+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Knox -Hegel's Attitude to Kant's (Kant.1958.49.1-4.70)

Knox -Hegel's Attitude to Kant's (Kant.1958.49.1-4.70)

Date post: 03-Jun-2018
Category:
Upload: daniel-perrone
View: 221 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend

of 12

Transcript
  • 8/11/2019 Knox -Hegel's Attitude to Kant's (Kant.1958.49.1-4.70)

    1/12

    HEGEL S

    ATTITDE

    TO

    KANT S

    ETHICS

    by T. M.Knox, St. Andrews

    In

    bis

    L ectures on theHistory of Philosophy

    1

    ), Hegel described

    himself

    s a

    Lutheran? with

    no

    less justice

    he

    might

    have

    claimed

    to b e

    f

    in

    ethics

    2

    ),

    a

    Kantian. It

    is t rue

    that

    bis orthodoxy may be suspect in

    theology and ethics

    alike,

    and

    there

    may now seem to be an air of paradox

    about the

    assertion

    that Hegel was essentially a K ant ian in

    ethics.

    Never-

    theless,

    this

    is the paradox which I propose to defend.

    The Charge that Hegel had no ethics was made against him in

    bis

    own

    lifetime (W.XVIII.XX) and has often been repeated. What he

    published

    on

    the topics

    whidi

    Kant discussed at length in

    bis ethical

    works is small in

    bulk, but the fundamental reason for this seems to me to be that he was

    substantially in agreement with Kant and had nothing new to say on the

    subject. The

    general

    impression that Hegel was not a Kant ian in ethics

    arises

    from

    concentrating to o much attention on bis commoner criticisms

    of Kant and too little on their context and

    drift.

    He Tisually indicates that

    bis criticisms are secondary

    by

    going

    out of

    bis

    way to pay a

    t r ibute

    to

    K ant s u nd yin g m erit in ethics

    3

    ).

    The criticisms

    often

    do not

    affect

    the

    substance of Kant s doctrine, b ut only details, and more frequently still

    the

    object

    of

    Hegel s attack

    is the insufficiency of

    morality

    s such, not

    of

    K ant s view

    of m orality, or the

    contradictions

    in

    m oral experience itself,

    not in K ant s Interpretation of it. Hegel s quarrel with Kant was not that

    Kant

    was mistaken about niprality but that he did not clearly Supplement

    bis

    teaching with

    a

    doctrine

    of Sittlichkeit.

    This general thesis I propose to

    argue

    by considering (a)Hegel s clear

    devotion to Kant in bis

    early

    writings and the ground of bis revolt against

    bim,

    (b )

    those

    passages in Hegel which might b e adduced against m e,

    namely bis

    chief

    published criticisms

    of K ant s ethics, and (c) his

    concep-

    tion of Sittlichkeit which in substance is not so far removed from K ant s

    way of thinking

    s

    is sometimes supposed.

    Werke

    XIII.

    89. I quote, from

    Glockner s edition,

    the volume and

    page

    of the original edition.

    ~

    ,

    2

    ) I use the word

    in

    its ordinary English

    sense.

    Where I have

    occasion

    to

    allude

    to Hegel s own

    distinction

    between Moralitt and Sittlichkeit l use the

    German words.

    3

    ) Hegel deplored

    the

    neglect

    of

    Kant

    by his contemporaries (W.

    XVII. 238.

    cf,

    III. 52). He

    never

    minimised his own debt to Kant s

    philosophy: was

    brought up on it (Letter to Duboc, 30 July 1822).

  • 8/11/2019 Knox -Hegel's Attitude to Kant's (Kant.1958.49.1-4.70)

    2/12

    With the exception of Th. L.Haering, to

    whose

    monumental work all

    students of Hegel are indebted, readers ofHegel's

    Theologische

    Jugend-

    Schriften

    have

    found

    in the

    papers written

    at

    Berne

    the dominating

    in-

    fluence of

    Kant. Hegel

    had studied the

    three Critiques

    at

    Tbingen

    and he

    resumedtheirstudy

    at

    Berne

    in 1794,but his main

    interest

    until

    1800

    was

    concentrated on religion and

    theology,

    history and politics; and

    although

    it was

    Kant

    who stimulated him to

    write iii Berne,

    the Stimulus

    came

    not

    from the Critiquesbut from the essay on

    Religion

    within the

    Sounds

    of

    >Reason alone

    Hegel's

    writings

    in

    17956

    4

    ),

    are

    inspired

    almost

    entirely

    iby

    this

    essay.

    Religion,

    Kant

    maintained, is, on its

    subjective

    side, the

    knowledge

    of

    all our duties

    s

    divine

    commands

    (Pt. IV.

    l,

    ad

    iniL).

    Revealed religion

    would hold

    that

    ourduties are

    dutiesbecause they

    are divinely

    command-

    ed,

    but a

    natural

    or rational religion recognises that duty is the law of

    man's

    own reason, sothatman does not need to have it revealed to him

    or

    to be

    provided with

    any

    motive

    fo r

    observing

    the

    mora l

    law

    over

    and

    iabove

    reverence fo r

    the law

    itself.

