+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Is Carl F. H. Henry a Modernist Theologian?

Is Carl F. H. Henry a Modernist Theologian?

Date post: 23-Nov-2015
Category:
Upload: michael-metts
View: 52 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend
Description:
Examines God, Revelation and Authority, pointing out Henry's strong critiques of modernist and anthropocentric thought. Assesses the criticisms of both postliberal and postconservative critics. Re-examines Henry's theological method for evidence of modernist thought.
Popular Tags:
20
CARL HENRY’S GOD, REVELATION AND AUTHORITY: MODERNIST, FOUNDATIONALIST METHODOLOGY? __________________ A Paper Presented to Dr. Joseph Wooddell Criswell College __________________ In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for PHI 502 __________________ by Michael Metts May 18, 2014
Transcript
  • CARL HENRYS GOD, REVELATION AND AUTHORITY:

    MODERNIST, FOUNDATIONALIST

    METHODOLOGY?

    __________________

    A Paper

    Presented to

    Dr. Joseph Wooddell

    Criswell College

    __________________

    In Partial Fulfillment

    of the Requirements for PHI 502

    __________________

    by

    Michael Metts

    May 18, 2014

  • ii

    TABLE OF CONTENTS

    Page

    INTRODUCTION .......................................................................................................1

    Modernity and Foundationalism ..................................................................................1

    Ren Descartes ....................................................................................................2

    John Locke ..........................................................................................................3

    Foundationalism ..................................................................................................5

    Carl Henry's Theological Method ...............................................................................6

    Charges of Foundationalism ........................................................................................9

    Postconservative Criticism ..................................................................................9

    Postliberal Criticism ..........................................................................................12

    Answering the Criticism ............................................................................................13

    CONCLUSION .........................................................................................................16

    BIBLIOGRAPHY .....................................................................................................18

  • 1

    CARL HENRYS GOD, REVELATION AND AUTHORITY:

    MODERNIST, FOUNDATIONALIST

    METHODOLOGY?

    Whether a result of the rapid spread of postmodernism following the linguistic turn in

    philosophy, or the growing influence of narrative theologians of the Yale school, evangelical

    theologians are becoming increasingly favorable towards postmodern approaches to

    understanding Christian doctrine. In this age of postmodern influence, the propositionalism

    evidenced in former evangelical theologies has been criticized as modernist, foundationalist

    philosophy by recent critics. Chiefly among those criticized is neo-evangelical Carl F. H. Henry

    (1913-2003). This paper will examine Henrys theological method for evidences of modernist,

    foundationalist philosophical influence, limited in scope to selections from the first and third

    volume of his magnum opus, God, Revelation and Authority, and evaluate both postconservative

    and postliberal criticisms of his work. The conclusion is that while Henry does display a weak

    foundationalist influence, it is of an entirely different sort than the anthropocentric rationalism of

    Enlightenment thinkers.

    Modernity and Foundationalism

    Beginning with the work of geometrician1 and founder of modern philosophy Ren

    1On the importance of geometry for Descartes and his philosophy see Colin Brown, From the Ancient

    World to the Age of Enlightenment, in Christianity and Western Thought: A History of Philosophers, Ideas and

    Movements, vol 1, (Downers Grove, IL: IVP Academic, 1990; reprint 2010) 178-84. Descartess ideal and method

    was modelled on mathematics (179). Brown quotes Descartes himself in his modernist and inestimably influential

    work Discourse on Method: Those long chains composed of very simple and easy reasonings, which geometers

    customarily use to arrive at their most difficult demonstrations, had given me occasion to suppose that all things

  • 2

    Descartes (1596-1650), but also inclusive of the rationalist empiricist philosopher John Locke

    (1632-1704), is a period in which an anthropocentric innate reason came to be seen as the chief

    judge of truth; the pursuit of a truth by which all knowledge is to be grounded or founded in

    certainty is called foundationalism.

