ordisambiguating the sentence—must be done based on otherknowledge, for example on knowledge about the situation orcommon-sense knowledge about how the world generally is.

In both cases, however, we can use the trees for somethingmore than just showing the groupings into phrases. Assuggested now in our discussion a number of times, the treealso gives us a very good indication of the phrases that serveparticular ideational functions—i.e., the Processes,Participants and Circumstances. This should be expected: aswe have noted, the syntactic structure is not arbitrary—itsfunction is partly to make sure that we can find themeanings encoded in the sentence.

In general, the Process is to be found as the first child of theVP node: which is in this example the verb; the Participantsare generally to be found as the first child of the entiresentence (the S node) and the first NP node following the

(A fast car with twin cams) sped (by the children)(on the grassy lane)

A fast car with twin cams

PP

prep

noun noun

NP

adj noun

NP

det

NP

the children on lane

PP

prep

noun

NP

noun

NP

det

grassy

adj

the

det

by

PP

prep

VP

S

sped

verb

Page 13: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

verb in the VP; and remaining PPs in the VP areCircumstances.

This is showngraphically on theleft. Since we, asspeakers of English,know how thesyntactic trees areorganised, we alsoknow where in thosetrees the particularmeaningful elementsare distributed.Recognising thestructure thus helpsus with the task ofknowing what a

sentence can mean. In the example offered by one of theabove structural trees, then, we can see as expected that thefirst NP—“a fast car with twin cams”—is a Participant and,in fact, is the only Participant. There is no NP following theverb in the VP, we come immediately to a PP, which is thenthe one and only Circumstance of the sentence.

If, however, we take the other structural possibility—showngraphically below right, then we find that there are now twoPP nodes following the verb in the VP, and there aretherefore twoCircumstances:both sayingsomething aboutwhere the speedingoccurs—the firstgives a relativeposition, thespeeding was pastthe chi-dren, thesecond gives anabsolute position,the speeding wason the grassy lane.We will see, when

(A fast car with twin cams) sped (by the children)(on the grassy lane)

A fast car with twin cams

PP

prep

noun noun

NP

adj noun

NP

det

NP

the children on lane

PP

prep

noun

NP

noun

NP

det

grassy

adj

the

det

by

PP

prep

VP

S

sped

verb

CIRCUMSTANCES:CIRCUMSTANCES:where the Process occurswhere the Process occurs

PARTICIPANTPARTICIPANT PROCESSPROCESS

A fast car with twin cams

PP

prep

noun noun

NP

adj noun

NP

det

NP

the children on lane

PP

prep

noun

NP

noun

NP

det

NP

grassy

adj

the

det

by

PP

prep

VP

S

sped

verb

CIRCUMSTANCE:CIRCUMSTANCE:where the Process occurswhere the Process occurs

PARTICIPANTPARTICIPANT PROCESSPROCESS

Page 14: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

we have discussed both the interpersonal and textualpossibilities, that we can also argue for another distributionof information for these sentences concerning the role thatthe children play; but for the moment the analysis given isone possible interpretation that serves to make it clear thatstructure and meaning are indivisible.

This then also allows us to reject impossible interpretations.The box picture of a sentence structure shown below isanalogous to several that we have seen and correspondsdirectly to our example sentence: ‘The small gnome on thehill wiped his hands’.

The structural tree for this sentence is as follows. .

We can see from this structure that there is no possibility offinding a Circumstance role for the PP ‘on the hill’—it isquite simply in the wrong place in the tree to be sointerpretable: it is hidden in the ‘shadow’ of the NP thatfunctions as the first Participant. Knowing the structure can,therefore, indicate very clearly what the possibilities forfunctional interpretation are.

The gnome in the garden is sadParticipant Circumstance Process

The small gnome on the hill wiped his hands

adjdet

NP

N

NP

det

VP

S

verb

PPprep

N

NP

detN

NP

PARTICIPANTS

Page 15: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

8.1.2 Interpersonal meaning

The interpersonal meanings that we introduced in Chapter 2were also described loosely as being associated withparticular positions in the sentence. Recall that the mainfunctional elements carrying the interpersonal meaningsthat we examined were the Mood element consisting ofSubject, Finite and indications of polarity (yes/no) andmodality (should, could, would, and so on). We saw that theSubject was often somewhere near the beginning of its clauseand the Finite part of the verbal information followed this.But again, this was a bit too simple. Now we can be muchmore precise because we can rely on our newly introducednotions of structure to pinpoint these positions moreaccurately.

In addition, although the view of interpersonal meaning thatwe saw in before concentrated on the Mood element of asentence, we can also look at the other elements in thesentence—the elements of what is called the Residue. Herealso there are elements which it is useful to describeinterpersonally because they are then viewed in contrast tothe decisions taken in the Mood element. This is where arange of different grammatical ‘Objects’ occur—there arecalled, for example, Direct Object, Indirect Object and‘Oblique’ Objects.

An example of a full interpersonal structure for a clause isshown in the following box diagram:

John gave Mary the book in the park

Subject Finite IndirectObject

DirectObject

ObliqueObject

Mood Residue

Another way of describing the Objects, which makes theirinterpersonal function clearer in English, is to describe themas Complements. Complements can be understood as being‘complementary’ to Subjects: they are constituents that could

Page 16: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

have been straightforwardly selected as Subjects if the textdemanded it: this gives us the passive sentences:2

Mary was given the book by John in the park.

The book was given Mary by John in the park.

The Oblique Object is not so willing to be made into aSubject (although we will see some cases below where it canbe managed in English):

* The park was given by John Mary the book in.

For this reason, the two kinds of interpersonal constituentare distinguished from one another. There is also a feelingthat the complements are more central, more necessary, fora meaningful sentence than the remaining constituents: theOblique Objects are therefore also called Adjuncts—a termindicating that they are merely added, or are additional, tothe main information.

Then there is one final interpersonal element that needs tobe distinguished, and that is the Predicate. This isnecessary because in English the verbal information is oftenspread over several words: as with the complicated tensedexpression:

John has been going to give Mary the book for ages.

The Finite element here is only the portion of the verb thathas the first bit of the tense information and which agreeswith the Subject: i.e., the ‘has’. The rest of the verbalinformation belongs to the Predicate and the most importantelement of the Predicate is the final one: which we call thelexical verb, in the above case: ‘give’.

In many languages, there is much less evidence forseparating out Finite and Predicate. This led to the basicdistinction drawn in classical Greek grammars and sincetaken up in logic and philosophy between Subject andPredicate. But, for English, this would make certain

2 Judgements about the acceptability of the second of these sentences vary: what do youthink? Also note that the definition of Complement used here is just one of several that can befound in the literature; again, one can ask why are there differences? What questions were theindividual authors trying to answer with their formulations? What other terms doesComplement contrast with? This is discussed a bit further below.

Page 17: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

grammatical patterns, and alternatives between patterns—for example, the use of the do-verb support for questions,more difficult to explain.

As with the ideational meanings, we can now make clearwhere some of the above types of constituents appear. Theseoverlap with the positions that we have described forParticipants, Processes, and Circumstances because veryoften, Participants ‘are’ Subjects and Objects, Processes ‘are’Finite and Predicator (combined), and Circumstances ‘are’Adjuncts: but this correspondence is not a rule. Moregenerally valid is the structural correspondence set out tothe right. The firstchild of thesentence node is theSubject; the firstNP after the verb isthen the DirectObject orComplement; andall PPs after thisare Adjuncts. Acomplete descrip-tion of any sentenceshould then includeboth the ideational and the interpersonal elements; a largepart of the flexibility of a language is to be found in how alanguage relates these two kinds of description to each other.

As we have suggested, and particularly when comparingEnglish and German, we can see that English is, in manytext types, very free with just what can become Subject—sometimes we even find things in this position which are notParticipants: therefore, although this position is sufficient todefine what is a Subject, it is only suggestive of what is aParticipant.

Languages can help their interpreters out when complexrelationships are being signalled by using the regularstructural patterns as a clear scaffold within whichparticular meanings will be made in particular places. A‘non-neutral’ use of the Subject position for Participants or

The small gnome wiped his hands on the hill

adjdet

NP

N

NP

det

VP

S

verb

PP

prep

N

NP

det

GrammaticalFunctions

N

Subject

Finite

interpersonal

Page 18: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

Circumstances other than you might expect can be indicatedby, for example, making the sentence use a passive form.

While this makes clearer some of the positions in thestructure of sentences that function interpersonally, we mustalso note that there are positions of strong interpersonalprominence where the ‘boundaries’ are, as with Theme andNew, not sharp. Or rather, better expressed, they are sharpbut they respect their own boundaries rather than ideationalconstituent boundaries. This is one of the reasons why weneed to describe interpersonal structures at all: if they werejust other names for the ideational structures or for thesyntactic structures then they would be redundant. Wewould have different names for the same things. They arenot, however; they introduce their own structurings ofsentences, some of which have been considered in arguing forparticular syntactic structures over others and some of whichhave been omitted from syntactic discussions altogether.

Some of the examples of Chapter 2 were already moving inthis direction. Consider the sentence from our interrogationdialogue:

Perhaps I should ask you as a matter of finality, were you in thelounge room when Mr. R was escorted through the house?