    A

    rational

    religion,

    while

    not

    required

    for morality,mayneverthelessbe implied by it and be an aid to it by the

    strengthening of our moral

    motives through

    the idea of God s amoral

    lawgiver. Kant proceeds to consider what religious beliefs

    oan

    be

    justified

    by reason unaidedand tocarry on apolemic against allattemptstobase

    faith on a

    special revelation,

    on

    historical

    facts

    or on miracles,s

    well

    s

    against the tyranny

    of

    priests

    and the

    fetishism

    of

    religious

    observances,

    s if any acts could be pleasing to God

    except

    the fulfilment ofmoral

    duties The Christian religion should be purified of dross by rational

    criticism,andKant goeson toshowhowsomeof itsleading doctrines

    can

    be reinterpreted

    s

    rational instead of s given

    or

    positive or statutory.

    In particular,

    "Christianityhas

    the great advantage over

    Judaism

    of being

    presented to us s issuing

    from

    the

    mouth

    of its

    first teacher s

    a moral

    religion, and hence, being thus intimately associated with reason, could

    be disseminated to all ages and all pupils by reason alone, without any

    historical learning

    Pt.

    IV.

    1.

    I. ad.

    fin.).

    Hegel accepts

    all this. The fragment

    printed

    in Nohl pp. 6071 fre-

    quently eciioes Kant's phraseology and repeats his illustrations. The

    im -

    portant point is that

    Kant's

    essay on Religion

    1792)

    presupposes the

    ethical

    doctrine expounded in the Critiqueo f Practical Reason 1788), and

    Hegel is

    following

    Kant in both religion and ethics.

    Kant

    had suggested

    thatan attempt to harmonise the

    teadiing

    ofJesuswith the

    holiestteaching

    of

    reason

    was not

    only

    a

    possibility

    but

    bounden duty (Pt.

    II.

    2),

    and

    Hegel set

    himself

    to

    this

    task by

    writing

    a life ofJesus, exhibiting him

    s

    a

    human moral teacher proclaiming

    a

    doctrine wholly

    in accordance

    with Kant's ethics. Presumably sudi a document mightbe regarded s

    contributing to the moral education of

    mankind

    by being the scriptures

    of

    a new rational religion. In any event,Hegel

    took

    painswithhis task,

    4

    ) Theologische Jugendschffen Nohl)

    f

    pp. 60213,

    71

  • 8/11/2019 Knox -Hegel's Attitude to Kant's (Kant.1958.49.1-4.70)

    3/12

    though

    the

    result

    of

    discharging

    the

    duty laid

    on him by his

    master may

    eventually havehelped to convince himthat

    there

    was somethingwrong

    with the enterprise.

    In a similar spirit ofdiscipleship he wrotehis

    essay

    on the Positivity

    the

    Christian

    Religion,in order to answer the question: Granted that,

    s Kant averred, the teaching of Jesus was in

    conformity

    with pure

    reason, how is it that the teaching of orthodox Christianity has become

    so authoritative and

    positive ?

    In

    both oftheseessaysthe problem is Kantian: their

    background

    is the

    Kantian distinction between the positive law of legality and the natural

    or

    rational law of

    morality:

    and their spirit is Kantian,s isshown espe-

    cially by the conclusion of the

    second

    essay (Nohl, 2112) where the

    Christian

    religion s taught by the Churdi is said to

    afford objective

    motives whichare not the lawitself,i. e. ispositive and notrational.Both

    essays rest

    on

    Kantian doctrine about

    religion,

    about

    the

    teaching

    of

    Jesus, and

    about morality, but

    the

    significant thing

    for

    Hegel's develop-

    ment is that the essays subject this doctrine to the

    test

    of history. Kant

    had not

    taken history seriously enough,

    and in ef fec t he

    admitted

    s

    much

    when he said that a moral use may be

    made

    of anhistoricalstatement in

    Scripture without considering what the author's meaning was: historical

    knowledge which

    has no universally

    valid moral bearings belongs

    to the

    adiaphora (Pt.LIV., fn.ad. fin.).

    Between

    the

    Kantian essays

    and The Spirit of

    Christianity

    1798)

    there

    is a

    gulf

    so

    wide that

    the

    later essay,writtens

    it is

    with suchassurance,

    such

    passion, and such independence of mind, may seem at f i rs t

    s

    if it

    could

    scarcely have come

    f rom

    the same pen. When he wrote this essay,

    Hegel had come to believe that Kant was wrong not onlyabout the teach-

    ing of

    Jesus

    and the

    spirit

    of the

    Christian religion,

    but

    about religion

    altogether.-He

    had discovered that moral experience (about which,

    s

    he

    continued to believe, Kantwas right)was onething,religiousexperience

    (about

    which

    Kantwaswrong) another; thatJesuswas areligious teacher,

    not

    merely

    a

    moral

    one?

    and

    that

    an

    historian's

    eye was

    needed

    to

    discern

    alike

    the

    meaning

    of

    Christianity

    and the

    deficiencies

    of

    orthodoxy.

    What was it that produced the revolution inHegers thinking between

    what

    Ihavecalled the Kantian essays and all his later works? Like other

    revolutions it was not unheralded. Even in the Kantian essays there are

    occasional

    hints

    of a

    more original

    line of

    thought.

    But

    what

    was it

    that

    led

    Hegel

    to

    develop them,

    to reorientate his

    thinking,

    to

    renounceKants

    guidance in religion,and toproduce work in a newspirit

    altogether?

    Some

    would answer:

    the

    influence

    of

    Hlderlin.

    The

    answer

    is

    unsatis-

    factory

    because it would

    still

    be necessary to ask what it was that made

    Hegel so susceptible to that influence at that

    time.

