+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Lec. 1 of 19/Pg. 1 of 26 MA-101/2018 Preliminaries

Lec. 1 of 19/Pg. 1 of 26 MA-101/2018 Preliminaries

Date post: 16-Apr-2022
Category:
Upload: others
View: 1 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend
26
Lec. 1 of 19/Pg. 1 of 26 MA-101/2018 Preliminaries 1. Natural numbers or Counting numbers : N = {1, 2, 3,...}. (a) Addition is closed, associative and commutative. (b) Multiplication is closed, associative and commuta- tive. 1 is the unique multiplicative identity. (c) Multiplication distributes over addition. (d) There is no additive identity. We cannot talk of additive inverses. (e) There are no multiplicative inverses except for 1. (f) Principle of mathematical induction is valid, viz., Assume P (n) is a well-defined statement for each natural number n which is either true or false. If (i) P (1) is true and (ii) For each natural k, P (k) true implies P (k + 1) true, then: P (n) is true for each natural n. (g) There is an order relation 1 < 2 < 3 < ··· (h) {Well–ordering principle} Every non-empty subset of naturals has a least element. (i) ...... many other derived/inferred properties. (j) Subtraction? 2. Integers : Z = {1, 2, 3,..., 0, -1, -2, -3,...}. (a) Addition is closed, associative and commutative. 0 is the unique additive identity. (b) Multiplication is closed, associative and commuta- tive. 1 is the unique multiplicative identity. (c) Multiplication distributes over addition. (d) Every integer has a unique additive inverse. (e) There are no multiplicative inverses except for ±1. (f) There is an order relation ···- 3 < -2 < -1 < 0 < 1 < 2 < 3 < ··· (g) Subtraction is a closed operation. (h) ...... many other derived/inferred properties (i) Principle of mathematical induction? (j) Does every non-empty subset of integers have a least element? (k) Division? 3. Rationals : Q = {1, 2, 3,..., 0, -1, -2, -3,... 1 2 , 3 2 ,..., - 1 2 , - 3 2 ,..., 1 3 , 2 3 ,..., - 1 3 , - 2 3 ,..., }. (a) Addition is closed, associative and commutative. 0 is the unique additive identity. (b) Multiplication is closed, associative and commuta- tive. 1 is the unique multiplicative identity. (c) Multiplication distributes over addition. (d) Every rational has a unique additive inverse. (e) Every non–zero integer has a unique multiplicative inverse. (f) There is an order relation ... (g) Subtraction is a closed operation. (h) Division of a rational by any non-zero rational is possible (i) ...... many other derived/inferred properties 4. Despite earlier education on these matters, who can prove: (a) -1 times -1 equals +1 (b) 2 3 ÷ 5 7 = 2·7 3·5 5. Fundamental drawback: Negative numbers and Rationals were introduced through notation! 6. How to rectify? Study Robert Anderson’s Set theory and construction of numbers or equivalents or wikipedia 7. A very brief hint: (a) Put equivalence relation on N × N where (a, b) (c, d) if a + d = b + c to get equivalence classes as integers. So, the integer -2 is the equivalence class [(5, 3)] (b) Put equivalence relation on Z × Z \{0} where (p, q) (r, s) if ps = qr to get equivalence classes as rationals. So, the rational -2 3 is the equivalence class [(-2, 3)]
Transcript
Page 1: Lec. 1 of 19/Pg. 1 of 26 MA-101/2018 Preliminaries

Lec. 1 of 19/Pg. 1 of 26 MA-101/2018 Preliminaries

1. Natural numbers or Counting numbers : N = {1, 2, 3, . . .}.

(a) Addition is closed, associative and commutative.

(b) Multiplication is closed, associative and commuta-tive. 1 is the unique multiplicative identity.

(c) Multiplication distributes over addition.

(d) There is no additive identity. We cannot talk ofadditive inverses.

(e) There are no multiplicative inverses except for 1.

(f) Principle of mathematical induction is valid, viz.,Assume P (n) is a well-defined statement for each

natural number n which is either true or false. If(i) P (1) is true and (ii) For each natural k, P (k)true implies P (k + 1) true, then: P (n) is true foreach natural n.

(g) There is an order relation 1 < 2 < 3 < · · ·(h) {Well–ordering principle} Every non-empty subset

of naturals has a least element.

(i) . . . . . . many other derived/inferred properties.

(j) Subtraction?

2. Integers : Z = {1, 2, 3, . . . , 0,−1,−2,−3, . . .}.

(a) Addition is closed, associative and commutative. 0is the unique additive identity.

(b) Multiplication is closed, associative and commuta-tive. 1 is the unique multiplicative identity.

(c) Multiplication distributes over addition.

(d) Every integer has a unique additive inverse.

(e) There are no multiplicative inverses except for ±1.

(f) There is an order relation · · ·−3 < −2 < −1 < 0 <

1 < 2 < 3 < · · ·

(g) Subtraction is a closed operation.

(h) . . . . . . many other derived/inferred properties

(i) Principle of mathematical induction?

(j) Does every non-empty subset of integers have aleast element?

(k) Division?

3. Rationals : Q = {1, 2, 3, . . . , 0,−1,−2,−3, . . . 12 ,32 , . . . ,−

12 ,−

32 , . . . ,

13 ,

23 , . . . ,−

13 ,−

23 , . . . , }.

(a) Addition is closed, associative and commutative. 0is the unique additive identity.

(b) Multiplication is closed, associative and commuta-tive. 1 is the unique multiplicative identity.

(c) Multiplication distributes over addition.

(d) Every rational has a unique additive inverse.

(e) Every non–zero integer has a unique multiplicative

inverse.

(f) There is an order relation . . .

(g) Subtraction is a closed operation.

(h) Division of a rational by any non-zero rational ispossible

(i) . . . . . . many other derived/inferred properties

4. Despite earlier education on these matters, who can prove:

(a) −1 times −1 equals +1 (b) 23 ÷

57 = 2·7

3·5

5. Fundamental drawback: Negative numbers and Rationals were introduced through notation!

6. How to rectify? Study Robert Anderson’s Set theory and construction of numbers or equivalents or wikipedia

7. A very brief hint:

(a) Put equivalence relation on N×N where (a, b) ∼ (c, d) if a+ d = b+ c to get equivalence classes as integers.So, the integer −2 is the equivalence class [(5, 3)]

(b) Put equivalence relation on Z×Z \ {0} where (p, q) ∼ (r, s) if ps = qr to get equivalence classes as rationals.So, the rational −23 is the equivalence class [(−2, 3)]

Page 2: Lec. 1 of 19/Pg. 1 of 26 MA-101/2018 Preliminaries

Lec. 1 of 19/Pg. 2 of 26 MA-101/2018 Real Numbers: Bachmann’s Construction

1. Fundamental Question:

What is the set of numbers which is sufficient to measure physical quantity like ‘Length’? [and likewise Mass andTime]

2. More precisely: What magical set M do we need so that there is a one-to-one correspondence between elementsof M and points on a idealized physical straight line L?

Attempted answers: Naturals, Integers, Rationals . . . all necessary but insufficient!

3. Recall that square root of 2 is not a rational number. Inspired by this we have an incomplete answer: Add√2,√

3, . . .−√

2,−√

3, . . . 1√2, 1√

3, . . . ,− 1√

2,− 1√

3, . . . , 3

√2, 3√

3, . . .???

4. Some tools: Pick a stick and call it of ‘standard’ length, say 1 foot or 1 metre or 1 unit length or merely 1. Bytrial and error, take two sticks of equal length [ equal as far as you can see with eye, magniying glass, microscopeetc. ] and line them up and match with the standard. Then each of these has length 1

2 . Likewise other fractionallengths. Including lengths of 1

10 ,1

100 ,1

1000 , . . .

5. Now by experience we can say a measurement of the length ` of a stick is between 1 and 2 metres, is between 1.4and 1.5 metres, is between 1.41 and 1.42 metres, etc. . . .

6. Mathematically a measurement is an interval I1 = [s1, b1] where s1 and b1 are rational numbers and we implicitlyassume that s1 < b1 and we want to indicate that the length ` is between the smaller number s1 and the biggernumber b1.

7. Second measurement is an interval I2 = [s2, b2] where s2 and b2 are rational numbers. It is an improvement overthe first if and only if I1 ⊃ I2.

8. A lab measurement for length is thus a finite sequence of intervals with rational endpoints such that I1 ⊃ I2 ⊃I3 ⊃ · · · ⊃ In, for some natural number n.

9. What is a perfect measurement for length? Is it an infinte sequence of intervals [s1, b1] ⊃ [s2, b2] ⊃ [s3, b3] ⊃ · · · ⊃· · · , such that:

(a) s1 ≤ s2 ≤ s3 ≤ · · · and b1 ≥ b2 ≥ b3 ≥ · · · ? –or –

(b) s1 < s2 < s3 < · · · and b1 > b2 > b3 > · · · ? –or –

(c) ?

10. A perfect measurement for length is an infinte sequence of intervals [s1, b1] ⊃ [s2, b2] ⊃ [s3, b3] ⊃ · · · ⊃ · · · , suchthat:

(a) For each natural number k, there is a natural number n such that width of In = bn − sn < 110k

.

(b) Equivalently, for each positive rational number ε, [no matter how small], there there is a natural number nsuch that width of In = bn − sn < ε.

(c) Equivalently, “limit” of widths of interval, limn→∞width (In) = 0.

