+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Is Acounting a Measurement Discipline

Is Acounting a Measurement Discipline

Date post: 05-Apr-2018
Category:
Upload: rabibay
View: 223 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend

of 21

Transcript
  • 7/31/2019 Is Acounting a Measurement Discipline

    1/21

    Measurement in Accounting: What is the Scale?

    In the last few years the field of accounting has been the subject of a critical review,the intensity

    of which is increasing as time goes by. Somehow, both within and without the accounting

    profession, there is a feeling of dissatisfaction with the information generated by the accounting

    process. Such dissatisfaction is leading to questions about the fundamental bases of Accounting.

    The practitioner claims to identify,collect,measure,record,analyse and report financial data useful

    for a variety of purposes. Unfortunately, recent financial turmoil emanating from some of the

    uses applied to accounting reports is causing accountants and other stakeholders to question thefoundations of accounting. Some ask questions like is Accounting a Science or Art? If it is a

    science, what is its foundation in Science? Are their theories guiding the focus of accounting

    scholars? Are these theories the result of empirical findings and observations? Are the findings

    the outcome of diligent and rigorous measurement of phenomena? Does accounting measure any

    phenomena? Is the accounting phenomena amenable to measurement? Inshort is Accounting a

    measurement Discipline? Scholars are therefore re-examining the foundations of accounting to

    determine its suitability as a Science. A Science Discipline is founded on theories which are

    prediction of phenomena. These predictions are possible because rigorous and precise

    measurements of phenomena is achieved using instruments or tools. Therefore measurement is

    critical to any science discipline.

    STATEMENT OF THE PROBLEM

    Accounting is regarded as a Social Science. The Social Science Disciplines are also regarded as

    Measurement Disciplines. These disciplines have theories based on quantitative and qualitatively

  • 7/31/2019 Is Acounting a Measurement Discipline

    2/21

    observed phenomena. The phenomena observed in accounting is performance of economic

    activities. Thus accounting claims to measure performance achieved by attaching number values

    to economic activities. The problem is whether the accounting criteria for measuring economic

    performance is relevant and valid for a measurement discipline. All measurement disciplines

    must have a measurement theory. Therefore, we ask which theory of measurement is accounting

    measurement borrowing from?

    OBJECTIVE OF THE STUDY

    The objective of this paper is to determine whether the belief that accounting is a measurementdiscipline is justified;

    To examine whether accounting measurement has any scale of measurement and;

    To examine the relationship between accounting measurement and measurement theory.

    SIGNIFICANCE OF THE STUDY

    This work is important to both academics, practicing accountants and other stakeholders because

    it will determine whether accounting reports can be considered objects of scientific

    endeavours.Scientific endeavours are based on objectivity. Objectivity is crucial because

    accounting reports affect economic activities.

    SCOPE AND LIMITATION

    The scope of this work is a review of literature which the scholar accessed on measurement

    theory and accounting measurement. Unfortunately, the span of literature review is limited by;

    a) Limited library resource on the relevant field

    b) Materials available online on limited access for preview only. Full access available on

    paid subscription which is unfortunately affordable.

  • 7/31/2019 Is Acounting a Measurement Discipline

    3/21

    LITERATURE REVIEW

    Measurement is the process or the result of determining the ratio of a physical quantity, such as a

    length, time, temperature etc., to a unit of measurement, such as the meter, second or degree

    Celsius. The science of measurement is called metrology. With the exception of a few seemingly

    fundamental quantum constants, units of measurement are essentially arbitrary; in other words,

    people make them up and then agree to use them. Nothing inherent in nature dictates that an inch

    has to be a certain length, or that a mile is a better measure of distance than a kilometre. Over the

    course of human history, however, first for convenience and then for necessity, standards of

    measurement evolved so that communities would have certain common benchmarks. Lawsregulating measurement were originally developed to prevent fraud in commerce. Today, units of

    measurement are generally defined on a scientific basis, overseen by governmental or supra-

    governmental agencies, and established in international treaties, pre-eminent of which is the

    General Conference on Weights and Measures (CGPM), established in 1875 by the Treaty of the

    metre and which oversees the International System of Units (SI) and which has custody of the

    International Prototype Kilogram. The metre, for example, was redefined in 1983 by the CGPM

    as the distance travelled by light in free space in 1299,792,458 of a second while in 1960 the

    international yard was defined by the governments of the United States, United Kingdom,

    Australia and South Africa as being exactly 0.9144 metres.

