+ All Categories
Home > Documents > [Liana Giorgi] Democracy in the European Union to(BookFi.org)[1]

[Liana Giorgi] Democracy in the European Union to(BookFi.org)[1]

Date post: 17-Dec-2015
Category:
Upload: bertea-madalina
View: 14 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend
Description:
democracy
Popular Tags:
234
Transcript
  • Democracy in the European Union

    The process of European integration has given rise to a new object of study theEuropean society. Several old questions concerning citizenship, democracy, govern-ment and institutions must be raised anew, this time at the European level. These arenot only academic issues, but also major political concerns at European and memberstate level.

    There are fears that transfers of power to European institutions produce a char-acteristically new and worrying form of democratic decit. The recent rejection ofthe Constitutional Treaty in France and the Netherlands suggests that this demo-cratic decit is beginning to impact on the Unions legitimacy, further endangeringthe European project of ever closer union.

    How can this crisis be overcome, and in which direction should the EuropeanUnion be moving? This new volume

    takes a closer look at the Unions democratic decit in an effort to establish itsprecise character and location;

    scrutinizes top-down institutional opportunity structures for participation, theactors that are shaping bottom-up mobilization, and the ideologies and dis-courses that are informing attempts to generalize political claims beyond thenational level;

    provides a detailed insight into the scope and character of participatory practicein decision-making, the structure and visions of the European political class, andthe role of civil society organizations and trans-national movements;

    looks at the debate on the EU as a community of values, as well as views aboutEurope in the new member states.

    This book will be of strong interest to students and researchers of the EuropeanUnion, European politics and European studies, as well as those concerned withmore theoretical aspects of governance and the public sphere.

    Liana Giorgi is Vice-Director of the Interdisciplinary Centre for ComparativeResearch in the Social Sciences (ICCR), Austria.

    Ingmar von Homeyer is a Senior Fellow at Ecologic, the Institute for Internationaland European Environmental Policy, Berlin/Brussels.

    Wayne Parsons is Professor of Public Policy and Head of Department at QueenMary College, University of London, UK.

  • Routledge Advances in European Politics

    1 Russian Messianism

    Third Rome, Revolution,Communism and after

    Peter J. S. Duncan

    2 European Integration and the

    Postmodern Condition

    Governance, Democracy, Identity

    Peter van Ham

    3 Nationalism in Italian

    Politics

    The Stories of the Northern

    League, 19802000

    Damian Tambini

    4 International Intervention in the

    Balkans since 1995Edited by Peter Siani-Davies

    5 Widening the European

    Union

    The Politics of Institutional

    Change and Reform

    Edited by Bernard Steunenberg

    6 Institutional Challenges in the

    European Union

    Edited by Madeleine Hosli, Adrian

    van Deemen and Mika Widgren

    7 Europe Unbound

    Enlarging and Reshaping the

    Boundaries of the European UnionEdited by Jan Zielonka

    8 Ethnic Cleansing in the Balkans

    Nationalism and the Destruction ofTradition

    Cathie Carmichael

    9 Democracy and Enlargement in

    Post-Communist Europe

    The Democratisation of the

    General Public in Fifteen Central

    and Eastern European countries,19911998

    Christian W. Haerpfer

    10 Private Sector Involvement in the

    Euro

    The Power of Ideas

    Stefan Collignon and

    Daniela Schwarzer

    11 Europe

    A Nietzschean Perspective

    Stefan Elbe

    12 European Union and

    E-Voting

    Addressing the EuropeanParliaments Internet Voting

    Challenge

    Edited by Alexander H. Trechsel

    and Fernando Mendez

    13 European Union Council

    Presidencies

    A Comparative PerspectiveEdited by Ole Elgstrom

  • 14 European Governance and

    Supranational Institutions

    Making States Comply

    Jonas Tallberg

    15 European Union, NATO and

    Russia

    Martin Smith and

    Graham Timmins

    16 Business, the State and

    Economic PolicyThe Case of Italy

    G. Grant Amyot

    17 Europeanization and

    Transnational States

    Comparing Nordic Central

    Governments

    Bengt Jacobsson, Per Lgreid and

    Ove K. Pedersen

    18 European Union Enlargement

    A Comparative History

    Edited by Wolfram Kaiser and

    Jurgen Elvert

    19 GibraltarBritish or Spanish?

    Peter Gold

    20 Gendering Spanish Democracy

    Monica Threlfall,

    Christine Cousins and

    Celia Valiente

    21 European Union Negotiations

    Processes, Networks and

    Negotiations

    Edited by Ole Elgstrom and

    Christer Jonsson

    22 Evaluating Euro-Mediterranean

    RelationsStephen C. Calleya

    23 The Changing Face of European

    Identity

    A Seven-nation Study of

    (Supra)National AttachmentsEdited by Richard Robyn

    24 Governing Europe

    Discourse, Governmentality and

    European Integration

    William Walters and

    Jens Henrik Haahr

    25 Territory and Terror

    Conicting Nationalisms in the

    Basque Country

    Jan Mansvelt Beck

    26 Multilateralism, German Foreign

    Policy and Central Europe

    Claus Hofhansel

    27 Popular Protest in East Germany

    Gareth Dale

    28 Germanys Foreign Policy

    Towards Poland and the Czech

    Republic

    Ostpolitik RevistedKarl Cordell and Stefan Wolff

    29 Kosovo

    The Politics of Identity and Space

    Denisa Kostovicova

    30 The Politics of European Union

    EnlargementTheoretical Approaches

    Edited by Frank Schimmelfennig

    and Ulrich Sedelmeier

    31 Europeanizing Social

    Democracy?

    The Rise of the Party of European

    SocialistsSimon Lightfoot

  • 32 Conict and Change in EU

    Budgetary Politics

    Johannes Lindner

    33 Gibraltar, Identity and Empire

    E. G. Archer

    34 Governance Stories

    Mark Bevir and R. A. W Rhodes

    35 Britain and the Balkans

    1991 until the PresentCarole Hodge

    36 The Eastern Enlargement of

    the European Union

    John OBrennan

    37 Values and Principles in

    European Union Foreign PolicyEdited by Sonia Lucarelli and

    Ian Manners

    38 European Union and the

    Making of a Wider Northern

    Europe

    Pami Aalto

    39 Democracy in the European

    Union

    Towards the Emergence of a Public

    SphereEdited by Liana Giorgi,

    Ingmar von Homeyer and

    Wayne Parsons

    40 European Union Peacebuilding

    and Policing

    Michael Merlingen with

    Rasa Ostraukaite

    41. The Conservative Party and

    European Integration since 1945

    At the Heart of Europe?

    N.J. Crowson

    42. E-Government in Europe

    Re-booting the stateEdited by Paul G. Nixon and

    Vassiliki N. Koutrakou

  • Democracy in theEuropean UnionTowards the emergence of a public sphere

    Edited by Liana Giorgi,Ingmar von Homeyer and Wayne Parsons

  • First published 2006by Routledge2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon, OX14 4RN

    Simultaneously published in the USA and Canadaby Routledge270 Madison Ave, New York, NY 10016

    Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business

    # 2006 Liana Giorgi, Ingmar von Homeyer and Wayne Parsons for selection and editorialmatter; the individual contributors, their contributions

    All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised in anyform or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented,including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system,without permission in writing from the publishers.

    British Library Cataloguing in Publication DataA catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library

    Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication DataDemocracy in the European Union: towards the emergence of a public sphere /edited by Liana Giorgi, Ingmar von Homeyer, and Wayne Parsons.

    p. cm. (Routledge advances in European politics; 39)Includes bibliographical references and index.1. DemocracyEuropean Union countries. 2. Political participation ;

    European Union countries. 3. European Union. I. Giorgi, Liana. II. Homeyer,Ingmar von. III. Parsons, Wayne. IV. Series.JN40.D475 2006341.2422dc22

    2005037154

    ISBN10: 0415369096

    ISBN13: 9780415369091

    This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2006.To purchase your own copy of this or any of Taylor & Francis or Routledgescollection of thousands of eBooks please go to www.eBookstore.tandf.co.uk.