11. Can two perfect measurements represent the same length? If so, under what conditions? Two perfect measure-ments I1 ⊃ I2 ⊃ I3 ⊃ · · · ⊃ · · · and J1 ⊃ J2 ⊃ J3 ⊃ · · · ⊃ · · · are equivalent if for each natural number n, there isa natural k such that Jk ⊂ In and vice-versa. Equivalently, if In ∩ Jn is non-empty for each natural n.

12. Real numbers are exactly equivalence classes of perfect measurements. The set of real numbers is denoted by R.

13. Some hints: How to add, subtract, multiply, divide? How to put order relation? How to prove some properties ofthese operations and of the order relation?

14. Short-cut: Axioms

Page 3: Lec. 1 of 19/Pg. 1 of 26 MA-101/2018 Preliminaries

Lec. 1 of 19/Pg. 3 of 26 MA-101/2018 Real Numbers: Axioms

1. Axioms for the complete ordered field R.

(a) There is a function f+ : R× R→ R, called the addition function. Assume four axioms about addition, viz.,commutativity, associativity, existence of an identity and existence of an additive inverse for each real.Inferences:

i. Prove that there is a unique additive identity. Denote it by 0 and call it zero.

ii. Prove that every real has a unique additive inverse. Denote the additive inverse of a real a by −a.

(b) There is a function f× : R × R → R, called the multiplication function. Assume four axioms about multi-plication, viz., commutativity, associativity, existence of an identity and existence of a multiplicative inversefor each real not equal to zero.Inferences:

i. Prove that there is a unique multiplicative identity. Denote it by 1 and call it one.

ii. Prove that every real not equal to zero has a unique multiplicative inverse. Denote the multiplicativeinverse of a non–zero real a by 1/a.

(c) Multiplication distributes over addition.

(d) There exists a non–empty subset, P ⊂ R, called the set of positive real numbers which is closed under additionand multiplication. Further given any real x, exactly one and no more of the following is true:

(N) −x ∈ P(Z) x = 0

(P ) x ∈ P.

Further definitions and inferences:

i. Given any reals a and b, define a < b if and only if b+ (−a) ∈ P. Say a ≤ b if either a < b or a = b.

ii. Given a subset S ⊂ R, define u ∈ R to be an upper bound of S if s ≤ u for every s ∈ S. We say a set isbounded above if it has an upper bound.

iii. Given a subset S ⊂ R, define l ∈ R to be a least upper bound of S if l is an upper bound of S and l ≤ ufor any upper bound u of S.

(e) Every non–empty subset of R which is bounded above has a least upper bound. This is the completenessaxiom.

Following is a list of some of the derived properties of R.

2. a · 0 = 0 for every a ∈ R.

3. a+ x = a+ y implies x = y. Corollary: a+ x = a implies x = 0.

4. a · x = a · y, a 6= 0 implies x = y. Corollary: a · x = a, a 6= 0 implies x = 1.

5. a · b = 0 implies a = 0 or b = 0.

6. Define subtraction of any two reals a− b := a+ (−b). It is neither commutative nor associative. However, 0 worksas the identity and every element is its own inverse. Addition and subtraction are opposites of each other, viz.,(a+ b)− b = a and (a− b) + b = a for any reals a and b.

7. Define division of any two reals a/b := a · 1b , for b 6= 0. It is neither commutative nor associative. 1 works as theidentity and every non–zero element is its own inverse. Multiplication and division are opposites of each other,viz., (a · b)/b = a and (a/b) · b = a for any reals a and b 6= 0.

8. Multiplication distributes over subtraction and division distributes over both addition and subtraction.

9. The relation ≤ is transitive, compatible with addition and compatible with multiplication.

10. For any non–zero a ∈ R, 0 < a2. Corollary: 0 < n for every natural n.

11. Archimedean Property viz., for any real number x, there exists a natural N such that x < N .

12. Density of Rationals viz., given any two real numbers x < y, there exists a rational x < r < y.

Page 4: Lec. 1 of 19/Pg. 1 of 26 MA-101/2018 Preliminaries

Lec. 2 of 19/Pg. 4 of 26 MA-101/2018 Sups and Infs

1. Give a precise definition of the maximum (and the minimum) of a finite collection of reals.

2. Is it legitimate to use the concept of max/min for infinite sets?

(a) For example, consider the set of rationals S := { nn+1 |n ∈ N}. What is the maximum of S?

(b) If there is no element u ∈ S such that s ≤ u for all s ∈ S, can you find such a u ∈ R?

Can you find all such u?

(c) Among all such u that you found, what is special about 1? What is wrong with saying 1 is the minimum ofall such u? Can you give a better definition which will pick out such a maximum (more precisely, extendedconcept of maximum) in all cases?

3. Complete a similar exercise of finding the ‘minimum’ for the set T := {1 + 1n |n ∈ N}.

4. Definitions of upper bound, lower bound and bound for a subset of reals. Definition of a bounded set. Examples.

5. Definition of supremum [sup] or least upper bound [lub] and infimum [inf] or greatest lower bound [glb] for a subsetof reals. Examples.

6. Existence of sup as guaranteed by the completeness axiom. Can you prove existence of inf using the completenessaxiom?

(a) Write statements of completeness property for naturals, integers and rationals.

(b) Show that completeness is valid for naturals and integers, but not for rationals.

7. sup and inf of a set, if they exist, are uniquely determined.

8. (a) {Anything less than the supremum is not an upper bound}Proposition: If h is the supremum of S ⊂ R, then for any real ε > 0, h− ε is not an upper bound for S.

(b) {Anything more than the infimum is not a lower bound}Proposition: If m is the infimum of S ⊂ R, then for any real ε > 0, m+ ε is not a lower bound for S.

9. (a) {If anything less than an upper bound is not an upper bound, then it is the least upper bound}Proposition: Let S ⊂ R be non-empty and let u be an upper bound for S. If for every real ε > 0, there existsa t ∈ S such that u− ε < t ≤ u, then u = supS.

(b) {If anything more than a lower bound is not a lower bound, then it is the greatest lower bound}Proposition: Let S ⊂ R be non-empty and let ` be a lower bound for S. If for every real ε > 0, there existsa t ∈ S such that ` ≤ t < `+ ε, then ` = inf S.

10. Proof of Archimedean Property using completeness.

If there is no natural number bigger than a given real number r0, the set of naturals is bounded above by r0.Using completeness, let s be the supremum of naturals. Then, s − 1 is not an upper bound for the naturals andhence there is a natural n such that s − 1 < n. This implies s < n + 1 with n + 1 a natural greater than s, thesupremeum of naturals: a contradiction.

11. Proof of density of rationals: Read up

12. Discussion topic:

Archimedean Property can be interpreted simply as: ‘there is no greatest real number’.

Question: Is there a smallest real number?

More interesting: Is there a smallest positive real number?

Isn’t ∞ the greatest real number?

Page 5: Lec. 1 of 19/Pg. 1 of 26 MA-101/2018 Preliminaries

Lec. 3 of 19/Pg. 5 of 26 MA-101/2018 Motivation for sequences and series

1. Finite sequence example to illustrate growth of terms where finite analysis is adequate: The size of economy ofUSA is $15 trillion, while that of India is $1.5 trillion. US economy grows at a rate of 3%pa while India’s economygrows at a rate of 8%. Will the Indian economy ever overtake US’ economy? If so when?

2. Pocket money: Would you rather have 1 crore rupeesfor a month or a paisa doubled every-day for a month?

Hint:

n days in a month Rupees: 1100

∑nk=0 2k

28 26,84,354.5529 53,68,709.1130 1,07,37,418.2331 2,14,74,836.47

3. A corrupt telecom minister has set up a kickback planwhere he gets 1 Rupee for the first phone call, 1/2 of aRupee for the second call, 1/3 of a rupee for the thirdand so on. Will he ever become a crorepati?

Hint:

n∑n

k=11k

1 110 2.928968254100 5.18737751761000 7.485470860610000 9.787606036100000 12.09014612991000000 14.392726722910000000 16.6953113659100000000 18.99789641391000000000 21.300481502310000000000 22.064778

4. Zeno’s Paradox: World famous runner Achilles who runs at a speed of 1Km/min is pitted against a tortoise whichcrawls at a speed of 100m/min. They start a race with the tortoise given a head start of 1Km. By the time (1min)Achilles runs 1Km, the tortoise has moved 100m. In the next 1/10 of a minute, Achilles covers the latter 100m,but the tortoise has moved 10m. In the next 1/100 of a minute, Achilles covers this 10m – but the tortoise coversanother 1m. And so on for ever. If Achilles is always catching up with the marks left by tortoise at min., 1+1/10of a minute, 1+1/10+1/100 of a minute and so on, how can Achilles ever overtake the tortoise?

5. Grandi’s series: 1− 1 + 1− 1 + 1− 1 + · · · What is the sum?

Zero? (1− 1) + (1− 1) + (1− 1) + · · · = 0 + 0 + 0 + · · · = 0

One? 1− (1− 1)− (1− 1)− (1− 1)− · · · = 1− 0− 0− 0− · · · = 1,

Half? S = 1− 1 + 1− 1 + 1− · · · and S = 1− (1− 1 + 1− 1 + 1− 1 + 1− · · · ) implies S = 1− S and S = 1/2

next Try S2 = 1− 2 + 3− 4 + 5− 6 + · · · . Add it to itself (with a shift) to get S2 +S2 = S1 so that S2 equals 1/4.

more Take S3 = 1 + 2 + 3 + 4 + · · · and S3−S2 = 0 + 4 + 0 + 8 + 0 + 12 + · · · = 4S3 and hence S3 = −1/12. Really?