    In the classical definition, which is standard throughout the Physical Sciences, measurement is

    the determination or estimation of ratios of quantities. Quantity and measurement are mutually

    defined: quantitative attributes are those possible to measure, at least in principle. This definition

  • 7/31/2019 Is Acounting a Measurement Discipline

    4/21

    is not suitable for the Social Sciences which measure attributes of human behaviour.Social

    Sciences therefore base there measurements on a different theory.

    For measurement to be valid scientifically, there must be a scale. The scale concept is integral

    to measurement. Ryan,Scapens & Theobald (2002) show that every measurement process begins

    with scale specification. The specification of a scale of measurement is proof that the process is

    indeed one of measurement. IASB(2009) state that accounting is considered to be a measurement

    discipline. Thus, one would expect to find specified scales of measurement in accounting. A

    scale distinguishes the amount of a specified property in a specified class of phenomena. But it issaid that such variation of specified property into specified classes does not exist in

    accounting.The works of Staubus(2004) and Ryan et al. (2002) all lend credence to this. Studies

    by Chambers (1997) and Willet (1987) reached similar conclusions. This contradicts the view

    that accounting is a measurement discipline. Narens (2002) also makes the point that a theory of

    measurement consists of a precise specification of how a scale is formed. The absence of

    specified scales of measurement in accounting therefore points to the absence of a theory of

    measurement in accounting. According to Luce, Krantz, Suppes and Tversk (1971), every

    process of measurement must have a theory of measurement. This means that every

    measurement discipline must have an underlying theory of measurement. The presence of a

    theory of measurement evidently guarantees the empirical validity of information produced by a

    process of measurement. Authors such as Staubus (1985) and Ijiri (1975) indicate a consensus

    that the accounting discipline has not succeeded in inferring a comprehensive and coherent

    theory of measurement from the observation of accounting measurement practices.

    Consequently, this suggests that researchers have not succeeded in specifying either how scales

  • 7/31/2019 Is Acounting a Measurement Discipline

    5/21

    are formed in accounting measurement or whether the empirical validity of accounting

    information can be guaranteed. The above discussion points out that accounting is considered to

    be a measurement discipline in the absence of evidence (scales) confirming that it is such a

    discipline. As a result, it is necessary to investigate whether this accounting perspective is a

    delusion. Accounting is classified as a social science (Ryan et al., 2002). This means that

    measurement in accounting is viewed from the perspective of social science. The theory that

    establishes measurement in social sciences is the representational theory of measurement (Luce

    et al., 1971, 1989, 1990). The concept of scale in accounting is thus discussed from the

    perspective of representational measurement theory.

    THEORETICAL FRAMEWORK

    This paper views the representational theory of measurement as the framework under which

    accounting may or may not fit into the realm of measurement science. Unlike the real theory of

    measurement, the representational theory is more amenable to social sciences. Recall that we

    earlier stated that accounting is regarded as a social science..

    The Representational Theory of Measurement

    The classical or real theory of measurement is relevant to the physical sciences because it only

    recognises measurement of quantitative phenomena. To facilitate measurement in the Social

    Sciences, the representational theory of measurement was developed in 1958. Scott and

    Suppes(1958) developed this theory of ordering for the social sciences influenced by application

    of ordering to psychology(Luce,1956).This group of measurement theories requires in common a

    scale that can be defined by a set of structure preserving mappings from a qualitative or

  • 7/31/2019 Is Acounting a Measurement Discipline

    6/21

    empirically-based structure onto a structure from mathematics. The representational

    measurement theory offers an abstract theory of the kinds of well-behaved scales encountered in

    science. It places great emphasis on the uniqueness of representations. Empirical examples of all

    scale types can be found in the representational theory of measurement. These scale types are

    also commonly found in science. They were conceptualised by Stevens(1946,1951) as ordinal,

    interval, ratio and nominal scales. Other works of Naren(1981a) and Naren(1981b) reveal that

    there can be scales between the ratio and interval scales which have not yet been applied to

    scientific measurement. Luce and Suppes(2001) agree to the existence of these scales and their

    non usage in scientific measurement.