    (Print Edition)

  • Contents

    List of illustrations

    Notes on contributors ix

    Acknowledgements xi

    1 Introduction: the political sociology of the European public sphere 1

    JOHN CROWLEY AND LIANA GIORGI

    2 Democratization and the European Union 24LIANA GIORGI

    3 Participatory governance in the European Union 43

    INGMARVON HOMEYER

    4 The emergence of a European political class 79

    ELISE FERON, JOHN CROWLEY AND LIANA GIORGI

    5 The anti-globalization movement and the European agenda 115

    ELISE FERON

    6 The European Union as a Community of Values 135

    LIANA GIORGI, NIKI RODOUSAKIS, MARISOL GARCIA AND

    MARTIN PETERSON

    7 EU accession and the public sphere in new member states: thecase of the Czech Republic 157

    MICHAL ILLNER, DANIEL CERMAK, TOMAS KOSTELECKY AND

    JANA STACHOVA

    8 Conclusion: what future for European integration and democracy? 180

    WAYNE PARSONS

    Bibliography 199Index 209

    viii

  • Illustrations

    Figures

    4.1 Map of the European political class 85

    7.1 Public support for the Czech Republics application formembership of the EU by education 167

    7.2 Public support for the Czech Republics application for

    membership of the EU by party preference. 168

    7.3 Public support for the Czech Republics membership of the

    EU; voting likelihoods in the accession referendum 169

    Tables

    3.1 Case specic overview of conditions for participation 48

    3.2 Effects on participation 74

    4.1a Educational background of respondents by gender 91

    4.1b Educational background of respondents by nationality 91

    4.1c Educational background of respondents by political afliation 91

    4.2 Experience studying and working abroad 93

    4.3 Multiple mandates and current position 95

    4.4 No mandate in the past or future 964.5 Re-election rates among elected MEPs following June 2004

    elections 97

    4.6 Share of holding ofcial positions at national level 98

    4.7 Euro-enthusiasm (or Euro-scepticism) index 107

    4.8 Political disenchantment index 108

    4.9a European political ideologies by nationality of respondent 110

    4.9b European political ideologies by politics of respondent 110

    7.1 Answers to the question Do you think that you have enoughinformation about the accession process? 161

    7.2 Support for Czech political parties 175

  • Contributors

    Daniel Cermak is doctoral student at the Institute of Sociology, Academy of

    Sciences of the Czech Republic.

    John Crowley is Senior Programme Specialist at UNESCO, Editor of the

    International Social Science Journal, and Executive Director of the

    Centre Interdisciplinaire de Recherche (CIR-Paris).

    Elise Feron is lecturer at the Institute of Political Science of the Universityof Lille, and Senior Research Fellow at the Centre Interdisciplinaire de

    Recherche (CIR) in Paris.

    Marisol Garcia is Assistant Professor at the University of Barcelona.

    Liana Giorgi is Vice-Director of the Interdisciplinary Centre for Compara-

    tive Research in the Social Sciences (ICCR) in Vienna.

    Ingmar von Homeyer is a senior fellow at Ecologic, Institute for Interna-

    tional and European Environmental Policy, Berlin.

    Michal Illner is Senior Scholar at the Institute of Sociology, Academy of

    Sciences of the Czech Republic, Department of Local and Regional Studies.

    Tomas Kostelecky is Senior Scholar at the Institute of Sociology, Academy

    of Sciences of the Czech Republic, Department of Local and RegionalStudies.

    Wayne Parsons is Professor of Public Policy at Queen Mary College, Uni-

    versity of London.

    Martin Peterson is Professor at the universities of Bergen, Norway, and

    Goteburg, Sweden and member of the Globalisation Committee of the

    Swedish Research Council.

  • Niki Rodousakis is a research fellow at the Interdisciplinary Centre for

    Comparative Research in the Social Sciences (ICCR) in Vienna.

    Jana Stachova is doctoral student at the Institute of Sociology, Academy ofSciences of the Czech Republic.

    x Contributors

  • Acknowledgements

    The research reported in this volume was carried out in the framework

    of the EU RTD Framework Programme project The European Public

    Sphere: Assembling Information that Allows the Monitoring of European

    Democracy (EUROPUB) (Fifth RTD Framework Programme Improving

    Human Research Potential and the Socio-Economic Knowledge Base).

  • 1 Introduction

    The political sociology of the Europeanpublic sphere

    John Crowley and Liana Giorgi

    At the beginning of the twenty-rst century, the European Union nds itself

    at the crossroads. On the one hand, the ambitious European project of ever

    closer collaboration has signicantly advanced through the Eastern enlar-

    gement and the ever growing scope of economic integration. On the other

    hand, institutional and implementation decits place serious barriers to

    further integration and raise, more urgently than before, the question of

    political integration including its desirability and feasibility. The rejection

    of the Constitutional Treaty by the French and Dutch publics in 2005, aswell as the ongoing budgetary crisis, testify to a serious legitimacy crisis.

    How can this crisis be overcome and where is or should the European

    Union be moving towards?

    There are three distinct narratives responses to this question. The rst

    considers further efcient and effective integration to be possible only once

    a political integration framework has been agreed upon and put into place.

    Institutional reform is a term used to refer to these considerations, yet

    ultimately this is also a discussion about the EU political multi-level gov-ernance system, a possible Constitution and, for some, a state model. The

    second narrative with regard to the EU legitimacy crisis emphasizes the

    absence of a symbolically unifying European identity or Europeanness

    among EU citizens and sees the legitimacy decit closely linked to an iden-

    tity decit. According to the proponents of this narrative, as long as EU

    citizens are rst and foremost nationals, pledging their solidarity to those

    like them within their national territorial boundaries and identifying their

    national territory as the only legitimate sphere for politics, the EU as apolity will remain decient. For this reason, it might be more sensible to

    concentrate any institutional reform efforts to rendering the EU an efcient

    expert-led international cooperation framework for making policy rather

    than politics. The third narrative links the legitimacy crisis to a democratic

    decit: the reason why the European Union and the European integration

    project is not genuinely recognized as both lawful and justiable has to do

    with the fact that it is non-transparent and unaccountable vis-a`-vis its citi-

    zens, hence undemocratic. Overcoming the legitimacy decit thus requiresovercoming the democratic decit.

  • These three narratives are not exclusive of each other. However, in

    the present ofcial and academic discourse they tend to represent distinct

    views about what to emphasize or prioritize in either policy or research

    about European integration in the near- to mid-term future. This discoursefragmentation is to blame at least in part for the emerging impasse in

    European studies faced with increasing disciplinary and thematic over-

    specialization. It is also a barrier with regard to envisioning futures for

    European integration.

    This book tries to break with this tradition. The starting point of our

    analysis has been that there is indeed an organic link between the European

    Unions legitimacy and democratic decit, but that this is not the problem

    alone of any specic institution, a set of institutional rules or any singlelevel of analysis. We need to scrutinize political institutions and rules (or the

    lack thereof) as much as policy processes, citizens concerns or patterns of

    participation (or the lack thereof). Such an approach requires a robust the-

    oretical and normative framework in order to avoid that it spirals into a

    nave discourse of the a bit of everything (and ultimately nothing) type.

    For us this is provided by the model of a strong democracy as delineated

    by the notion of the public sphere. The objective of this introductory chapter

    is to outline this model and relate it to the individual chapters of the book.

    Models of democracy and key considerations

    The idea that it is helpful to approach the theory of democracy from the

    perspective of a range of competing models is a familiar one. In a widely

    quoted book, David Held (1996) proposes a series of distinctions between

    ten generic models.

    The Greek idea of citizenship: democracy is dened as the direct politicalparticipation of (a very low number) of citizens.

    Republicanism and self-government: individual liberty is dened in poli-tical terms the active citizen, after being replaced by the religious

    man, appears again in political theory.

    Liberal democracy: individual liberty is not political but private andeconomical; the intervention of the state must be limited in the economy

    and in private lives. Direct (Marxist) democracy threatens the concept of modern politics

    and presupposes in its canonical form the withering away of the state.

    The technocratic and administrative conception of democracy emphasizesthe importance of experts and centralized power. Elites are far from

    citizens who do not take part in political decisions; deliberation and

    parliaments are under the domination of party competition. Social and

    political conicts are weaker, although freedom of opinions is high.

    Pluralism is characterized by the balance of powers and respect ofminorities as well as different opinions; moreover, the political system is

    2 John Crowley and Liana Giorgi

  • composed of various political parties and is based on the separation of

    powers.

    Legal democracy underscores the role of the constitution and theseparation of powers; it favours minimal state intervention in private lifeand in the economy as well as a strong civil society; it seeks to restrict

    the role of interest groups and supports weak collectivism.

    Participatory democracy seeks the promotion of individual liberty, ofself-development and of a collective awareness of common issues

    through the direct citizen participation in the regulation of the key

    institutions of society.

