+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Is Existence a Predicate in Anselm's Argument.pdf

Is Existence a Predicate in Anselm's Argument.pdf

Date post: 02-Jun-2018
Category:
Upload: edd1929
View: 229 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend

of 8

Transcript
  • 8/10/2019 Is Existence a Predicate in Anselm's Argument.pdf

    1/8

    Is Existence a Predicate in Anselm's Argument?Author(s): David M. LochheadSource: Religious Studies, Vol. 2, No. 1 (Oct., 1966), pp. 121-127Published by: Cambridge University PressStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/20004641.

    Accessed: 12/12/2014 13:53

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    Cambridge University Pressis collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access toReligious

    Studies.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 193.63.81.241 on Fri, 12 Dec 2014 13:53:25 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=cuphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/20004641?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/20004641?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=cup
  • 8/10/2019 Is Existence a Predicate in Anselm's Argument.pdf

    2/8

    Rel. Stud.

    2, pp.

    12

    I-I

    2

    7.

    DAVID M.

    LOCHHEAD

    St. Paul s

    United

    College,Waterloo,

    Ontario

    IS

    EXISTENCE A

    PREDICATE

    IN ANSELM S

    ARGUMENT?

    One

    of the

    most

    annoying

    things

    to

    many

    a

    student

    of

    St

    Anselm s

    Proslogion

    is the way inwhich many philosophers assume that they can make Anselm s

    argument

    disappear simply by

    uttering

    the

    incantation,

    Existence is not

    a

    predicate .

    Some recent studies of

    the

    argument

    have tried

    to

    rescue it

    from

    Kant s

    dictum

    by showing

    that this

    criticism

    does not

    apply

    to Anselm s

    so-called

    second

    ontological argument.

    This

    argument appears

    in

    chapter

    in

    of

    Proslogion

    and

    depends

    on

    a

    distinction

    between

    necessary

    existence

    and

    contingent existence .

    Both

    Malcolm

    and

    Hartshorne are

    content,

    however, to let the better known first

    argument

    (Proslogion,chapter ii)

    rest

    in

    the

    oblivion to which Kant

    assigned

    it.

    Recently, in a careful and penetrating examination of Anselm s text,

    M.

    J. Charlesworth2 shows

    that we cannot

    superficially

    assume thatKant has

    demolished

    even

    the

    first

    argument

    of Anselm.

    However,

    Charlesworth

    bases

    his defence on

    the

    assumption-shared

    by

    most critics

    of the argument

    -that

    for

    Anselm,

    existence

    is

    a

    predicate.

    It

    is this

    interpretation

    of Anselm

    that

    I

    want

    to

    call

    into

    question.

    In

    Charlesworth s

    interpretation

    of the

    argument, Anselm s

    second

    premise

    is a

    general

    rule

    comparing conceptual

    and

    real

    existence: that

    which

    exists

    in

    reality is greater

    than that

    which exists

    in

    themind

    alone.3My

    difficulty is

    that, in

    reading Anselm,

    I

    can

    find no

    evidence

    that

    he

    understood this rule

    as

    having general

    validity. Let

    us look at

    Charlesworth s

    own

    translation of

    Anselm s text:

    And

    surely

    that-than-which-a-greater-cannot-be-thought cannot exist in

    the mind

    alone.

    For if

    it

    exists solely

    in the mind

    even,

    it

    can

    be thought to exist

    in reality

    also,

    which

    is

    greater.

    (Proslogion,

    chapter

    ii).

    The

    question is, of what

    can it be said that real

    existence is greater

    than con

    ceptual existence? Of anything? The text doesn t say. All that the text

    claims is

    that

    it is

    greater

    for

    that-than-which-a-greater-cannot-be-thought

    to

    exist

    really

    than

    conceptually.

    Anselm

    does not

    commit himself to the

    1

    Norman

    Malcolm,

    Anselm s

    Ontological

    Arguments in

    Philosophical

    Review,

    vol.