    The Concept of a Representational Scale

    The concept of a scale is of fundamental importance in representational measurement. A scale is

    a rule used for the assignment of numerals to properties of objects or events(Stevens, 1951). This

    equates a scale to a specific method of measurement. It is also noteworthy that measurement

    always occurs in a specific way, which means that every measurement process must have a rule

    of measurement. Consequently, it is clear that in a process of measurement the random

    assignment of numbers to objects is excluded. Luce et al. (1971) argue that measurement can

    take place only if the rule that maps an empirical relational structure onto the numerical

    relational structure is specified. This indicates that the process of measurement takes place only

    in the presence of a standardized rule of measurement. From the foregoing, we can assume that

    the word rule as used above means the presence of a scale in every measurement process.

    Therefore it suffices to conclude that every process of measurement must have a scale of

    measurement. We can define a representational scale as that which exists when there is a

  • 7/31/2019 Is Acounting a Measurement Discipline

    7/21

    qualitative structure X and a mathematical representing structure N for X such that the scale is a

    subset of one to one homomorphisms from X to N.

    This definition points out that a scale of measurement can exist only when the quality in a

    structure can be represented by a numerical relational structure. It is also clear that a scale is part

    of the homomorphisms that map a qualitative structure onto a numerical relational structure. A

    homomorphism is a function that maps an algebraic structure onto another in a way that

    preserves the properties of the algebraic structure being mapped(Bhattacharya, Jain & Nagpaul,

    1986). It is evident from this that a scale indicates the relationship that enables a qualitativestructure to be mapped onto a numerical relational structure. It follows, therefore, that a scale

    explains how the properties of a qualitative structure are represented by an algebraic structure or

    a rule that explains the representation of an empirical relational structure by a numerical

    relational structure. According to Luce et al. (1971) the scales of measurement are subject to

    arbitrary conventions. It can be argued from this that scales of measurement are socially

    constructed. It also suggests that each process of measurement has its own rules of measurement.

    As a result, there is the possibility of a proliferation of rules of measurement for a single process

    of measurement. Thus we see that we can have different scales and different kinds of

    measurement because we can have different rules for assigning numerals to qualities of

    structures(Stevens,1951:1). This may result in the proliferation of measurement rules.If we agree

    with this then there are several measurement methods. Thus, each type of scale distinguishes one

    form of measurement from another. These numerous methods of measurement lead to different

    kinds of scales. It can also be inferred that each frame of reference can have its own rules of

    measurement. In addition, it should be noted that the rules of measurement are not part of the

  • 7/31/2019 Is Acounting a Measurement Discipline

    8/21

    phenomenon being measured. The empirical relational structure and its empirical properties are

    not a matter of convention. Luce et al . (1971) argue that the empirical relational structure and its

    empirical properties should be treated as a set of qualitative empirical laws. This means that the

    phenomenon being measured should be invariant under any set of measurement procedures. A

    set of measurement procedures does not change the underlying property it is measuring (e.g., a

    mans height is not changed in being measured by a metre rule). Stevens (1951) characterized

    scales into four types, namely, nominal, ordinal interval and ratio scales. The type of scale

    achieved in measurement depends upon the character of the basic empirical operations

    performed on the property being measured. Ordinarily, these operations are limited by thepeculiarities of the thing being scaled and by our choice of the concrete procedures. However,

    once selected, these procedures determine the type of scale that will eventuate (Stevens, 1951).

    The type of a scale indicates the level of measurement.Associated with each level of

    measurement is a set of mathematical operations that may be performed on a measure. Each level

    of measurement involves different properties(relations and operations) of the numbers or

    symbols that constitute the measurements. The mathematical operations that may be performed

    on a measure without changing its meaning are termed permissible transformations on its scale.

    Permissible transformations on a scale preserve the relevant relationships of the measurement

    process (Luce et al. , 1971). For example, changing the unit of measurement of distance(say, from

    inches to centimetres) multiplies the measurements by a constant factor. This multiplication does

    not alter the correspondence of the relationships greater than or the correspondence of addition

    and concatenation. Hence, it follows that the change of units is a permissible transformation with

    respect to these relationships. The concept of a representational scale is inextricably linked to the

    uniqueness and the existence of theorems of representational measurement. A number assigned

  • 7/31/2019 Is Acounting a Measurement Discipline

    9/21

    to measure a property is unique once a unit of measurement has been chosen (Luce et al. , 1990).