    Democratic autonomy: equal rights and duties for individuals: they areconsidered as free and equal provided they do not threaten the freedomof others.

    Cosmopolitan democracy is characterized by the reform of national andinternational governing institutions and the evolution of governance;

    similar processes of globalization characterize the economy and the

    civil society.

    The details of the above classication might be discussed at length, but its

    purpose is to provide a conceptual mapping rather than a catalogue. Wecannot, of course, choose the model that best suits us or any particular

    political situation; but we can sharpen our approach to practical or theore-

    tical political problems by taking account of its contrasts. Each of the ten

    models summarizes some salient features of a real political system and also

    gives an account of the language in which its citizens have sought to make

    sense of it. Furthermore, identifying the models, even if they are regarded

    merely as ideal-types, points to the tensions between them and to the prac-

    tical and theoretical issues that may be at stake in adopting or emphasizingone or the other. To describe democracy in terms of competitive elitism (as

    did Schumpeter, for instance) is to reject competing descriptions (in

    Schumpeters case, mainly in participatory terms) as unrealistic, and thus to

    circumscribe the range or scope of real-world democracy. Even if polemical

    considerations did not intervene, in other words, analytical options would

    carry normative baggage; in addition, democracy has been a persistently

    contested notion since its modern re-emergence as a possible real-world

    model in the eighteenth century. Mapping models of democracy thus helpsto clarify what is actually at stake in analytical and normative quarrels

    about democracy.

    Using Helds own approach, a series of issues appear to have particular

    signicance in driving competing interpretations of the supercially

    straightforward idea of democracy as the rule of the people:

    The place of the state within the overall conception of democracy andpolitics, which can be generalized as the signicance given to deliberateordering (via authoritative command) as distinct from more or less

    Introduction 3

  • spontaneous self-ordering (via the unintended consequences of interac-

    tion) as a template for collective existence. The importance given to civil

    society (however named) in democratic theory is a converse criterion.

    The scale of political action, which relates closely to its nature and pur-pose. If politics is conceived in terms of the collective reexive life of a

    people, then the scale of politics will naturally tend to be thought of as

    unitary and uniform (e.g. in the modern context, by reference to the

    nation-state). Conversely, if politics is envisaged primarily in terms of

    problem-solving, there are likely to be as many scales or arenas of poli-

    tical authority and action as there are problems: politics will therefore be

    neither unitary nor uniform, and the nation-state as indeed the strong

    normative idea of the people will tend to be regarded as a ratherarbitrary historical inheritance rather than a necessary political template.

    The processes that make up politics: a wide range of perspectives exist,from an emphasis on struggles and power relations to a privileging

    of dialogue and deliberation, with bargaining or negotiation models

    occupying a notional intermediate position.

    The subject matter or scope of politics. To say that the people should ruleis not to specify over what they should rule (simply that no one else

    should rule, strictly speaking, over anything); even to say that politics isabout solving problems is not to prejudge which problems are political.

    In the contemporary context, this issue points in three crucial directions,

    all of which remain profoundly controversial. First, what should be the

    link between the economy and politics? Second, are human rights a

    political issue, or an intangible framework within which politics must

    operate? Third, is there a conceptual limit (e.g. the limits of the human

    body, however dened) beyond which democratic politics cannot go

    without self-destructing? Needless to say, none of these questions is infact dichotomous, and all sophisticated positions occupy some kind of

    middle ground. But the polar opposites are, nonetheless, the structuring

    factors of public debate.

    The nature of the people: whom does the people include, and whomdoes it exclude? On what is membership of the people conditional? What

    sense are we to make of the suspicion about the people that underlies

    traditional rejections of democracy as a viable template for government?

    Needless to say, these questions intersect with considerations about theterritorial scale of political authority: patterns of inclusion and exclusion

    appear very differently if politics is circumscribed a priori by territoriality

    or merely contingently related to it, in the sense that many (but not all)

    issues that political systems need to deal with are themselves inherently

    territorial. Also of crucial signicance in this respect are such institu-

    tional questions as rules for decision making and the existence of a

    status, possibly including specic rights and capacities, for minorities.

    The nature of political judgement. Again, this overlaps to a considerableextent with consideration of the nature of the people, but is nonetheless a

    4 John Crowley and Liana Giorgi

  • distinct question. To regard political capacity as an aspect of common sense,

    a skill that can be learned in principle by everyone, an aspect of character

    that itself may or may not be universally accessible, a gift that is likely to

    be rare and to ourish unpredictably, or a correlate of some kind ofhierarchically ordered wisdom, is to offer vastly different interpretations

    of what membership of a political community entails. Undoubtedly, the

    democratic temper tended to conne the debate to a fairly limited con-

    trast between political judgement as common sense and citizenship as

    popular education, but it would be misleading to view the other histori-

    cally attested positions as having solely antiquarian signicance. Current

    debates about the role of (especially scientic) expertise within democratic

    polities clearly show the survival of traditional issues and categories.

    What is important about these issues is that none can plausibly be regarded

    as foreclosed by common sense or theoretical logic. Arguably, all possible

    answers to all of them capture something of empirical signicance about

    observable political systems, as well as something of normative signicance

    about the fundamental idea of democracy. It is, in that sense, not simply an

    accident of the history of political thought that the various competing gen-

    eric models have emerged and survived through centuries of debate. Allow-ing for the vagaries of intellectual fashion, they sketch the conceptual

    universe of democratic thinking.

    Strong democracy and the concept of the public sphere

    Central to our understanding of a strong democracy is the notion of a

    public sphere. In discussions on democracy, and drawing in particular from

    the civic republican tradition, the term public sphere or public space isused to refer to the scope of citizen interaction found in democratic socie-

    ties. It is, to use Habermas (1989) terminology, the publicly relevant pri-

    vate sphere of interaction: here, individuals relate to one another not in

    terms of market transactions, nor in terms of power relations, but rather as

    politically equal citizens (subjects) of a polity.

    A public sphere delineates that space in which citizens come together to

    discuss and debate issues of common or public concern. The public space

    thus dened is easy to imagine and also realize in the ancient city republicor the local level of contemporary societies. It is much more difcult to

    bring about in metropolitan areas or the trans-national multi-lingual con-

    text. It is for this reason perhaps that contemporary discussion on the

    public space in general, and the European public space in particular, is very

    communication-centred, concerned with the role of the media in modern

    democracies and the potential of new communication technologies, like the

    internet, to provide virtual public spaces that can effectively replace real

    (physical) public spaces. Our approach in this book has been to focus on thepublic sphere as a guiding principle in democratic polities making necessary

    Introduction 5

  • the establishment and maintenance of public spaces, rather than a single

    public space. Our overall aim has been to judge the links between these

    multiple public spaces across different territorial levels of government, and

    especially across member states, and how these impact on each other and onthe European level of governance.

    A democratic polity centred on the public sphere has the following char-

    acteristics with reference to the six key questions identied in the previous

    section as central to democratic theory, i.e. the role of the state, the scale of

    political action, the processes that make up politics, the scope of politics,

    the nature of the people and the nature of political judgement:

    A democratic polity centred on the public sphere relates to an idea ofgovernment as authoritative command and emphasizes transparency

    of rule understood democratically as self-rule. Whether the state is a

    necessary framework in this respect is a matter of vigorous debate, but it

    is at least clear that in so far as the traditional territorial state is regar-

    ded as obsolete, the solution is to be sought in a hierarchically ordered

    scheme of territorial scales, i.e. in some form of federalism.

    Politics expresses the collective reexive life of a people. It is engaged inproblem-solving only (albeit necessarily) to the extent that such collectivelife brings the people up against problems, which become so only

    within the democratic process itself.

    Deliberation is the fundamental democratic process. Bargaining andpower struggles are acceptable only to the extent that they are norma-

    tively subordinate to deliberation and, ideally, set within an institutional

    framework where they can be regulated by deliberation.

    The subject matter of politics is indeterminate. However, a properlyordered democracy will be such that, at any time, the limits of politicalcompetence will be quite sharply drawn. In Habermas (1999) well

    known phrase, sovereignty and human rights are co-originary.

    The people includes, in principle, all those affected by the decisions takenin the course of the democratic process. The absolute minimum principle

    of inclusion is, of course, that all those who are subject to laws enacted

    democratically should participate equally in the process of deliberation

    and enactment.

    Political judgement is a skill that can be learned by anyone, and is indeeduniversally acquired in the context of socialization and education.