    Ren Descartes

    Descartes, troubled by the conflicting claims which erupted in the Reformation,

    discerned the need for a deeper foundation, a means of establishing certainty and authority that

    could act as the proper and exclusive fulcrum of judgment concerning biblical interpretation and

    varying traditions.2 It should be observed here that Descartes does not operate as an empiricist,

    as does Locke, but solely as an innatist-rationalist. Since Descartes was a studied geometrician,

    his philosophy was deeply influenced by the fine exactitude of geometrys developmentally

    established theorems and proven axioms. Just as the axioms of geometry were built one upon

    another, so would be Descartes method of establishing truth. All that remained was establishing

    a point of origin for all subsequent truths, which Descartes found not in God, much to the

    detriment of theology, but in his own anthropocentric reason cogito, ergo sum (I think,

    therefore I am). That Descartes could doubt demonstrated that he existed indubitably.3 This was

    which can fall under human knowledge are interconnected in the same way (179-80).

    2W. P. Abraham, epistemology, religious, in The Blackwell Encyclopedia of Modern Christian

    Thought, ed. Alister E. McGrath, et al. (Oxford: Blackwell, 1993) 156. Calvinist theologian and philosopher Gordon

    Haddon Clark writes the following concerning Cartesian philosophy: if only a single point be found solid, then like

    Archimedes we can move the universe. The meaning is that the beginning foundationalist point acts as authoritative

    and certain for subsequent axioms within the system, all of which can be demonstrated as truthful. Clark, The Works

    of Gordon Haddon Clark, Christian Philosophy, vol. 4 (Unicoi, TN: The Trinity Foundation, 2004), 141.

    3If we are deceived, we must be thinking; and if we think, we exist it is impossible to deny I am

    thinking without thinking. Since doubting is a form of thought, I cannot doubt that I think without thinking the

    doubt. I think, therefore, is an indubitable truth. Clark, The Works of Gordon Haddon Clark, 142.

  • 3

    the first principle of his philosophy as he explains in his Discourse on Method:

    But immediately I noticed that while I am trying thus to think everything false, it was

    necessary that I, who was thinking this, was something. And observing that this truth I am

    thinking, therefore I exist was so firm and sure that all the most suppositions of the

    sceptics were incapable of shaking it, I decided that I could accept it without scruple as the

    first principle of the philosophy I was seeking.4

    The existence of God as a perfect being was Descartes second principle and the

    effects of this subordination would become forcibly prescriptive for the discipline of theological

    science until the present day.5 It was as a rationalist, therefore, that Descartes main argument

    for the existence of God was a restatement of Anselms ontological argument.6 In the Age of

    Reason, God came to be grounded in proofs established by the mind of man.

    John Locke

    Locke continued heavily in the rationalist tradition of Descartes. As a rationalist-

    empiricist Locke also grounded the existence of God in the power of the human intellect to the

    end that the truths of theism were seen according to reason, rather than revelation.7 To be fair,

    Locke does allow room for divine revelation though to what degree is debated but reason

    4Brown, From the Ancient World to the Age of Enlightenment, 180; quoting Descartes, Discourse on

    Method, Part 4.

    5Brown, From the Ancient World to the Age of Enlightenment, 181. Cf. also Abraham, epistemology,

    religious, 156, reason becomes the foundation upon which the whole of Christian theology has to be erected

    methodically.

    6Brown, From the Ancient World to the Age of Enlightenment, 182. Concerning Anselm, however,

    Descartes failed to recognize that the intellectual feats of the Proslogion operated within the context of faith

    seeking understanding. Cf. Carl F. H. Henry, God, Revelation and Authority, 6 vols. (Waco, TX: Word Books,

    1976-83; reprint Wheaton, IL: Crossway Books, 1999) 1:300: the Anselmic tendency commended the ontological

    argument to later modern philosophers aligned in revolt against special revelation.

    7Abraham, epistemology, religious, 157. In John Locke we see how a deeply pious Christian and

    philosopher works out a rational case for Christianity. The cosmological and teleological arguments prove the

    existence of God; so the truth of theism is according to reason (157).

  • 4

    must be judge and guide in everything.8 The order of operations, to put it in one sense, is

    understanding seeking faith rather than the reverse which is the hallmark of any evangelical

    theological tradition certainly the hallmark of a neo-evangelical heritage.

    Like Descartes, Locke was also troubled by the many religious opinions of his day.