    The two men had

    been friends for ten years at least, and

    although

    Hegel's poemEleusis,

    addressed

    to

    Hlderlin,

    has

    been quoted s evidence that

    he

    shared

    his

    friend's

    romantic

    and pantheistic ideas in August 1796, it is perfectly

    clear

    f rom

    Hegel's other contemporary writings that what

    the

    poem

    expresses is the spiritof the addressee and not of the

    author.

    Contrastit,

  • 8/11/2019 Knox -Hegel's Attitude to Kant's (Kant.1958.49.1-4.70)

    4/12

    H

    ^ o fo r example, with

    the

    almost exactly

    contemporary

    diary ofbis tour in

    V.the Bernese Oberland

    5

    ). Thepoemis anearlyexample of

    Hegel's

    remark-

    J{able skill in adopting another's point o f view and accurately describing

    ? i v ,

    what isseen f rom it. In thediary hespeaks in propria

    persona:

    inEleusis

    ^.;, the mask he wears is Hlderlin's.

    ^

    The

    revolution

    in

    Hegel's thinking

    came

    abou-t

    because, during

    bis f i rs t

    i e

    :

    two

    years in

    'unhappy Frankfur t

    1 6

    f

    in

    order

    to eure

    himself

    o f melan-

    diolia,he

    worked

    withallbis

    energies

    at

    Greek literature

    and

    philosophy,

    ^ . r s well s at

    history

    and

    politics,

    and

    theh brought

    the

    result

    of

    these

    Ji

    studies

    to

    bear

    anewon the

    reinterpretation

    of the life andmessageof

    f

    Jesus.

    | The root o fHegel's entire difference f rom Kant lies in this reorienta-

    ition

    of his

    thought

    in

    Frankfurt. Kant

    was not

    much

    interested

    in the

    Greek philosophers, and he wasmoredevoted to physical sciencethanto

    history, although his essay on the latter topic showedhow alert his uni-

    ,

    yersal

    mind was to the

    importance

    of a new and

    growing discipline.

    But

    henceforward

    every

    one of Hegel's

    m a j o r

    works

    is

    a history,

    and his

    philosophy owes s much

    to

    Plato

    and

    Aristotle s

    to

    Kant.Itwas, how-

    lever, his religious insight bove all that separated him f rom Kant.His

    early theologiQal writings have been called antitheologicar by an acute

    critic

    7

    ),

    but this is only partly just. All these writings, especially the

    later

    of

    them,throb with

    a

    religious conviction which

    is

    absent

    f rom

    Kant's

    cautious

    essay.

    They

    attack

    orthodoxy

    indeed, in terms similar to

    those

    used

    by

    Kant

    and many other

    writers

    of the Aufklrung but

    what Hegel

    wishes

    to

    substitute

    for

    orthodoxy

    is not a dry

    rationalism

    but a living

    religious faith, carried out in practice in a

    rationally

    ordered

    social

    com-

    munity.

    The

    basis

    of

    this faith

    is a

    doctrine

    of the HolySpirit The spirit

    of man,

    his reason, is the oandle of the

    Lord,

    and its powers are thus not

    subject to the

    limitations which Kant

    had

    placed

    on

    them

    in the first

    Critique.Doubtless

    these limitations

    left

    room

    for

    faith,

    but unfortunately,

    in

    Hegel's view,

    not

    only

    fo r

    a

    rational

    faith

    founded

    on the

    postulates

    of

    practical reason,

    but also for the whole panoply of

    orthodoxy,

    s the

    Tbingen theologians

    had

    quickly realised. Hegel's

    eirenicon

    between

    faith and

    reason thus depends

    on

    regarding reason s

    free f rom

    limitations,

    and

    it is because the self-legislating reason ofKant's ethioal works has

    this

    f reedom that

    Hegel

    never renounced their leading

    principles.

    II

    But

    was

    Hegel

    not a

    constant

    critic of the

    second

    Ctique?

    His

    published

    criticisms

    of Kant's ethics are directed against this workalone

    amongst

    Kant's writings

    on the

    subject,

    and the chief of

    them must

    now

    be

    examined.

    Haering, who

    mentions

    everything eise, omits this diary: nor, so far

    s

    I know, has any other writer on

    leusis

    seen that the diary is the

    best commen-

    tary on it.

    e

    Letter to

    Sinclair,

    mid-October

    1810.

    7

    W - A .

    K aufmann

    in

    Philosophiert

    Review

    1951,

    p.

    460.

  • 8/11/2019 Knox -Hegel's Attitude to Kant's (Kant.1958.49.1-4.70)

    5/12

    In

    the

    essay

    on the

    Scientific Ways of

    Treating

    Natural LawHegel's

    argument

    is:

    Kant

    argues correctly

    that

    practical

    reason

    is

    concemed

    with

    th e

    form

    of

    moral

    action, the

    correspondence

    of the

    form

    of our

    maxim

    with

    the

    universal mo>ral law

    of

    duty.

    The inference, however,

    ought

    to

    be

    that practical reason should content itself with saying what duty

    in

    general

    is and

    ought

    not to try to

    provide

    a touchstone for

    recognising

    whatact is adutyon aparticular occasion, for Kanthadheld (K.d. .

    V.

    A.

    589) that while pure reason could

    say whait truth is in general, it

    could not

    provide

    a test of the

    truth

    of any

    given Statement

    of

    fact.