    Undoubtedly, some people may be less effectively taught; and, possibly,

    some may prove inherently more skilful. But neither of these distinctions

    offers any ground for distinguishing either in principle or in practice

    between those endowed with and devoid of political capacity.

    While such a model is fairly determinate in the context of democratic

    thinking and is in particular clearly and sharply opposed to other inuentialdemocratic modes of thinking, such as Schumpeterian elitist pluralism or

    6 John Crowley and Liana Giorgi

  • Hayekian liberalism, it still offers considerable scope for variation. If pub-

    licity-oriented democracy has a generic name in contemporary political

    theory it is republicanism, and in order to clarify how this analysis can

    contribute to a sharper conceptualization of the idea of a public sphere inthe specically European context, it is useful to specify some of the dis-

    tinctions between varieties of republicanism. These refer ultimately to four

    main titular gures: Aristotle, Machiavelli, Rousseau and Kant. It would be

    mistake, however, to conclude that there are four distinct varieties of

    republicanism: on the one hand it is possible, to a certain extent, to com-

    bine several of the above inuences (notably, of course, Rousseau and

    Kant); and on the other hand, important recent gures (most notably

    Arendt) have contributed to a redistribution of some of the classic issues. Asurvey of republicanism would be quite beyond the scope of this intro-

    ductory chapter, and the suggestions offered here, along with the theorists

    chosen, are mainly illustrative.

    Strong democracy structured by institutions

    Benjamin Barber, drawing inspiration primarily from Rousseau and to a

    lesser extent from Aristotle, offers a theory (and a prescription) of strongdemocracy as a way of life structured by institutions (Barber 1984, 1988).

    The current crisis of democracy, for example, is analysed by Barber in terms

    of the erosion of democratic institutions, including education, the public

    media and the state generally, particularly under the pernicious inuence of

    contemporary modes of globalization (Barber 1995). Neither liberalism nor

    tribalism can be faithful solutions because the notions of individuals and of

    communities are not solutions in themselves. It is not old-fashioned to

    believe in politics, including in concrete and pragmatic politics rather thanideal politics. This is why both the idea and especially the structures of

    democracy should be improved: the representative institutions on which

    Europe depends have drifted away from citizens. Liberty, in Barbers char-

    acteristically republican view, is distinctively political: it involves essentially

    the capacity to act together, and only in a subsidiary sense the capacity to

    protect myself from the encroachments of others. The existence of liberty

    as a tangible and situated good depends on the stability of national political

    institutions and on our capacity to modernize them and help them to playtheir role. Education the key to what Barber, in a striking phrase, idealizes

    as the aristocracy of everyone (Barber 1992) but also nationalism and

    religion are means of making this goal attainable. Politics does not mean

    trying to nd absolute truth or justice but making everyday choices taking

    reality into account: there are no a priori solutions. Political liberty thus

    entails being a responsive and responsible politician or citizen. This is why

    the state is not inherently far from citizens, or to be feared as liberals and

    conservatives tend to: state and citizens can work together to change theworld in the name of common political participation.

    Introduction 7

  • Undoubtedly, the common will of citizens, that is to say their collective

    feeling of membership, based on a common participation in the building of

    political society, a feeling of sovereignty, should be taken into account. As

    Aristotle wrote, men are political animals. Although each country has itsown political culture and traditions, the remarks above can and should

    be applied in all Western societies. Europe would not be ill advised to take

    inspiration from local participation in American society and to encourage

    political powers to be less centralized. Moreover, contemporary immigra-

    tion and multiculturalism can help us to nd political answers to the new

    identity claims which could mean the improvement of civic faith. Follow-

    ing Habermas, Barber argues that democracy is fed by a collective feeling of

    membership in a common (political) society. To welcome otherness there-fore entails building a common citizenship based on responsibility, popular

    sovereignty, political will and strong participatory institutions.

    A sense of community through political action

    Although clearly within it in a generic sense, Barber expresses scepticism

    about the republican tradition as expressed in contemporary political

    theory, precisely because of its traditional character. He is concerned, inparticular, that contemporary Machiavellianism may lack an adequate

    understanding of the public and of citizenship, and that the inuence of

    Arendt tends to be uncomfortably anti-modernist. Other contemporary

    republicans, on the contrary, take Arendt and/or Machiavelli as their key

    reference points. Etienne Tassin (1999), for instance, thinks that philosophy

    is very useful to politics because it allows men to understand common life

    in politics. This does not mean that an absolute truth conditions politics as

    individual and collective actions, but that understanding the political con-dition of individuals implies nding the sense of living together, which is

    not easy precisely because both events and political decisions are uncertain.

    Historicism must be banished, as well as relativism. As a consequence, a

    public political sphere of actions must be created and nourished to give

    politics a concrete dimension, to help it to be close to individuals and

    encourage them to participate in it. But, as Arendt said, since political

    action is much more than work (the goal of which is private, individual

    survival) because it gives sense to common life, common belonging to theworld and pluralism have the same foundations. We must not avoid the

    concrete world, reality, because politics is praxis. Once we have plurality, we

    have to build a political community of citizenship, that is to say the imple-

    mentation of common and deliberative political action.

    Pluralism means mutual recognition and shared culture, whereas collec-

    tive political action implies citizenship, political action and power, which is

    the opposite of domination, of strength. Moreover, the political sphere is a

    public sphere, it is not just a common and shared national or culturalsphere, as the latter concerns a limited number of people and the former the

    8 John Crowley and Liana Giorgi

  • whole political community of citizens. Tassin (1999) has specically applied

    this argument to the emergence of a European polity and has logically, on

    the basis of this interpretation of what publicity entails, expressed scepti-

    cism about the conceptual basis of a European public sphere. Politicalaction gives the individuals their real common identity. Furthermore, poli-

    tical judgement is collective and reinforces the common sense of the com-

    munity. Thus, the common world is composed of individuals who, as

    individuals, judge politically and, as a consequence, give a common sense to

    the political action which is part of the judgement. Tassin refers to Arendts

    interpretation of Kant, who considered that such a collective political jud-

    gement created a feeling of universality and cosmopolitan citizens.

    Tassin criticizes sovereignty because it implies submission and the absenceof common world, of freedom and of pluralism. As a matter of fact, power

    cannot belong to an individual or to a restricted group of people, it does

    not imply relationships, even between institutions and men. It belongs to

    the whole political community, even when some people represent other people

    within the political sphere. Indeed, the political sphere is fragile, because

    politics is fragile, indeterminate, threatened: time is abolished except in the

    concepts of beginning and promise. Politics exists only in collective action,

    in deliberation which does not have specic goals except itself. Politicalpower is, by denition, useless as it aims only at making individuals work

    together and take collective decisions for their common world. It does not

    aim at reaching a consensus, contrary to what Habermas claims, because

    politics is not government. More concretely, according to Tassin, there should

    be a balance of powers, because the law does not submit individuals, it rather

    links them to each other. Procedures, communication between people within

    the public sphere are not the point: the feeling of belonging to the same

    political community is much more crucial. Politics is an institution. Thecommon world both conditions citizenship and gives it its meaning. Indivi-

    duals are equals and independent, but they are also linked to each other

    through a fragile common feeling of membership and responsibility, and

    through the idea of political confrontation by virtue of the res publica.