    This existence of so many different and conflicting opinions was partly cause for his important

    work An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Noted philosopher Alvin Plantinga explains

    Lockes influential work as follows:

    The Essay was Lockes attempt to do what he could to put matters right. Book IV, Of

    Knowledge and Probability, is the end of the book both in comprising the last three

    hundred pages or so and in dealing with the question whose resolution is Lockes goal; and

    even in book IV he spends another two hundred pages before explicitly addressing it. That

    main question is: how should we regulate our opinions with respect to belief in general? In

    particular, how should we regulate our opinion with respect to religious belief?9

    Locke was further knowledgeable of Newtonian science which understood the

    universe in a closed, mechanistic causal manner; and mindful of the implications of Newtonian

    science concerning the possibility of miracles.10

    Miracles such as resurrection were understood

    by Locke to be above reason, meaning that the trustworthiness of their propositions could not

    8Abraham, epistemology, religious, 157. Cf. also Brown, From the Ancient World to the Age of

    Enlightenment, 222: Locke rejected the rationalist idea that the mind had stamped on it from birth certain primary,

    self-evident notions. He likewise repudiated the idea, found in Cicero by Calvin and his followers, that human

    beings have a sense of the deity inscribed on their hearts. Brown quotes Locke, An Essay Concerning Human

    Understanding, 4.18.2: Reason is the discovery of the certainty or probability of such propositions or truths, which

    the mind arrives at by deduction made from such ideas, which it has got by the use of its natural faculties, viz. by

    sensation or reflection.

    9Alvin Plantinga, Warranted Christian Belief (New York: Oxford University Press, 2000) 74.

    (Emphasis original.)

    10Newtons laws of motion helped to establish the mechanical view of the universe which dominated

    physics down to modern times. Newtons Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica (1687) gave an account

    not only of the motion of bodies on the earth but throughout the universe. Newtons views raised big questions for

    theology. Where did God fit into this mechanistic world? Brown, From the Ancient World to the Age of

    Enlightenment, 218.

  • 5

    be established by reason.11

    Foundationalism

    It is clear from the two aforementioned modernists that mans own innate reason is

    both generative and formative for propositional beliefs, and that this rationalism should operate

    under such conditions that any knowledge or belief claim made by a person must be

    authoritatively founded so as to be indubitable to his or her modern mind. Due to the nature of

    foundationalism, axioms of knowledge which form a part of any intellectual structure are only

    upheld when the source of such knowledge is indubitably grounded. Descartes used the

    metaphor of building knowledge on an absolute foundation, hoping to free us from tradition-

    based knowledge.12

    And according to Locke, a belief is acceptable only if it is either itself

    certain with respect to propositions that are certain for me.13

    The principle at work in the rationalist philosophy of both Descartes and Locke is

    simply a critical concern to establish a proposition on the basis of another which is

    unquestionably sound beyond criticism. However, evidenced within the foundationalism of

    Descartes and Locke is a rationalist effort for founding knowledge within an anthropocentric

    standard of universal reason; meaning that truthful propositions cannot be located externally

    from mans own independent creaturely ability to rationalize.14

    Rationalism is operative in

    11Brown, From the Ancient World to the Age of Enlightenment, 224. See also Clark, The Works of

    Gordon Haddon Clark, 142, who writes: Lockes view of revelation may be a little too complicated, or possibly too

    disguised, to describe accurately. Although he seems to have admitted the fact of revelation, some interpreters judge

    it to be grudging admission.

    12David K. Clark, To Know and Love God: Method for Theology, Foundations of Evangelical Theology

    Series (Wheaton, IL: Crossway Books, 2003) 153.

    13Plantinga, Warranted Christian Belief, 81.

    14Cf. Alvin Plantinga, The Reformed Objection to Natural Theology, in Christian Scholars Review

  • 6

    relation to the thinking subject and must be governed by the modern mind, and this, as noted

    above, includes the truths of theistic beliefs. Revelation springs forth from mans reason

    Carl Henrys Theological Method

    No matter what starting point a reader may choose, it rapidly becomes apparent when

    reading God, Revelation and Authority that Henry identifies any means of discerning truth which

    does not posit at first divine revelation as fundamentally flawed. Before examining the structures

    of his theological method, a few points concerning Henrys work will help reveal his reasons for

    criticizing modernity and the compromises of its rationalistic and anthropocentric

    foundationalism.

    According to Henry, Descartes mistakenly proclaims mans own ego, or individual

    intelligence, as the first certainty.15

    The fundamental distinction between Henrys methodology

    and any modernist one is identified by this claim more than anywhere else it is found here.