    This means that a scale of measurement makes a measure unique. It follows that the proof of the

    uniqueness theorem is equivalent to identifying all possible scales for the measurement of the

    elements of a given empirical relational system. It can therefore be concluded that the type of

    measurement can be known if, and only if, the scale of measurement is known.

  • 7/31/2019 Is Acounting a Measurement Discipline

    10/21

    CHAPTER THREE

    DISCUSSIONS

    The discussions in this section seeks to highlight the significance of absence of a scale in

    accounting measurement and the wider implication of non conformity with the theory of

    representational measurement. Critical literature review will serve as our aid on these

    discussions.

    3.1 Importance of a Measurement Scale

    From review of different studies it is apparent that a scientific measurement cannot hold without

    a scale. The scale serves as rule to guide every measurement process. It serves to direct theprocess of relating empirical properties to the assignment of numerical properties. Scales are

    classified into different types according to information implied in their usage(Stevens,1951).We

    know that accounting reports economic performance using numerical assignments. Are there any

    scales used to map out the relations between the properties measured and the numbers

    attached?Mattessichi(1964) seems to believe that accounting communicates its information using

    the media of the four known scale types. He cites nominal, ordinal, interval and ratio scales as

    those used in accounting. He however fails to specify how each property measured is related to

    the numbers assigned based on these scale types.

    The theory of measurement suggests that every measurement scheme should specify the type of

    scale used in order to indicate the amount of information contained by the measures it produces.

    It can thus be argued that a scale of measurement is an embodiment of the properties of the

    phenomenon being measured. It follows that, without the specification of a scale of

    measurement, it would be not possible to know what a particular numerical assignment

  • 7/31/2019 Is Acounting a Measurement Discipline

    11/21

    represents. Therefore, if accounting were a measurement discipline, it should have been capable

    of specifying the rules of measurement employed in its measurement processes to give meaning

    to its numerical assignments. Failure to do so calls into question the status of accounting as a

    measurement discipline. Measurement is about stating the relationship between the numerals and

    the objects. A rule of measurement states the relationship between the numerals and

    objects(Luce,1961) This means that, if accounting has no specified rules of assigning numerals

    to objects, it implies that the relations between the numerals and objects are not known. If these

    relations are not known it would be difficult to determine the meaning of a measurement. It

    follows that the concept of a scale influences the meaningfulness of a measure. This indicatesthat a scale used in a process of measurement must be specified. The scale gives empirical

    significance to measurements. Thus, a scale specifies the conditions under which a measurement

    has been made. It is clear from the above that the essence of meaningfulness is embodied in the

    description of the scale type and permissible statistics. This evidently highlights the fact that the

    statistics that can be performed on a measure depends on the scale type used to get the

    measure.The scale also affects the meaningfulness or lack of it in a measure.

    The meaning of a measure is therefore embodied in the description of the meaning of the

    standard unit. For example, the meaning of a length will be embodied in the description of a

    metre. The meaning of 0 C(0 degree Celsius) is embedded in the description of what a degree

    Celsius is. 0 C is the temperature at which water freezes to ice. This is a standard measure which

    is acceptable all over the world. Such measure facilitates comparism with say 100 C which is the

    temperature at which water boils. This measure(100 C) is also regarded as standard and

    acceptable all around the world. Therefore any mention of temperature in degrees Celsius any

  • 7/31/2019 Is Acounting a Measurement Discipline

    12/21

    where in the world will inspire the understanding of the level of coldness or hotness of the

    location.. Where-as scientific measurements are amenable to comparism, this cannot be said of a

    valuation of assets in currency. For starters most currencies are heavily influenced by politics.

    There values are mostly fixed by fiat and may have nothing to do with actual worth. How then

    do we measure values of assets and liabilities based on these currencies.