    Beyond liberalism to emphasize civic virtues

    By contrast with both Barber and Tassin, John Pocock (1975) offers aninterpretation of republicanism in which Machiavelli is perhaps the most

    powerful inuence. Underlining Barbers point that modernity is one of the

    things at stake in debate within republicanism, Pocock qualies the exces-

    sively positive image of modernity understood in terms of open societies,

    private liberties, political rights, liberal economy and peace, by offering a

    critical historiography of liberalism. Politics in Western countries has been

    reduced to private interests and pluralism for more than thirty years. What

    we have forgotten are the key questions of living together and commonprinciples. This is why Machiavelli is a model for many authors for whom

    Introduction 9

  • politics means civic virtues and political ideals, i.e. political freedom, prop-

    erly understood. For Pocock, Machiavelli plays a major role in the Amer-

    ican imagination of nation building, which cannot be reduced to political

    and economical liberalism. He argues for a civic and humanistic denitionof politics: people are citizens before being traders. And virtue means that

    people work together for their common destinies through a stable and plur-

    alistic political order in which all can recognize themselves. Such a repub-

    lican order is based on autonomy, civicness, limited specialization of

    political functions, and active participation of all citizens in politics. In

    Pococks opinion, the debate on modernity must take into account indivi-

    dual rights and the limitation of political authority, but discussion of poli-

    tics cannot be restricted to such liberal concerns.According to Quentin Skinner (1978) and others (for example, Alasdair

    MacIntyre), there is a moral gap between the liberal conception of politics

    and the Aristotelian political tradition. The conception of negative liberty,

    for instance, has made political liberty a negative notion something is

    lacking. One of the claims about political liberty in this line of thinking

    links freedom to self-government, to civic virtues (personal liberty is linked

    with the notion of public service). This means that only some well dened

    ends deserve to be pursued. Another claim is that freedom implies con-straints: freedom depends on our willingness and capacity to maintain civic

    virtues. Virtue is thus a constraint; we must force ourselves to be free (which

    explicitly relates Rousseau to the tradition under discussion). The supposed

    tension between individual rights and duties may thus be simply a mis-

    placed liberal obsession. In fact, according to Skinner, real freedom, based

    on political participation, is not an obligation, since humans are naturally

    social (Aristotle); moreover, they are moral beings with human purposes. As

    a consequence, human freedom may be a positive notion. This is whyhumans need to create a political association in order to realize their nature

    and liberty.

    In the classical republican tradition (Machiavelli, Harrington, Milton),

    the condition for freedom thus understood is to abolish absolutism in order

    to live in a free state. The benets of living in free states, from the Machia-

    vellian perspective, are civic greatness and wealth, and also personal lib-

    erty (individuals remain free to pursue their private ends, whatever they

    are). In order to maintain individual liberties, we must promote the respublica, a self-governing republic, which implies that citizens cultivate civic

    virtue, the will to serve the common good, to improve the freedom of the

    community. The required qualities are courage, determination to defend our

    country against foreign conquerors, and prudence; and the required insti-

    tutional conditions, which in some ways are even more difcult to establish,

    are guarantees that political decisions are taken by the entire political body

    and the avoidance of corruption. The means are the coercive power of the

    law, but not in a Hobbesian sense. For Machiavelli, the priority is to protectindividual liberties and avoid servitude.

    10 John Crowley and Liana Giorgi

  • Republican thinkers in what is often called the classical tradition thus

    connect social freedom with self-government, but also link the idea of per-

    sonal liberty to that of virtuous public service. That the preservation of

    individual liberty should imply coercion and constraint (duties which mayhave to be enforced) is only supercially paradoxical (pace liberalism)

    because our ends, being indeterminate, are not always moral (pace Aris-

    totle). There is nothing contradictory in proposing to place moral con-

    straints on oneself. Today, it is commonly said (or wished) that there are

    many areas of public life where increased participation may improve the

    accountability of our representatives. But the most important goal is not to

    build a genuine democracy based on power to the people. Rather, we

    must rst of all put our duties before our rights to warrant the latter.

    Dialogue towards rational consensus

    Jurgen Habermas (1999) self-consciously relates himself to the republican

    tradition, but derives it primarily from Kant, with the added inuence of

    Rousseau. His interpretation is thus signicantly different from both Bar-

    bers straightforward Rousseauism and classical Machiavellianism, and

    also conicts on a number of points with the Arendtian tradition. Further-more, his sustained attention to the post-metaphysical fact of pluralism

    places him in a closer and more internal connection to liberalism (e.g.

    Rawls) than most republicans for whom, indeed, liberalism is often the

    main conceptual adversary. Habermas himself would argue that his theories

    offer a synthesis of liberalism and republicanism and reveal many of the

    supposed oppositions between them to be bogus. While we may not accept

    that conclusion, it is clear enough that it conveniently summarizes his

    overarching intellectual objectives.Habermas conceptual framework seeks to combine law, justice, democ-

    racy and rights. Therefore, morality is a key concept, as well as a law which

    is to be procedural and discursively grounded. This project is bound to

    create a common and participatory political sphere, a common feeling of

    membership in the same political community. Habermas does not agree

    with Arendt, who thought that conict more exactly peaceful conict

    was the key to democracy and in a sense even its ultimate goal. According

    to him, pluralism, differences of opinions and values (e.g. different concep-tions of the good) can be handled only through rational consensus, not

    conict. The consensus, in turn, cannot be strictly substantive (in the post-

    metaphysical context), but must have a procedural character. Referring to

    Kant, Habermas insists on the importance of dialogue and considerations

    of differences, while rejecting communitarianism. Habermas also seeks to

    bridge or at least narrow the gap between democracy and rights in stressing

    the importance of commonly shared values, which implies that laws should

    be self-imposed and binding in order to reconcile legal and factual equality(the discourse principle links self-legislation to law).

    Introduction 11

  • European democracy in terms of publicity

    Why give a democratic model centred on the public sphere ideology pre-

    cedence for the European Union? There are two main reasons for this. Our

    argument is rst, that this model has some kind of normative priority;

    second that that there are specic reasons within the dynamics of the

    emerging European polity for competing models to be less likely to be

    available here than at the national level.

    Normative considerations

    What is most distinctive about the civic republican model as a general the-

    oretical approach to democracy is that it is premised on scepticism about

    the two fundamental processes that lie behind the most practically sig-

    nicant competing models: aggregation and delegation.

    The aggregative principle states that, citizens preferences being diverse,often conicting, chaotically uncoordinated and imperfectly known, the

    political process must offer processes for them to be bundled (by setting a

    manageable agenda framed by issues on which people can adopt a fairly

    limited range of relevant and possibly sharply conicting positions) as

    well as decision procedures that ensure that, on the whole, policies (dened

    as choices among bundled positions) that are opposed by the majority or by

    powerful vocal minorities are not implemented. The principle of delegation,

    which is compatible with the rst though not necessarily combined with it,states that politics is, for technical reasons, subject to the same general laws

    of division of labour as all other forms of collective human activity.

    Competence, taste, ability, ambition, along with various random factors,

    lead some to concern themselves with the management of public affairs and

    others to be passive or indifferent. Not only is there nothing wrong with

    this it is actually more efcient in producing the public good than a

    participatory system where everyone tries to do a bit of everything. It fol-

    lows that it is both likely and desirable for democratic systems (dened forthese purposes as systems where everyones voice counts for something and

    everyones vote counts equally) to develop mechanisms for efcient division

    of political labour. Representative institutions, political parties, opinion polls

    and the mass media are among the characteristic institutions of delegation

    democracy in this respect.

    It is a reasonable summary to regard contemporary democratic systems

    as relying, on the whole, on a combination of aggregation and delegation, in

    the sense that their characteristic institutions depend on both principles andthat the standard justications offered of them depend on claims about the

    mutually supportive operation of delegation and aggregation. At the theo-

    retical level, the Schumpeterian model of competitive elite liberalism is an

    ideal-type in this regard. The question, then, is what might be wrong with

    this generic model and what might lead us, in spite of its undoubted

    12 John Crowley and Liana Giorgi

  • descriptive usefulness, to give normative priority to civic republicanism? The

    answer lies in two sets of considerations that are entirely familiar from the

    literature, but the signicance of which nonetheless needs to be appreciated.

    First, the formal justication of aggregation is open to a series of dama-ging objections. Voting paradoxes are sufciently familiar not to require

    detailed discussion here. Sufce it to mention Kenneth Arrows impossi-

    bility theorem which, generalizing Condorcets paradox, shows that the

    conditions required for voting procedures to produce collectively stable

    decisions in terms of xed prior preferences are, theoretically, highly

    restrictive. In addition, as a model of democracy considered substantively

    rather than formally, aggregation is open to the challenge that, by con-

    sidering preferences to be xed and largely independent from the politicalprocess, it excludes any idea of citizenship as participation in a process of

    collective self-determination. It is not necessary to subscribe to the strong view

    that, in the words of Pierre Bourdieu (1980), public opinion does not exist in

    order to justify scepticism about the stability, coherence and even signicance

    of opinions expressed publicly. But, if preferences are in some sense inde-

    terminate, the very idea of aggregation becomes largely meaningless.

    Second, and to a large extent independently, the idea that delegation as a

    principle of political organization might be justied in democratic termscomes up against some fairly massive issues of political sociology. At a

    formal level, democratic delegation requires both a robust conception of

    public opinion regarded as not essentially exposed to manipulation in the

    context of elite competition and an elite that is fairly open, or at the very

    least not entirely endogamous. There is extensive evidence that really exist-

    ing democracies tend to violate both conditions indeed, arguably, the his-

    torical trend in so far as there is one is towards increasing violation.