    LXIX

    (1960),

    pp.

    4I-62. Charles

    Hartshorne,

    The Logic of

    Perfection

    Lasalle. Open

    Court,

    I961).

    2

    M. J.

    Charlesworth, St Anselm s

    Proslogion

    (Oxford,

    I965).

    3

    Ibid.

    p.

    58.

    This content downloaded from 193.63.81.241 on Fri, 12 Dec 2014 13:53:25 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Is Existence a Predicate in Anselm's Argument.pdf

    3/8

    I22

    DAVID.LOCHHEAD

    relative merits of

    real and

    imaginary pounds,

    dollars,

    thalers-or

    even

    islands. On the other hand,

    ifAnselm s

    second

    premise

    is not an application

    of

    a

    general

    rule comparing real

    and imaginary existence, what

    is it?What

    are the other possibilities?

    The

    first possibility is that

    Anselm understands

    the principle as being

    relevant only to the

    concept of God; that

    only in the case of God

    is it intelli

    gible

    to compare real and conceptual

    existence. I

    will offer evidence later

    in

    the paper to support

    the view

    that

    this

    interpretation

    is closest to Anselm s

    intention.

    The

    other

    possibility

    is

    that

    there is

    a

    general

    rule involved here, but not

    the

    one

    that Charlesworth

    supposes. According to

    this interpretation

    real

    existence differs from conceptual

    existence, but

    the difference is not that

    real

    existence

    is

    greater than conceptual

    existence

    in abstract. Rather,

    the

    difference

    is one of what

    I shall call intensity .

    Real existence intensifies

    conceptual existence.

    Thus

    it is

    greater

    for

    that-than-which-nothing-greater

    can-be-thought

    to exist

    in

    reality

    than

    to

    exist

    in the mind alone. The

    greatness has

    been intensified or-better

    yet-it has been

    made operative

    by the

    transition from conceptual

    to

    real

    existence.

    As we shall see, under

    this interpretation

    it is

    quite problematic

    whether of

    anything

    less

    than

    God

    it can be said that real existence is greater than conceptual

    existence.

    In

    order

    to

    clarify

    this

    interpretation,

    let us

    apply

    it to the issue

    in

    which

    its

    consequences

    are

    decisively

    different from those of

    the

    interpretation

    advanced

    by

    Charlesworth:

    the

    existence of the devil. Charlesworth notes,

    correctly,

    that

    if his

    interpretation

    is

    correct,

    it

    implies

    that thatwhich

    nothing

    less

    great

    can be

    thought

    cannot

    possibly

    exist in

    reality.

    If

    it

    existed

    in

    reality

    it

    would

    be

    greater

    than

    if

    it existed

    in the mind alone.

    A

    less

    great

    being

    could

    be

    imagined;

    a

    being

    who

    existed

    in

    the

    mind

    alone.2

    In a

    footnote

    to this

    passage,

    Charlesworth

    objects,

    with

    good reason,

    to

    identify

    ing this least great being with the devil of Christian orthodoxy. But

    we

    shall return

    to

    this

    point

    later.

    This

    argument

    is not

    original

    with

    Charlesworth,

    as

    indeed

    he

    points

    out

    in the same footnote.

    He cites

    C. K. Grant3

    and A. A. Cock4

    as

    others

    who

    have called

    attention

    to

    this

    consequence

    of the

    ontological argument.

    As

    a

    matter

    of

    fact,

    A.

    A. Cock

    did

    not

    advance

    an

    ontological disproof

    of

    the

    devil.

    On the

    contrary,

    Cock

    argues

    in favour of an

    ontological proof

    of

    the devil.

    Cock s

    article is

    of

    great significance

    for

    any

    student

    of

    Anselm s

    argument.

    He approaches his subject sympathetically and with a reverence that is

    rare

    1

    It is

    also relevant

    to the objection

    that

    existence cannot

    be

    a

    perfection

    in things like

    cancer

    or

    slums.

    Cf. ibid.p.

    64.