    Henrys concern is not expressive of a disinterest in philosophy or philosophers, on the contrary

    he understands both philosophy and theology to operate within the same plane of objective

    reference;16

    his concern is rather indicative of a proper Christian appreciation for an externalist

    divine revelation standing sharply opposed to any anthropocentric innatism such as that found in

    the foundationalism of Descartes.17

    Whereas modernity posited mans own rational and

    epistemic faculties as the grounds of authority and certainty, Henry grounds certainty in divine

    11 no. 3 (1982): 187-198.

    15Henry, God, Revelation and Authority, 1:302.

    16Henry, God, Revelation and Authority, 1:200.

    17Henry, God, Revelation and Authority, 1:76, 301-8.

  • 7

    revelation.18

    The truths of God and therefore of his creation are divinely granted to the divinely

    enabled knower. But this is not to deny that an atheist or agnostic might have true knowledge of

    the natural, created world. A lengthier account of Enlightenment rationalism seen opposed to

    revelation is given by Henry in volume three and may help to clarify the difference:

    There was never a denial that the mind of man has the power, on which recent modern

    knowledge-theory concentrates, of conceptually ordering phenomenal realities or sense

    impressions in a creative way. But the human mind was not considered to be constructive of

    the order of external reality. As the source of created existence, the Logos of God grounded

    the meaning and purpose of man and the world, and objective reality was held to be

    divinely structured by complex formal patterns. Endowed with more than animal

    perception, gifted in fact with a mode of cognition not to be confused with sensation, man

    was therefore able to intuit intelligible universals; as a divinely intended knower, he was

    able to cognize, within limits, the nature and structure of the externally real world.19

    So, against a modernist internalist grounding of truth, Henry propounds that God has

    revealed himself. There are in fact ontic referents to the knowing individual since he is within

    Gods created world; is himself a creature of this creation; and is in fact created in the image of

    God. Henry writes, Reason is a divinely gifted instrument enabling man to recognize revelation

    or truth. He can do this because by creation he bears the image of God (Gen. 1:26), and is

    specially lighted by the divine Logos (John 1:9)20

    This understanding of Henry's subsumes

    the entire Enlightenment project within an anthropocentric logos (or reason), showing man to be

    lost in his own efforts at rationalizing the natural world apart from divinely granted revelation.

    Rightly understood, divine revelation for Christians is a philosophical a priori, and not a

    subjective conclusion of human reasoning.21

    18Henry, God, Revelation and Authority, 1:213-224.

    19Henry, God, Revelation and Authority, 3:167.

    20Henry, God, Revelation and Authority, 1:228.

    21Henry, God, Revelation and Authority, 1:201: The Christian revelation is not to be confronted by

  • 8

    The first three criteria of Henrys theological method are of primary importance for

    understanding Henry: (1) God in his revelation is the first principle of Christian theology, from

    which all the truths of revealed religion are derived; (2) Human reason is a divinely fashioned

    instrument for recognizing truth; it is not a creative source of truth; and (3) The Bible is the

    Christians principle of verification.22

    These criteria do function, in a sense, foundationally for

    Henry and his subsequent theses concerning theology, but there are critical distinctions between

    the sort of modernist epistemologies observed beforehand and the grounding of knowledge that

    Henry conceptualizes.

    Henry sees himself standing within an evangelical theological tradition beginning with

    Augustine followed by Anselm, Luther and Calvin.23

    Each of these theologians enshrine a faith

    seeking understanding approach, in one fashion or another, where the epistemic knower is

    divinely gifted with reasoning faculties which by design include knowledge of the objective

    created world, of God himself, and of others. Gods revelation is what is foundational if the

    critic insists that Henry evidences such an epistemology and man by created design is able to

    rationalize, not of his own innate potential, but as consequence of his operative creaturely

    faculties gifted to him by the Creator. Authority is established, therefore, clearly by God and

    revelation. Hopefully, then, the reader of Henry is able to understand the meaning of his projects

    title: God, Revelation and Authority. More desirable would be for the reader to see Henry as

    already prescribed philosophical conceptions to which its content must be conformed.

    22Henry, God, Revelation and Authority, 1:215, 1:225, and 1:229.