    Specic European considerations

    The general normative priority of the characteristic features of civic repub-

    licanism takes on a specic signicance at the European level. Elite plural-

    ism in historically established democracies can rely on a dense web of

    institutions, practices, and background values and preconceptions, that

    correct some of the bias inherent in the principles of aggregation and dele-

    gation. On the one hand, some idea of the public interest is embedded innationhood and statehood: this may be imperfectly articulated and far from

    consensual, but it nonetheless remains a background resource that reduces

    the need for the formal institutions of political authority to produce their

    own legitimacy within the terms of their own operation. On the other hand,

    and in many ways more importantly, political authority is only one aspect

    of a whole web of regulation that corresponds to what we might call soci-

    etal governance.

    Institutional density undoubtedly sharply distinguishes the EU from itsmember states. Whatever one may think of elite pluralism or its corporatist

    Introduction 13

  • variants in normative terms, it is abundantly clear that the background

    resources on which it can rely at national level are signicantly lacking at

    European level. The lack of a common language is merely one aspect of this

    decit, and in many ways not the most important. Of more profound sig-nicance is a degree of institutional fragmentation that is a barrier to the

    emergence of a shared political culture and, simultaneously, a major factor

    in the absence of a focused political agenda. Comparison with cohesive

    federal states perhaps brings this contrast into sharper relief. The United

    States has regional political systems embedded both in institutions and in

    an available language of identity. But there is unquestionably a national

    political system that serves to organize patterns of regional variation, and

    furthermore one that, inside the Beltway, is highly cohesive. In so far as theEU can be considered from the same perspective, the situation is almost

    precisely the opposite. In other words, it is the thickness and self-contained

    nature of the characteristic institutional systems of each of the member

    states, rather than any substantive difference between them, that best

    accounts for the unquestionably and correlative thinness of the EU.

    These facts are very familiar, but their signicance seems not to be ade-

    quately appreciated. It is striking that even a defender of the EU such as

    Jacques Delors has gone on record as regarding four policy areas as beinginherently inappropriate for Europeanization: education, culture, social

    welfare, and law and order. In light of earlier comments, this list looks very

    like an enumeration of what is institutionally constitutive of state-centred

    nationhood; its effect, if taken seriously, is certainly to entrench an irre-

    ducible difference between the member states, which remain heirs to the

    nation-state tradition and continue to reect it in modied form, and the

    EU, which cannot aspire to the same degree of institutional and symbolic

    cohesiveness. It follows that, unless the democratic decit is taken to be anecessary feature of Europeanization which implies that, as Euro-sceptics

    would claim, a choice must be made between democracy and Europe the

    EU must, for structural reasons, draw more on the distinctive resources of

    civic republicanism than the member states. Publicity may be a background

    resource at national level; it cannot be at European level. It is to this extent

    that consideration of the specic features of the political integration of

    Europe reinforces the general normative arguments for a generically civic

    republican approach to the assessment of contemporary democracy.The reader will note that we consistently avoid considering the problem

    of democracy at European level as one of identity that emphasizes the

    symbolic elements (passports, anthems, ags and the other paraphernalia of

    nationhood). It is often presented in public debate if not also in academic

    contributions that subscription to a form of European collective identity

    could possibly overcome both the actual and the perceived democratic def-

    icit. In other words, the democratic decit is closely related to an identity

    decit. However, rather than formulating such an identity at the symboliclevel, it is both more theoretically coherent and more practically plausible to

    14 John Crowley and Liana Giorgi

  • relate it to the democratic process itself. This idea that democracy might be

    self-legitimizing is a little more plausible. If people are given procedures that

    enable them to be genuinely citizens, then they will tend to act as citizens

    and feel themselves to be truly members of a political community. Intui-tively, a public sphere or space is one in which genuine citizenship is possi-

    ble. Adequate democratic procedures would thus promote a sense of

    identication, and vice-versa, leading to a virtuous cycle of truly European

    citizenship.

    The public sphere as a sociological process

    The previous sections tell us what a public sphere would look like and whythe EU is unlikely to be democratic without one. What they do not tell us is

    how public spheres emerge in general. The question is what sociological

    features might guarantee, or less ambitiously permit, the emergence and

    stability of a public sphere structured by a language of political justication

    based on impartial argument that serves as a regulatory ideal. The point is

    not, of course, that political actors cease to have distinctive interests, values

    and identities when speaking or acting publicly. They cannot, and even if

    they could there would be no normative reason to demand it of them.Rather the regulatory language is one that enables actors to know what

    kinds of arguments count as good and what things cannot be said in public

    without discrediting a claim and its author. In a very formal sense, such

    criteria are indistinguishable from political correctness, which may be

    understood in a very derogatory way. For public language to have normative

    signicance, therefore, some standard of conformity to the public interest

    needs to be available at least in principle. To make this requirement positive

    would be highly implausible: indeed, we should be suspicious of anyattempt to dene the public interest independently from the democratic

    process itself. It is more plausible, however, as a negative constraint: the

    idea of the public interest equips us with tools to detect arguments, whether

    explicit or implied by claims advanced, that are prima facie bad in the sense

    that they are designed solely to use public means to obtain private advan-

    tage. In democratic terms, obviously, such a language can be neither chosen

    nor imposed; it necessarily emerges, and one would expect it on general

    sociological grounds to emerge as an aspect of procedures and processes inwhich it is embedded and to which it gives meaning. Publicity, understood

    in terms of public accountability (accountability in public and account-

    ability to the idea of the public), is simply a convenient and sociologically

    resonant name for this kind of evaluative language.

    The rst feature of publicity is what Habermas (1996) puts at the centre

    of his analysis: the fact that the public sphere relates politics to law. Law-

    making involves dening general rules for persons and circumstances

    unknown, or at least imperfectly known. It means shifting attention frombargaining about resource sharing for any specic issue to deliberating

    Introduction 15

  • about rules to guide resource sharing more generally. The planning and use

    of physical infrastructure, such as housing and leisure facilities, offer

    numerous examples. Such infrastructure obviously occupies specic spaces,

    and issues of access and quality are themselves highly localized. It may,however, be more politically effective to mobilize at a higher level. In that

    case, one would expect to encounter the claim that the state should provide

    (or order the council to provide) resource x for group Y. However, forms of

    mobilization that succeed in federating a durable coalition usually have a

    rather different character, expressing more abstract, more generalizable in

    a word, more political concerns. Typically, the revised claim is that law A

    should be passed in order to guarantee equitable access to resource x (or

    some broader class X of resources) for all groups (including, of course, Y).In other words, claims that are legislative in the generic sense that they are

    about the rules of politics are political in a way that typically does not make

    sense locally because the local is by denition not so much a space as a

    sub-space. It is of its nature to be embedded in a larger-scale entity. The

    complexity of Europe, on the other hand, is underlined by the fact that the

    member states are neither strictly autonomous, nor merely local with

    regard to the EU.

    What is important sociologically is that the politicization of claims, andthe corresponding shift from bargaining to deliberation, depend on the

    dynamics of mobilization rather than on the good intentions of the actors

    involved. Otherwise, the idea of a public sphere would be purely wishful

    thinking. Whether the dynamics of mobilization sufce to impose delibera-

    tion on actors who do not have an interest in generalizing and politicizing

    their claims is, however, doubtful. The process sketched with reference to

    the nationalization of local claims depends crucially on the comparative

    weakness of the initial mobilization and the structural necessity to changescale, because of the lack of legislative capacity at the local level. Pure bar-

    gaining may be a perfectly stable format for other kinds of claims. Haber-

    mas himself would of course argue that the dynamics of argument even

    within a bargaining format force the participants towards deliberation.

    But this is inadequate, since it leaves willingness to participate in good-faith

    argument ungrounded within the dynamics of mobilization.

    The problem for a sociological analysis of the public sphere is, therefore,

    to specify the structural conditions that make participation in deliberation arational political strategy even for actors who are unreasonable in the

    Rawlsian sense that they are not motivated by a desire for just cooperation.

    Such conditions cannot, of course, provide guarantees, or even impose

    enforceable constraints on political participation. Arguably, indeed, democ-

    racy depends on the absence of guarantees or constraints of this kind. The

    conditions are simply those that make it more probable that membership of

    a society organized as a political community should take the form of parti-

    cipation based on public-spiritedness in other words what one wouldusually call, for normative purposes, citizenship.