    2

    Ibid.

    pp. 69-70.

    3

    C.

    K.

    Grant,

    The Ontological

    Disproof

    of the

    Devil in Analysis,

    vol.

    I

    7

    (I956-I957),

    pp.

    71-72.

    Albert A. Cock,

    The

    Ontological

    Argument

    for

    the Existence

    of God

    in

    Proceedings

    f

    the

    Aristoteliani

    ociety,

    New Series,

    vol.

    XVIII

    (1917-19I8),

    pp.

    363-384.

    This content downloaded from 193.63.81.241 on Fri, 12 Dec 2014 13:53:25 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Is Existence a Predicate in Anselm's Argument.pdf

    4/8

    IS EXISTENCE A PREDICATE IN ANSELM S ARGUMENT?

    I23

    in

    philosophical

    studies. While his article

    is

    not

    always clear,

    it

    contains

    flashes

    of

    insight which put

    Anselm s

    argument

    in an

    entirely

    new

    light.

    Cock

    holds

    that,

    in Anselm s

    argument,

    real

    existence

    is

    not

    some sort

    of

    predicate

    that

    is

    added to

    a

    concept. Rather,

    it

    is

    the

    fool who denies the

    existence

    of

    God

    who must subtract existence.

    In

    so

    doing

    he involves

    himself

    in

    contradiction.

    Anselm s

    addition

    is

    apparent only, resulting

    from the previous subtraction of the fool. Cock holds,

    in

    agreement with

    my

    contention,

    that Anselm s second

    premise

    has

    no

    generalvalidity:

    The Fool has attempted to subtract reality

    in

    re,

    not

    from

    any

    reality

    in

    intellectu,

    but

    from id quo

    nihii

    maius cogitari potest.

    In

    attempting

    the

    impossible

    he

    has, ipso

    facto,

    demonstrated the reality.

    When Cock turns

    to the

    problem

    of the

    devil,

    what

    emerges

    is

    an

    ontological

    proof of the devil s

    real

    existence.

    Cock defines

    the

    devil

    as that than

    which

    a

    lesser

    (or

    worse)

    is

    inconceivable .

    The

    argument proceeds:

    Surely,

    that than

    which

    a worse

    is

    inconceivable

    cannot

    exist

    only

    in

    the under

    standing.

    For

    if, indeed,

    it

    exist

    only

    in

    the

    understanding,

    it

    can

    be

    thought

    to be

    also

    in

    reality, and this

    is worse than a

    thought

    evil

    being.2

    Thus, Cock argues,

    if

    the

    ontological argument

    is

    valid for

    God,

    it

    is

    valid for

    the devil.

    It is

    undeniable

    that

    Cock s argument

    is

    parallel

    to

    that

    of

    the

    Proslogion.

    Furthermore,

    there

    is

    nothing in

    the

    Proslogion

    that

    would suggest

    that

    Cock

    has

    not

    grasped

    its

    intention

    correctly.

    But if

    Cock

    is

    correct, Charlesworth s

    contention-that

    as a

    general rule,

    real

    existence is

    greater

    than

    conceptual

    existence-must

    be

    mistaken.

    Roughly

    speaking,

    Cock s

    interpretation

    of

    the

    argument implies that real

    existence must function in

    such

    a

    way

    that

    it

    makes goodness greater and evil worse . In other words, real existence

    must function to

    intensify

    or make

    operative

    what

    is

    contained in the

    conceptual existence of

    a

    thing-be

    it

    good

    or

    evil. Thus

    a real

    God

    is

    greater

    than

    a

    conceptual

    God and

    a

    real

    devil

    is

    worse

    than

    a

    conceptual

    devil.