6. Before you analyse the latter three questions, first prove that the multi–variable sum function Σ : R×R×· · ·×R→ Rcan be defined for finitely many variables. Using induction establish that this sum is both independent of orderingof the variables and the bracketing which dictates the partial sums.

7. The three questions raised, viz., Zeno’s paradox and about the corrupt minister and the Grandi’s series demand adefinition for a sum of infinitely many reals. What would be your definition for the infinite sum a1 + a2 + a3 + · · ·where each an is real?

8. On can define a sequence of partial sums viz., σ1 = a1, σ2 = a1 + a2, σ3 = a1 + a2 + a3, . . . and see whether thesequence of numbers σ1, σ2, σ3, . . . is getting closer and closer or approaching a fixed real number. This will beformalized via Cauchy’s definition in the next lecture.

9. Discussion topics:

Page 6: Lec. 1 of 19/Pg. 1 of 26 MA-101/2018 Preliminaries

Lec. 3 of 19/Pg. 6 of 26 MA-101/2018 Motivation for sequences and series

(a) In how many ways can you add 2 numbers? 3 numbers? 4? 5? . . .

Answers: 1, 2, 5, 14, 42, 132, 429, 1430, 4862, 16796, 58786, 208012, 742900, 2674440, 9694845, 35357670,129644790, 477638700, 1767263190, 6564120420, 24466267020, 91482563640, 343059613650, 1289904147324,4861946401452,..

Page 7: Lec. 1 of 19/Pg. 1 of 26 MA-101/2018 Preliminaries

Lec. 4 of 19/Pg. 7 of 26 MA-101/2018 Cauchy’s definition

1. Definition and notation for a sequence.

2. Given a sequence (an), there is no concept of the eventual value of (an) – simply because we have not defined a∞.However, we have some idea of whether the given sequence (an) is or is not getting closer and closer to a fixedreal number a. Denote this by an → a. Let us attempt to give a criterion which should satisfy the conditions:

(a) in every example where we believe an → a, the criterion should be true,

(b) in every example where we believe an 6→ a the criterion should be false and

(c) there should be no need to modify the criterion in the face of new examples.

3. (a) Take a small real number, say, ε1 = 1.Criterion 1: We say an → a if there exists a natural number N1 such that |an − a| < ε1 = 1 for all n ≥ N1.Note that this criterion demands that all but a finite number of terms of the sequence be within a distanceof 1 from a.This criterion works in proving: (i) every constant sequence an = a satisfies an → a, (ii) ( 1

n) → 0 and even(iii) (−1)n 6→ −1, 0, 1. However, consider the sequence bn = b+ 1

2 · (−1)n for all n. We do not believe (bn) isgetting closer and closer to b, but Criterion 1 makes bn → b.

(b) Perhaps ε1 = 1 is not small enough. Take ε2 = 12 .

Criterion 2: We say an → a if there exists a natural number N2 such that |an − a| < ε2 = 12 for all n ≥ N2.

This criterion works in cases (i)–(iii) listed above. This criterion works in the case of (bn) given above toshow bn 6→ b. So Criterion 2 is better than Criterion 1. However, consider the sequence cn = c + 1

4 · (−1)n

for all n. We do not believe (cn) is getting closer and closer to c, but Criterion 2 makes cn → c.

(c) Perhaps ε2 = 12 is not small enough. Take ε3 = 1

3 .Criterion 3: We say an → a if there exists a natural number N3 such that |an − a| < ε3 = 1

3 for all n ≥ N3.This criterion works in all the cases Criteria 1 & 2 work given above. It also works to show cn 6→ c. However,consider the sequence dn = d + 1

6 · (−1)n for all n. We do not believe (dn) is getting closer and closer to d,but Criterion 3 is true here.

(d) Perhaps ε3 = 13 is not small enough. Take ε0 > 0 to be some fixed small real number.

Criterion 0: We say an → a if there exists a natural number N0 such that |an − a| < ε0 for all n ≥ N0.This criterion works in all cases where Criteria 1–3 work, if ε0 <

13 . Also, one can show (dn) 6→ d if ε0 ≤ 1

6 .However, consider the sequence an = a + ε0

2 · (−1)n for all n. We do not believe (an) is getting closer andcloser to a, but Criterion 0 is true here.

4. Observation: Each of the criteria 0–3 has to be necessarily true in the examples we have of sequences approachinga real number. Whereas, on the contrary, given any fixed criterion among them, there is an example for a sequencefor which the criterion believes that the sequence approaches a real number – while we do not believe this to beso. Moreover, varying the value of ε0, Criterion 0 is actually a collection of infinitely many criteria.

5. Thus we are faced with a situation where infinitely many criteria are necessary for our notion of a sequence gettingcloser and closer to a real number, whereas, no single one of them is sufficient. Cauchy gathered all the conditionstogether to capture our notion in the definition below.

6. Cauchy’s definition: We say an → a if (and only if) the following is true:For any given real ε > 0, there exists a natural N such that |an − a| < ε for all n ≥ N .

7. Constant sequence, Tail of a sequence

8. We claim the following limits

(a) ( 1n)→ 0

(b) ( 1n2 )→ 0

(c) ( 1np )→ 0 for each fixed natural p

(d) ( 11+nα)→ 0 for each fixed real α > 0

(e) (bn)→ 0 for every fixed real −1 < b < 1

(f) (c1/n)→ 1 for every fixed real c > 0

(g) (n1/n)→ 1

Brief hints: Given any real ε > 0, we have 1ε as a real number and there exists a natural number N such that

1ε < N , which implies that for all n > N , we have 1

n <1N < ε.

Page 8: Lec. 1 of 19/Pg. 1 of 26 MA-101/2018 Preliminaries

Lec. 4 of 19/Pg. 8 of 26 MA-101/2018 Cauchy’s definition1

1+nα <1nα

Since 0 < b < 1, we can write b = 1/(1 + a), where a := (1/b) − 1 so that a > 0. By Bernoulli’s Inequality, wehave (1 + a)n > 1 + na. Hence 0 < bn = 1

(1+a)n ≤1

1+na <1na

9. Prove (−1)n does not converge, i.e., diverges.

10. Prove limn→∞

√n+ 1−

√n =?

11. Template for applying Cauchy’s definition to prove an → a:

Rough Work Credit worthy work

START: Given a real ε > 0 START: Given a real ε > 0

DO SOMETHING: ? ? SAY: My N is equal to . . .

FIND: A natural N =? ASSUMING: n ≥ NDO SOMETHING∗ ? ?

GET FINALLY: |an − a| < ε

Page 9: Lec. 1 of 19/Pg. 1 of 26 MA-101/2018 Preliminaries

Lec. 5 of 19/Pg. 9 of 26 MA-101/2018 Limit properties

1. Uniqueness of limits. If an → a, b, then a = b. Proof: Use the lemma: if a non-negative number issmaller than every positive number, it has to be zero.

Can you make |a − b| smaller than every positive num-ber?

2. If two sequences converge to the same real number, are the two sequences ‘equal’? If two sequences converge tothe same real number, do they have to be on ‘different’ sides of the limit?

3. A sequence X = (xn) is bounded if the set {xn|n ∈ N} is bounded or equivalently there exists a real B such thatfor every natural n, |xn| ≤ B. Picture.

4. Why can’t one take B = max(x1, x2, x3, . . .)?

5. Proposition: Convergent implies bounded. Proof:

Method 1 Except for finitely many terms, all others clus-ter around the limit.

Method 2 Can you explain when an 6→ a?

6. Building new sequences from one given sequence (an):

(a) Constant multiple sequence (c · an) for some real c

(b) Square sequence (a2n)

(c) Cube sequence (a3n)

(d) p–th power sequence (apn) for natural p. The lattercan be extended to include p = 0

(e) To extend this to all integral p, need to assumenone of the an = 0

(f) Similarly get fractional powers under additional as-sumptions, if necessary

(g) Further, let f : R→ R be any polynomial function,viz., f(x) = ckx

k+ck−1xk−1+ · · ·+c1x+c0 for real

numbers c0, c1, · · · , ck and natural k. Then (f(an))is a new sequence

(h) Fundamental question: If an → a, does f(an) →f(a)?

7. Building new sequences from two given sequences (an) and (bn):

(a) their sum (an + bn)

(b) their difference (an − bn)

(c) product (an · bn) and

(d) quotient (an/bn) [assuming none of the bn is zero]

(e) Proposition: If an → a and bn → b, then an+ bn →a+ b.

(f) Proposition: If an → a and bn → b, then an− bn →a− b.

(g) If an → a and bn → b, then an · bn → a · b.(h) If an → a and bn → b, and none of the bn = 0 and

b 6= 0, then anbn→ a

b .

(i) How about proofs of these propositions?

8. Building new sequences from more than two given sequences.

9. Discussion topic:

(a) Examples for bounded sequences which are not con-vergent.

(b) Sequences which seem to have two “limit–like”points? [NOT a formal phrase: don’t use it!]

(c) three limit–like points?

(d) four limit–like points?,. . .

(e) infinitely many?

(f) all rationals as limit–like points?

(g) all irrationals?

(h) all reals???

(i) any given subset of reals?

(j) when is a real number c, a “limit-like” point of agiven sequence an: definition?