    23Henry, God, Revelation and Authority, 1:76-7, 183-4, 303-4, 288-300, 322, 323-43.

  • 9

    establishing as part of evangelical Christian identity a theology clearly owing no debts to the

    works targeted modernist opponents who champion a very obvious different rationality.

    Charges of Foundationalism

    There have been numerous objections to Henrys work categorizing him as a

    rationalist, foundationalist, or propositionalist, each understood in the modernist sense or as

    influenced by it; and this is so despite the incredible aforementioned labors of Henry to present

    his work in the traditions of Augustine and the Reformers, and, more particularly, as a corrective

    to the modernist innatism of Cartesian indebted speculative philosophies. Several critics are

    presented here, all of which evidence a clear absence of a careful understanding of Henry in this

    regard; the reader finds, rather, a readiness by critics to categorize Henry within an outdated fold

    of theologians whose work is considered foundationalist philosophy, chiefly headed by the Old

    Princetonian Charles Hodge. Critics of Henry, then, can be divided into one of two camps: (1)

    The postconservative camp, including Henry H. Knight III, Stanley J. Grenz and John R. Franke,

    and Roger E. Olson. And (2) the postliberal camp, including George A. Lindbeck and Hans W.

    Frei.

    Postconservative Criticism

    Henry H. Knight III, a postconservative evangelical theologian, writes the following

    of conservatives: The propositionalist approach, while seeking to be faithful to scripture, has

    been led by its apologetic concern to embrace many of the presuppositions of the

    Enlightenment.24

    Knight continues his criticism by primarily targeting Henry as the crown

    24Henry H. Knight III, A Future for Truth: Evangelical Theology in a Postmodern World (Nashville:

    Abingdon Press, 1997) 90.

  • 10

    thinker of such approaches and explicitly associates his theological method with Cartesianism.

    He states:

    Such rationalism enshrines the Cartesian mind/body dualism within theology, and defines

    revelation as the mind of God communicating information to the human mind. The essence

    of the imago Dei and presumably of God is rationality, understood as a cognitive and

    logical capacity.25

    While the connection with Descartes is qualified more fairly than certain other critics, an

    obviously absent distinction between the innatism of Cartesian philosophy and the externalist

    and divinely gifted rationality in the understanding of Henry is confronting. The reader may also

    be excused for wondering how critics like Knight make the connection between Henry and

    Descartes to begin with, when the former has written extensively critical of the latter and is

    solely concerned to correct his philosophical speculative influence. It seems that it is Henrys

    propositional understanding of Scripture that incriminates him as a Cartesian:

    If revelation is both rational and true, then Henry believes that it must also be in the

    form of propositions. A proposition is a verbal statement that is either true or false; it is a

    rational declaration capable of being either believed, doubted, or denied. () It is no

    surprise, then, that Henry finds the Bible to be essentially composed of propositions 26

    propositionalists often see themselves as the defenders of historic Christianity against the

    corrosive forces of modernity. Certainly that is their intent. They are apt to see those who

    question strict inerrancy as capitulating to modern relativism and abandoning objective

    truth27

    In their mutual criticism against foundationalism, postfoundationalists Stanley J.

    Grenz and John R. Franke also identify Descartes foundationalism with late nineteenth and

    25Knight, A Future for Truth, 91.

    26Knight, A Future for Truth, 88; citing Henry, God, Revelation and Authority, 3:456.

    27Knight, A Future for Truth, 90.

  • 11

    twentieth-century evangelical propositionalist theologies, connecting Henry with them.28

    The

    claim is made that such theology is buoyed by the assumptions of modernity.29

    Also likening

    Henrys method to that of Hodge, Grenz and Franke criticize:

    conservative theologians also searched for a foundation for theology that could stand

    firm when subjected to the canons of a supposedly universal human reason. Conservatives

    came to conclude that this invulnerable foundation lay in an error-free Bible, which they

    viewed as the storehouse for divine revelation. Hence, the great Princeton theologian,

    Charles Hodge, asserted that the Bible is free from all error, whether of doctrine, fact, or

    precept. This inerrant foundation, in turn, could endow with epistemological certitude, at

    least in theory, the edifice the skilled theological craftsman constructed on it.30