    Cock does

    recognise

    that

    the

    interpretation

    that Charlesworth holds

    would

    involve the non-existence of the devil. But he rejects it out of

    hand: We

    could not

    say

    that not

    to

    be is

    worse than to

    be, and, therefore, no devil at all,

    for

    it

    is

    clear

    that

    to be

    a

    devil isworse than

    not

    to be one .3

    Clearly, Cock s justification of his position ismistaken. Having defined the

    devil

    as

    that thanwhich a

    worse

    is

    inconceivable ,

    all

    that can be proved from

    To be a devil is worse than not to be one is that devilishness is a

    quality

    1

    Albert A.

    Cock,

    The

    Ontological Argument

    for the

    Existence

    of

    God

    in

    Proceedings

    f

    the

    Aristotelian

    Society,New Series,

    vol.

    xviii

    (1917-19I8),

    p.

    365.

    2

    Ibid.

    p. 381.

    3

    Ibid.

    p.

    381.

    This content downloaded from 193.63.81.241 on Fri, 12 Dec 2014 13:53:25 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Is Existence a Predicate in Anselm's Argument.pdf

    5/8

    I24

    DAVID M. LOCHHEAD

    which the devil must have.

    The proposition To be a devil isworse than not

    to

    be

    one does not imply

    the crucial proposition It isworse for the devil to be

    than not to be unless the

    ontology which Cock is trying to justify is assumed.

    However, Cock s mistake

    does not mitigate the fact that his proof of the

    devil

    seems

    to

    have the

    same

    force

    as

    Anselm s

    proof

    of God.

    As

    I

    anticipated earlier,

    Cock s position (or, rather, the ontology that I

    have inferred from it) implies

    that of nothing else but God can it be said

    unambiguously that real

    existence is greater than conceptual existence. Only

    of God

    can all

    perfections

    be predicated. The real existence

    of an imperfection

    isworse than its conceptual existence. Of no imperfect

    being, i.e. of no being

    who

    is

    less than

    God,

    can

    it be said-unambiguously-that

    real existence is

    greater than purely conceptual existence.

    However,

    as

    Cock has shown, this interpretation

    of Anselm s argument

    seems

    to involve that if God exists necessarily, so does

    an absolutely evil

    being. This,

    as

    Charlesworth points out, isnot the devil

    of Christian orthodoxy.

    Cock s ontological proof

    of the devil establishes-not a fallen angel-but a

    being

    on

    the

    same

    metaphysical

    level

    as

    God.

    This is

    a

    kind

    of dualism which

    Anselm s Christian faith could

    not

    tolerate.

    Cock s

    interpretation seems to

    involve Anselm

    in

    heresy.

    In fairness toCock s interpretation itmust be said that the heresy lies in

    the

    presupposition of the

    argument and not

    in Cock s

    understanding of

    Anselm s

    ontology.

    Cock

    can

    only get

    started in

    his

    proof of

    the

    devil

    because

    he assumes

    that evil has

    an

    independent

    reality. Christian theology

    has

    traditionally

    seen

    evil

    as

    in

    some

    way

    parasitic

    on

    the good, having

    no

    reality

    independent

    of the good. Anselm could, therefore,

    admit that insofar

    as

    something

    was

    imperfect,

    its real

    existence

    was

    worse

    than merely con

    ceptual

    existence while

    denying

    that the

    notion

    of

    an

    absolutely

    evil

    being

    was

    an

    intelligible

    one.

    To recapitulate: Anselm s second premise is capable of three interpreta

    tions:

    (i)

    Real

    existence is

    greater

    than

    conceptual

    existence.

    This is

    Charlesworth s

    interpretation.

    (2)

    Real

    existence

    is

    an

    intensification

    of

    conceptual

    existence.

    This

    interpretation

    is

    inferred from Cock.

    (3)

    The

    comparison

    between

    real and

    conceptual

    existence

    is

    only intelligible

    in

    the

    case of

    God.

    This,

    I

    believe,

    is

    how Anselm

    understood

    his

    argument.

    The evidence for

    my

    preference

    is

    entirely

    circumstantial.

    In

    general,

    I

    would

    simply

    observe

    that

    Anselm shows

    little

    or

    no awareness

    of

    using

    a

    general ontological

    principle

    in

    his

    second

    premise.