Page 10: Lec. 1 of 19/Pg. 1 of 26 MA-101/2018 Preliminaries

Lec. 6 of 19/Pg. 10 of 26 MA-101/2018 Monotone, Bolzano & Sandwich

1. Proposition: Suppose an → a and for every natural n, an ≥ 0. Then a ≥ 0.

Picture and Proof: If a < 0, take ε = −a > 0 and get a natural N from the definition such that for all n ≥ N ,we have a − ε < an < a + ε. In particular for n = N , we get a − (−a) < aN < a + (−a) = 0 contradicting thehypothesis that aN ≥ 0.Question: If an → a and for every natural n, an > 0, then is a > 0? If an ≥ c for every n, then is a ≥ c? Similarquestions with ≤, etc..

2. Proposition: Suppose an → a and bn → b with an ≤ bn for every n. Then, a ≤ b.Picture and Proof: Apply previous proposition to the difference of given sequences.

3. Proposition: Suppose an → a and α ≤ an ≤ β. Then α ≤ a ≤ β.

Picture and Proof: Apply previous proposition to the constant sequence bn = β, etc..

4. Squeeze/Sandwich/Pinching Theorem: For three sequences, an ≤ bn ≤ cn with an → l and cn → l. Then thesequence bn converges and the limit is l.

Picture and Proof: Given a real ε > 0, find a natural N such that for every n ≥ N , both |an − a|, |bn − b| < ε.Then, −ε < an − a ≤ bn − a ≤ cn − a < ε for all n ≥ N . This proves the required.

5. Nested interval property: Let for each natural n, In be an interval of real numbers, viz., In = [an, bn] for somereal numbers an ≤ bn. Of course, each such interval is non-empty and bounded. If I1 ⊃ I2 ⊃ I3 ⊃ · · · and widthof In = bn − an → 0, then ∩∞1 In is a set with exactly one real number.

Is this property true for rational numbers?

6. Increasing, decreasing and monotone sequences. Additional qualifier: ‘strictly’

7. Every increasing sequence is bounded below. There are examples of increasing sequences which are not boundedabove. Analogous statements for decreasing sequences.

8. Whereas boundedness for a general sequence does not imply convergence, it does for the restricted class of monotonesequences.

9. Monotone Convergence Theorem: An increasing sequence which is bounded above converges to the supremum ofthe set formed by the sequence.

Picture and Proof: Let s be the supremum. Given any real ε > 0, recall s − ε is not an upper-bound of thesequence and hence there is a natural N such that s − ε < aN . What can you say about an for n ≥ N? Whereare they??

Analogous statement for decreasing sequences and a proof.

10. Given any strictly increasing sequence of naturals n1 < n2 < n3 < · · · , and a sequence of real numbers (an), thesequence (ank

) is called a subsequence of the given sequence (an).

Examples

11. Proposition: If a sequence an → a, then every subsequence ank→ a.

Contrapositive gives a divergence criterion.

12. Bolzano–Weierstrass Theorem: A bounded sequence of real numbers has a convergent subsequence.

Picture and Proof: Let I1 = [inf S, supS], where S = {an|n ∈ N}, is the set of terms of the sequence.

Set L2 = [inf S, 12(inf S+ supS)] and R2 = [12(inf S+ supS), supS]. Let A2 = {n|an ∈ L2} and B2 = {n|an ∈ R2}.At least one of A2 or B2 is infinite and if A2 is infinite, set I2 = L2 and if not, set I2 = R2.

Continue ... and apply nested interval property

Page 11: Lec. 1 of 19/Pg. 1 of 26 MA-101/2018 Preliminaries

Lec. 7 of 19/Pg. 11 of 26 MA-101/2018 Cauchy sequences

1. If we want to apply Cauchy’s definition of convergence, we need to know the limiting point in advance. However, inmany cases we may guess a sequence to be convergent without knowing the limiting point. {Example: A sequence(xn) defined by x1 = 1; x2 = 2; xn+1 = 1

2(xn + xn−1): See text for full discussion} To handle such cases, isit possible to give a criterion which, if true, would enable us to conclude convergence of the sequence? Note thatthis criterion should be in terms of the given sequence only.

2. Such a criterion was given by Cauchy. It is based on differences between terms of the sequence.

3. Before we see that condition, let us prove: If a sequence bn → b then, the sequences bn+1 − bn, bn+2 − bn, bn+3 −bn, . . .→ 0. Thus, if bn → b, then given any natural p the sequence bn+p−bn → 0. Thus if a sequence is convergent,its p–th difference sequence should converge to 0 for every natural p. Let us call this poochy for short. Thus beingpoochy is necessary for being convergent.

4. Warning: poochy is a non-standard term. Please do not use it after the end of this semester!

5. Does poochy imply convergent? The example of∑ 1

n illustrates that this is not true. We need something strongerthan poochy.

6. Cauchy found such a condition by making the difference sequences converge to zero uniformly in p. See tutorialsheet #2 for more inspiration.

7. A sequence (ck) is cauchy if for every (real) ε > 0, there exists a natural number N such that for all m,n ≥ N ,|cn − cm| < ε.

8. Proposition: Convergent implies cauchy.

Proof: Let c be the limit of a cauchy sequence (ck). Given any real ε > 0, there exists a natural number Ksuch that for all k ≥ K, |ck − c| < ε

2 . Now, using triangle inequality: For all m,n ≥ K, we have |cm − cn| =|cm − c− (cn − c)| ≤ |cm − c|+ |(cn − c)| < ε.

9. Proposition: Cauchy implies bounded.

Proof: Taking ε = 1, there exists a natural number K such that for all m,n ≥ K, |cm − cn| < 1.

Thus for all n ≥ K, −1+cK < cn < 1+cK . Set L = min(c1, c2, . . . , cK−1,−1+cK) and U = max(c1, c2, . . . , cK−1, 1+cK) and all terms of the sequence are between L and U .

10. Proposition: Cauchy implies convergent.

Proof: Given a cauchy sequence (cn), define the sequence of infimums αn := inf{ck|k ≥ n} Prove the followinginequalities

α1 ≤ α2 ≤ α3 ≤ · · · ≤ αn ≤ · · · .By the Monotone Convergence Theorem, αn → α∗ for some real α∗.

Given a positive real ε, by definition of cauchy sequence, there exists a natural L such that for all natural m,n ≥ L,we have |cm − cn| < 1

3 · ε. . . . (1)Since αn → α∗, there exists a natural M ′ such that α∗ − 1

3 · ε < αM ′ ≤ α∗. However, the sequence of infimums isincreasing and we can find a natural M ≥ max(M ′, L) such that α∗− 1

3 · ε < αM ≤ α∗, i.e., |αM −α∗| < 13 · ε.. . . (2)

Since αM + 13 · ε > αM , it is not the infimum of the set {ck|k ≥ M}. Hence, there exists a natural N ≥ M such

that αM ≤ cN < αM + 13 · ε, i.e., |cN − αM | < 1

3 · ε. . . .(3)Now, combine (1), (2) and (3) in the following.Given any natural m ≥ N , |cm − α∗| ≤ |cm − cN |+ |cN − αM |+ |αM − α∗| < ε.

11. For extra-credit:

Define the sequence of supremums (βn) by βn := sup{ck|k ≥ n}. Prove the following inequalitiesα1 ≤ α2 ≤ α3 ≤ · · · ≤ αn ≤ · · · ≤ βn ≤ · · · ≤ β3 ≤ β2 ≤ β1.

By the Monotone Convergence Theorem, βn → β∗ for some real β∗. One can prove that α∗ = β∗.

12. Remark: The α∗, β∗ in the above proof are respectively termed the lim inf and the lim sup of the given sequence.You can try to prove that a given sequence (cn) is convergent if and only if these two lim inf cn and the lim sup cnexist and are equal. This may be viewed as an alternative to cauchy’s formulation of convergence criterion.

Page 12: Lec. 1 of 19/Pg. 1 of 26 MA-101/2018 Preliminaries

Lec. 8 of 19/Pg. 12 of 26 MA-101/2018

1. Infinite series generated by a sequence, terms of the series, partial sums and sequence of partial sums, conver-gent/divergent series, sum or value of series. Notation.

2. Proof of coonvergence of geometric series∑rn = 1

1−r for |r| < 1.

Proof of divergence for r ≥ 1: Partial sums are unbounded.

Proof of divergence for r = −1: Odd and even terms of sequence of partial sums have different limits.

Proof of divergence for r < −1: ?

Simplify proofs ...

3. Telescoping series∑ 1

n(n+1) = 1.

Other examples like∑ 1

n(n+1)(n+2) = 14 .

4. n–th term test – necessary but not sufficient for convergence of a series. Proof: an = sn − sn−1.

5. As a corollary to monotone convergence theorem: A non–negative series converges if and only if the sequence ofpartial sums is bounded.Applications: 2–series converges and in general p–series for p > 1 converges by arguing on s2k−1.Harmonic series diverges by arguing s2k ≥ 1 + k

2 . By comparison, p–series diverges for 0 < p ≤ 1.

6. Cauchy criterion for series as a direct application of cauchy criterion for convergence.

7. Discussion topic:

(a) How many examples do you know where a series converges and you know the sum?

(b) Can you find “the answer” to∑∞

11n2 ?

Answer: π2

6

(c) Can you find “the answer” to∑∞

11n3 ?

Answer: “Unknown!”: What is “knowing” a real number anyway?

Only known to be rational

(d)∑∞

11n4 ?

Answer: Known: find out

(e)∑∞

11n5 ?

Answer: Not known whether rational or irrational!