    A lengthy case is presented demonstrating conservative evangelical theology, wrongly thinking

    itself as an heir of Reformation epistemology, is actually none other than a modernist

    foundationalism indebted to the rationalist philosophy of Descartes.31

    This is said to be the case

    because an inerrant Scripture forms the foundation for Henrys theological truth claims, rather

    than God and creaturely epistemic realities of reason. However, the error free Bible that Grenz

    and Olson want to posit within Henrys foundationalism is rather the result of it, and developed

    within the context of a greater, more foundational theological method. But in defense of their

    own postfoundationalist theology, they write:

    Above all, however, postmodern, chastened rationality entails the rejection of

    epistemological foundationalism. In the modern era, the pursuit of knowledge was deeply

    influenced by the thought forms of the Enlightenment, with foundationalism lying at its

    heart. The goal of the foundationalist agenda is the discovery of an approach to knowledge

    that will provide rational human being with absolute, incontestable certainty regarding the

    truthfulness of their beliefs. According to foundationalists, the acquisition of knowledge

    28Stanley J. Grenz and John R. Franke, Beyond Foundationalism: Shaping Theology in a Postmodern

    Context (Louisville, KY: Westminster John Knox Press, 2001) 3-54.

    29Grenz and Franke, Beyond Foundationalism, 13.

    30Grenz and Franke, Beyond Foundationalism, 34.

    31Grenz and Franke, Beyond Foundationalism, 29-35.

  • 12

    ought to proceed in a manner somewhat similar to the construction of a building.

    Knowledge must be built on a sure foundation.32

    Roger E. Olson is one more critic of foundationalism who shows sentiment for the

    work of Grenz and Franke and their postfoundationalist criticism of Henry.33

    As for his own

    criticism, Olson somewhat equivocally writes,

    Although Henry was not a classical rationalist in the Cartesian sense he did tend to

    elevate reason to a special governing role in Christian theology and he regarded revelation

    as primarily an intellectual phenomenon. According to Henry, Divine revelation is a

    mental activity. For him, Gods self-revelation is an intelligible disclosure that possesses

    propositional expressibility, which makes it amenable to rational systematization. He

    eschewed any probabilistic approach to theology and sought for certainty for theologys

    conclusions (doctrines) based on logical deduction from foundational axioms.34

    Again, indebtedness to Descartes is posited of Henry indirectly through identifying

    both thinkers with rationalist foundationalism, while also neglecting an explicit demonstration of

    how such a connection is made other than to generalize about Henrys rationalist theological

    method.

    Postliberal Criticism

    Probably more influential of the theological methodological mood in evangelical

    theology than any sincere desire to move beyond an understood and operative modernist

    rationalism is the book highly regarded within evangelical circles: The Nature of Doctrine.35

    George A. Lindbecks own method, as more conservative critics have properly assailed, is in

    32Grenz and Franke, Beyond Foundationalism, 23.

    33Roger E. Olson, Reformed and Always Reforming: The Postconservative Approach to Evangelical

    Theology (Grand Rapids: Baker Academic, 2007) 130-1.

    34Olson, Reformed and Always Reforming, 130.

    35George A. Lindbeck, The Nature of Doctrine: Religion and Theology in a Postliberal Age, 25th

    Anniversary ed. (Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 2009).

  • 13

    essence a sociological impression of religious community rules without much remaining for

    attribution to divine revelation. Doctrines have propositional value only within believing

    communities, or propositional values only in a strict functionalist sense.36

    But attempting to

    understand how objective truth might function within such a model clearly initiates confusion

    when it is recognized that different communities believe different things.

    Lindbecks work has had a far reaching impact in the discussion of both ecumenism

    and theological method, even within evangelicalism as some pockets become increasingly

    favorable of sociological and communal models of theological doctrine, e.g., Grenz and Franke,

    against a divinely revealed, rationally intelligible model such as found in the work of Henry.

    Why this is so continues to impress anyone who observes theology to include in any meaningful

    way divine revelation. For, what is revealed becomes essential to doctrine as opposed to what a

    religious community might value. But this is getting too far ahead.

    With his colleague Lindbeck, Hans W. Frei also dismisses Henry, criticizing his

    method as foundationalism. Writing of Henry, Frei states: the basic affirmation [is] that

    theology must have a foundation that is articulated in terms of basic philosophical principles.37

    Answering the Criticism

    While critics are united in their association of Henry with foundationalist rationalism,

    and perhaps they are correct to a degree, their criticisms seem to regard only the form of Henrys

    method and not its specific content; content which might go a long way in providing clues as to

    why Henry dismisses his so-called modernist philosophical parentage. Of course in philosophy

    36Lindbeck, The Nature of Doctrine, 50-1.