    But

    in relation to practical

    reason,

    Kant

    fal ls

    todraw the same

    inference,

    and

    he

    attempts (vainly,

    in

    Hegel's view)

    to

    give guidance

    in

    practice

    by

    telling us to act so that the maxim of our action can hold good s a

    principle of universal

    legislation;

    and the commonest understanding, he

    holds,

    can

    readily discern what

    form

    of

    maxim

    is

    adapted

    for

    this

    pur-

    pose: for if Iprbpose to appropriate a deposit which is in my

    hands

    and |

    whoseownerhad died without leaving any evidence of it, I must askmyself

    whether I can legislate that everyone may deny a deposit ofwhichno

    one can

    produce

    a

    proof ,

    and I

    soon

    see

    that

    I cannot. The law

    would

    annihilate itself,

    because

    if it

    existed there would

    be no

    deposits. Hegel

    points out that the argument s stated lacks cogency. ^What the non-

    existence of deposits contradicts is not reason

    or

    the universal law, but

    the

    existence

    ofother,

    equally specific

    and

    limited, social

    and

    legal insti-

    tutions,

    and

    only

    on

    some undisclosed assumption about

    the

    worth

    of

    these will

    a law

    leading

    to the

    non-existence

    of

    deposits

    be

    morally

    inadmissible on

    Kant's principles

    (W . I. 349ff.). The

    criticism,

    so far s it

    goes,

    issound,and it is not the

    least

    of

    Professor

    H. J.

    Paton's Services

    to

    Kant ian scholarship that he has brought out

    clearly

    what Kant's

    assump-

    tions are

    8

    ), and expounded the totality ofKant's'ethical

    teaching

    and not

    merely those isolated aspects

    of it

    which Hegel

    and many

    critics have

    selected

    for

    examination.

    In any event Hegers criticism here

    touches

    one aspect only of Kant's

    doctrine and not its main principles. His

    final

    point in this essay is one

    that he repeated

    later

    (W . v. 320 ff. Cf.

    234, Zusatz :

    moral

    effort

    aims

    at its

    own

    cancellation, so that the moral will remains finite, despite

    the

    universality

    of the

    moral

    law

    which

    it

    issues.

    The aim of

    moral action

    is to

    remove

    evil; but if it

    succeeds there

    is no

    longer

    any

    need

    for it;

    diarity

    constantly endeavours to remove the occasion for its exercise.

    As the Dialectic of the Critique of Practical Reason

    shows,

    Kant was not

    unaware of the

    problem.

    But the important point is that Hegel is not

    questioning Kant's theory

    of

    moral experience?

    he is

    accepting

    it and

    simply

    arguing that there must be a higher, experience in

    wihich

    its con-

    tradictions

    are

    transcended.

    The two other explicit criticisms of Kant which require attention are

    those

    in the

    Encyclopaedia

    54 and the

    Philosophie des Rechts,

    135.

    These

    are

    likewise based essentially

    on

    passages

    in the Critique

    l

    Practical Reason. They take no account of the Metaphysik der Sitten;

    8

    ) The Categorical Imperative pp. 149157.

    74 .

  • 8/11/2019 Knox -Hegel's Attitude to Kant's (Kant.1958.49.1-4.70)

    6/12

    and nowhere in

    Hegel s

    writings, .so fa r s I know, is

    there

    *any reference

    al all, even implicit,t the GrundlegungderM etaphysik

    der

    Sitten

    The

    Grundlegung was published

    when

    Hegel was fifteen and it is not

    impos-

    sible that he ignored it altogether. This is un for tuna te , for

    Kan t s

    concep-

    tion

    of a

    Kingdom

    of Ends,

    expounded

    more

    fully

    in

    that

    eesay than

    in his

    later works, must have

    interested

    him, even if he may have thought it

    difficult

    to reconcile with some of the Statements in the second Critique

    which

    come in for

    most

    of

    his criticism. Kant

    has

    always suffered

    f rom

    critics

    who have failed to

    realise

    that he waswont to expound hisviews

    gradually,beginning on a

    foun dation

    of common sense, an d then

    modifying

    Jiis starting

    point bit by bit; butHegel at

    least

    ought to have

    sympathised

    with

    this

    method and adjusted his criticism accordingly. But thetarget of his

    criticisms was precisely those elements in Kan t s doctrine which had been

    most

    popularised

    by

    Fichte

    an d

    which therefore

    had become commonplace

    in the literature of

    Hegel s

    own day;

    these

    criticisms of his appeared

    (1821 and

    1827) between

    30 and 40

    years af ter

    the

    publication

    of the

    second Crilique Nowhere does Hegel

    profess

    to expound

    Kan t s

    ethics

    s

    a

    whole

    9

    ]

    or to subject the

    whole

    of his writings on this subject to

    detailed examination.

    Nevertheless,itmustbe admitted that in these passages in hispublish-

    ed

    works, Hegel

    is less

    than

    fa ir to Kant ,

    unless

    he

    uses Kan t s

    name

    simply to describe certain views which his contempcraries had come to

    regard

    s

    the kernel of his master s teaching. The brden of

    Hegel s

    criticism is that although Kant was right to emphasise the pure

    uncondi-

    tioned self-determination of the will s he root of duty, he could n ot

    extract

    f rom his formulae an y

    doctrine

    of determinate

    duties, Thus

    he

    had to

    throw away

    all he had

    gained

    in

    superseding eudaemonism by

    reducing

    ethics to an empty

    formalism

    and the pieaching of duty for

    duty s sake.