    This is what

    really

    distinguishes Anselm s proof from that of Descartes.

    But,

    in

    addition

    to

    this

    negative

    reason,

    I

    think

    that

    interpretation

    (3)

    makes better

    sense

    of

    two

    textual

    questions

    than does

    either

    interpretation

    (i)

    or

    interpretation

    (2).

    These

    are

    the

    meaning

    of

    Anselm s

    reply

    to

    Gaunilo s

    Lost Island

    criticism and

    the

    significance

    of the

    Proslogion,

    chapter

    v.

    This content downloaded from 193.63.81.241 on Fri, 12 Dec 2014 13:53:25 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Is Existence a Predicate in Anselm's Argument.pdf

    6/8

    IS EXISTENCE

    PREDICATE

    N

    ANSELM

    ARGUMENT?

    I25

    In his critique

    of Anselm, Gaunilo

    applies

    what he

    understands

    to be

    Anselm s

    logic to a Lost-but

    most

    excellent-Island

    and concludes

    that

    this

    Island

    must

    necessarily

    exist. Anselm

    replies:

    Now,

    I

    truly promise that

    if anyone should discover

    for me

    something existing

    either

    in

    reality or

    in the mind alone except

    that-than-which-a-greater-cannot

    be-thought -to

    which

    the logic

    of

    my argument

    would

    apply,

    then I shall find

    that

    Lost Island

    and give it, never more

    to

    be

    lost,

    to that person.

    (Reply

    to

    Gaunilo,

    Iii).

    Charlesworth comments:

    Anselm s

    reply

    to

    Gaunilo

    here, however,

    needs

    to

    be

    filled

    out in

    more

    detail

    to

    be

    satisfactory. Thus, for

    example,

    he would need

    to

    say

    that

    the notion of the

    most

    excellent island is

    a

    notion

    of merely

    a relative

    greatest ,

    for

    no matter how

    excellent

    or

    perfect

    or

    great

    an island may

    be,

    it can never be

    so

    great

    that

    we

    cannot

    conceive

    of

    a

    greater,

    and it

    will

    certainly

    never

    be the

    most

    excellent

    or

    most

    perfect

    or

    greatest

    being absolutely

    speaking.

    On

    St

    Anselm s

    premises,

    of

    course,

    an

    actually existing

    island will be

    greater

    or more

    perfect

    than

    one

    merely

    thought of,

    but

    this

    does

    not

    imply

    that

    there is an

    actually existing

    island.

    The

    case of

    that than which

    nothing

    greater

    can

    be

    thought

    is

    different,

    for

    here,

    so

    St

    Anselm claims,

    we have

    the

    concept of something which

    is

    the greatest

    absolutely speaking,

    something

    than which

    it

    is

    not

    possible

    in

    any way

    to

    think

    of

    a

    greater.

    We can

    agree with

    Charlesworth that

    if,

    for

    Anselm,

    an

    existing island is

    greater than

    an

    imaginary one, his argument

    does need to be filled

    out in

    more detail

    in order to be satisfactory .

    Indeed it is scarcely satisfactory,

    even

    when

    the distinction

    between absolute

    and relative greatness has

    been

    made.

    If, however, Anselm did

    not hold that an existing island

    is greater than an

    imaginary island, the

    exegesis of this passage ismuch

    simpler. We do not

    need the distinction-unfounded in the text-between relative and

    absolute

    greatness.

    If

    we

    do not assume that Anselm s

    second premise is a

    general rule, we do not

    have

    to

    suppose that Anselm saw

    in

    his argument

    or

    in Gaunilo s

    objections

    to

    it-what both Gaunilo and Charlesworth

    take

    for

    granted.

    If

    Anselm

    really

    saw the

    point

    of Gaunilo s criticism, his

    answer

    to

    Gaunilo

    is

    virtually incomprehensible.

    Gaunilo s criticism

    assumes

    what Charlesworth does:

    that, for Anselm,

    existence

    is a

    perfection.