    16 John Crowley and Liana Giorgi

  • The sociology of political participation, of which work inspired by the

    theories of Pierre Bourdieu is exemplary, is generally regarded as and to a

    real extent is self-consciously constituted as a critique of and alternative

    to the idealism of Habermas and other proponents of Offentlichkeit. WhatBourdieu calls the political eld (champ politique) coincides empirically

    with the public sphere: it is characterized by the mobilization of resources,

    the expression of interests and the articulation of justicatory language

    (Bourdieu 2000). It is the forum in which membership of a society orga-

    nized as political community is constituted the forum, in other words, of

    citizenship. In Bourdieus interpretation, however, the political eld is also

    the point where political domination converges, in mutually reinforcing

    ways, with economic and symbolic domination to arrange and justifyunequal participation. It is the place, in other words, where domination

    dresses up as citizenship. As people confronted with cross-dressing tend to,

    Bourdieu views this with a mixture of technical admiration and moral

    revulsion.

    At rst sight, no two things could be more different than a public sphere

    and a political eld. In fact they are, pace both Bourdieu and Habermas,

    mutually reinforcing. What prevents citizenship being simply a sham in the

    political eld is the competitive pressure to which those who attempt tomonopolize it are subjected. And what prevents the public sphere being

    merely wishful thinking is precisely the same competitive pressure. What

    develops, in other words, is an uneasy balance between the tendency of

    public-spiritedness to emerge from cynical politics and the tendency of even

    the most idealistic politics to close in on itself. This balance, like citizenship

    itself, is a question of empirical degree: there are no knock-down argu-

    ments, sociological or quasi-transcendental. Effectively, a public sphere is an

    open political eld: one from which nothing is excluded a priori and inwhich practical limits to inclusion can be overcome if people care about

    them enough. If it did acquire closure in any of these respects, it would

    cease, ultimately, to be public in the full sense of the word. Meaningful

    citizenship is the correlate of such openness.

    The most crucial point to be noted about this outline characterization is

    that it makes the emergence of a public sphere a matter of degree. Publicity

    is not either present or absent; it is more or less signicant within a political

    system. Its signicance grows as a wider range of actors and issues areregulated by publicity, and conversely declines when larger sections of the

    political process are condoned off from the kind of normative assessment

    that republican citizenship entails. More formally, it may be useful to dis-

    tinguish for these purposes between three dimensions of openness that are,

    in principle, fairly independent, and the impact of which on the strong idea

    of publicity is cumulative. Furthermore, the three dimensions summarize

    the thrust of the extensive research on the forms and implications of poli-

    tical exclusion especially the subtle exclusion that affects those who areformally included as citizens, but whose concerns remain unheard and

    Introduction 17

  • unrecognized. The rst dimension of openness is in terms of persons. A

    genuinely public sphere would be open in principle to all and, in practice,

    would offer a sufciently wide range of options and relevant resources

    including opportunities to establish innovative coalitions for no one to bestructurally excluded. The democratic ideal, of course, would demand truly

    equal access, but this standard is so exacting that it is of little assistance in

    assessing real-world systems that are, to varying degrees, imperfect. The

    second dimension of openness is in terms of issues. A genuinely public

    sphere would be indeterminate with respect to questions that can be raised

    and problems that matter. At any point in time, a political community will

    tend to rely on a broadly shared common sense within which some things

    are not political, not topics for public discussion, not recognized as thingsat all. This is normatively acceptable so long as that common sense is

    provisional not in the sense that all actors submit it to reexive criticism

    (which would be incompatible with the very idea of common sense) but,

    much more simply that nothing prevents it being challenged at any time by

    any one. Again, it would be absurdly exacting and ultimately self-defeating

    to insist that everything must always be up for grabs, but the principle of

    publicity does give us the critical resources to be sceptical of things that are

    persistently and routinely taken for granted. The third, and in some respectsmost challenging, dimension of openness is in terms of modes of discourse.

    One interpretation of publicity associates it closely with a particular kind of

    public intervention one based on impartiality and reasoned argument

    from general principles and abstract concerns. It is a familiar nding of

    critical sociology, especially from a feminist perspective, that such rules of

    engagement even if only at the level of entrenched common sense are

    highly exclusive. A necessary corollary of openness to persons and issues is

    that discourse is not regulated other than by the requirements of delibera-tion itself, and we might indeed add, against Habermas own views on the

    communicative process, that civility as a condition of open-endedness is a far

    more appropriate standard here than rationality as a condition of consensus.

    Arguably, the public sphere might benet hugely from the deliberate foster-

    ing of non-standard forms of engagement, precisely because our taken-for-

    granted notions of impartiality carry heavy unacknowledged baggage.

    Contents and structure of this book

    Let us start by summarizing the theoretical argument of the previous sec-

    tions. This is that the democratic model centred on the public sphere, which

    should and is being given precedence for the European Union by reason of

    the latters institutional thinness, implies a twofold focus on citizenship:

    from the top-down perspective, on the institutional opportunity structures

    for participation and, more specically, their openness with regard to per-

    sons, issues or modes of discourse; from the bottom-up perspective, on theforces and actors that are shaping mobilization and, in turn, the generalization

    18 John Crowley and Liana Giorgi

  • of political claims beyond the national, hence at the European level. At the

    same time, a public sphere is not clearly delineated in that it either exists or

    it is absent. Its emergence is rather a matter of degree: a strong European

    democracy is that in which the public sphere plays a signicant role; a weakEuropean democracy is that where the opposite is the case.

    This theoretical argument provided the basis for the research that is

    documented in this volume. All of the contributors in this volume worked

    together over a period of three years studying public debates and instances

    of participation across policy domains and several countries, as well as at

    the level of the EU supra-national institutions, in an attempt to both

    document and analyse the emergence of the European public sphere and its

    degree of signicance. Our research design was guided by two principalconsiderations that follow directly from our theoretical argument: First,

    that in order to tap on the emergence of the European public sphere it is

    necessary to look into the decision structures and procedures, and examine

    to what extent these allow for the contestation of decision-making by citi-

    zens and their representatives. Second, that insofar as the consolidation of

    the European public sphere depends equally, if not more signicantly, on

    the ability of relevant intermediaries civil society organizations, political

    parties or social partner organizations to Europeanize political claims,assessing the degree and scope of the European public sphere implies that

    we have to look into the patterns of mobilization and narratives of these

    actors. Accordingly, the contributions to this volume deal respectively with

    opportunity structures for participation (Chapter 3), the emergence of new

    European actors (Chapters 4 and 5), and the latters narratives on the

    European Union at the supra-national and national levels (Chapters 6 and

    7). Chapter 2 places this research in the context of the democratic audit

    scholarship. Following this short overview, let us take a closer look at theindividual chapters.

    In search of a methodological framework that would allow us to measure

    and monitor the degree to which publicity informs European democracy,

    Liana Giorgi, in Chapter 2, suggests that it might be more reasonable to

    think about these questions in terms of democratization. Even in the

    absence of supra-national institutions such as those of the European Union,

    contemporary societies would still be facing democratic challenges by

    reason of the complexity brought about by the growing inter-dependenciesbetween territorial and societal levels of governance, within as well as

    beyond the nation-state. The extension of the scope of the democratic audit

    scholarship to consider ever more social and political institutions supports

    this view. From this perspective, it is more reasonable to think about

    democratic practices in terms of governance mode rather than in demo-

    cratic modelling terms. As argued earlier in this chapter, contemporary

    democratic systems tend to rely on a combination of aggregation and dele-

    gation to arrive at collective decisions, and following our theoretical argu-ments, deliberative procedures are or should be gaining in signicance in a

    Introduction 19

  • democratic framework centred on the public sphere. Giorgi extends this line

    of reasoning to apply to the institutional level. In turn, this means that

    monitoring democracy in order to assess the degree of its openness in terms

    of publicity must not only be carried out at different territorial levels andacross different societal institutions, but also with the overall objective of

    establishing the extent to which different procedural modes for aggregating

    or integrating citizen interests are used and with what effect. This is the

    approach subsequently adopted in Chapter 3.