Most of the first half of this sentence is in factinterpersonally motivated. Given that the speaker is a legalofficial in a trial and has all the power, the use of “perhaps”and “should” cannot be seen as indications of uncertainty orhesitation. It is more an evaluation of the informationpresented so far as being in some way deficient, or less thanentirely truthful, or needing to be stated absolutely baldlyand without ‘hedging’ of any kind. The utterance then makesspace, interpersonally, for the questioned individual to haveone last chance of providing the information requested.

An even more striking example is the following:

I ain’t never been to nowhere like that.

This is not a sentence in “standard English”, although thereare many variants of English where it is acceptable.3 What

3 We see the status of some of these variants in the readings.

Page 19: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

happens in this kind of structure is that an interpersonalprosody. Prosody is a term taken originally from intonation,where particular intonational tunes are used during anutterance’s delivery by a speaker. We might then have a‘questioning’ prosody—usually one in which the intonation,or ‘pitch’ rises towards the end of the sentence—or a‘statement’ prosody—where the pitch falls. This notion of alinguistic detail running through an entire linguistic unitwas extended radically by the British linguist J.R. Firth.Firth discusses other kinds of prosody, for examplegrammatical prosodies, where some grammatical choice‘runs through’ an entire unit instead of occurring at oneparticular place. In the current example we have theprosody of ‘negation’ running through the sentence as awhole. This means that negation is not here expressed withone particular part of structure, but is continually expressedwherever the sentence structure allows it.

Note that the standard English equivalent shows exactly thesame behaviour, but it is often not recognised as so doing. Sowhen we have the sentence:

I have never been to anywhere like that.

Once the negative meaning has been expressed with thenegative word ‘never’, then the rest of the places in structurethat can express a positive or negative meaning have to beselected as positive: thus, ‘have’ and ‘anywhere’ are bothselected in contrast to the ‘ain’t’ and ‘nowhere’ of the non-standard variety. But the mechanism is the same.

We can show this more clearly perhaps by picking out theparticular choices, e.g., have/have not, ever/never,anywhere/nowhere, that are available to the speaker orwriter in this sentence thus:

Ihave

have not

been toanywhere

never

ever

nowhere

like that

Here we show the positive and negative options for thoseitems that naturally carry a polarity choice.

Page 20: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

If we then look at the ‘standard’ English alternatives, we seea clear pattern. Both of the following paths through theoptions available are classified as ‘standard’.

Ihave

have not

been toanywhere

never

ever

nowhere

like that

Ihave

have not

been toanywhere

never

ever

nowhere

like that

The pattern is that if there is one negative option taken inthe Mood element, then we need to take only positive optionsin the remaining choice points.

This is not a rule of logic; it is a rule of grammar. Anargument that one often hears is that the multiple negationsare ‘obviously wrong’ because they ‘logically cancel eachother out.’ This confuses linguistic facts with valuejudgements about how things should be expressed and hownor. As stated above, there are many variants of Englishthat happen not to have become the ‘standard’ and whichindeed require instead precisely paths such as the following:

Ihave

have not

been toanywhere

never

ever

nowhere

like that

Here the rule of grammar is simply different to that favouredfor the standard: if we wish to express a negative meaning,then we select negative for all the options that we can. Whatis crucial for our discussion here, however, is not that thereare different varieties of language, but rather that themeaning is not expressed in one place in the structure: themeaning needs to be expressed at several points and if weget that selection wrong, then we fail to have an acceptablesentence.

Another just as striking example of this prosodic nature ofinterpersonal meaning is given by utterances such as:

‘That stupid animal has damn well run a-bloody-way again.’

Where the interpersonal negative ‘appraisal’ of the state ofaffairs reported is expressed not in a single element of

Page 21: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

structure but repeatedly throughout the structure—even, inthe case of ‘a-bloody-way’, in the middle of a word!

When we are confronted with sentences such as these,searching for an exhaustive phrase structure tree can be adifficult business indeed. One effective strategy is thereforeto begin by removing the particular interpersonal bias, useour rules of structure to work out the grouping, and then toplace the interpersonal additions in again at the appropriateplaces. Therefore, to analyse the last sentence ideationally itis enough to take out the interpersonal ‘spice’ giving:

The dog has run away again.

This can be analysed as a simple Participant, Process andCircumstance. This also lets us presume interpersonally thatwe have a Subject ‘the dog’, followed by the verbal material‘has run’ (which divides into Finite: ‘has’ and Predicate: ‘runaway’), and finishing with a Circumstance (an adverbialphrase: ‘again’). We know that ‘run away’ belongs togetherbecause our probes and tests do not like them beingseparated:

* It was away that the dog has run again.

So in some respects the syntactic structure is quite simpleand can be set out as in the trees below, where the structuraltree can be seen to act as a go-between, a scaffold orstructure on which the various meanings required can behung. Moreover, having the structure clearly set out like thislets us see exactly just where the different kinds of meaningcan be made in a sentence and how.

Phrase structure and ideationalfunctions

Phrase structure and interpersonalfunctions

Page 22: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

The dog has run away againdet particle

VB

verb

VP

S

adverb

AdvP

N

NP

PARTICIPANTCIRCUMSTANCE

PROCESS

The dog has run away againdet particle

VB

verb

VP

S

adverb

AdvP

N

NP

AdjunctSubject Finite

Predicator

Note, however, that this simplification then leaves out someof the important parts of the meaning of the sentence, and ingeneral we will want to (un)cover these meanings too.Therefore, in addition to the simple (ideationally motivated)structure, we should also recognise the interpersonal prosodyrunning through the structure. This is very similar to otherinterpersonal aspects of the sentence: for example, if there isa strong negative or positive appraisal, then the entiresentence is probably being said in a louder voice than usual,with a particular intonational force, and so on. Similarinterpersonal aspects are also found in the grammatical andlexical material (i.e., the words) selected: thus we can havecontinual repetitions of material with particularinterpersonal force; the more repetitions, the ‘louder’ orstronger the utterance with respect to the meanings made(which is not to be confused with ‘more persuasive’ or ‘moreeffective’!).

The two kinds of structures superimposed here—the phrasestructure and the functional structures—also bring out wellthe different views of clause structure introduced above interms of maximal and minimal bracketing. The maximalbracketing perspective tries to explain as much as is possiblein terms of quite complicated tree structures; the minimalbracketing approach is content to explain some of theproperties of clauses in terms of trees (primarily the basicsyntactic structure in terms of nominal groups, verbalgroups, prepositional phrases, etc.), and the rest in terms ofadded functional information or labels. As very often inlinguistics, there are different ways of sharing out the workto be done: different descriptive mechanisms can be

Page 23: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

appropriate for different tasks and being able to movebetween these flexibly provides a very powerful (andempowering) way of looking at language.

It is interesting to note that some views of grammar, andespecially ‘school grammar’, take the elements ofinterpersonal meaning as basic without even noticing thatthere are other phenomena that are occurring at the sametime. This makes it more likely that things that appear to be‘exceptions’ occur because therir real sources are leftunclarified. However, for languages, such as English, whichactually place a heavy burden on interpersonal structures,the simplification is quite understandable.

Nevertheless, the ‘traditional’ school grammar views of theparts of sentences—Subjects, Objects, etc.—can best beunderstood in English as belonging to the interpersonal areaof meaning: which leads to quite a bit of confusion whenpeople attempt, as they sometimes do, to give ideationaldescriptions of them: for example, the ‘Subject’(interpersonal) is the one doing the action (ideational), or the‘Direct Object’ (interpersonal) is the object or person to whichthe action is done (ideational). Languages tend to be moreflexible in the relations they draw between ideational(Participant, Process, Circumstance) and interpersonal(Subject, Finite, Object) elements: and some languages aremore flexible than others. English, for example, issignificantly more flexible in this regard than German andwe frequently find considerable disassociation betweeninterpersonal and ideational elements.

Some of the difficulties, however, that can arise when theinterpersonal elements corresponding to ‘grammaticalfunctions’ are singled out as the basic organisation ofsentences can be seen in the following table, which depictsthe ‘basic sentence orders’ assumed by one introduction toEnglish linguistics (Kortmann, 1999: 96).

Page 24: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

Here we can see that there are some differences inclassification: e.g., Objects are distinguished fromComplements, and Adjuncts are referred to as Adverbiale.Kortmann notes that the definitions of complement varywidely and restricts his usage to refer to constituents thatcomplete copula expressions (e.g., the object of verbs like ‘tobe’). On the basis of this, this author gives ‘seven’ basicpatterns for English clauses. But, and given the variation inthe definitions that one may find, it should not be surprisingto learn that other authors give different numbers.

It is, of course, difficult to specify once and for all that alanguage has so and so many “basic sentence patterns”—thisis probably not a linguistic statement at all, but rather one ofthose ‘simplifications’ of the map adopted to make some task,such as language teaching, easier. Teaching these seven mayafter all present a more manageable arrangement of thematerial. Whether it makes the teaching of linguistics easierdepends on how well one understands the nature ofsimplified maps of the territory. Certainly being aware ofthis as a simplification places one in a far better position tounderstand that sentences that do not conform to the givenpatterns (and there are very many of these) are notnecessarily curious ‘exceptions’.

Moreover, regardless of the particular simplifications thatany particular author may suggest, all such sentencepatterns must correspond in some way to the syntacticstructures of the language being addressed: thus if we cantake any sentence apart according to its constituencystructure, we should also be able to work out what theparticular patterns of any sentence are without needing to

Page 25: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

state that some are ‘basic’ and others are not. It is only whenwe are not in a position to describe the syntactic structuresof a language that we need to resort to simplifications suchas ‘basic patterns’. As linguistically more sophisticated‘language professionals’ the safety net given by a simpleshort list of ‘basic structures’ should of course no longer benecessary, for neither the teacher nor the practicing linguist.