    If

    Gaunilo

    and

    Charlesworth

    are correct,

    Anselm

    could not have

    helped

    seeing the point of

    the Lost Island analogy. And

    if he

    understood the criticism, Anselm could not have avoided addressing himself

    to

    it;

    to show

    (as Charlesworth attempts

    to do) why, although existence

    is a

    perfection,

    the

    perfect

    island does not

    exist.

    Similarly,

    if

    Anselm did

    not hold existence

    to be

    a

    perfection, but

    did see

    what Gaunilo

    was

    getting

    at,

    it

    would

    be incumbent on Anselm

    to call

    Charlesworth,

    op. cit. pp. 93-94.

    This content downloaded from 193.63.81.241 on Fri, 12 Dec 2014 13:53:25 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Is Existence a Predicate in Anselm's Argument.pdf

    7/8

    I26 DAVID M.

    LOCHHEAD

    attention to Gaunilo s mistaken assumption and to contrast his own position

    with it. Anselm does neither of these things.We must wonder then ifAnselm

    saw Gaunilo s point at all. An indication that

    Anselm

    did not understand

    Gaunilo s criticism is the fact that

    Anselm

    consistently speaks as if the force

    of that

    criticism lay

    in

    the conceivabilityof the island rather than in

    its

    excellence.

    It must be assumed that Anselm regarded his remarks as an appropriate

    reply toGaunilo s criticism. It is difficult to see how he could regard the reply

    that he actually makes as appropriate

    if

    he really saw the force of Gaunilo s

    argument. It seems best to conclude then, that Anselm did not understand

    Gaunilo s objection. But if Anselm did not understand the objection, it is

    impossible

    to

    understand how

    he

    could have

    held

    the

    assumption that lies at

    the

    basis

    of that

    objection:

    that existence is

    a

    perfection.

    Anselm s misunder

    standing of Gaunilo s criticism is only intelligible on the assumption that he

    did

    not hold the

    ontology upon

    which that criticism

    is founded.

    So much for the

    Lost Island. Let us look at the second textual point: the

    significance

    of

    chapter

    v

    of

    the

    Proslogion.

    The

    concept of perfection

    in

    Anselm

    is

    quite

    clearly

    defined.

    A

    perfection

    iswhatever, absolutely speaking, it is better to be than not to be. Thus, for

    example, justice is a perfection since it isclearly better tobe just than not tobe

    just.

    Anselm

    recognises

    relative

    perfections,

    but these do

    not concern

    us here.

    Anselm s idea of perfection is developed in the Monologion, chapter

    xv and

    in

    the

    Proslogion, chapter

    v.

    It is Anselm s

    use of the concept of perfection

    in

    the

    Proslogion

    that

    is

    important to our problem.

    He starts from his definition: God is

    that-than

    which-nothing-greater-can-be-conceived.

    From

    this

    definition,

    he

    establishes

    God s perfection

    in

    general.

    As

    the

    being greater

    than which

    nothing

    can

    be

    conceived,

    God must

    be

    supremely perfect.

    Otherwise

    a

    greater

    can

    be

    conceived. Having established God s perfection in general, Anselm proceeds

    to

    predicate particular

    perfections (goodness, justice, etc.)

    of him.

    In

    Charlesworth s interpretation,

    real

    existence

    is

    a

    perfection.

    It

    is

    better

    to be real than

    not

    to be real

    (i.e.

    to

    be

    merely possible).

    If

    this is

    the

    case,

    Anselm

    had a

    procedure already developed

    in the

    Monologion

    with which

    he

    could

    deal

    with

    it.

    His

    proof

    could have

    proceeded

    as

    follows: God

    is

    that

    than-which-nothing-greater-can-be-conceived.

    It

    follows

    that God is

    supremely perfect.

    A

    perfection

    is

    whatever

    is

    better to

    be

    than not

    to be.

    It

    is

    better

    to

    be

    real than

    not to

    be

    real.

    Therefore

    God

    really

    exists.