    Inorder to justify this

    criticism

    a

    critic

    would

    have

    to plead

    that Hegel

    was

    dealing only with

    the

    second Critique that

    he was

    attadiing great

    importance

    to

    Kant s

    own

    preference

    for

    the

    first

    formulation

    of the

    categorical imperative,

    and

    that

    he was

    taking some

    of

    Kant s Statements

    a t their face value without considering their context or what

    modification

    they

    received in other contexts. The

    plea

    would be an admission that

    justice was not being done to the many-sidedness of Kant s doctrine, but

    it

    would

    be

    doing less than justice

    to

    Hegel s attitude

    to

    Kan t s ethics

    to

    suppose that these criticisms

    represent

    it adequately. To discover what

    his attitude is, it is necessary to look at other passages in Hegel where

    the

    relation between

    the mora l

    consciousness

    and the

    religious,

    and

    be-

    tween

    Moralitt

    an d

    Sittlichkeit

    comes to the fore, an d others again

    (un~

    published in his lifetime) in whidi he expounds his own moral doctrine.

    ) The History of

    Philosophy

    might have been expected to contain such an

    exposition, but the second Critique is the only one of Kant s ethical writings

    whidi

    it mentions.

    Hegel s

    criticisms

    there

    are in

    substance

    s imar to

    those

    summarised

    in the

    following paragraph.

    .

  • 8/11/2019 Knox -Hegel's Attitude to Kant's (Kant.1958.49.1-4.70)

    7/12

    III

    In the

    Enc. Logic

    234

    there

    is adirect transition from morality, ex-

    pounded

    mainly

    s

    Kant

    had

    expounded

    it, to

    religion;

    it is in the

    latter

    that the contradictions of the

    f o r m e r

    are resolved. The same is

    true

    in

    the

    Phenomenology

    where

    Hegel

    Sketches, s he didlater in the Philoso-

    phie des Rechts 140, the

    dangers

    to

    which

    an ethical

    iridividoialism

    may

    be

    exposed if ,

    ignoring th e

    complexities

    o f

    Kant's

    teadhing, it emphasises

    the individual's

    mo ra l convictions alone.

    But in

    Enc. Phil.

    d.

    Geistes

    50 8 ff. and in Phil.d. Rechts th e

    transition

    is

    from morality

    to

    Sittlich-

    keit

    while religion is ahigher sphere

    still.

    The

    difference between these

    two transitions, however,

    is more apparent than real, because the

    diaracteristicallyHegelian conception of

    Sittlichkeit

    is religious in essence

    and

    is intelligible

    only

    if its religious origin and

    background

    is kept in

    view.

    Although this

    conception is not explicitly taught by Hegel until 1817

    (in the first

    edition

    of the Encyclopaedia , it is

    foreshadowed

    in someof

    the Jena writings fifteenyears earlier, and it has its

    roots

    in his thinking

    when he was writing

    The

    Spirit

    of

    Christianity in 1798 and liberating

    himself from th e preponderating influence ofKant's view of religion.

    Hegel's problem in

    this

    essay is to expound the

    nature

    and signi-

    ficance of the moral teaching of

    Jesus.

    He begins by contrasting it with

    th e

    Mosaic

    law

    and the

    teaching

    of

    Kant (Nohl,

    262266).

    The

    Mosaic

    lawhe

    regards

    s a set of

    arbitrary commandswhich

    might beissuedby a

    master to aslave.Hetakes it for granted,

    like

    a

    good

    pupil of

    Kant, that

    this

    heteronomy

    of the human will is

    below

    the moral

    level.

    Against

    purely objective commands Jesus

    set

    something totally -alien

    to

    them,

    namely

    the subjective in

    general ,

    i. e. not human

    passivity

    and slavery

    but a unified ideal life

    confirmed

    -and expressed in deeds. W e might

    have expected h im , Hegel writes (i. e. if we were Kantians, convinced

    by the

    Religion

    essay)

    f

    to show that any ought,

    qua

    a product of reason

    s the capacity for universality, loses its positivity and heteronomy, so

    that the thing commanded is

    revealed

    s grounded in an

    autonomy

    of

    the

    human

    will'.But by

    this line

    of

    argument, positivity

    is

    only partially

    removed.

    Kant had contrasted the slavery of obedience to

    ritual

    com-

    mands with

    th e freedom of the man who

    listens

    to his own c o m m a n d of

    duty.But the difference is

    really

    between tw okinds o fslavery;

    tihe former

    has his lord outside himself while the latter carries his lord in himself,

    yet is at the

    same time

    his own

    slave.

    One whowished to

    restore

    man's

    humanity

    in its

    entirety could

    not

    possibly

    have

    taken

    a

    course like

    this; for the individual would be torn against

    himself ;

    the cleavage

    between inclination

    and

    reason would

    not be healed.

    What

    Hegel

    is

    saying here

    is not that

    Kant's

    analysis of

    duty

    and

    moral experience is mis taken, but that there is an experience of a differ-

    ent

    kind which

    'transcends it. In the

    Kantian conception

    o f

    virtue

    the

    Opposition

    between universal

    and

    particular

    remains, the one s

    master

    th e

    other

    s

    mastered.