(f) Read about Basel problem

Page 13: Lec. 1 of 19/Pg. 1 of 26 MA-101/2018 Preliminaries

Lec. 9 of 19/Pg. 13 of 26 MA-101/2018

1. Given two numbers a and b, they can be added in two ways, viz., a+ b and b+ a. The two answers are equal bycommutativity. Given three numbers a, b and c, they can be added in twelve ways, viz., a+ (b+ c), a+ (c+ b), b+(c + a), b + (a + c), c + (a + b), c + (b + a), (a + b) + c, (b + a) + c, (b + c) + a, (c + b) + a, (c + a) + b, (a + c) + b.These twelve answers are equal by commutativity and associativity.

2. Given any finite collection of real numbers, we expect the different ways of adding them to yield the same answer.Having proved this expectation, the coinciding answer can be defined as the sum of these numbers.

3. The axioms for reals provide a 2–input addition function f+ : R × R → R. The identity function may be taken,artificially, as the 1–input addition function. Inductively, given a natural k ≥ 3, define a k–input addition functionfrom Rk to R as a function of the form f+(g(∗ · · · ∗), h(∗ · · · ∗)) for an l–input addition function g and an m–inputaddition function h such that l+m = k and l,m ≤ k− 1. {Here, the first l components of the k component inputare fed as input to g and the remaining m components as input to h.}As an exercise, find the number of k–input addition functions. By induction, prove that any two k–input additionfunctions are equal.

4. Given a k–tuple x = (x1, x2, . . . , xk) ∈ Rk, a reordering of x is a k–tuple xϕ = (xϕ(1), xϕ(2), . . . , xϕ(k)) for abijection ϕ : {1, 2, . . . , k} → {1, 2, . . . , k}.As an exercise, find the number of reorderings of a given k–tuple. If f0 is a k–input addition function, prove thatfor any two reorderings x and y of each other, the evaluations f0(x) and f0(y) are equal.

5. Given k real numbers, a way of adding them is an evaluation f(x) of a particular k–input addition function f atx – a particular ordering of the given numbers.Find the number of ways of adding k real numbers. Prove that all such ways yield the same answer. This is calledthe sum of the given numbers. The following theorems were necessary in the steps leading up to our definition ofsum.

Finite Regrouping Theorem: Given a k tuple x ∈ Rk, f(x) = g(x) for any two k–input addition functions f and g.Finite Rearrangement Theorem: Given a k–input addition function, f , f(x) = f(y) for any two reorderings x andy of the same k–tuple.

6. Can we extend the above two theorems to infinite series?

7. Devise a definition and find an analogue of the regrouping theorem for infinite series.

8. If ϕ : N → N is a bijection, the series∑aϕ(n) is called a rearrangement of the

∑an. We explore an analogue of

rearrangement theorem for infinite series.

9. We have seen∑ 1

n diverges. How about∑ 1

2n and∑ 1

2n−1?

10. Alternating harmonic series∑ (−1)n+1

n converges. For a proof, observe that s2n is monotonically increasing ands2n+1 is monotonically decreasing. Further, 0 < s2n < s2n + 1

2n+1 = s2n+1 < 1 which implies that the even andodd partial sums are bounded and hence converge. By squeeze theorem to the same inequality, they converge tothe same limit. Finally conclude that the series is convergent.

11. Based on this example, we make the definitions: For a given series∑an, if

∑|an| converges the series converges

absolutely and if∑an converges while

∑|an| diverges, the series converges conditionally. By Cauchy’s criterion,

one sees that∑|an| converges implies

∑an converges.

12. Rearrangement theorem: If∑an converges absolutely, then every rearrangement of the series converges to the

same value. For a proof, let∑an = a, sn and tn the sequence of partial sums of the given series and its

rearrangement. Pick a natural N such that for n ≥ N , both |sn−a| < 12ε and

∑∞N |an| <

12ε are true. Let M be a

natural number such that the terms a1, a2, . . . aN appear in the rearranged partial sums tn for n ≥M . Naturally,M ≥ N . Then, for n ≥M ≥ N , we have |tn − a| ≤ |tn − sn|+ |sn − a| ≤

∑∞N |an|+

12ε < ε. Done.

13. Demonstrate that the alternating harmonic series can be rearranged to converge to any real number.

14. Statement of Riemann’s rearrangement theorem.

Page 14: Lec. 1 of 19/Pg. 1 of 26 MA-101/2018 Preliminaries

Lec. 10 of 19/Pg. 14 of 26 MA-101/2018

1. Alternating Series Test: If (zn) is monotonically decreasing sequence of non–negatives converging to zero, theseries

∑(−1)n+1zn converges. Proof is analogous to the example of alternating harmonic series. One just observes

that the even subsequence of partial sums s2n is monotonically increasing and the odd subsequence of partial sumss2n+1 is monotonically decreasing. Further 0 ≤ s2n ≤ s2n + z2n+1 = s2n+1 ≤ z1. This makes the two subsequencesbounded and hence convergent. Using z2n+1 → 0 and squeeze theorem they converge to the same value. Usingthis establish that the alternating series converges.

2. Comparison test for non–negative series. Similar one for negative series. Statement:Let 0 ≤ xn ≤ yn for n ≥ K, some natural. Then (i)

∑yn converges implies

∑xn converges. Also, (ii)

∑xn

diverges implies∑yn diverges.

How about if∑xn converges or

∑yn diverges?

3. Limit comparison test: (xn) and (yn) are positive sequences and r = lim xnyn

exists. Then:(i) If r 6= 0,

∑xn is convergent if and only if

∑yn is convergent.

Proof: Take ε = 12r. There exists a natural K such that n ≥ K implies |xnyn − r| <

12r, i.e., 1

2r <xnyn< 3

2r whence

(12r)yn < xn < (32r)yn. Now apply comparison test.(ii) If r = 0, and

∑yn is convergent then

∑xn is convergent.

Proof: Take ε = 1. There exists a natural K such that n ≥ K implies −1 < 0 < xnyn

< 1 whence 0 < xn < yn.Now apply comparison test.

4. Examples:∑ 1

n2+n+1by comparison with

∑ 1n2 . Limit comparison of

∑ 1n2−n+1

with∑ 1

n2 . Limit comparison of∑ 13√n+9

with∑ 1

3√n

5. Value Root Test: Let (an) be a sequence of reals.

Suppose for some real r, |an|1n ≤ r for all n ≥ K for some natural K. If r < 1, the series

∑an (and

∑|an|) are

convergent. For a proof, compare with geometric series.Suppose |an|

1n ≥ 1 for all n ≥ K for some natural K. Then the series

∑an (and

∑|an|) are divergent. For a

proof, use n–th term test.

6. Limit Root Test: Suppose (an) be a sequence of reals such that r = lim |an|1n exists.

If r < 1, then∑an (and

∑|an|) are convergent.

If r > 1, then∑an (and

∑|an|) are divergent.

7. Value Ratio Test: Let (an) be a sequence of non–zero reals.

Suppose that for some real r,∣∣∣an+1

an

∣∣∣ ≤ r for all n ≥ K for some natural K. If r < 1, the series∑an (and

∑|an|)

are convergent. For a proof, compare with geometric series.

Suppose∣∣∣an+1

an

∣∣∣ ≥ 1 for all n ≥ K for some natural K. Then, the series∑an (and

∑|an|) are divergent. For a

proof, use n–th term test.

8. Limit Ratio Test: Suppose that (an) is a sequence of non–zero reals such that r = lim∣∣∣an+1

an

∣∣∣ exists.

If r < 1, then∑an (and

∑|an|) are convergent.

If r > 1, then∑an (and

∑|an|) are divergent.

Page 15: Lec. 1 of 19/Pg. 1 of 26 MA-101/2018 Preliminaries

Lec. 11 of 19/Pg. 15 of 26 MA-101/2018

1. An IITian is smart if there exists some day N of his (indefinite) stay in IIT such that for any day n ≥ N , theIITian solves tutorial sheet problems on day n. Who is a non–smart IITian?

2. An IITian is super smart if there exists some day N of her stay in IIT such that for any day n ≥ N , if n is aworking day, the IITian solves tutorial sheet problems on day n. Who is a non–super smart IITian?

3. Examples of graphs of functions with and without breaks at a certain point of their domain.

4. (SC) Sequential criterion: for every sequence xn → c, assuming xn ∈ domain(f), it should be true that f(xn) →f(c).OPP.(SC): there exists a sequence xn → c such that xn ∈ domain(f) but f(xn) 6→ f(c).

5. (WC) Weierstrass criterion: for any real ε > 0, there exists a real δ > 0 such that for every x satisfying |x− c| < δ,if x ∈ domain(f), it should be true that |f(x)− f(c)| < ε.OPP. (WC): there exists a real ε0 > 0 such that for any real δ > 0, there exists an xδ ∈ domain(f) which satisfies|xδ − c| < δ but it is true that |f(xδ)− f(c)| ≥ ε0.

6. Proof of OPP.(WC) implies OPP.(SC). This proves (SC) implies (WC).

7. Proof of (WC) implies (SC).

8. Domain: A subset A ⊂ R is a domain if for every c ∈ A, at least one one of the following three types of sets[c, c+ α0), (c− α0, c+ α0) or (c− α0, c] ⊂ A for some real α0 > 0.

9. Suppose f : A→ R is a function on a domain A. Say f is continuous at c by (SC) ≡ (WC). Say f is continuousif it is continuous at every point of its domain.

10. In domain(f), ‘domain’ associates an object to a function f . In a subset A ⊂ R being a domain, ‘domain’ is anadjective for subsets of reals.