Another problem is that there are of course many variationson the basic ordering given in the above table. Sometimesthe objects are not after the verb but before it for example. Isthis then a new pattern—presumably not, otherwise it wouldhave been included as one of the ‘basic’ patterns. We needthen to look beyond abstract general patterns to be able torecognise any particular sentence pattern that occurs in anactual text. This is again a good example of a simplificationmade for the purposes of teaching: we could single out arange of different aspects of linguistic structure and use thisas the description of what is going on, as the map of theterritory we are introducing.

But whenever we make a simplification like this, thencertain phenomena, certain differentiations, are going toappear unmotivated or difficult to understand—simplybecause the distinctions necessary to make sense of them havebeen withheld. A very valuable component of learning towork linguistically is to be able to make these kinds ofjudgements—what simplifications are appropriate for whatsituations for what audiences—yourself.

8.1.3 Textual meaning

The last of the three basic kinds of meaning to be consideredhere is textual meaning. Textual meaning, as we saw inChapter 2, is to do with the organisation of text. It is acrucial component of meaning, because without it therewould not be any text. However, when you readintroductions to linguistics or grammatical structure, thetextual pulse will often be left out or explained in terms ofsome of the other kinds of structure that we have seen. Thismakes some real sentences as we may find them in naturaltexts more difficult to explain and to analyse than necessary.

Page 26: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

Choices of what to make textually prominent often cut acrossother kinds of organisation. For example, consider thefollowing sentence:

No one has slept in this bed for many years.

We can employ our tests and probes from above to find theconstituents of this sentence. We would find that we have aProcess slept, a Participant no one, and two Circumstances:a time for many years and a place in this bed. We can also dopermutation tests to see that we can move these constituentsaround somewhat—for example, we can take in this bed tothe front of the sentence:

In this bed no one has slept for many years.

As we now know, this would have the effect of making ‘inthis bed’ the Theme of the sentence: it occurs at the strongestpoint of the textual pulse. But what of the followingsentence?

It was this bed that had not been slept in for years.

If you try to carry out a rank-based (minimal bracketing)grammatical analysis and a phrase-structure (maximalbracketing) analysis of this sentence, you will probablyencounter a range of difficult decisions.

What makes this kind of sentence difficult is the fact thatthere is so much going on in it that is not simply a reflectionof a configuration of process, participants and circumstances.Somewhere in the sentence we would like to find that theProcess is something to do with sleeping and that there areboth a spatial circumstance (in the bed) and a temporal one(for years) as we saw with the more straightforwardrenditions above.

But in addition to this we are left with a number of looseends when we try to complete our analysis using the phrasestructure perspective map of the clause. For example, if weindeed have a circumstance of location of ‘in the bed’, wherehas our expected prepositional phrase gone? Thestraightforward structural PP that we would like to find:

[PP in [NP the bed ]]

is not there any more. It has, using the analogy above, been‘deformed’ due to the functional load of needing to stress or

Page 27: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

emphasis or focus (all words that need to be understood farmore closely when we look at them linguistically) particularelements of the clause rather than others. This can lead tomisleading and inaccurate analyses where we mightpresume that there is a special verb ‘to sleep in’, similarly to‘to call up’ or ‘to look up’. But this is not at all motivated: inthe example sentence there is no special meaning for thecombination ‘to sleep’ plus ‘in’.4

The meaning of the example sentence clearly containsadditional information concerning its textual use. That is, itis only going to be used in contexts where the particular bedin question is being picked out and isolated for some reasonin the interaction or text. In the terms being used here, thetextual meaning has required a particular arrangement ofthe ideationally motivated elements. This can occur in avariety of ways, for example in:

This bed has not been slept in for years.

we see that what is in the textually most prominent positionis now the phrase ‘this bed’. But this is not a Participant,Circumstance or Process of the sentence. Nor, as notedabove, do the words ‘sleep in’ make up a phrasal verb in thissentence. The textual pulse has in an important senseignored the ideational constituents of the clause for its ownpurposes.

Many kinds of apparently ‘discontinuous’ constituents—i.e.,parts of a sentence that appear to be spread across asentence rather than all occuring in one place—are the directresult of the pushing and pulling of the textual pulses. Thisnaturally presents substantial problems for those accountswhich have too rigid a notion of consituency. Constituency isimportant and central for language interpretation, but mustalso allow sufficient flexibility to ‘bend in the wind’ of textualneed.

One strategy for dealing with this kind of phenomenon isthen as with the variations caused by the interpersonalmeanings: i.e., to think what the sentence might be without

4 There is, of course, a phrasal verb “to sleep in”—but this is not the form or the meaning thatis being used here.

Page 28: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

the textual variation and to establish what that sentencemight have as a structure. This will usually allow theideational meanings to be established and also provide agood starting point for the syntactic phrasing involved. Thenthe textual pulse will ‘pull’ that structure apart somewhat,but the syntax of languages has evolved precisely to allowsuch pushing and pulling and the basic relationshipsestablished in the ‘neutral’ version will still be interpretablein the non-neutral version.

Another compatible way of seeing what is going on here is toinvolve the interpersonal elements of the sentence. We haveseen that Circumstances (such as ‘in this bed’) are commonlyexpressed by prepositional phrases; we have not said muchabout how interpersonal Adjuncts are expressed however.These are, in fact, very flexible: this is to be expected becausethe work that they do, the ‘load’ that they carry, isinterpersonal and not ideational: that is, they can beproviding a slot for very different kinds of information. Wecan therefore give the interpersonal structure of theproblematic sentence above as follows:

This bed has not been slept in for years

Subject Finite+Negation Predicator Adjunct Adjunct

Mood Residue

Thus, from the interpersonal perspective, it does not look asif anything particularly problematic has occured. We havequite a normal sentence in which the ‘in’ appears more like aparticle of a phrasal verb: thus, even though there is nophrasal verb ‘to sleep in something’ the grammar of Englishis flexible enough to make an expression that has some of thefeeling of a phrasal verb should it need to. The motivation for‘needing to’ comes from the textual meanings that are to beexpressed. We also see this kind of structure in a sentencesuch as the following, which you might hear whennegotiating topics for an assignment:

Sorry, that topic is already being written on.

Page 29: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

Again, there is no phrasal verb ‘to write on’, but wenevertheless have the possibility of constructing a structuresuch as:

write on

Predicator Adjunct

One final example of ‘discontinuity’ motivated by textualconsiderations comes from some Telecom example textsdrawn from newspaper reports; it is the following sentence:

Telecom employees are likely to reimpose work bans or strikewithin a week unless their demands are met on pay negotiations.

When we try and find the constituents in this sentence weshould find that demands and on pay negotiations are quitestrongly connected. You typically have ‘demands on’ or‘demands about’ something. We can also write sentencessuch as:

Their demands on pay negotiations have not been met.

You must meet my demands on pay negotiation or otherwise I willresign.

But in the text we find these two parts of the phrase splitapart. This splitting serves again largely textual functions. Itallows the main point of news or information to be mademore strongly.

If we read this sentence with the main emphasis on ‘met’ (asa newsreader might well do), we express that this is themain point of news of this part of the sentence while ‘on paynegotiations’ is strongly given (because the news item hasbeen running for a few days and, after all, for thisnewspaper, what else would the demands be about if notpay?). If we left the two parts of the phrase together, as in:

Telecom employees are likely to reimpose work bans or strikewithin a week unless their demands on pay negotiations are met.

We have a much weaker phrasing where the neutral newinformation is ‘met’, ‘on pay negotiations’ is also quite new,and ‘demands’ is so weakly new or given that it is impossible

Page 30: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

to clearly decide. It is virtually impossible to put much stresson ‘met’ even if we wanted to.

In summary, textual meanings are an important part oftexts—and they often have ‘distorting’ effects on thestructure of sentences that are difficult to explain ormotivate unless you keep the textual meaning in sight. Thesyntactic scaffold of a clause revealed to us in the phrasestructure rules can thus be ‘bent’ in various ways—but notwithout limits; the most interesting studies, therefore, useboth these ways of looking at clause phenomena to try andchart the limits of the possible and to describe the functionsthat such ‘distortions’ have when constructing connectedwritten or spoken texts.5

While that completes our view of different kinds ofstructurings for different kinds of meanings, we will seebelow that these notions reoccur when we are consideringother aspects of the linguistic system than grammar. We willsee that constituency, prosody and pulse turn up again andagain—whether we are talking about sounds or about text.And their linking with these different kinds of meanings isoften a very useful hint as to what work the patterns foundare doing.

8.2 Compositional semantics

Traditionally discussions of the meanings of sentences havedrawn much of their impetus from notions of logic. This hasalso influenced the kinds of grammatical structures thathave been developed for describing languages. This can becontrasted with approaches to meaning that draw more on‘rhetoric’ than logic—i.e., accounts that describe whatspeakers are doing and what to achieve with their languagerather than language as a description of states in the world.The kinds of meanings that we have discussed so far in thischapter, involving the ideational, interpersonal and textualperspectives, are very much in the rhetorical tradition. In

5 Some linguists take these ‘distortions’ and their power to overrule simple grammaticalstructures as convincing arguments against having syntactic structure at all. This argument is,of course, much easier to make for spoken language than it is for written language. It isunlikely that the structural complexity observable in written language can be dealt withwithout at least some notions of recursive phrase structure however.