    Jesus

    Supplements

    th e deficiency of the law

    r

    or

    fulfils it, by a

    unification

    of law and inclination in love? or s Hegel

  • 8/11/2019 Knox -Hegel's Attitude to Kant's (Kant.1958.49.1-4.70)

    8/12

  • 8/11/2019 Knox -Hegel's Attitude to Kant's (Kant.1958.49.1-4.70)

    9/12

    o f

    the

    truth of the human will...

    Love

    is itself away above mora l con-

    siderations:Mary anoints Christ instead of giving to the

    p o o r

    r

    and Christ

    approves .

    For Kant, however, this sphere above morality is beyond the

    reach

    of

    human reason,

    and

    man's will

    can

    never become

    the

    holy will

    in

    which

    there

    is a complete coincidence between inclination and

    law;

    while for

    Hegel

    the

    scope

    of

    reason

    is

    wider

    and

    man's ability

    to rise

    above morality is greater. In his view it is open to man to

    rise

    above

    the

    moral experience typified

    by

    ought

    there

    is

    amorallaw

    and man

    ought to school himself to obey it to the is , the experience in which

    man

    lives the law instead of being tmder it

    12

    ). Against all attempts

    to base morality on sentiment, or to

    justify

    the subjective dictates of

    anindividual

    conscience, however unschooled,Hegel always

    uses

    Kantian

    arguments. But, although he accepts the cleavage between Law and

    Morality which

    is

    vital

    to the

    Metaphysik

    der

    Sitten

    he

    believes

    he can

    point to human experiences in which this cleavage is overcome and a

    higher synthesiscan and ought to be achieved.

    Amongst

    the experiences which Hegel might adduce are marriage and

    a man's attitude

    to his

    Professional calling (Letter

    to

    Niethammer,

    10 October

    1811).

    The basis o f a

    true

    marriage (i. e. of a marriage

    whidi exemplifies

    Sittlichkeit)

    is not

    love

    s a

    romantic feeling (for that

    may

    perish

    and

    the marriage will be dissoluble) no r ,

    s

    Kant had supposed, a contract,

    but a

    fusion

    o f

    love

    and

    duty

    in a

    reverence

    for an

    eternal ideal.

    The

    parties are then so devoted to their

    union

    that the individuality of both

    is

    transcended

    in a

    living relationship wherein duties

    are

    fulfilled without

    any

    thought

    o f them. Inclination and law are perfectly coincident Phil,

    d.

    Rechts.

    161

    ff.).

    A

    similar coincidence

    may

    occur

    in the life o f a

    Professional man,

    s

    it doubtless did in Hegel's o wn experience of his Professional work. A

    mein utterly devoted

    to a

    cause

    or an

    Institution does

    not

    spare himself;

    his day to day

    duties come before

    him

    s

    the

    ordinary routine

    of his

    affairs

    and he

    carries them

    o ut

    selflessly,

    cheerfully,

    devotedly.

    His in-

    clinations chime

    in

    with

    his

    duties

    so

    that

    he

    fulfils

    them

    single-mindedly?

    there is no tension, no awareness o f Oppos ing inner forces'. There may

    well

    be no

    consciousness

    o f

    ought

    1

    '

    at all

    until

    his

    strength

    fails and

    he is tempted of the

    devil

    to

    idleness,

    or

    until courage sinks

    and he feels

    God- forsaken.

    Moreover,

    his

    devotion

    to his

    cause,

    or

    Institution,

    is not

    merely the bringing into being o f what ought to

    existj

    his activity,

    animated

    by this

    devotion,

    is at the

    same time

    the

    existence

    of the

    cause,

    the maintenance of the Institution.

    'Ought'

    1

    has given place to is .

    Mere devotion to a calling,

    however,

    is. not enough; there

    must

    be

    devotion to an ideal of goodness which transcends it. Hegel is trying to

    describe

    an

    experience which

    is

    moral

    and

    more ,

    not an

    experience with-

    out a

    moral content. Hitler

    may

    have

    had

    devotion such s

    has

    just

    been described,*but that does no t exempt him f rom moral blame. The

    point of

    Hegel's

    teaching, and we have seen that there are similar hints

    12

    ) E. Weil in Deucalion 5 (Neuciiatel,

    1955)

    p.

    106.

    78

  • 8/11/2019 Knox -Hegel's Attitude to Kant's (Kant.1958.49.1-4.70)

    10/12

    inKant , isthat it is theloveof God.which transforms the moral

    conscious-

    ness

    ofIhe individualand makes.it possible

    for him

    to rise to the fusion

    of

    inclination

    and

    law

    in

    devotion

    to a supra-individual

    end.

    Although Kan t

    w asprepared to see in thelove of God

    Ihe complement.

    of

    duty

    r

    nevertheless,

    in the

    Professional devotion which

    has

    just been

    described

    he

    saw

    tw o dangers: Suppose that such a devotee were asked

    whether

    he did what he did because he enjoyed it or because it was

    bis duty. He might reply that he did it

    from

    mere love oforder. In that

    event

    he wouldbe

    thinking

    that he was above the thought of duty,

    like

    a volunteer, s if he wanted to do of his ow n pleasure what he needed

    ;n o

    command to do.This would be to forget the discipline ofreason and

    to pretend to be

    sovereign

    in the

    Kingdom

    of Ends, not merelya subject

    in it. On the other

    band,

    he

    might reply that

    he did his

    work

    for the

    love

    of God, in

    fulfilment

    of

    God's will.