    Lets take a case of a hypothetical regime which may fix the value of its currency against two

    others by fiat. It may as it wishes fix it lower against one and higher against the other. But it may

    be the case that the exchange rate against both currencies are the same or reverse of the fixedrates. Comparing values of assets in the fixed currency. against the values in the other two

    currencies might be problematic. We may not know the basis for comparism. Therefore without

    specifying the scales, measurements in accounting lack meaning and are not amenable to

    comparism. In the light of this, it is surprising that accounting information is considered

    comparable. One objective of establishing international standards in accounting reports is to

    facilitate comparism(IASB, 2009).This comparism can be done within one firm through time

    using time series. Comparism can also be done between different firms using a cross sectional

    analysis. This suggests that it is possible for users of accounting information to compare

    information from different entities in the absence of specified scales of measurement. The IASB

    (2009) points out that the measurement and display of the financial effect of like transactions and

    other events must be carried out in a consistent way throughout an entity and over time for that

    entity, and in a consistent way for different entities. This highlights the existence of a belief in

    accounting that measurement is possible in the absence of a specified scale of

    measurement.However, a scientific discipline cannot be based on mere belief. There has to be an

  • 7/31/2019 Is Acounting a Measurement Discipline

    13/21

    objective base for carrying out a scientific endeavour. It can thus be concluded that the concept

    of a scale of measurement is not recognized in the accounting discipline. The nature of

    accounting measurements demands that the scales of measurement should be specified before

    they are compared. This is because accounting measurements are dependent on the intuition of

    the accountant.

    The value attached to accounting measurement is even more so questionable in the light of

    different valuation methods that may yield different values for same asset or liability. This issue

    is corroborated by Mattessich (1964:79).He says accounting measurement is in the category of measurement by fiat where values are arbitrarily fixed subject to the whims and caprice of the

    market or of the regime that determines the value of the currency in which the item of interest is

    valued. He insists accounting measurement cannot be inferred through natural laws or a

    combination of fundamental measures which result in a derived measure. The conclusion to this

    lack of natural or fundamental laws guiding measurement in accounting is a certain definitional

    arbitrariness to accounting discipline. It means that the meaning of a measure in accounting is

    subject to several interpretations.

    This emphasizes that accounting measurements are dependent on the intuition of the accountant,

    as accounting is not a natural, but a social science. The use of the phrase definitional

    arbitrariness of our discipline implies that accounting definitions are not based on consistent

    rules or plans, but are instead dependent on the context in which they are used. It is clear that

    accounting measurements are socially constructed. Consequently, this suggests a need to specify

  • 7/31/2019 Is Acounting a Measurement Discipline

    14/21

    clearly the nature of the social context of accounting measurements before they are evaluated.

    There could be a difference between the kinds of assigning of numbers arising from different

    procedures of measurement. Therefore, if a scale of measurement was not specified in a

    measurement discipline, it would not possible to tell whether there were any other numbers that

    could be assigned as measures of the same property. Such knowledge of other numbers that

    might be assigned is important in determining the uniqueness of a measure. Luce et al.(1971)

    state that the number assigned to measure a property of an object is unique once a unit has been

    assigned to it. The concept of a scale is thus also important for the quality of uniqueness of

    measures. A lack of specified scales of measurement implies that the uniqueness of numbersassigned to represent the properties of accounting objects cannot be determined. The lack of

    specified scales of measurement has negative implications for the mathematical operations that

    could be carried out on accounting measurements. All known measurement scales from ordinal

    to ratio scales have permissible mathematical operations.

    It is usual to add up income and subtract expenses in order to arrive at net income in income

    statements. What is not known is whether such mathematical operations are permissible on these

    items which may have been valued using different methods. The scale used to measure incomes

    and expenses is unspecified. Such unspecification makes any mathematical operation

    arbitrary.Every scale of measurements or rather measurements taken in them have different

    mathematical characteristics(Chambers,1997). As a result, it is necessary to consider the

    conditions under which addition and other forms of relation is mathematically permissible. That

    is, the values of assets and liabilities are added in the balance sheet and in the income statement

    without first verifying whether these measurements have been made under the same scale of

  • 7/31/2019 Is Acounting a Measurement Discipline

    15/21

    measurement. The lack of specified scales causes inconsistencies in the classification of

    measures in accounting.