Page 31: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

this section, we turn to the very different take on therelation between structure and meaning that we find in thelogical tradition.

One of the points we have made right from our firstintroduction to structure is that different structures lead todifferent interpretations. But how? How can a structure leadto any kind of interpretation at all? In order to be explicitabout this—and we need to be explicit about it if we are to besure that we know what are talking about—we need to spellout in considerably more detail just what it is that structureand interpretation have to do with one another.

One of the most basic assumptions that has been madeconcerning the interpretation of the meaning of sentences isthat this meaning, the semantics, can be built up on thebasis of the structure. This kind of semantics is calledcompositional. Compositional semantics means that you canput the meaning of the whole together out of the meaning ofthe parts.

This is then one of the most important purposes of phrasestructure. The particular tree structure that we have shows(i) exactly the order in which the meaning of the parts maybe combined in order to work out the meaning of the whole,and (ii) which parts go with which others. This is a veryuseful working hypothesis because it means that if we cansay what the meaning of the parts is (and this is hoped to bea simpler task than saying directly what the meaning of aclause is, for example), then we can work out the meaning ofthe whole more or less automatically.

As a simple example, we can see this in a syntactic structurefor a piece of arithmetic.

43

+ -

×

5 2×

4

(3 + 4) × (5 - 2 x 4) = ? COMPOSITIONAL

SEMANTICS

Page 32: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

If we take the ‘meaning’ of the arithmetic expression to be itsvalue when we work out the sum, then the syntactic treetells us exactly how to do this. We first take the 3 and the 4and add them together; then we take the 2 and last 4, andmultiply those together. Then we take this away from the 5.Finally we multiply the result of (5-2×4) by the result we gotearlier by adding 3 to 4 to get the meaning of the whole.

The idea of compositional semantics is then that we haveexactly the same kind of thing going on with expressions inlanguage. Of course, we do not have numbers, and we are notdealing with addition, multiplication, etc. but the principleremains. We combine (in a way to be specified) smallermeanings to arrive at larger ones.

To see this in action, lets take a simple linguistic kind ofexample: how to work out the semantics of the clause ‘thedog chased the boy’.

First, we need to know what the parts to be combined are.This is easy because it is exactly what a phrase structureanalysis tells us. Expressed as a labelled bracket expression,the clause structure is simply:

[S [NP the dog ] [VP chased [NP the boy]]]

For the meaning of the parts, we need to assume some basicsemantics to start from. This is generally handled by thearea of lexical semantics, introductions to which you willhave seen in the reading. As a shortcut for now, let usassume that the semantics of ‘the dog’ is something thatpicks out the particular object in the world that we aretalking about; the same with ‘the boy’. This relates to thestandard ‘semiotic triangle’ discussed by a number oflinguists, semioticians and philosophers of language.

meaning

linguisticsign

object in the world“referent”

meaning

linguisticsign

object in the world“referent”

Page 33: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

The meaning of the verb ‘chase’ is more complex. We cannotjust say that the meaning of ‘chase’ is that it picks out somechasing in the world that we wish to talk about: that wouldavoid the very problem that we wish to solve. Again, for nowwe will adopt a simplification and just describe what kind ofthing the meaning of a verb such as ‘chase’ could be.Essentially we need to say that there is some event and thatthere are participants in that event. This is very similar tothe notions of Process and Participants used above, althoughnow we are moving to wholly into semantics rather thanconsidering grammatical patterns.

We then have the following bits of semantics to be combined:

language expression semantics

“the dog” some dog X in the world

“the boy” some boy Y in the world

“chase” someone chases something

It is then the syntactic phrase structure tree that guides thecombination. This can be depicted graphically as follows.

The dog

noundet

NPVP

S

chased

verb

the boy

det

NPnoun

‘the-boy’

s.o. chased s.t.s.t. = the-boy

s.o. chased the-boys.o. = the-dog

‘the-dog’

That is, we make the meaning of a VP by taking the meaningof the V and combining it with the NP it ‘dominates’. Thisgives us the piece of semantics

someone chases the boy Y that we are talking about

Page 34: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

We then form the meaning of the S by combining the NP andVP that it dominates. This then replaces the ‘someone’ in thesemantics by the meaning of the NP, giving:

the dog X that we are talking about chases the boy Y that weare talking about

This then makes it clear how different structures lead todifferent interpretations.

When we are describing semantics, we often use logicalnotation—logic is in fact very useful when working withsemantics of this kind. We can see this here as a way ofwriting our rather unwieldy statements such as “someonechases the box Y that we are talking about” much moresuccinctly. Lets do this just for this example as anillustration so that you can see that, when used in readingsof various kinds, nothing mysterious is being done. Wetypically write ‘some dog X’ simply as:

dog’ (x)

and ‘some boy Y’ similarly as:

boy’ (y)

The dash after the word is to remind us that we are heredealing now with semantic terms rather than simple words.These are names for the items at the top of our semiotictriangle above and correspond to the meaning rather thanthe words and the objects in the world. A logical expressioncan be true or false. The expression dog’(x) is then true inthose situations where ‘x’ is a name for something in theworld that is actually a dog. This kind of representation iscalled the predicate calculus because it deals withpredicates, i.e.., the terms dog’ and boy’ that apply tovariables such as ‘x’ and ‘y’.

Because these predicates only apply to single variables, theyare called one-place predicates. For the semantics of morecomplex entities, such as the ‘chasing’, we need what arecalled two-place predicates, because they relate to othersimpler entities (the thing chasing and the thing chased).This can be written simply in logic as the expression:

chase’ (x, y)

Page 35: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

Then as a last step we can write our compositional semanticsin terms of semantic interpretation rules. And these,crucially, refer to particular chunks of phrase structure. Thetwo interpretation rules that we need for our examplesentence could be written then as follows, using all that wehave seen so far.

VP

NP : xV : e

: e (__ , x)VP

NP : xV : e

: e (__ , x)

VP interpretation

S

NP : x VP : e

: e (x ,__)S

NP : x VP : e

: e (x ,__)

S interpretation

The left-hand rule says how we take the semantics of theparts of a verb phrase and can combine these into a skeletonof a semantic representation: the semantics of the verb gives

us the predicate while the semantics of the NP gives us thesecond term of the predicated (the ‘chased’ in our currentexample). The right-hand rule does the same for the parts ofa sentence. How this fills in particular values is shown for asentence such as ‘John chases something’ in the followingdiagram:

The crucial idea is that that it does not make any differenceprecisely which sentences we have, the same rules ofsemantic interpretation can apply. Exploring meanings interms of logic is a very powerful way of showing exactly whatcontributes to the meanings of linguistic terms. The closelink with phrase structure should also make it very clear justwhat role is played by phrase structure: it is an essentialsignpost for directing how meanings can be worked out.

S

NP : John VP : chase (__, x)

: chase (John ,__)S

NP : John VP : chase (__, x)

: chase (John ,__)

Page 36: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

Nevertheless, the value of this exercise of semanticcomposition may perhaps still be being obscured somewhatby our English descriptions of the semantics; if we insteadwere trying to describe the semantics of a language that wedid not know, then the role of the phrase structure shouldbecome even clearer. For example, consider the followingsentences, the first from the language Malagasy, the secondfrom the language Hixkaryana spoken in the Amazon Basin:

(a) Nahita ny mpianatra ny vehivavy

(b) Kana yanmno bryekomo.

In linguistics, when we are discussing sentences fromlanguages that the reader might not be familiar with, it isgenerally advisable to provide what is called an interlineargloss—this simply means that we write below the actualsentence (i.e., ‘between the lines’: interlinear) arepresentation of what the words used mean. For these twoexamples this would look as follows:

(a) Nahita ny mpianatra ny vehivavysee the student the woman

(b) Kana yanmno bryekomo.fish catch boy

This can give us an indication of the meaning but, as weshall see, it is not yet enough.

If we take the meanings of the individual parts of thesesentences and describe their semantics, again using Englishand set out in a table, we will soon see very clearly that thesemantics is not just ‘the same again’ as our example withEnglish above. We will omit the Malagasy word ‘ny’, which,as we see from the gloss above, corresponds to the Englishdefinite article ‘the’.

language expression semanticsnahita someone sees somethingmpianatra some student X in the worldvehivavy some woman Y in the worldkana some fish X in the world

Page 37: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

yanmno someone catches somethingbryekomo some boy Y in the world

In order to work out the meaning of the sentences as awhole, we need to know the phrase structures that thelanguages employ. If we do not have access to this structure,either implicitly by virtue of knowing how to speak thelanguage concerned or explicitly as a piece of linguisticknowledge about the languages, we cannot work out whatthe sentence actually means. This is particularly importantin the case of our two examples because they actually havevery different structures to those for English (or German).

Let’s take the Malagasy sentence first. We will examine thephrase structure and apply what we have seen aboveconcerning compositional semantics. An appropriate phrasestructure for the example sentence, i.e., one that the test andprobes would reveal when answered by a speaker of thelanguage, is the following. Note that this structure would notbe one that is possible for English!

NPNPV

VP

S

Nahita ny mpianatra ny vehivavyseeing student woman

Now, although we can apply the same kinds of rules ofsemantic interpretation that we saw for English, thelinguistic elements we take and their order of combination isautomatically different—different because the phrasestructure gives us different instructions for putting thoseelements together.