    37Hans W. Frei, Types of Christian Theology, ed. by George Hunsinger and William C. Placher (New

    Haven: Yale University Press, 1992) 24.

  • 14

    one is always philosophizing, even when one thinks otherwise, and Henry is no exception. But

    is it right to dismiss so readily as simply modernistic foundationalism a project as extensive as

    God, Revelation and Authority simply because it bears some semblance in structure with

    foundationalist philosophy, without looking more closely at the internal workings which might

    explain such a similarity? Is such similarity only superficial?

    For some critics who are so poorly read of Henry, the assumption is that the

    foundation upon which he builds is the inerrancy of Scripture. Henry is camped with those who

    espouse an unassailable and bulletproof textbook for scientific and propositional compilation,

    devoid of any meaningful emotive aspects of religious authority. Again, it invites curiosity on the

    part of the student, however, to question how such conclusions are reached, for they are not

    reached certainly by reading God, Revelation and Authority. Gods general revelation of himself

    to the rational conscience of every man is what is foundational for Henry, i.e., the imago Dei, not

    the inerrant Scriptures. In the ordering of his volumes it is no mistake that the subject of

    inerrancy in Henrys work does not arise for definite treatment until volume four, which is

    certainly a delayed treatment for any theologian who might regard such doctrine as foundational

    for all his subsequent theological theorems. Such ordering would be tantamount to placing

    prolegomena after treating the dogmas of God and Scripture perhaps creation as well.

    Henrys theological, philosophical structuralization of revealed biblical theism, as he

    likes to refer to it, also follows no clear pattern of basing one proposition upon another in the

    manner of the geometrist mind of Descartes or subsequent internalist speculative philosophies. It

    may be granted, however, that to a certain degree such statements of Henry as follows do

    evidence a very broad foundationalist structure:

    Divine revelation is the source of all truth, the truth of Christianity included; reason is the

    instrument for recognizing it; Scripture is its verifying principle; logical consistency is a

  • 15

    negative test for truth and coherence a subordinate test. The task of Christian theology is

    to exhibit the content of biblical revelation as an orderly whole.38

    This is, according to Henry, his governing theological method in concentrated form.

    While such methodology may evidence a degree of foundationalism, it could only be a very

    weak form as opposed to the strong foundationalism resulting from the troubled conscience of

    Descartes. But to this the critical mind beckons us: Do we all not, as Alvin Plantinga has written,

    have a sort of noetic structure that believes some things on the basis of others? Is not

    foundationalism to a certain extent part of common sensibilities, understood in no

    philosophically distinguished way? Even in the carefully written work of Grenz and Franke one

    finds language betraying weak foundationalist philosophical influence, such as their view that

    the church functions, as in Lindbeck, as a basis in establishing doctrinal values. In fact, the

    term basis appears numerous times throughout the postfoundationalist work of Grenz and

    Franke, and frequently in the form of very telling interrogative sentences such as on what basis

    something critically can be held. The term is also found in critical subheadings and in

    conclusions to critical motifs. In their chapter on the community as an integrative motif, The

    Basis of Theology is observed as a subheading; and again in the chapter on eschatology, The

    Basis for an Eschatological Theology.39

    38Henry, God, Revelation and Authority, 1:215. (Emphasis original.)

    39Grenz and Franke, Beyond Foundationalism, 232, 252. Additional mention of basis is found in the

    following places: 90, Reading the Bible as one canon forms the basis of reading the texts of the Hebrews as

    Christian scripture, and it suggests what constitutes the interpretive center for reading both Testaments together.;

    160, But on what basis and in what sense can we speak of culture as the voice of the Spirit?; 253, We maintain,

    therefore, that an eschatological theology is closely connected to the biblical narrative. But on what basis can we

    make this claim?; 259, We have outlined as well the basis for the claim that the way toward an eschatological

    theology leads through the biblical narrative, the story of Gods action in history, which cradles the Christian

    community. There are at least twenty additional uses of the term in their work in the sense revealed here. Are we

    really beyond foundations if we still need to base components of an evangelical theology?