    AAA(1971) provides some examples of accounting measures. They include primary measures

    which are counts of physical quantities and prices of non-monetary goods. These prices maybe

    historical, current or expected prices. It however does not tell us if these apply to physical counts

    also. In any case if these are applicable to physical counts, how do we physically count a

    measure in the past or the future unless we can travel through time. If we assume they are not

    applicable then it means they do not belong in same class of measurement. Hence we cannot add

    or subtract physical measures to/from non-monetary measures. It appears that accountingmeasures that differ are grouped in the same class, and that physical counts and prices are

    regarded as measures of the same property. It is also clear that there is no specified property

    represented by physical counts or by prices. Furthermore, there is no specification of the scale of

    measurement that could be used to distinguish the extent to which physical counts and prices

    possess a particular property. Consequently, it is not clear whether physical counts and prices are

    measures of the same property. This leads to incorrect classification of measures. In this way, the

    lack of specified scales in accounting casts doubt on the current belief in the literature that

    accounting is a measurement discipline.

    Recall that Luce et al(1971) insists that the empirical property being measured must not change

    with the measurement method. It does not matter whether we measure distance in metres or

    kilometres.The distance being measured remains the same. All we need do is to convert distance

    measured in metres to kilometres using a constant factor. This constant factor will not change

    whether it is summer or winter and whether it is boom or depression.Here in lies the dilemma of

  • 7/31/2019 Is Acounting a Measurement Discipline

    16/21

    accounting valuation methods. Converting from historical costs to current or market prices may

    not necessarily be hinged on a constant factor. Infact the factor may depend on time and

    place.Thus the conversion factor at a particular time may be different from a previous or future

    period. Also the conversion factor at a particular locale may be different from another locale both

    intra and international.

    For illustrations, the value paid for rainboots bought during dry season will be less than it will

    cost during the rainy season. Again this value will keep changing depending on stage of the

    season at hand. Assuming an Accountant seeks to measure the value of such an asset, he will

    have no constant factor to guide his conversion of historical cost of purchase to any of eithercurrent or future prices. What he does is to wait for an event to happen before he gets the factors

    to use for his conversions. If we take the fact that value is attached to quality of assets,then

    valuation of assets is an indication of quality.Hence,measuring the value of an asset is akin to

    measuring the quality of an asset.In measurement, the empirical property being measured does

    not alter with the method of measurement.Since we are measuring quality by valuing assets in

    accounting and these measures sometime depend on time and location,then the property being

    measured may be said to vary with the method of measurement.

  • 7/31/2019 Is Acounting a Measurement Discipline

    17/21

    CHAPTER FOUR

    RECOMMENDATION AND CONCLUSION

    The concept of measurement is often misunderstood as merely the assignment of a value, but it is

    possible to assign a value in a way that is not a measurement in terms of the requirements of

    additive conjoint measurement. One may assign a value to a person's height, but unless it can be

    established that there is a correlation between measurements of height and empirical relations, it

    is not a measurement according to additive conjoint measurement theory. Likewise, computing

    and assigning arbitrary values, like the "book value" of an asset in accounting, is not a

    measurement because it does not satisfy the necessary criteria. The criteria for measurement is

    the presence of a scale which serves as a rule for measurement. The absence of a scale in

    accounting makes it difficult to qualify as a measurement discipline.

    In this work we have reviewed previous studies that sought to situate accounting measurement.

    The result of such studies have been negative or problematic. Problematic because the theory

    underlying accounting measurement is unknown. The theory is unknown because the scale of measurement is unspecified. This study is also reaching the same conclusion that accounting

    measurement is at best still at infancy and in the process of developing a measurement theory or

    in the worst case scenario not fit for a measurement discipline.

    4.2 Recommendations

    However, choosing the best case scenario, this paper recommends that further studies be

    undertaken to unravel the theory and specify scales of accounting measurement. Such discovery

    will elevate the status of our discipline to that noble height of scientific disciplines and shut the

    mouth of our detractors once and for all.

  • 7/31/2019 Is Acounting a Measurement Discipline

    18/21

    BIBLIOGRAPGHY

    ABDEL-MAGID, M.F.(1979). Toward a better understanding of the role of measurement in

    accounting. The Accounting Review , April:346-357.

    AMERICAN ACCOUNTING ASSOCIATION, 1971. Report of the committee on foundations

    of accounting measurement. The Accounting Review Supplement,

    BHATTACHARYA, P.B., JAIN, S.K. & NAGPAUL, S.R. 1986. Basic abstract algebra,

    Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.