The first elements to be put together are, as before, those ofthe verb phrase. This VP combines the semantics of the V‘someone sees something’ with the semantics of its noun

Page 38: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

phrase, the NP ‘student’. We saw above, and for the presentwe will just reuse this fact, that the VP incorporates whatwould in English be called the object, or the ‘thing which iseffected or perceived’. Whereas in our English example, thesemantics of the VP therefore because ‘someone chased theboy’, in the Malagasy example we have similarly ‘someonesaw the student’.

We then go up the tree to consider the semantics of theentire sentence, which is formed by putting together thesemantics of the S node in the tree—i.e., we combine thesemantics of the VP, ‘someone saw the student’, with thesemantics of the NP for ‘woman’. And again, with the S node,the child NP can be considered for the moment ascontributing the Actor or Agent of the overall semantics.Actually, and as we saw above, it may be better viewed ascontributing the Subject, but we can omit this subtlety fornow. Carrying out the combination then gives us the finalsemantics for the sentence:

‘the woman saw the student’

Since this is exactly the opposite order of elements to thosethat we have in the original sentence, we can see thatwithout the phrase structure there to guide ourinterpretation, we would not have been able to decide who itwas who was doing the seeing and who was being seen.

The Hixkaryana sentence is againsimilar, but different. An appropriatephrase structure is as shown on theleft. We can build up the semanticsas we did with our last example: firstbuilding the semantics for the VP,i.e., ‘someone caught a fish’, and thencombining this with the NP child ofthe S node, to give the finalsemantics:

‘the boy caught a fish’

In this case, we may have been able to guess the semanticsbecause it is more often the case that boys catch fish than itis that fish catch boys: this shows the pervasive influence ofsemantics in our interpretative efforts. But this could just as

NPNP V

VP

S

Kana yanömno b öryekomofish caught boy

Page 39: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

easily have been a wrong guess: the boy could have beenquite small and the fish quite large. It is only the phrasestructure of the language that allows us (in these cases) toarrive at a definitive answer as to the intended meaning ofthe sentence.

Languages often vary in the way shown here and in manyothers too. The fact that we do not reflect very often on ourown linguistic habits leads us to assume that many moredetails of our language are ‘natural’—i.e., they could not beany other way. This is a particularly dangerous assumptionand is usually wrong: many cases of interculturalcommunication problems arise out of this, often unstatedand unrealised assumption. This is also an obvious source ofproblems in language learning and teaching: differencesbetween languages of this kind clearly indicate areas wherelearners will need more explicit and detailed instruction andpractice in order to overcome the habits of their ownlanguage. In grammar, as our last two examples have shownus, there is in fact considerable variation and one needs to bevery aware of this when dealing with members of languagecommunities where such variation occurs.

This kind of variation is the general subject matter oflinguistic typology and contrastive linguistics.Malagasy is said to be a VOS language, indicating the‘usual’ order of elements in a simple sentence is first the V,then the Object, and finally the Subject. Hixkaryana, incontrast, is thought to be an example of a very rare class oflanguages, those which are typologically OVS, i.e., first theObject, then the Verb, and finally the Subject. Both areclearly distinct from the familiar SVO order of English. Wewill hear more of these different classifications of languagelater.

Naturally, a statement such as “English is SVO” cannot beinterpreted over-literally—there are very many sentenceswhere this order is not reflected directly (e.g., in questions,in many textually re-organised clauses, and so on). Thestatement is a typological one that serves to distinguishEnglish from a whole collection of other typologically distinctlanguages (such as the Hixkaryana we have just seen). Thisactually leads us back to phrase structure: what the

Page 40: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

statement means is that we will find certain phrasestructure configurations rather than others—not that whenyou build sentences you will always find Subjects beforeVerbs before Objects. But the main message for now is thatwithout the underlying phrase structure grammar for alanguage, we cannot interpret even the simplest of sentencesreliably.

We have now seen in this section how modern linguistics,particularly semantics, has come to address one of the oldestand most difficult questions concerning language at all: howis it that speakers can attribute meaning to the utterancesthey encounter. A sufficiently detailed view of the syntax of aclause, plus a set of rules for semantic interpretation thatare associated with the syntactic constructions found, canprovide a blueprint for constructing complex semanticinterpretations. The view of semantics that we constructusing predicate logic and that of grammar given by thephrase structure map fit together naturally because both aredrawn from the ‘logic-based’ approached to meaning andlanguage mentioned above.

Working out the details of these accounts is in fact a veryactive area of research in linguistics for both theoretical andpractical reasons. Practically, being able to specify the rulesby which utterances are interpreted semantically is a crucialstep towards being able to understand utterances andproduce them automatically—this is one of the areas ofhuman language technology, which is rapidly redefiningjust what it means to ‘apply’ linguistic results. Areas oflinguistics previously considered more abstract ortheoretical, such as detailed semantic interpretation, arebeing looked to for precise specifications for how to buildcomputer-based tools for helping writers via more accuratestyle checking, for information retrieval, and a host of othervery practical concerns.

This view of semantics is also a very important ‘reality check’for people who are trying to work out more exact syntacticdescriptions. If the syntactic descriptions proposed make itmore difficult, or impossible, to uncover a semanticinterpretation, then this can be considered a strong pointagainst the proposed model. Much of current linguistic

Page 41: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

research concerns this consideration of the mutual constraintoffered by different levels of linguistic description. It lets ussee what makes a ‘good’ structure from the semanticperspective.

Current work in semantics is also coming to grapple with thefact that semantic interpretations are not complete: theyprovide only a framework, or skeleton, which particularreaders and particular contexts may come to fill in indifferent ways. The important technical term here isunderspecification. Approaches to semantics are trying toleave the semantics that is worked out in the mannerdescribed in this section with particular well-defined ‘holes’that allow further refinement from the knowledge of thereader or the context. This again is an example where thelatest directions in semantics overlap with other attempts tounderstand the fundamental issues of text interpretation.Constructing explicit and detailed accounts of themechanisms of semantics, which also are sufficientlypowerful to allow variation in meaning according to readerand context, is an extremely exciting research area.

References

The VOS/OVS language examples were taken from:

Aleksandra Steinbergs (1996) “The classification of languages”,Chapter 9 in O’Grady, Dobrovolsky and Katamba (1996)Contemporary Linguistics: an introduction. (3rd edition).Longman.

The basic types of sentence structures in English were taken from:

Kortmann, B. (1999) Anglistische Sprachwissenschaft.Cornelsen.

Page 42: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

9 “And what would you say it’s made of?”— Trees and Rules

WHAT WE ARE DOING THIS CHAPTER.

We have seen syntactic trees as used for phrase structureand have considered some of the information that they needto carry. In this chapter we have a brief introduction to themodern tools of linguistics that are used for working withtrees and similar kinds of linguistic representations moreeffectively. This is the area covered by grammatical rules,which tell us exactly which trees are allowed and which not.These are rules in the linguistic sense rather than that oftraditional grammar books. A linguistic rule is a property ofthe language, not a guide to how one should speak. Thesekinds of rules cannot be broken!

Page 43: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

We saw in one of our opening examples in Chapter 2 aninterviewee rather placed on the spot with the followingcurious question about language—“what is it made of”? Inthis chapter we provide more detail concerning the answerthat linguistics currently provides. By now we have also seena wide range of different kinds of linguistic structures andhave shown some of what can be revealed about theadditional meanings of texts when we go about looking atthose structures systematically: i.e., when we look to seewhat has been chosen to appear as Processes, Participants,and Circumstances, what selections have been made forTheme, and for Subject. These kinds of analysis can be takenvery much further, providing ever closer readings of texts.But we have also come across a range of sentences whosestructures are quite difficult to describe. With the rules andprobes that we have explored so far, we may still be in somedoubt occasionally as to exactly what is the Circumstance orwhat is the Subject and so on.

As long as the analysis is unsure, the results of analysis aremore likely to stray into error and so make the patterns ofmeaning by which texts work more difficult to perceive.There is also a much greater likelihood that differentanalysts will come up with differing analyses: it is a primarygoal of being systematic and of employing well definedcriteria for any decisions made that different analysts willarrive at the same analysis. Only with this cross-coderconsistency (or, equivalently as it is also called: inter-coder reliability) can we really lay claims to having arrivedat a more stable interpretation of a text than we might haveachieved by guesswork. We can make an analogy to trying toget the sense of a TV programme if the signal is very bad, orif there is interference: the actual patterns that let usrecognise images on the screen might be more or lessdistorted so it is difficult to see what is going on; pooranalysis can have exactly the same effect on our ability touncover the patterns in texts.

This then brings us back to one of the most important andcentral areas of linguistics—one which has almost come todominate the field for many people. This is the area ofgrammatical structure. We have attempted not to let

Page 44: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

grammatical structure take complete hold of thediscussion—it is, after all, merely a tool for revealing more ofthe meanings that are being made in texts—but it willnevertheless be necessary to provide more detail here for youto see how the kinds of descriptions of syntactic structureseen above have now grown into a view of language almostinconceivable a mere 50 years ago. As stressed above: we arenot just concerned with the introduction of some theoreticalconcepts in this course, it is also an aim that you be able toapply this knowledge in the analysis of all texts that youcome across. This will naturally require refinement andextension later on, but one function of this introduction is toget you started on this.