11. Proof that the constant, identity and square functions are continuous by (WC).

12. Exercise: continuity of power, modulus, exponential and root functions.

Page 16: Lec. 1 of 19/Pg. 1 of 26 MA-101/2018 Preliminaries

Lec. 12 of 19/Pg. 16 of 26 MA-101/2018

1. Rules about continuity of resultant function at a point/over domain with respect to operations of addition,subtraction, multiplication, division and composition.

2. Applications: Continuity of polynomial and rational functions.

3. Non-traditional functions like Dirichlet’s and Thomae’s examples.

4. Thousand Dollar Challenge: Find a function from reals to reals which is discontinuous at irrationals and continuousat rationals.

5. A function is bounded if its range is bounded. Supremum of a function is the supremum of its range. Likewiseinfimum.

6. A function has an absolute maximum if it attains its supremum. Likewise for absolute minimum.

7. Examples for functions which are unbounded and do not attain their sup/inf on R, on half–rays, on boundedintervals of various kinds.

8. Failure to produce such examples on intervals of type [a, b] for real a ≤ b.

Page 17: Lec. 1 of 19/Pg. 1 of 26 MA-101/2018 Preliminaries

Lec. 13 of 19/Pg. 17 of 26 MA-101/2018

1. Intermediate Value Property for a subset of R. An interval is a non–empty subset of R satisfying the INTERme-diate VALue Property. Examples for intervals.

2. Exhibition theorem for intervals: Every interval is of exactly one of the following forms: (1) {a} = [a, a] (2) [a, b](3) (a, b] (4) [a, b) (5) (a, b) (6) (−∞, b] (7) [a,∞) (8) (−∞, b) (9) (a,∞) (10) (−∞,∞) = R, for some reals a < b.Proof: Use sup/inf.

3. IVP and Continuity: Recall that a subset A ⊂ R is a domain if for every a ∈ A, there exists an interval I 6= [a, a]of R such that a ∈ I ⊂ A. We expand our study of continuous functions to those defined on domains.

(a) A continuous function preserves IVP.

(b) A continuous function takes an interval to an interval.

(c) (Weak Preservation of Intervals Theorem) If f : I → R is a continuous function defined on an interval I,then Range(f)=f(I) is an interval.

(d) (Strong Preservation of Intervals Theorem) If f : A → R is a continuous function on a domain A, then forany interval I ⊂ A, Range(f)=f(I) is an interval.

(e) (Bolzano’s Intermediate Value Theorem) Let f : A → R be a continuous function on a domain A such thatthe interval [a, b] ⊂ A. Case (I) For any real k satisfying f(a) < v < f(b) there exists a real i ∈ [a, b] suchthat f(i) = v. Case (II) Analogous.

(f) (Trap Root Theorem) Let f : A→ R be a continuous function on a domain A such that the interval [a, b] ⊂ A.If f(a)f(b) < 0, there exists a z ∈ (a, b) such that f(z) = 0.

4. Can you prove the equivalence of the latter four statements?

5. Trap Root Algorithm: For a function satisfying the above hypotheses, find a zero with an error of less than a realε > 0. The procedure is

INITIALIZE left1=a, right1=b, mid1=12(left1+right1), error1=

12(right1−left1).

DO

IF f(midn)=0, THEN a root has been located.

SET leftn+1 = 12(leftn+midn), rightn+1 = 1

2(midn+rightn)

SET midn+1 =midn, errorn+1=12(rightn+1−leftn+1)

(On a machine, exit LOOP.)

IF (f(midn)>0), THENIF f(leftn > 0), THEN SET leftn+1=midn, rightn+1=rightn.

IF f(leftn < 0), THEN SET leftn+1=leftn, rightn+1=midn.

SET midn+1=12(leftn+1+rightn+1), errorn+1=

12(rightn+1−leftn+1)

IF (f(midn)<0), THEN

IF f(leftn > 0), THEN SET leftn+1=leftn, rightn+1=midn.

IF f(leftn < 0), THEN SET leftn+1=midn, rightn+1=rightn.

SET midn+1=12(leftn+1+rightn+1), errorn+1=

12(rightn+1−leftn+1)

WHILE errorn+1 ≥ ε.When the procedure exits on iteration N , take midN+1 as an approximation for the root. Either f(midN+1)=0 inwhich case we have the root. Or |midN+1− z| <errorN+1 < ε, in which case we have the root to desired accuracy.(Note the N + 1, not N)

6. Proof of Trap Root Theorem: Use the procedure to define sequences leftn, midn, rightn and errorn inductively.Verify that leftn and rightn are monotonic and bounded and hence convergent to say L and R. Since

|rightn−leftn| = 2·errorn = 2(b−a)2n , by squeeze theorem L = R = z, say. Further, since leftn < midn < rightn, by

squeeze theorem again midn → z. We claim that f(z) = 0. For a proof, note that in the special case if f(midk)=0for some natural k, then, by definition, midn=midk for all n ≥ k. Hence midn is an eventually constant sequenceconverging to z with f(z) = 0. If f(midn)6= 0, for every natural n, then f(leftn)f(rightn) < 0 for every n andcontinuity implies f(z)f(z) ≤ 0 and being real f(z) = 0.

Page 18: Lec. 1 of 19/Pg. 1 of 26 MA-101/2018 Preliminaries

Lec. 13 of 19/Pg. 18 of 26 MA-101/2018

7. Now, write a program in a suitable language, compile and run for a few functions.

Page 19: Lec. 1 of 19/Pg. 1 of 26 MA-101/2018 Preliminaries

Lec. 14 of 19/Pg. 19 of 26 MA-101/2018

1. Especial Property of compact intervals: If αn is a sequence in any compact interval [a, b], then there exists asubsequence αnk

→ α ∈ [a, b]. Proof: Bolzano–Weierstrass and Squeeze.

2. Boundedness Theorem: A continuous function on a compact interval is bounded. If f : [a, b] → R is unbounded,then there exists a sequence αn ∈ [a, b] such that |f(αn)| is an unbounded monotonic sequence. By EspecialProperty, a subsequence αnk

→ α ∈ [a, b] which implies that |f(αnk)| converges to f(α) by continuity. This

contradicts unboundedness of |f(αnk)|.

3. Lemma: If S ⊂ R is bounded, there exists sequences (yn) and (zn) s.t. yn, zn ∈ S for every natural n andyn → supS and zn → inf S.

4. Min–Max Theorem/Attainment Theorem: A continuous function f : [a, b] → R on a compact interval [a, b] forreal a ≤ b attains its supremum and infimum.By the lemma, there is a sequence (αn) such that αn ∈ [a, b] and f(αn)→ sup f . By the Especial Property, thereexists a subsequence αnk

→ α ∈ [a, b]. Being a subsequence, f(αnk)→ sup f and by continuity, f(αnk

)→ f(α) =sup f . Done. Likewise with inf.

5. Compactness Theorem: The range of a continuous function is a compact interval, if the domain is a compactinterval. Proof: Now, the range is a subset of [inf f, sup f ], by definition of inf/sup. By Attainment Theorem, theend points are in the range. But since the range is an interval, the range is exactly [inf f, sup f ].

6. Converse/contrapositive of above property/theorems?

7. Remark: Especial Property fails for every other type of interval. These three theorems fail for continuous functionson other types of intervals and also for discontinuous functions on compact intervals. Provide explicit examples.

8. Fake proof of boundedness theorem: Start with continuity at x = a and get δ1 > 0 such that |f(x) − f(a)| < 1for all |x− a| < δ1. Next continuity at x = a+ 0.99δ1 yields a δ2 > 0 such that |f(x)− f(a+ 0.99δ1)| < 1 for all|x− (a + 0.99δ1| < δ2. These two together give |f(x)− f(a)| < 2 for all |x− a| < 0.99δ1 + 0.99δ2. Continue thisargument and reach b. Done. Where is the flaw?

9. Fake proof leads to the definition of uniform continuity as a convenient hypothesis to obtain boundedness. Afunction f : A → R on a domain A is uniformly continuous if for every real ε > 0 there exists a δ > 0 such thatfor any x, y ∈ A satisfying |x− y| < δ, it should be true that |f(x)− f(y)| < ε. A uniformly continuous function iscontinuous. Prove that a uniformly continuous function on a bounded interval is bounded. Further a continuousfunction on a compact interval is uniformly continuous.

Page 20: Lec. 1 of 19/Pg. 1 of 26 MA-101/2018 Preliminaries

Lec. 15 of 19/Pg. 20 of 26 MA-101/2018

1. Let I and J be intervals. For functions f : I → J for A ⊂ R definitions of increasing, decreasing, monotonic,strictly increasing, strictly decreasing, strictly monotonic.

2. Examples for: monotonic 6⇒ injective, strictly monotonic 6⇒ surjective (continuous), continuous 6⇒ monotonic(injective, surjective), injective 6⇒ monotonic (continuous), surjective 6⇒ monotonic (continuous).

3. Failure to provide examples contradicting: strictly monotonic ⇒ injective, continuous and injective ⇒ strictlymonotonic, monotonic and surjective ⇒ continuous, monotonic and bijective ⇒ inverse is strictly monotonic.

4. If you are giddy, here is the general principle: Suppose A1, A2, A3, . . . An are adjectives which can be applied to acollection of nouns (objects) in N . It is only natural to ask the questions:

(a) First Order: For any x ∈ N , if x is A1?⇒ x is A2 and similar n(n− 1) questions.

(b) Second Order: For any x ∈ N , if x is A1 and x is A2?⇒ x is A3 and similar 1

2(n)(n− 1)(n− 2) questions.

(c) Third Order: Formulate and count.

(d) Fourth–(n− 1)th Order: Formulate and count.

Show that the total number of such questions is n(2n−1 − 1).