    In

    that event,

    he

    might

    be claiming

    holiness,

    a perfect

    purity

    of

    will

    and disposition, and

    this would

    be a

    self-conceit readily leading to a religious fanaticism. The only safe route

    for

    man to follow is to recognise his finitude and hislimitations and take

    the moral law s the only guide in his conductThe proper moral con-

    dition whichhe can and outjht to attain is virtue, not holiness

    13

    ).The

    argument

    is typical of

    Kant's 'caution

    andhumility.

    It

    might

    be

    possible

    to be less

    cautious without being

    less humble,

    if it be less caiutious to accept more of the Gospel than Kant did. Hegel

    did accept

    more,

    but he may not have been humble

    enough.

    In criticising

    the passage in the Critique oi Practical Reason

    from

    whidi I have just

    been quoting, Hegel points

    out

    (Nohl,

    p.

    267) that Kant's exegesis

    of the

    Gospel command Love God, and they neighbour s thyself res-ts on

    taking this command out of its religious context and treating it s a

    merely moral precept. And we have already seen how Hegel, by writing

    a Life of

    Jesus

    on Kantian lines, had come to realise that

    Kant

    w as

    mistaken in

    endeavouring

    to twist the moral teaching of

    Jesus

    into the

    teadiing

    of the categorical imperative. To this insight Hegel held fast.

    He clings also,

    s

    has already been said, to his doctrine of the

    Holy

    Spirit, The

    Kingdom of God iswithin you .He can thus hold that when

    man elevates

    himself

    to the

    Christian

    religion orto the

    philosophy which

    expounds explicitly the contentofthat religion,the

    chasm

    between trans-

    cendence and imm anenceisbridged,and he attainsunityandlivessingle-

    mindedly Enc. 234,

    Zusatz)

    in the rational order which is

    from ever-

    lasting toeverlasting and inwhich all men find fll satisfactionby living

    its

    laws.

    In other words this ethical liie

    u

    is the Kingdom of God on

    earth.This

    is the key to

    Hegel's

    conception

    of

    Sittlichkeit.

    For Kant the Kingdom ofEnds remains an

    ideal?

    but fo r Hegel it is

    being

    progressively

    actualised in the process of

    history.

    along

    with

    the

    progress

    of the human spirit. Plato's Republic describes the rational

    order

    in the

    form

    in

    which

    it was

    actualised

    in

    Greece

    and so

    portrays

    the essential

    substance

    of Greek moral and political

    life

    (W .VIII. 17).

    Since his day

    f

    owing

    chiefly

    to the Christianrevelation,man has

    advanced

    K.p.V.

    PL l

    III,

    von den Triebfedern der

    r.p.V.,

    ad fin.

    79.

  • 8/11/2019 Knox -Hegel's Attitude to Kant's (Kant.1958.49.1-4.70)

    11/12

    in

    self-knowledge;

    in particular he has come to recognise himself s an

    individual, s

    a self-legislating

    moral

    will. The forms of his social

    life

    have changed accordingly; his deeper

    knowledge

    of himself is also a

    deeper knowledge of what the rational social order, or Kingdom of

    Ends

    is. And

    this knowledge Hegel expounds

    in the

    third

    part

    of the

    Philosophie des

    Rechtswhere

    the

    state described

    is no

    existing state

    but

    the rational

    substance

    ofpolitical life in the world ofHegel's day. Thus

    far has consciousness

    advanced

    (W. IX. 546). Further advances willreveal

    new

    aspects

    of the

    ideal,

    and

    pari passu

    the

    ideal will

    be

    actualised

    anew in a higher form still. Deeper

    self-knowledge

    is at the same time

    a deeper knowledge of the will of God -and it is.achieved step by step

    along with the

    further

    realisation of God's purpose on earth. Hegel's

    conception

    of

    Sittlichkeit

    might thus be described s a philosophical

    distillation

    of a religioois

    insight into

    the

    Kingdom

    o f

    God.

    The

    Kingdom

    of Ends is not an ideal

    towards

    which we ought.to struggle

    ad

    infinitum

    without ever reaching it; it is already present s the rational essence of

    social and political

    life,

    so that, given religious

    faith

    or philosophical

    insight, we can live within it here and now.

    Nevertheless

    it seems plain that it is for religious

    faith

    -alone that

    ought

    gives

    place to is , and

    then

    only fitfully. Hegel seeks to out-

    soar the limitations ofhuman life and to live in arealm where all conflict

    has been

    overcome,

    but can he succeed? Consider,

    for

    example, one of

    the

    contradiotions

    which

    he finds in

    moral experience;

    the

    categorical

    imperative isUniversal, while,a given duty is particular, and there may

    be difficulty in deciding what precise act here and now is our duty,

    because duties m ay

    confliot Enc.

    508).