This chapter will therefore introduce the basic concept thatunderlies the kinds of constituency structure that we sawearlier: that is phrase structure grammar. This isundoubtedly where some of the most detailed results havebeen achieved in linguistics to date: the understanding thatwe now have of the nature of linguistic structure bares littleresemblance to how it was understood even during the 1940sand 50s; we can accordingly do little more here than scratchthe surface in this rapidly expanding and exciting series ofdevelopments. But even this will provide a considerablydeeper understanding and additional tools that can help uscarry out analyses of texts such as illustrated above withmore accuracy and less uncertainty. An appreciation of‘structure’ is essential to many areas of linguistics (and otherdisciplines!) and so the time spent on this is in any case welljustified.

9.1 Syntactic rules and phrase structure grammars

The final step away from chains of words to somethingapproaching modern linguistics lies in a furthergeneralisation over the kinds of phrase structure trees thatwe have been using up to now. Noam Chomsky, anotherfounding father of this particular line of linguistics, showedin his slim book from 1957 simply called SyntacticStructures, that a particular kind of mathematical rule—called the rewrite rule—could be used to good effect formany of the linguistic structures that we have seen. Startingfrom this simple observation, the landscape of linguistics as

Page 45: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

a whole gradually changed over the 1960s and 1970s so thattoday an understanding of language without a knowledge ofbasic phrase structure grammars and their rules isinconceivable.

The rewrite rule provides a straightforward way of sayingwhat trees are possible in a linguistic description. This letsthe linguist away from the position of having to describeevery sentence as it comes, for better or worse. With phrasestructure rules it is possible to make general statementsabout what trees can be built at all. This was a fundamentalchange in how one goes about linguistic description andstarted off an entirely different kind of inquiry. Linguistsstarted talking about the language system as such, thegrammatical system, etc. as abstract constructions that hadtheir own properties. It became possible, therefore, to askquestions as to what would be a possible grammar for ahuman language and what not. Questions which later feeddirectly into debates about the difference between humanlanguage and other kinds of communication systems (such asthat used by chimpanzees or bees) and to issues of how it isthat language learning by children can proceed so reliably.

This also marked the development away from observationsthat sentences appear to have phrase structure of variouskinds, and towards a theory about language structure. Therules specify, i.e., predict, what kinds of trees are possible,and hence what kinds of linguistic structure is possible. Acrucial property of such theories is that they can be wrong:that is, we can make predictions about structures that are

possible that are not found in alanguage or are rejected byspeakers of a language as beinganomalous. As we saw inChapter 3, testing predictionagainst the empirical ‘facts’ isthe driving force that can resultin new, improved (i.e., moreaccurate) theories.

The form of a rewrite rule is quite simple: a left hand side(typically a syntactic label such as NP, PP, etc.) is broken

DATAbits of languagetexts...

DESCRIPTIONS

THEORIES

HYPOTHESES

collectingand systematising

generalising

predictingtesting+

verifying

Observing

Page 46: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

down into its immediate constituents by the right handside of the rule. Thus, we can sum up the possible structureof all prepositional phrases in English with a single rulesuch as:

PP → preposition NP

This states directly that whenever we see a node in a treelabelled PP, we can replace (rewrite) it as containing twoimmediately dominated nodes, a preposition and a NP.Other rules that would go with the structures that we haveseen so far would be the following for NPs such as:

NP → determiner noun

NP → determiner adjective noun

The first describes noun phrases such as ‘the gnome’, ‘theboy’, ‘the garden’, etc.; the second describes noun phrasessuch as ‘the small boy’, etc. Our next rule then combines NPswith PPs, to cover phrases such as ‘the boy in the garden’:

NP → NP PP

Note that because we have used the general label NP on theright hand side of the rule as well as on the left, the verysame rule also covers all such phrases as: ‘the gnome in thegarden’, ‘the small boy in the garden’, while the embeddedNP within the PP means that the rule also covers ‘the boy inthe small garden’.

Another way of viewing these rewrite rules is as a way ofmaking explicit just what substitutions are going to beallowed in our grammar. Remember that substitution wasone of our tests and probes for grammatical constituency.When we write a rule for a grammatical category such asnoun phrase, NP, we are saying that anything that can bedescribed as an NP can be substituted at that point. So ourlast rule means that whenever we have something that weare happy to call a noun phrase, we should be equally happyabout seeing that same noun phrase with a prepositionalphrase after it. Naturally this works fine for NPs such as ‘theboy’, ‘the small gnome’, etc., because we are also going toaccept NPs such as ‘the boy with the telescope’ and ‘the smallgnome in the garden’. If, however, we are also happy toaccept a simple pronoun, such as ‘she’, as a NP, then the

Page 47: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

above rule would mean that we should also be happy toaccept ‘she in the garden’ and ‘she with the telescope’. If youdo not find these phrases equally acceptable, than that is afurther empirical result that would suggest that the rule infact needs to be changed. The ability to measure what agrammar ‘does’, i.e., what structures it predicts to beacceptable, against what is actually the case for a languageis precisely what is meant by talking about the empiricalcycle in grammar writing.

The rules we have so far just describe structuralconfigurations, i.e., possible structural ‘shapes’ thatsentences in English can be made up from. We also need tosay which words can actually occur in these syntactic forms.And for this we need a slightly different rewrite rule, called alexical insertion rule, because it is responsible for sayingwhich words can be ‘inserted’ into structures. A simpleexample of such a rule would be the following for nouns:

N → {dog, boy, gnome}

With this rule, we are saying that trees can be built whereany N node in the tree (i.e., any noun) can be expanded(‘rewritten’) as one of the nouns specified. In theory, mightwant to have a rule with all the nouns of a language—butsince this would obviously be a rather long rule to write, wecommonly talk of a lexicon instead. The simplest view of alexicon is as a list of words, like a dictionary, with particularinformation attached to each entry. For syntax, the leastinformation that should be present is the grammaticalcategory. So if we take the rule above and write this insteadas a small lexicon, it would look as follows:

dog Nboy Ngnome N

This is exactly equivalent to the rewrite rule given above. Itis not, however, very interesting by itself and usuallyconsiderably more information is placed in the lexicon witheach word—this again leads to the area of lexicalsemantics, that has the meaning of words as its mainconcern.

Page 48: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

With phrase structure rules we are to subsume aconsiderable amount of linguistic variation under a singlerule—and this is precisely their purpose: rather thandescribe individual structures, we can instead make verygeneral statements about the kinds of linguistic structuresthat are possible. Rather than resort to examples standing infor linguistic generalizations, or as Edward Sapir wrote in1921: “One example will do for thousands, one complex typefor hundreds of possible types”, we can describe thosethousands directly by saying how they can be built, orgenerated. This had already become an aim of linguistics inthe 1950’s (as we see in the citations from Hockett andothers in Chapter 2 and below), but it had remainedcompletely unclear how it might possibly be achieved.

The rewrite rule, together with Chomsky’s other maincontribution at that time, the transformation, was the firstconvincing indication of how it might be done. In Chomsky’smodel from 1957, the basic structures of a language areproduced directly by a collection of rewrite rules and then

these could be further extended bydefining rules that could turn, forexample, an active sentence into apassive sentence, or a positivesentence into a negative sentence.Notice how this corresponds verydirectly to our strategy for dealingwith complex structures produced byinterpersonal and textual meaningsin Chapter 8: the phrase structurerules give the simple constituencystructure, and then thetransformations could ‘distort’ orstrain these as necessary. The use ofsuch rules was then the beginning ofthe prominent direction in linguisticsstill known as generative grammarwhich had a very significant effect onlinguistics for over two decades.

A grammar rule such as

NP → NP PP

Phrase Structure Rules:

‘rewrite rules’ +

Lexicon

Noam Chomsky 1957

NP

NPV

VP

Sproduce

phrase structures

The boythe cat

chases

Transformational Rules:

e.g., ‘passive’

NP NPVThe cat the boywas chased by

NP1 V NP2 ⇒ NP2

be+V+by NP1

Phrase Structure Rules:

‘rewrite rules’ +

Lexicon

Noam Chomsky 1957

NP

NPV

VP

Sproduce

phrase structures

The boythe cat

chases

Transformational Rules:

e.g., ‘passive’

NP NPVThe cat the boywas chased by

NP1 V NP2 ⇒ NP2

be+V+by NP1

Page 49: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

whatever its merits or otherwise, also gives an example ofthe very special kind of embedding called ‘recursion’mentioned earlier in our introduction to syntactic structure.Recursion is when a phrase may contain another phrase ofthe same kind within it: in this case, a NP can include a NP.Note how we can see this very clearly in the rule itself as agrammatical category appears both on the right-hand sideand the left-hand side. This is important because it opens upthe grammar so as to be able to produce not only ‘thousands’but, in theory, an infinite number of structures: an NP caninclude an NP can include an NP etc. Recursion is the basisof such words games as:

This is the wolf that chased the dog that frightened the cat thatchased the mouse that ate the cheese that came from the house thatJack built.

But recursion is also the basis of the fundamental propertyof human language that no matter how complicated ameaning we have to express, there will always be a way ofcovering that meaning grammatically.

That is, the grammar will not ‘run out of steam’ halfway andonly be able to produce, for example, two PPs, or three NPs;there is always the possibility of having more if the meaningrequires it. We mentioned this fundamental property ofhuman language in the previous chapter and now, withrules, we have a way of explicitly stating how this can be.