5. In our example, our nouns are ‘functions from intervals to intervals’. Our six adjectives are ‘monotonic’, ‘strictlymonotonic’, ‘injective’,‘surjective’,‘bijective’, ‘continuous’. How many questions of 1–5 orders can I ask you? Howmany can you answer?

6. Injective & continuous implies strictly monotonic.Let f : I → J be continuous and injective from an interval I to an interval J . Then f is strictly monotonic.Proof: Assume f is not strictly monotonic. Then f is not strictly increasing or strictly decreasing (and hence thereexists ξ1 < ξ2 and ξ3 < ξ4 such that f(ξ1) ≤ f(ξ2) and f(ξ3) ≥ f(ξ4)). This implies (fill the gap!) we can findthree points in the domain x1 < x2 < x3 such that either (i) f(x1) ≤ f(x2) ≥ f(x3) or (ii) f(x1) ≥ f(x2) ≤ f(x3).Injectivity of f allows us to infer that either (i) f(x1) < f(x2) > f(x3) or (ii) f(x1) > f(x2) < f(x3) is true. Case(i) has three sub-cases: (i.a) f(x1) < f(x3), (i.b) f(x1) = f(x3) and (i.c) f(x1) > f(x3). Sub-case (i.b) violatesinjectivity. For other two sub-cases, apply intermediate value property to get contradictions to injectivity. Case(ii) is similar.

7. Invertible & monotonic implies monotonically invertible.f : A→ B be an increasing bijective function from a set A to a set B. Then the inverse of f is strictly increasing.Like wise for a decreasing bijective function.Proof: Let g : B → A be the uniquely defined inverse of f . Suppose b1 < b2 are any two elements in B. Sinceg is injective, g(b1) = g(b2) is not allowed. Suppose g(b1) > g(b2). f being increasing and injective, we getf(g(b1)) > f(g(b2)), i.e., b1 > b2, a contradiction. Conclude that g(b1) < g(b2).

8. Lemma on monotonic and discontinuous

Let f : (a, b)→ B be monotonically increasing. For each c ∈ (a, b), define

Lc := sup{f(x)|x < c} and Uc := inf{f(x)|x > c}.

Then, f is continuous at c ∈ (a, b) if and only if Lc = Uc.

(continuity at c implies equality) Proof: Clearly Lc ≤ f(c) ≤ Uc. If Lc = f(c) < Uc, find a sequence (xn) such thatxn > c, xn → c, and f(xn) → Uc 6= f(c), contradicting continuity. Similarly, if Lc < f(c) = Uc, find a sequence(xn) such that xn < c, xn → c, and f(xn)→ Lc 6= f(c), contradicting continuity.

(equality of Lc and Uc implies continuity) If Lc = f(c) = Uc, by making given ε smaller, if necessary, takeδ = min(δ1, δ2) where δ1 =

9. Monotonic & surjective implies continuous.Let f : A→ B be a monotonic and surjective function from a domain A to a domain B. Then f is continuous.Proof: We write the proof for f being increasing, the other case being analogous. Assume f is discontinuousat c ∈ A. Then, there exists a real ε0 > 0 and a sequence δn → 0 such that |f(c + δn) − f(c)| ≥ ε0. By

Page 21: Lec. 1 of 19/Pg. 1 of 26 MA-101/2018 Preliminaries

Lec. 15 of 19/Pg. 21 of 26 MA-101/2018

passing to subsequences, we may assume that either δn < 0 for each n or that δn > 0 for each n. In theformer case, sup{f(x)|x < c, x ∈ A} = sup{f(c + δn)|n ∈ N} ≤ −ε0 + f(c) < f(c) while in the latter casef(c) < f(c) + ε0 ≤ inf{f(c + δn)|n ∈ N} = inf{f(x)|x > c, x ∈ A}. As a result, in the former case, f , beingmonotonic does not realize the value −1

2ε0+f(c), while in the latter it does not realize f(c)+ 12ε0. This contradicts

its surjectivity. (There is a bug in this proof as it assumes that f(c) + 12ε0 or −1

2ε0 + f(c) belongs to B. For thisto happen, B should be an interval. The error was pointed out by a tutor to me on 19th Nov. So I am modifyingmy claim.)

10. Invertible & continuous implies continuously invertible.

Inverse Function Theorem (in the world of continuous functions): Let I and J be intervals and f : I → J abijective continuous function. Then its inverse g : J → I is continuous.Proof: Relying on the previous three results, f is injective and continuous implies f is strictly monotonic, f ismonotonic and bijective implies g is monotonic, g is monotonic and surjective implies g is continuous. Done.

11. Application: Existence and continuity of n–th root functions.

Page 22: Lec. 1 of 19/Pg. 1 of 26 MA-101/2018 Preliminaries

Lec. 16 of 19/Pg. 22 of 26 MA-101/2018

1. Recall definition of a domain A in R. Quick mention of limit of g at c, for a function g : A→ R at a point c ∈ A.(Deliberately exclude x = c, anticipating definition of derivative).

2. Analogous to limit of a sequence and definition of continuity. Comparable results are true: uniqueness of limit if itexists and the rules: power, sum, difference, product, quotient (be delicate), chain/composition. Squeeze theorem.Write down proofs by yourself.

3. Galileo’s law of motion states that an object/body/particle without any external force/disturbance continues itsstate of rest or uniform velocity (constant speed in a straight line).Challenges faced by Newton:

(a) To give an absolutely accurate definition of instantaneous velocity from the crude calculations of averagevelocity.

(b) Having answered (a), to quantify amount of instantaneous change in velocity.

4. Certainly, you have seen the definition of instantaneous velocity for a particle whose position has been co–ordinatedby real numbers. It is the ‘eventual value’ of average velocity quotient f(c+h)−f(c)

h as the time window h ‘be-comes’/‘approaches’ zero. The definition is accurate. Indeed, using this and an analogous definition for instan-taneous acceleration, Newton calculated that moon is falling towards earth at a rate 1

602that of a stone thrown

up. Knowing that the distance between moon and earth is 60 times the radius of earth – he hypothesised theUniversal Law of Gravitation.

5. Latter day mathematicians have made these notions rigorous. Stripped of any and all physical interpretation,consider a function f : A→ R for a domain A in R. For a c ∈ A, we say that

f is differentiable at c ∈ A if limh→0

f(c+h)−f(c)h at c exists.

Note that g(h) = f(c+h)−f(c)h is defined on a subset of R not containing 0 and we are seeking lim

h→0g(h).

6. Define differentiable to mean differentiable at all points of the domain.

7. Notation for derivative.

8. Proposition: Differentiable at c implies continuous at c.

9. Rules: Power, Sum, Difference, Product, Quotient, Chain. Proof of chain rule is delicate. See BaSh.

10. The inverse function theorem in the world of continuous functions assures a continuous inverse for a bijectivecontinuous function. Bijectivity is necessary if you want to invert a function. And if the inverse of a function iscontinuous, by the inverse function theorem, the function is continuous. (all this is for functions between intervals).What should one do to get a differentiable inverse? Certainly we need a bijective function. And if the inverseis differentiable, the inverse is continuous and by our previous observation, the function is continuous. But isthe function differentiable? The function x 7→ x

13 from (−1, 1) to (−1, 1) is not differentiable (at zero) but has a

differentiable inverse, viz., x 7→ x3. Likewise, the function x 7→ x3 is differentiable and has a local differentiableinverse at all points of its domain except zero.These two examples illustrate that for bijective functions, differentiability is neither necessary nor sufficient to geta differentiable inverse. This is explained by the observation (in examples, at least) f ′(xn)→ 0 as xn → c causes|f−1′(yn)| → ∞ as yn = f(xn)→ f(c).Challenge: Give an example for a function f : R→ R such that f is bijective, f is differentiable at all points of apre-specified subset S ⊂ R and not differentiable at points of Sc.Another one: Can you find an example of a bijective function f : R → R which is differentiable nowhere but theinverse is differentiable (everywhere).

11. Infinitesimal Inverse Function Theorem (in the world of differentiable functions): Let f : I → J be a bijectivecontinuous function between intervals I and J , with g : J → I as the inverse. If f is differentiable at c ∈ I andf ′(c) 6= 0, then g is differentiable at f(c) and g′(f(c)) = 1

f ′(c) .

12. Local Inverse Function Theorem: Let f : I → J be a bijective continuous function between intervals I and J ,with g : J → I as the inverse. Suppose that for a c ∈ I, there is a real ε > 0 such that f is differentiable and f ′ is

Page 23: Lec. 1 of 19/Pg. 1 of 26 MA-101/2018 Preliminaries

Lec. 16 of 19/Pg. 23 of 26 MA-101/2018

continuous on (c− ε, c+ ε) with f ′(c) 6= 0. Then, there is a real δ > 0 such that at every x ∈ (c− δ, c+ δ) ∩ I, gis differentiable and g′(f(x)) = 1

f ′(x) .

13. Global Inverse Function Theorem: Let f : I → J be a bijective differentiable function between intervals I and J ,with g : J → I as the inverse. If f is differentiable and f ′(x) 6= 0 for every x ∈ I, then g is differentiable andg′(f(x)) = 1

f ′(x) for every x ∈ I.

Page 24: Lec. 1 of 19/Pg. 1 of 26 MA-101/2018 Preliminaries

Lec. 17 of 19/Pg. 24 of 26 MA-101/2018

1. Definitions for relative minimum, maximum, extremum for a function defined on an interval or even a domain.Note the use of the words minimum/maximum instead of infimum/supremum. The word relative contrasts thesedefinitions with absolute used earlier.