    Kemt

    did not overlook the

    problem, but his treatment of it is more

    bold

    than convincing: Two

    opposite

    rules

    cannot be necessary at the same time, but if it is a duty

    to act

    according

    to one of them it is

    then

    inconsistent

    with duty

    to act

    according to the other; i t follows that a conflict of duties is in-

    conceivable

    14

    ). Even if it be granted that one act and one only is m y

    duty

    in a

    given

    Situation,

    so

    that

    one

    rule

    and one

    mle

    only

    is

    necessary

    therein, Ka n t is not telling us how on his principles we ought to decide

    in a given Situation which of two maxims, both conformable to the

    categorical imperative, we are to adopt if t h e Situation is such that we

    cannot act on

    both,

    though it is situations of this kind which give rise

    to the most

    acute

    moral perplexity, It may be

    held

    that the task of a moral

    philosopher

    is to say

    what duty

    is and not to

    teil

    me

    what

    my

    duty

    is

    here and now, but is this answer open to Kant who said that no far-

    reaching penetration

    is

    required

    to

    discover what

    my

    duty

    is: I

    have

    but

    to ask

    myself

    whether I can will that my

    maxim

    should also be a uni-

    versal

    law?

    15

    ).

    The difficulty may be

    specially acute

    for

    Kant

    who may

    have over-

    emphasisedthe

    place

    of

    ,rule or

    law in

    ethics.

    But it may be

    asked whether

    the difficulty is.^ny less acute

    for

    Hegel. In a

    perfect

    world the conflict

    of duties which is characteristic of moral experience m ay disappear, but

    14

    ) Metaphysik

    der

    Sitten

    Pt.

    l.Einleitung in die Md.S.,

    IV.

    )

    e.g. Grundlegung section I, and K.p.V. I. I. 4.

  • 8/11/2019 Knox -Hegel's Attitude to Kant's (Kant.1958.49.1-4.70)

    12/12

    even

    if

    marriage

    and a

    Professional oalling provide instances

    of an ex-

    perience in

    whidi law

    and inclination coincide and the

    thought

    of

    duty

    vanishes, m ay these

    tw o

    spheres

    not conflict? In this imperfect

    world

    emergencies

    occur

    -and in one of

    them

    Professional duty may have to

    be

    sacrificed

    on the

    altar

    of

    marital

    duty

    r

    or

    vice versa.

    In

    such

    an emer-

    gency is vanishes -and ought reappears.

    Hegel

    knew

    this perfectly

    well,

    even if

    his published writings often

    give

    a different

    impression.

    His

    conception

    ofSittlichkeitderives, I

    have

    been arguing, from

    the

    essay

    on The

    Spirit

    o

    Christianity,

    and the final

    sentence of

    that

    essay reads (Nohl, 342):The fate in this world of the

    ideal which Jesus taught is that Church and State

    r

    worship and life,

    piety and virtue,

    spiritual

    and mundane action, can never dissolve into

    cne .

    In

    other

    words,

    the

    fusion of

    morality with religion

    in a

    higher

    sphere

    of Sittlichkeit

    remains

    an

    ideal.

    The

    saint

    and the

    philosopher,

    however

    confident

    their

    faith or profound

    their

    insight,

    are

    still

    human

    beings, and the world in which human beings

    live

    is not the world of

    Hegel's Wirklichkeit but the

    imperfect

    and often

    irrational world

    of

    ReaJifi.

    However happy Hegel

    was in his family

    circle

    or in his

    pro-

    fessional

    work

    r

    however well ordered his

    life

    in these spheres, however

    secure

    his religious faith and however

    unruffled,

    in his study, his

    philo-

    sophic calm, the world of

    Realitt

    pressed hardly

    enough

    on him when

    he left his study for the University ofBerlin and

    found

    himself involved

    in difficulties

    with colleagues

    s

    unloving

    s

    they were irrational. When

    more than one

    privat-docent

    of his

    acquaintance

    was

    dismissed

    by the

    government

    s

    politically suspect, Hegel was far

    from

    resigned and far

    from inactive.

    And his

    action

    was on the

    plane

    of Moralitt. In the

    last

    resort Sittlichkeit

    remains for him just s rnuch an ideal s the

    Kingdom

    of

    Ends

    did for Kant , and it is an

    ideal

    of the

    same sort,

    one

    with

    a

    religious basis. No doubt the ideal was present in the real world

    s

    its

    essential

    substance,

    but

    could

    Kant

    not

    have s-aid

    the

    same about

    the

    Kingdom of Ends, which after all was not merely a far-off divine event

    but an

    operative

    ideal

    in the

    midst

    of

    human society? Hegel

    might

    say

    that Kant,

    like

    Moses,

    only

    saw the

    promised land,

    while he

    himself

    lived in it As

    philosopher

    or

    believer

    he may

    have done,

    but in

    practical

    ffairs

    and in education he was well enough aware that

    imperfection

    existed

    and ought to be

    11

    removed. Kants ethics

    had not

    been

    trans-

    cended,

    still less

    discarded;

    This is nowhere more clear than in Hegel's educational practice, it

    is

    here that

    his

    dependence

    on

    Kant's ethics

    is

    most obvious

    and most

    complete.

    When

    his fiancee had to be

    taught that happiness

    was not

    man's

    diief

    aim,

    he addressed a long letter to her

    which,

    s

    Glckner

    Hegel, L

    309)says would

    do

    honour

    to

    any Kantian .

    As

    Rector

    of the

    Gymnasium

    a t Nrnberg,

    he

    taught philosophy

    to his

    pupils,

    and his

    lecture notes have

    survived.

    The seyenty printed pages (W.

    XV IIL

    376)

    summarising

    his instruction to the JuniorClassonLaw,

    Duty,

    andR eligion

    contain the longest and the

    clearest

    exppsition which he has provided

    of his ethics. But for their conciseness they might almost have been

    written

    by the

    author

    of the

    Metaphysik der Sitten


Recommended