    Based on the results of an empirical study across several European policy

    domains, Ingmar von Homeyer (Chapter 3) is able to show that there is a

    signicant variation across policy domains with regard to both the institu-

    tional opportunity structures for participation and the total intensity ofparticipatory practice as such. However these two dimensions do not stand

    in an obvious direct relationship. In other words, participatory practice is

    not determined alone by the opportunity structures for participation, nor

    do the latter, when they exist, always lead to the desired democratic input in

    the decision process. The relationship is much more complex and needs to

    take into account various factors and primarily the decision procedures at

    work both at the European and national levels, the competencies of Eur-

    opean institutions as compared to their counterparts at national level, thedegree of felt common affectedness of the key issues under consideration, as

    well as the existence of key civil society organizations with strong advocacy

    coalitions. Indeed, argues von Homeyer, the latter two factors carry a far

    greater weight than the former. In other words, participatory governance is

    more likely to emerge in those areas that deal with themes which are per-

    ceived as shared across Europe and where there are key civil society or other

    organizations that mobilize at the European level. Interestingly, the degree

    to which interest organizations mobilize at the European level stands oftenin inverse relationship to the degree of organizational embededness of these

    actors at the national level. In other words, the more nationally embedded

    institutional actors are, the less they are likely to mobilize at the European

    level. For instance, the degree of European mobilization of environmental

    organizations is far greater than that of trade unions even though social

    policy issues display as high a level of common affectedness as questions

    related to environmental sustainability. The fact that social policy themes

    such as employment have till recently been diverted from public attention bydealing with them through the open method of coordination corroborates

    the tendency of long-established interest organizations at national level to

    work by lobbying national governments or in concert with other national

    interest organizations. To this should be added that on key sensitive topics,

    like social and welfare policy, national governments act as gatekeepers when

    it comes to launching or deepening European debates.

    These ndings lead von Homeyer to advance three principal propositions

    with far-reaching implications with regard to how to promote participatorygovernance. The rst is that the issue of modications of decision-rules or

    20 John Crowley and Liana Giorgi

  • stronger EU competencies is far less important than generally thought.

    Modications to decision-rules with regard to EU supra-national institu-

    tions might be necessary for efciency purposes. They are, however, not key

    for participatory governance. The second proposition is that timing has animportant effect on the emergence (or not) of participatory governance.

    From the perspective of civil society organizations, this of course means

    that it is important to remain always on the alert, seeking to capitalize on

    windows of opportunity that facilitate specic concerns being publicized

    widely. From the top-down perspective of state institutions seeking to pro-

    mote participatory governance and assuming that this is indeed sincerely

    aspired to it implies that a reactive mechanism ought to be structured

    into consultation or participation procedures in order to encourage thearticulation of concerns and demands as input to decision-making. Finally,

    the third proposition is that Europeanization begins at the national level

    and is directly linked to the desire and ability of national actors and stake-

    holders to attach a European dimension to political claims.

    That this Europeanization of political claims is only happening at a slow

    pace is shown by the research reported in Chapter 4, which deals with the

    (European) political class. In Chapter 4, Elise Feron, John Crowley and

    Liana Giorgi report on the results of an attitudinal survey carried outamong members of the European political class. These are persons holding

    or aspiring to a political ofce at European or national level or working in

    political functions for institutions dealing with European affairs. Our

    respondents can be distinguished between Euro-sceptics and Euro-enthusiasts,

    whereby Euro-scepticism is far more widespread than Euro-enthusiasm, which

    is mainly to be found among Swedish respondents and members of the

    Green and Liberal parties. At the same time, we nd across the political

    spectrum a majority being disillusioned with mainstream representativepolitics. More signicantly, however, we nd a complete dissonance with

    regard to the future of the European Union and of the project of political

    integration. This dissonance exists within national delegations as well as

    within political groupings. Only a minority (less than one quarter) appear to

    favour some form of federalism for the EU. The rest are equally divided

    between a model of cooperative intergovernmentalism and a view that sees

    no role for either the European Parliament or national elected ofcials and

    which we have termed, following Dahrendorf, glocalism.In other words, even though debates in Europe increasingly come to dis-

    play a shared policy language, as shown by von Homeyer in Chapter 3,

    debates about Europe have yet to nd a shared political language and their

    representatives, as shown by Feron et al. in Chapter 4. This dissonance or

    the lack of a unifying European ideology across the political spectrum or of

    unifying European political ideologies within political parties might explain

    the continuing legitimacy decit of European institutions and the European

    Union as a whole, which in the medium- to long-term can aggravate itsdemocratic decit or harm the nascent European public sphere.

    Introduction 21

  • In Chapter 5, Elise Feron looks at another emerging European political

    actor, namely the anti-globalization movement. The future of the European

    Union as a political system and its policies are also central concerns for the

    anti-globalization movement. The set of movements that gather under thebanner of anti-globalization (or advocating a different type of globaliza-

    tion) are not primarily targeting the European Union through their mobili-

    zation; rather they are using EU institutions, events or policies to bring

    forward specic concerns. By so doing they have been both favouring and

    accompanying the growth of the European public sphere and have con-

    tributed to renewing the old repertoire traditionally used by social move-

    ments at the European level. Perhaps more importantly they speak for the

    existence of a European civil society and for its desire to take a more activerole in decision-making.

    In Chapter 6, Liana Giorgi, Niki Rodousakis, Marisol Garcia and

    Martin Peterson take a closer look at the debate on the European Union as

    a community of values. The latter exemplies many of the challenges and

    contradictions entailed in the European political integration project and in

    turn, explains the difculties with ideological design. This debate, they

    argue, is neither new nor straightforward, yet until recently the natural

    tendency within European institutions has been to relegate it to expertcommittees and keep it away from the public sphere, probably because it

    was judged as potentially explosive. Giorgi et al. argue that there are three

    distinct narratives on the European Union as a community of values and

    that the ultimate choice for one or the other narrative or, more realistically,

    their combination, will determine both the character and scope of European

    political integration as well as the disposition of the European public

    sphere. The rst narrative links European values with democratic principles

    but is ultimately about the future of national sovereignty. The second nar-rative seeks the enlargement of European values to include social values and

    more, specically, the commitment of the EU to full employment, a social

    market economy and the welfare state. Despite the establishment of a Eur-

    opean social agenda and a European Employment Strategy, not much pro-

    gress could be made in this respect the main reason for this was the lack

    of agreement concerning the division of competencies between supra-

    national and national institutions. Finally, probably the most explosive of

    the three narratives concerning the EU as a community of values, is thatwhich attaches a cultural dimension to European values. The key question

    here is the extent to which European identity should and could transcend

    nationalist aspirations centred on cultural and religious homogeneity.

    In Chapter 7, the nal thematic chapter of this book, Michal Illner,

    Daniel Cermak, Tomas Kostelecky and Jana Stachova take a look at one of

    the new member states and illustrate, with reference to the referendum in

    the Czech Republic regarding EU accession, how overall approval for EU

    membership need not coincide with acceptance of the political project ofEuropean integration. Even though Czech citizens voted in favour of EU

    22 John Crowley and Liana Giorgi

  • accession by a clear majority, a juxtaposition of the referendum results with

    electoral results and the results of attitudinal/sociological surveys carried

    out at around the same time shows that this yes to the European Union

    was far from being enthusiastic. An equivalent amount of caution is prob-ably called for when assessing the referendum results in France and the

    Netherlands regarding the Constitutional Treaty. A yes can mean different

    things to different people just like a no. Perhaps more importantly, what a

    yes might imply in terms of a democratic political system has still to be

    specied. The debate has in fact just begun.

    Introduction 23

  • 2 Democratization and the EuropeanUnion

    Liana Giorgi

    The territorial scale and resulting complexity of trans-national democracies

    renders these fragile with regard to democratic standards and practices.

    Multi-level and exible governance mechanisms may appear as extending

    the opportunity structures for stakeholder and citizen participation in deci-

    sion-making, but assuring this materializes implies submitting these new

    institutional structures to democratic scrutiny. Social institutions in

    advanced democracies tend to substitute real with virtual representation

    and participation with technical expertise. This could lead to the transfor-mation of advanced democracies into modern forms of guardianship. One

    way to avoid this is through comprehensive democratic auditing that asserts,

    rather than negates, the signicance of mainstream criteria for democratic

    political systems and decision processes.

    A democratic assessment of the European Union political system as

    representing a trans-national form of democracy-in-the-making must be

    carried out at different territorial levels. The emergence of a supranational

    actor does not make national democracy (and assessment) obsolete, itrather presupposes it. Furthermore, in advanced democratic societies, like

    the European Union, democratic assessment must be extended to cover

    social institutions like civil society, the media and economic corporations, as

    well as policy domains. EU democratic auditing is best thought of as a

    nested activity that pulls together information from different sources and

    levels of government and concentrates on comparisons across territorial l


Recommended