    BOYCE, B.R., MEADOW, C.T. & KRAFT, D.H. 1994. Measurement in information science.

    Academic press limited.

  • 7/31/2019 Is Acounting a Measurement Discipline

    19/21

    CHAMBERS, R.J. 1997. Wanted: Foundations of accounting measurement, Abacus, (341):36-

    47.

    DECOENE, S., ONGHENA, P. & JANSSEN, R. 1995. Representationalism under attack.

    Journal of

    Mathematical Psychology , 39:234-242.

    436 SAJEMS NS 13 (2010) No 4

    HAWKER, S. 2003. The little Oxford dictionary, thesaurus and word power guide , Oxford

    University Press.

    IJIRI, Y. 1975. Theory of accounting measurement. American Accounting Association.INTERNATIONAL ACCOUNTING STANDARDS BOARD (IASB), 2009,

    INTERNATIONAL

    FINANCIAL REPORTING STANDARDS (IFRS), 2009: Including international accounting

    standards (IAS)

    and interpretations as at 1 January 2009.

    LUCE, R.D.; KRANTZ, D.H.; SUPPES, P. & TVERSK, A. 1971. Foundations of measurement,

    (Vol. 1)

    additive and polynomial representations , New York: Academic Press.

    LUCE, R.D., KRANTZ, D.H., SUPPES, P. & TVERSK, A. 1989. Foundations of measurement,

    (Vol. 2),

    Geometrical, threshold, and probabilistic representations, New York: Academic Press.

    LUCE, R.D., KRANTZ, D.H., SUPPES, P. & TVERSK, A. 1990. Foundations of measurement,

    (Vol. 3)

    Representations, axiomatization, and invariance , New York: Academic Press.

  • 7/31/2019 Is Acounting a Measurement Discipline

    20/21

    LUCE, R.D. & SUPPES, P. 2001 . Representational measurement theory. Available http://

    media.wiley.com /

    product_ data /except /87/ 04713788 0471378887.pdf.

    MATTESSICH, R. 1964. Accounting and analytical methods , Homewood 3, Irwin

    MCLEAN, R. 2006. New concepts in measuring value in Einstein (ed.) In the boardroom, John

    Wiley &

    Sons, Inc.

    NARENS, L. 1981a. A general theory of ratio scalability with remarks about the measurement

    theoreticconcept of meaningfulness. Theory and Decisions , 13:1-70.

    NARENS, L. 1981b. On the scales of measurement. Journal of Mathematical Psychology ,

    24:249-275.

    NARENS, L. 2002. A meaningful justification for the representational theory of measurement.

    Journal of

    Mathematical Psychology , 46:746-768.

    RYAN, B., SCAPENS, R.W. & THEOBALD, M. 2002. Research method and methodology in

    finance and

    accounting (2nd ed.) Mitcham, Surrey: International, Padstow, Cornwall.

    RUSSELL, B. 1920. Introduction to mathematical philosophy (2nd ed.) New York: Macmillan.

    STAUBUS, G.J. 1985. An induced theory of accounting measurement, The Accounting Review ,

    January,

    60(1):53-75.

    STAUBUS, G.J. 2004. Two views of accounting measurement. Abacus, 40(3):265-279.

  • 7/31/2019 Is Acounting a Measurement Discipline

    21/21

    STAMP, E. 1981. Why can accounting not become a science like physics? Abacus, June:13-27.

    STEVENS, S.S. 1946. On the theory of scales of measurement. Science , 103:667-680.

    STEVENS, S.S. 1951. Mathematics, measurement and psychophysics in Handbook of

    experimental

    psychology , New York: Wiley.

    SCOTT, D. & SUPPES, P. 1958. Foundational aspects of theories of measurement. Journal of

    Symbolic

    Logic, 23:113-128.

    TINKER, T. 1985. Paper prophets, A social critique of accounting . New York: Praeger.VICKREY, D. W. 1970. Is accounting a measurement discipline?, Accounting Review ,

    45(4):731-742.

    WILLET, R.J. 1987. An axiomatic theory of accounting measurement. Accounting and Business

    Research :

    155-171.

    WOLK, H.I., TEARNEY, M.G. & DODD, J.L. 2001. Accounting theory: A conceptual and

    institutional

    approach. South Western College Publishing.


Recommended