    But Anselm doesn t do this.Here is themajor distinction between Anselm s

    argument and those

    of Descartes

    and Leibniz.

    In

    Anselm,

    the idea

    of

    perfec

    tion

    is

    only introduced after

    God s

    existence

    is

    established.

    Anselm

    (deliber

    ately?) keeps

    the

    question

    of God s

    existence

    separate

    from

    that of

    his

    perfection.

    He shows

    no

    tendency

    whatsoever

    to

    subsume

    the

    concept

    of

    1

    Cf. Anselm,

    Reply to Gaunilo, I,

    111)

    V.

    This content downloaded from 193.63.81.241 on Fri, 12 Dec 2014 13:53:25 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Is Existence a Predicate in Anselm's Argument.pdf

    8/8

    IS

    EXISTENCE

    A

    PREDICATE

    IN ANSELM

    S

    ARGUMENT?

    127

    existence under

    that of perfection.

    In relation to

    the

    definition

    of God,

    existence occupies the

    same

    status

    as

    perfection .

    Both follow directly

    from

    the

    definition.

    This is not

    true

    of particular perfections.

    If commentators

    on

    the

    ontological

    argument

    wish

    to

    maintain that,

    for

    Anselm, real

    existence

    is

    greater

    than

    conceptual

    existence, they

    must give

    us answers

    to the following questions: Why

    is the

    perfection

    of God not

    established

    until

    chapter

    v

    of the Proslogion

    while

    the existence

    of

    God

    is

    Discussed

    in

    chapters

    II--Iv?

    Why

    is God s

    perfection

    not discussed

    first?

    Real existence,

    as

    interpreted

    by Charlesworth,

    fulfilsAnselm s own criterion

    for a

    perfection. Why

    does

    Anselm show no

    tendency

    to

    make

    this

    explicit?

    Why

    does he seem,

    rather, to

    resist

    assimilating

    the two

    concepts?

    To

    state

    my

    conclusions:

    (I)

    Anselm

    never

    discusses

    the

    comparison

    between

    real

    and conceptual

    existence

    except

    in relation to

    that-than

    which-nothing-greater-can-be-thought .

    There

    is

    little,

    if

    any,

    basis for

    the

    claim

    that,

    in

    general,

    real existence

    is

    greater

    than

    conceptual

    existence.

    There

    is

    evidence,

    as I

    have tried to show,

    that Anselm did

    not hold the view

    that

    Charlesworth

    attributes

    to

    him.

    (2)

    If

    Anselm

    does

    hold

    a

    general

    view

    concerning

    the nature of real existence-and

    there is no

    evidence

    that

    he

    does-there

    is

    still no basis for

    characterising

    this view as Charlesworth

    does.

    The interpretation

    inferred from

    Cock s

    treatment

    of Anselm s argument

    is

    a

    genuine-and

    perhaps better-alternative.

    The

    interpretation

    of

    Anselm

    which

    Charlesworth

    puts

    forward is shared,

    implicitly,

    by almost every

    commentator on

    the ontological

    argument.

    I

    have

    challenged

    Charlesworth

    in

    particular

    for

    two reasons.

    In

    the first

    place,

    Charlesworth

    challenges

    the orthodox view

    of Anselm on almost

    every

    other

    point

    of

    consequence. It

    is

    a

    pity that this

    point escaped him.

    Secondly,

    Charlesworth

    is

    aware

    of Cock s article

    and

    of its relevance

    to the question

    of

    the existence

    of

    the devil.

    He should have

    been

    aware,

    therefore, of the

    consequences for his interpretation.

    I

    have attempted in this paper

    neither to support

    nor refute

    Anselm s

    argument.

    This would

    be the subject of

    another study. I

    only insist here that

    before we

    pontificate on

    the validity of the

    argument,

    we

    must be clear about

    what the

    argument

    is.

    This content downloaded from 193.63.81.241 on Fri, 12 Dec 2014 13:53:25 PM

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

Recommended