2. Examples of existence and non–existence.

3. Derivative vanishes at interior points of relative extrema.On an interval I, let f : I → R be a function. Let c be an interior point of I, f have a relative extremum at c andlet f be differentiable at c. Then f ′(c) = 0.

Proof: Assume f ′(c) = ` 6= 0. Then there exists a real δ > 0 such that if 0 < |h| < δ, then `− 12` <

f(c+h)−f(c)h <

`+ 12`. Consider:

(a) Assume c is a point of relative maximum of f .

i. If ` > 0, using the above inequality, we have for all 0 < h < δ that f(c + h) − f(c) > 12` · h > 0 which

contradicts the assumption that c is a point of relative maximum.

ii. If ` < 0, using the above inequality, we have for all −δ < h < 0 that f(c + h) − f(c) > 32` · h which

contradicts the assumption that c is a point of relative maximum.

(b) The case of c being a point of relative minimum of f is similar.

Remark: To make sense of f(c + h), δ has to be sufficiently small. Since we are using both h > 0 and h < 0, cshould be an interior point.

4. The proof above tells us that if f is differentiable (even just) at c and f ′(c) > 0, then there exists a real δ > 0such that for all 0 < h < δ, f(c + h) − f(c) > 0 and f(c − h) − f(c) < 0. What this does not tell us is thatf(x) − f(y) > 0 for all x < y ∈ (c − δ, c + δ) – i.e., f is locally increasing. Indeed this is false as the example ofx 7→ x+ x2 sin(1/x) with 0 7→ 0 illustrates. Upshot: From the infinitesimal data f ′(c) > 0, we cannot conclude fis locally increasing.

5. Critical points of a function on a domain are defined as the collection which includes end points of the domain,those points where derivative fails to exist or those where the derivative exists and equals zero. If a function hasa relative extremum at a point, then that point is a critical point.

6. Rolle’s Theorem: Let f : [a, b]→ R be continuous on [a, b] and differentiable on (a, b). Suppose f(a) = f(b). Thenthere exists a (at least one) point ξ ∈ (a, b) such that f ′(ξ) = 0. (Here a < b)Proof: If sup f = inf f = f(a) = f(b), then f is a constant and any element in (a, b) may be used for ξ. Otherwise,an interior point ξ of the interval is a point of absolute extremum and hence relative extremum. By previoustheorem, f ′(ξ) = 0.

7. Mean Value Theorem: Let f : [a, b] → R be continuous on [a, b] and differentiable on (a, b). Then there exists a

(at least one) point ξ ∈ (a, b) such that f ′(ξ) = f(b)−f(a)b−a . (Here a < b)

Proof: Use Rolle’s Theorem on ϕ(x) = f(x)− f(a)− f(b)−f(a)b−a (x− a).

Example of Speeding Fine.

8. First Derivative Test.

Page 25: Lec. 1 of 19/Pg. 1 of 26 MA-101/2018 Preliminaries

Lec. 18 of 19/Pg. 25 of 26 MA-101/2018

1. Lengths: Definition of a unit length as a standard. Lengths of straight line segments which are natural numbers,fractions and real numbers.

2. Areas: Definition of a unit square as standard.

3. Area of a rectangle whose sides are of lengths which are natural numbers/non–negative integers. Extension torectangles having sides of lengths which are non–negative fractions. How about if sides are non–negative reals?

4. Area of a parallelogram. Area of a triangle. Area of a polygon.

5. Remark that with the definitions we have, the most general curves for which we can ask about their lengths areactually only straight line segments. Similarly the most general regions for which we can ask about its area arepolygons. Of course, minor variants like lengths of piece–wise straight line segments and a collection of polygonsany two of which intersect either in an empty set or in a point are allowed. It is inappropriate to ask aboutcircumference of a circle or an ellipse or area of a circular or an elliptical region, for instance.

6. Despite the remark, ancients considered the problem of lengths of more general curves and areas of more generalplanar regions. For calculating lengths of “curved” curves, their method was to approximate the curve by apiece–wise straight line segment and take “finer and finer” approximations. The method for calculating areas ofregions with “curved” boundaries is to approximate the region by a collection of triangles or rectangles and take“finer and finer” approximations.

7. What is the circumference of a circle of radius R? What is its area?

8. Proposition: There exists a universal constant denoted by π such that for any circle circumferencediameter = area

(radius)2= π.

Proof: (Using Trigonometry) Let C and A denote the circumference and area of a circle of radius R. Letpn, Pn, an, An denote respectively the perimeters and areas of regular n-gons (n ≥ 3) circumscribed by and cir-cumscribing the given circle. We then have

pn < C < Pn & an < A < An for every natural n ≥ 3.

Using trigonometry, one verifies

pn = 2R · 180 ·sin(180◦

n

)180n

, Pn = 2R · 180 ·tan

(180◦

n

)180n

, an = R2 · 180 ·sin(360◦

n

)360◦

n

, An = R2 · 180 ·tan

(180◦

n

)180n

Can you prove that there is a real number α such that limθ◦→0

sin(θ◦)θ◦ = lim

θ◦→0

tan(θ◦)θ◦ = α? . . .(*). Define π to be that

real number which is 180α. Then, one has lim pn = limPn = C = 2πR and lim an = limAn = A = πR2. Thiscompletes the proof.Note that your proof of (*) should not use lim sin ξ

ξ = 1, when ξ is measured in radians. This is owing to the factthat radian measure presupposes establishment of π and length of circular arc.

9. Can one find the circumference and area of a circle without using trigonometry?

10. Lemma: If sn and Sn are the lengths of sides of regular n–gons circumscribed by and circumscribing a circle ofradius R, then

s2nR

=

√2− 2

√1−

( sn2R

)2&

S2nR

=4SnR

√1 +

(Sn2R

)2

− 1

Proof: Elementary Euclidean Geometry.

11. Antiphon found lim p2k , Bryson found limP2k and Archimedes found limA2k using the above lemma as follows.One can verify that s4 =

√2R and S4 = 2R. Using the lemma, the sequences (s2k) and (S2k) are well defined. As

an exercise prove that (2ks2k), (2kS2k) and (2k 12RS2k) converge to 2πR, 2πR and πR2 for some real number π.

12. Corollary: Define α2 =√

2 and αk+1 =

√2− 2

√1−

(αk2

)2for each k ≥ 2.

Similarly, β2 = 2 and βk+1 = 4βk

(√1 +

(βk2

)2− 1

)for each k ≥ 2.

2k−1αk and 2k−1βk are monotonic sequences converging to π.

Page 26: Lec. 1 of 19/Pg. 1 of 26 MA-101/2018 Preliminaries

Lec. 19 of 19/Pg. 26 of 26 MA-101/2018

1. Ancient Problem of Areas: Given a region in a plane, find its area. In this form, the problem is ill–posed. Despitethis, like the example of circle, mathematicians of antiquity found area of elliptical regions, area of parabolicregions etc.

2. Issues with their methods: What is a definition for area of a region? If a sequence of polygons approximate aregion, over what kinds of such polygonal approximations should one take the limit to get the area of the region?Does every such limit yield the same answer?

3. The biggest challenge was to get the exact answer. Exact answers could be found in very few examples. Therewas nothing anyone could do for almost two thousand years.

4. We shall consider the problem of area under a function f : [a, b] → R. By this we mean the area of the regionwhose boundary is determined by the curves x = a, x = b and y = f(x). Question: Is this restricted problemsufficient to solve the Ancient Problem of Areas?

5. Given an interval [a, b], define a partition for that interval, subinterval, norm of a partition, tag for a subintervaland tagged partition.

6. The Riemann sum of a function defined on a compact interval w.r.t. a tagged partition is an approximation tothe yet-to-be-defined area under that function. One should find limits of Riemann sums over a sequence of taggedpartitions whose norm goes to zero. If all such limits yield the same answer, we say that area under the functionexists/well–defined and take that common answer to be the value of the area.

7. We say that f : [a, b]→ R is Riemann integrable or simply integrable if any of the following equivalent conditionshold:Sequential Criterion There exists a real number L such that if Pn is a sequence of tagged partitions of [a, b] such

that ||Pn|| → 0, then limS(f, Pn) = L.Riemann’s Criterion There exists a real number L such that for any real ε > 0, there exists a real δ > 0 such thatfor any tagged partition P of [a, b] with ||P|| < δ, we have |S(f, P)− L| < ε.Cauchy’s Criterion For every real ε > 0, there exists a real η > 0 such that if P and Q are tagged partitions of

[a, b] with ||P||, ||Q|| < η, we should have |S(f, P)− S(f, Q)| < ε.

8. If any of the above criteria hold, we say that f is integrable (over [a, b]) and its (Riemann) integral is L. We write∫ ba f(x)dx = L. This notation is unfortunate as it anticipates fundamental theorem of calculus.

9. Uniqueness of limit.

10. Proof: RC implies SC, CC are easy. For SC implies RC, do rather OPP(RC) implies OPP(SC). For CC impliesRC, see BaSh.

11. Examples of integrability of constant, identity and square functions on compact intervals.

12. Rules: Sum, Difference and Constant Multiple Rules of Riemann Integrability. Dominance/Comparison Rule. Allproofs are easy with Sequential Criterion.

13. Integrability of restrictions, Summation over restrictions.

14. Theorems: integrable implies bounded, continuous implies integrable and monotonic implies integrable. Howabout their converses?

15. Definition of integral for a = b and b < a. Interpretation for negative areas.


Recommended