  • 16

    But all of this misses the point. Henry has labored to establish philosophical

    categories for theological truth, a Christian philosophy of ontology, epistemology, axioms, etc.,

    and not as a foundationalist but in accordance with long recognized truths, such as God as

    Creator, man as made in his image, man as an intelligible, thinking, and reflective creature, and

    revelation as cognitive, rational communication. The universal rationality of man and his clear

    ability to think reflectively, critically and intelligibly, was the will of the Creator who gifted man

    with such abilities. With critics nowhere showing appreciation for Henrys content and the

    notion that it may be driving perceived foundationalism, rather than the reverse, one question in

    particular becomes gravitational: Why have we dismissed his work? It presses the student to

    wonder if postconservative evangelical critics are simply yielding to the critical pressures of the

    university postmodern ethos by acquiescing to the hazardous path forward charted by

    postliberals. For it is within the anti-authoritative ethos of postmodernism that the critique of

    reason extends beyond the works of any source and applies directly to the point of origin for any

    source; meaning, perhaps, Henry has been discredited, not because of any contradiction

    discoverable within his work, but because the postmodernist critique circumnavigates the work

    in question and applies itself directly to the thinking mind operative behind it. This is clearly

    incompatible with Christianity which without question understands truth only with a capital t.

    Conclusion

    By dismissing it based on form without regard for its content, the work of Henry will

    continue to haunt conservative evangelicals who have capitulated with the postmodernist ethos

    and have no demonstrable or agreed means of progressing forward of their own making within

    such an ethos; and no means by which divine revelation can function authoritatively within the

    sphere of creation. As both a philosopher and a theologian Henry answers speculative modernist

  • 17

    philosophies while providing structure for an evangelical mind that is biblical, defensible, and

    incorporative of reason.

    While he may be identified as a weak foundationalist, the student of Henry wonders if

    his shallow dismissal by critics may somewhat mirror the early churchs dismissal of Aristotle,

    before Augustine saw fit to plunder the Egyptians and retake all truth as Gods, thus saving

    classicism in the process. Like Aristotles later renewal in medieval theology, the critics may

    find that their dismissal of Henry will only result in his return at a later time to become

    influentially formative again for future evangelical theologies.

  • 18

    BIBLIOGRAPHY

    Abraham, W. P. Epistemology, Religious. In The Blackwell Encyclopedia of Modern

    Christian Thought. Edited by Alister E. McGrath, et al. Oxford: Blackwell, 1993.

    Brown, Colin, From the Ancient World to the Age of Enlightenment. Volume one of

    Christianity and Western Thought: A History of Philosophers, Ideas and

    Movements. Downers Grove, IL: IVP Academic, 1990; reprint 2010.

    Clark, David K. To Know and Love God: Method for Theology. In Foundations of

    Evangelical Theology Series. Wheaton, IL: Crossway Books, 2003.

    Clark, Gordon Haddon. The Works of Gordon Haddon Clark. Volume one of Christian

    Philosophy. Unicoi, TN: The Trinity Foundation, 2004.

    Frei, Hans W. Types of Christian Theology. Edited by George Hunsinger and William C.

    Placher. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1992.

    Grenz, Stanley J., and John R. Franke. Beyond Foundationalism: Shaping Theology in a

    Postmodern Context. Louisville, KY: Westminster John Knox Press, 2001.

    Henry, Carl F. H. God, Revelation and Authority. 6 vols. Waco, TX: Word Books, 1976-

    83; reprint Wheaton, IL: Crossway Books, 1999.

    Knight III, Henry H. A Future for Truth: Evangelical Theology in a Postmodern World.

    Nashville: Abingdon Press, 1997.

    Lindbeck, George A. The Nature of Doctrine: Religion and Theology in a Postliberal

    Age. 25th Anniversary edition. Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 2009.

    Olson, Roger E. Reformed and Always Reforming: The Postconservative Approach to

    Evangelical Theology. Grand Rapids: Baker Academic, 2007.

    Plantinga, Alvin. The Reformed Objection to Natural Theology. In Christian Scholars

    Review 11 no. 3 (1982): 187-198.

    _________. Warranted Christian Belief. New York: Oxford University Press, 2000.


Recommended