The nodes illustrating recursionare shown in the tree on theright, which shows quite acomplicated sentence structurethat we will return to below.Rewrite rules directly involvingrecursion are quite simple torecognise: they simply have ontheir right-hand side anoccurrence of the type of label that appears on the left-handside. Many cases are more complex, however, in that therecursion comes about indirectly, as in the tree above. Herethere is recursion because the PP has an NP which has a PPin it. We can only see this from the rewrite rules byconsidering what happens when we combine them: i.e., is it

(A fast car with (twin cams))

PP

prep

noun noun

NPadj noundet

NP

(the children [on lane)])]

PP

prepnoun

NP

noundet

NP

grassy

adj

(the

det

[by

PP

prep

VP

S

sped

verb

cases ofRECURSION

Page 50: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

possible to go round in circles in their application—apply theNP rule, then apply the PP rule, then apply the NP rule(again), and so on.

In general, it is crucial to realise that the tree structures andthe phrase structure rules are very intimately related. Givenany rule, we can say what bits of phrase structure tree arepossible; and given any bit of tree, we can say what rules arenecessary to produce that tree. This is illustrated in thediagram below. The rules corresponding to, or ratherlicensing two particular nodes in the tree are shownhighlighted.

The strike

noundet

NP

some weeks

noun

NP

det

for

PP

prep

VP

S

continued

verb

S→NP VP

The strike

noundet

NP

some weeks

noun

NP

det

for

PP

prep

VP

S

continued

verb

VP→verb PP

A tree is only really well-defined with respect to a given bodyof rules: and a body of rules is called a grammar. This iswhy it does not really make so much sense to ask whether atree is ‘correct’ or not: we need to say correct with respectwhich grammar. Each node of a tree must be licensed bysome rule in a specified grammar. Only when this has beendone can we know completely explicitly what our treediagrams are representing and also how we are allowed todraw them.

This is the way in which modern linguistics has sought to gobeyond the collection of various structures as needed todescribe the sentences that are encountered in a language.Not only do we need to describe the sentences that occur, wealso need to relate these (and only these) sentences to ageneral grammar that can produce them.

We must then be able to follow this connection between rulesand syntactic trees. We need to be able to say which treesfollow from a given set of rules. We also need to be able tojudge whether some tree is allowed by a set of rules or not.This is part of the stage of testing, verifying and possiblyfalsifying a theory of structure. Only when we can do this

Page 51: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

can we take the next important step: that of changing therules so that they do a better job of describing the languagethey are intended to cover: i.e., of developing new theoriesthat do a better job of describing the linguistic facts. It wasthis ability to link rules and trees in a clear andunambiguous fashion that allowed the development of thelinguistic understanding of syntax to scale completely newheights. Previous general tendencies and observations werereplaced by a far deeper view of the basic stuff out of whichlanguage is made: structure.

This development has steadily revealed not only more of thecomplexity inherent in language structure but also more ofthe regularities; modern grammars contain very generalstatements that apply both to a wide range of syntactic andsemantic phenomena that were previously considered to beunconnected or lacking in pattern and to a wider range oflanguages. This has allowed linguists, for the first time inthe long history of linguistics, to ask questions about alanguage system as a whole, about the properties that anentire grammar for a language must possess in order towork, and to move us beyond the study and collection ofindividual constructions.

Since the groupings that occur in language are there for apurpose, it is not the case that the kinds of phrases that wefind necessary in grammatical rules and, consequently, insyntactic trees, are arbitrary or random. The phrasesdescribed should always correspond to some meaningfulgrouping. To apply the semantic ‘reality check’ of theprevious chapter, it should be possible to find some sensiblesemantics for each node in the tree. Moreover, the relationsbetween phrases in a syntactic tree should also correlate tosome aspect of their meanings. A precise syntactic tree cantherefore make explicit ambiguities in the meanings ofsentences. Consider, for example, the following sentence.

The dwarf saw the gnome in the garden

We can try to build a structure for this sentence followingthe syntactic rules that we have seen so far with one smalladdition. For convenience we group the relevant rulestogether here, giving our first grammar. It has six rules:

1. S → NP VP

Page 52: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

2. NP → det N3. NP → NP PP4. VP → verb NP5. VP → verb NP PP6. PP → prep NP

This grammar illustrates that it is not necessary that thereis only one way of constructing a phrase: there can bealternatives. Thus rules (4) and (5) show that there are twopossibilities for a verb phrase, one with a prepositionalphrase and one without. This is necessary because, as wehave seen, not all sentences have Circumstances. Both thesentences,

John ate a cake.John ate a cake in the kitchen.

are acceptable English. A notational abbreviation that isoften used in phrase structure is to combine such rules intoone and to mark the element that appears in one rule but notin the other as optional. This optionality is indicated byenclosing the optional element in brackets; thus rules (4) and(5) could be rewritten as the single rule:

4′. VP → verb NP (PP)

It is the existence of alternatives of this kind that leads tothe possibility of ambiguity: both structural, in that morethan one syntactic tree is possible, and functional orsemantic, in that the different syntactic trees lead to morethan one interpretation of what the sentence could mean.For our sentence above, for example, we should be able torecognise the various grammatical ‘chunks’ without toomuch difficulty: we have three NPs ‘the dwarf’, ‘the gnome’,and ‘the garden’ and a PP ‘in the garden’. But how are theseconstituents to be put together? One possible tree uses rules(1), (2), (3), (4) and (6) to produce the tree:

Page 53: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

PP

prep

NP

The dwarf saw the gnome in the garden

det noun

NP

det nounverbnoun

NP

S

det

NPVP

But this is not the only possible way to use the rules of thegiven grammar in order to construct a tree that fits with thesequence of words that make up the sentence. In particular,we could also consider using rule (5) which allows us toattach a prepositional phrase directly to the verb phrase.This would give the following tree:

PP

prep

NP

The dwarf saw the gnome in the garden

det noun

NP

det nounverbnoun

NP

S

det

VP

The only difference between the two trees is where theprepositional phrase ‘in the garden’ has been attached tothe rest of the tree. But this difference is not an artificial onethat is caused by our rules. It corresponds to a genuineambiguity in the possible meanings of the sentence: was itthe gnome that was in the garden or was it the event ofseeing that was in the garden? We can bring out these twomeanings by adding some more detail: e.g.,

The dwarf in the park saw the gnome in the garden by using apowerful telescope.

Page 54: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

PP

The dwarf saw the gnome in the garden

NP

verbNP

S

??

VP‘PP Attachment’

In this sentence, it is likely that the seeing takes place wherethe ‘see-er’ (the dwarf) is, that is, in the park, and sodescription ‘in the garden’ must refer to the gnome—i.e., it isthe gnome in the garden that the dwarf sees (while in thepark). The two different meanings correspond to differentstructures. This problem ofso-called PP-attachment isa general source ofambiguities in sentences:since the grammar ofEnglish (and many otherlanguages) allows PPs tooccur in both NPs and VPs itis not always clear which ismeant. This is shown in thediagram to the right; here we also make use of a commonnotation found in syntax trees: when some details ofstructure are not relevant to the immediate point beingmade in a discussion, we can blank them out in shadedtriangles so as to focus the attention of the reader. Here theinternal structure of the NPs and PP is not at issue, it iswhere the PP is to be attached that is important.

This can also be shown to be more than a so-called ‘artefactof the description’; that is, it is not simply because we haveto write the trees down somehow that this kind of forcedchoice is created. Many studies in the area ofpsycholinguistics investigate with psychologicalexperimental methods the kinds of processing languageusing subjects employ during language understanding.These experiments can reveal, for example, when, and underwhat conditions, subjects need to do relatively moreprocessing. Cases of PP-attachment trigger this kind ofeffort, which is therefore revealed to be ‘real’: at least as faras our brains and their processing of language is concerned.

The uncertainty in attachment shown here is also the sourceof many misunderstandings as well as intended double-meanings as found in jokes such as the following allegedadvertisement:

For sale: mixing bowl set designed to please cook with roundbottom for efficient beating.

Page 55: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

The serious point here is that syntactic structure andmeaning go together: as we saw suggestively in our firstintroductions to phrase structure and more technically inChapter 8, if there are different syntactic structures, thenthere are also different meanings. Making sure that you canfind alternative structures when they are there, and not findthem when they are not there, takes some practise but is anecessary skill to develop. Being able to follow systematicallythe consequences of your statements makes it more likelythat logical inconsistency will be avoided and also providesthe tools for probing deeper to give more revealing analyses.

Here are some further ambiguous sentences with theirstructures shown with labelled brackets. Remember thatthese labelled bracket expressions are exactly equivalent tosyntactic trees and you should be able to draw the treescorresponding to each of these examples. In each case it isthe attachment of a PP that causes the difference. The effectis not always humorous—sometimes it just results in anunclear sentence.

• We will sell gasoline to anyone in a glass container.

[S [NP We] [VP [verb will sell] [NP gasoline] [PP to anyone] [PP in[NP a glass container]]]]

[S [NP We] [VP [verb will sell] [NP gasoline] [PP to anyone [PP in[NP a glass container]]]]]

• A fast car with twin cams sped by the children on the grassylane

[S [NP A fast car [PP with twin cams]] [VP [verb sped] [PP by [NP

the children]] [PP on [NP the grassy lane]]]]

[S [NP A fast car [PP with twin cams]] [VP [verb sped] [PP by [NP

the children [PP on the grassy lane]]]]]

The different structures give rise to different meanings. Inthe first example the question is whether the anyone towhom gasoline will be sold is in a glass container or not; inthe second example, the question is whether it is thechildren or the car that is on the grassy lane.

Page 56: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

Although the rules of English (and many other languages)allow a great deal of flexibility in how phrases are puttogether, they do not allow just any combination: if they did,then we would not need a grammar. So the followingexample that we have seen before as a candidate of asentence that might have been thought to be ambiguous andwhich actually is not:

The gnome in the garden is sad.

can be readily ruled out by the appropriate phrase structuregrammar. As we saw in Chapter 8, if we think solely ofProcesses as the action involved, Participants as thoseinvolved centrally in the action, and Circumstances aslocations where the action occurs, then we might, quitewrongly, produce an analysis like the following that wecriticised above:

The gnome in the garden is sadParticipant Circumstance Process

Such an analysis is wrong in two respects: first, it suggests astructure that does not exist in English and, second, itsuggests a meaning that is not the meaning of the sentence.

This sentence does not express that it is “in the garden” thatthe being sad occurred: it simply makes a statement about aparticular Participant—and that Participant is “the gnomein the garden”. This can almost be producedstraightforwardly by our little set of grammar rules givenabove; the only complication is the fact that we have adifferent type of clause here, one that is attributing aproperty to some participant. This involves a different verbphrase, one where there is a verb (typically but not alwaysthe verb ‘to be’, also called the copula) followed by anadjectival phrase. We will leave this detail out of thestructure for present though giving a tree like this:

Page 57: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

The gnome in the garden is sad

det

NP

N

NP

det

VP

S

PP

prep

N

NP

As we will show in more detail in the sections following, thisstructure is only compatible with a meaning where there is asingle Participant—“the gnome in the garden”—and thesentence assigns a property to this Participant, that of beingsad. If we were to try to associate the being in the gardenwith the Process, which would be what is necessary to makeit into a Circumstance, then we would need a structure morelike one of the following two:

The gnome in the garden is sad

det

NP

N

NP

det

VP

S

PP

prep

N

The gnome in the garden is sad

det

NP

N

NP

det

VP

S

PP

prep

N

But neither of these structures are supported by the grammaras given. We do not have any rule that lets us expand an Snode into an NP, PP and VP in that order; nor do we haveany rule that lets us expand a VP into something that beginswith a PP. This is for a goodreason: these are notstructures that occur inEnglish: in fact, we cannotinterpret the sentence as onein which the ‘in the garden’is related to the being sad.We can bring out thiscontrast by producing asentence which our grammarcan produce: i.e.,

The gnome is sad in the garden.

The small gnome on the hill wiped his hands

adjdet

NP

N

NP

det

VP

S

verb

PP

prep

N

NP

det

What rule???

N

Page 58: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

Here we have a straightforward VP ending with aprepositional phrase as we have often seen above. Abelievable follow-up to a statement such as this would bethat the gnome should perhaps go somewhere else, then hewould not be sad. This demonstrates that the garden and thebeing sad are indeed brought together in this sentence; nosuch follow-up would come to mind in the case of theprevious sentence used above.

This applies for all similar structures. For example, in thesentence:

The small gnome on the hill wiped his hands

it is not immediately obvious perhaps from the meaningwhether the constituent ‘on the hill’ is to be linked to the‘gnome’ or the ‘wiping’. But the structure tells us; anyattempt to link with the verb would not be sanctioned by ourgrammar. Since the grammar does not allow this but doesallow a straightforward linking with the ‘small gnome’ wecan assign our structure accordingly. This, as we will see,lets us straightforwardly decide what and what not areParticipants or Circumstances.

Thus, a useful grammar is constraining: it tells us whatstructures are possible and leads us away from impossiblecombinations. This is one of the aims of a good grammar. Itshould cover a wide range of the possible structures of alanguage, but also rule out those which are not possible. Agrammar that produces sentences that are not acceptable issaid to overgenerate. A good grammar should notovergenerate, but it should also not undergenerate, i.e., itshould still let us describe the structures that do occur.Although meeting these requirements is difficult, the resultsare well worth aiming for. Another important aim for a goodgrammar, one which we will now turn to in the next chapter,is that the grammatical structures produced should make iteasier to work out the meaning of any sentence: that is,syntactic grouping should correspond in some way tosemantic grouping.

The notion of ‘generativity’ here became a central one inlinguistics after it was introduced into the linguisticmainstream by the early work of Chomsky in histransformational model that we saw above. For many,

Page 59: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

linguistics is still essentially generative linguistics if it is tobe considered interesting. While we do not share this view atall here, it is necessary to be aware of it. It is perhaps anatural development in the style of linguistics that took‘prescriptivism’—i.e., saying what is allowed and what not—to the logical limit.

“A grammatical description must be a guidebook for the analysis ofmaterial in the language—both material examined by the analystbefore the description was formulated, and material observed afterthat. [...]

The description must also be prescriptive [...] in the sense that byfollowing the statements one must be able to generate nay numberof utterances in the language, above and beyond those observed inadvance by the analyst—new utterances most, if not all, of whichwill pass the test of casual acceptance by a native speaker.”(Hockett, 1954:232).

This view was taken up in force by Zelig Harris, anotherfamous name from the immediate ‘pre-Chomsky’ period andof whom Chomsky was a student:

“The work of analysis leads right up to the statements which enableanyone to synthesize or predict utterances in the language.” (Harris,1951: 372)

This is a very enticing carrot. If we think back to ourdescription of the empirical cycle in Chapter 3, here we havethe ultimate in prediction: linguistic theory was seen to be onthe verge of actually predicting what utterances can be madein a language and which not. This was a very newdevelopment—one which could not be matched in theprevious long history of linguistics.

Of course, the strong view of prediction has to be consideredrather carefully here. There are too many variables involvedto predict what any particular speaker will say in anyparticular situation. Where the strong predictive nature ofthe account has been extremely valuable, however, is in theability of a model to be precise enough to make wrongpredictions—this was also not possible before. For the firsttime, a linguistic account could be shown to be simply wrong,rather than a matter of opinion. This is the hypothesis-testing-rehypothesis cycle that has led to enormous

Page 60: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

developments that we have seen since 1960 in linguisticdescription.

9.2 The connection between rules and meanings

We can now also bring in our discussion of semantics fromChapter 8. We saw there that the phrase structure served togive instructions for constructing semantics. We suggestedthat that particular phrase structure tree configurationswent together with particular ‘instructions’. These werewritten in terms of semantic interpretation rules. Given aparticular configuration, the semantic interpretation wouldtell us how to combine the meanings of the parts to get themeaning of the whole. The step to relating syntactic rules tosemantics is then a simple one.

A ‘tree configuration’—such as, for example, a S made up ofan NP and a VP—is actually just another way of writing aphrase structure rule. That is, we can write a treeconfiguration in the way we were doing when we wereanalysing sentences:

But we can also write this tree configuration just as well asthe phrase structure rewrite rule:

VP → V NP

The same is captured in both cases .The point of the rewriterule is that it simply emphasises the fact that we can‘generate’ as many tree configurations as we like; we are notjust describing one tree, but one possible kind of tree.

So, given this connection between tree configurations andrules, we can similarly convert our semantic interpretationrules into phrase structure rules that include semantics.

This goes as follows.

NPV

VP

NPV

VP

Page 61: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

First, consider again one of our semantic interpretation rulesfrom Chapter 8, the rule for composing the parts of asentence to make a meaning for the whole:

S interpretation

Now, we express the tree configuration part of this diagramas a rewrite rule, thus:

S → NP VP

and finally we add in the semantic parts as additionalinformation associated with each part of our grammar rule.We can write such additional information in bracketsunderneath the constituent to which it applies, like this:

S → NP VP [ e (x, __ ) ] [ x ] [ e (__ , __) ]

As before, the “__” indicates empty spaces in the semanticsthat will be filled in by other rules of interpretation. Readingthe entire rule, we now have the following instructions allneatly combined:

1. Build a grammatical sentence (an S) by taking agrammatical verb phase (VP) and a grammatical nounphrase (NP) and putting them one after the other

2. Build the semantic interpretation of the sentence bytaking the event associated with the VP and the objectassociated with the NP and combining them in the wayshown for the S.

Naturally this can become much more complicated withmore complicated sentences. But the essential idearemains the same. Writing our rules like this captures thecentral idea of compositional semantics and tells usexactly how to put meanings together. The basicmechanism that is most commonly used for puttingtogether the individual parts of semantic information to

S

NP : x VP : e

: e (x ,__)S

NP : x VP : e

: e (x ,__)

Page 62: Introduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004 ... · PDF fileIntroduction to Linguistics Reading: Bateman (2004, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Linguistics ... within linguistics

get bigger or more explicit pieces of semantics is calledunification. That is, we unify the component parts inorder to get bigger parts.

Unification is one of the most important mechanisms usedin modern linguistics and can make linguistic descriptionsvery much simpler, while at the same time describingvery much more of language. Unification is also veryimportant in computational linguistics because it ispossible to spell out the mechanism sufficiently explicitlyfor computers to be able to perform it automatically. Amore detailed description of unification must wait forlater, more advanced courses however.

For now it is enough to know that rules correspond tofragments of trees, that the rules determine which treesare allowed and which not, and that we can associatesemantic information with rules in order to get oursemantic interpretations done. That is already quite a lot.

Reading and references

Chomsky, Noam (1957) Syntactic Structures. Mouton.

Harris, Zellig S. (1951) Methods in Structural Linguistics. Chicaco: Chicago University Press.(Reprinted as Structural Linguistics, 1960).

Hockett, Charles F. (1954) ‘Two models of grammatical description’. Word 10: 210—231.


Recommended