+ All Categories
Home > Documents > LILLA, Salvatore R. C., The Notion of Infinitude in Ps.-dionysius Areopagita

LILLA, Salvatore R. C., The Notion of Infinitude in Ps.-dionysius Areopagita

Date post: 26-Feb-2018
Category:
Upload: andrei-oroban
View: 226 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend

of 12

Transcript
  • 7/25/2019 LILLA, Salvatore R. C., The Notion of Infinitude in Ps.-dionysius Areopagita

    1/12

    Oxford University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Theological

    Studies.

    http://www.jstor.org

    THE NOTION OF INFINITUDE IN Ps.-DIONYSIUS AREOPAGITA

    Author(s): Salvatore R. C. LillaSource: The Journal of Theological Studies, NEW SERIES, Vol. 31, No. 1 (APRIL 1980), pp. 93-103Published by: Oxford University PressStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/23959150Accessed: 15-01-2016 15:27 UTC

    F R N SLinked references are available on JSTOR for this article:http://www.jstor.org/stable/23959150?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents

    You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of contentin a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship.For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    This content downloaded from 95.77.230.26 on Fri, 15 Jan 2016 15:27:31 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/http://www.jstor.org/publisher/ouphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/23959150http://www.jstor.org/stable/23959150?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contentshttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/23959150?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contentshttp://www.jstor.org/stable/23959150http://www.jstor.org/publisher/ouphttp://www.jstor.org/
  • 7/25/2019 LILLA, Salvatore R. C., The Notion of Infinitude in Ps.-dionysius Areopagita

    2/12

    NOTES

    AND

    STUDIES

    93

    He

    imitates the

    spiritual beings by

    his words while he is

    making

    supplication;

    and

    holily

    he teaches

    the

    people

    to

    cry

    1Holy'.

    The utterance

    of sanctification of the

    heavenly beings

    he recites to

    men,

    that

    they may

    be

    crying: 'Holy, Holy, Holy,

    Lord'.1

    There is

    good

    reason for the

    epiklesis

    and the Sanctus to be the

    only

    parts

    of the

    anaphora

    mentioned;

    the reason is hinted

    at

    by

    Edmund

    Bishop

    in the

    Appendix

    to

    Connolly's

    translation.

    Bishop

    carefully

    noted that after the Sursum corda the canon seems to have been recited

    silently except

    for three

    things:

    the

    concluding

    words of the Preface

    which

    led into the

    Sanctus;

    at

    the

    signing

    of

    the

    mysteries

    when the

    people

    said

    'Amen';

    and after the

    epiklesis,

    when 'the

    priest

    makes

    his

    voice heard to all the

    people,

    and

    signs

    with his hand over the

    mysteries,

    as

    before',

    but now 'to

    teach . . .

    that

    they

    are

    accomplished'.2

    Since

    Narsai

    was concerned

    to

    describe

    the

    priest's theological

    function

    in

    the

    Eucharist,

    he would

    naturally

    mention the

    epiklesiseven though

    it

    appears

    to have been recited

    silentlysince

    he

    regarded

    this as

    the

    moment

    of consecration. This was at the centre of the

    priest's

    function.

    But Narsai

    might

    be

    expected

    to turn back to

    give

    some

    explanation

    of

    what for the

    congregation

    must

    have been

    the

    most

    significant

    and

    puzzling interruptions of the silent canon, namely the recitation of the

    Sanctus.Sanctus.hat

    explanation

    could be

    given

    for this curious

    interruption,

    for the Sanctus

    plays

    no obvious

    theological

    role in the consecration?

    What obvious

    significance

    could Narsai

    give

    for the Sanctus?

    Simply

    that

    the

    priest

    raises his voice to

    give

    the

    congregation

    the cue for

    reciting

    it;

    that

    is,

    'he teaches men to

    cry "Holy"

    with the

    spiritual beings.

    The

    people

    answer after his words:

    Holy, Holy

    Power,

    hidden

    from

    all and

    revealed to

    all.'

    The

    explanation

    of the so-called

    anaphora

    in

    Homily

    XXXII offered

    here

    is,

    admittedly,

    not

    as

    fascinating

    as

    that

    suggested by

    Ratcliff,

    but

    it gives some consistency to the Eucharistic material in the liturgical

    homilies of

    Narsai;

    it also avoids the

    unlikely

    conclusion of drastic

    liturgical

    revolutions

    at

    Edessa and Nisibis

    during

    the latter

    part

    of

    the fifth

    century.

    Bryan

    D.

    Spinks

    1

    Ibid.,

    p. 57

    2

    Ibid.,

    pp. 125-6;

    the references in Narsai are

    pp.

    12, 13,

    and

    22.

    THE

    NOTION OF INFINITUDE IN

    Ps.-DIONYSIUS

    AREOPAGITA

    The

    problem

    of the

    relationship

    between the

    concept

    of infinitude and

    the first metaphysical

    principle

    does not

    play

    a

    secondary

    role in the

    This content downloaded from 95.77.230.26 on Fri, 15 Jan 2016 15:27:31 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/25/2019 LILLA, Salvatore R. C., The Notion of Infinitude in Ps.-dionysius Areopagita

    3/12

    94

    NOTES AND STUDIES

    history

    of Greek

    philosophy:

    from the Presocratics1 to late

    Neoplato

    nism,

    it never

    ceased to draw the attention of

    philosophical speculation,2

    and

    even some Greek and Latin

    patristic

    authors

    paid

    attention

    to

    it.3

    In

    Ps.-Dionysius' theology,

    too,

    the

    concept

    of

    or )

    has

    some

    relevance,

    and it

    may

    therefore be worth while to

    try

    to

    investigate

    it.

    In

    his

    longest

    treatise,

    the De divinis

    Nominibus,

    Dionysius

    represents

    God

    sometimes as

    being

    above

    and as its

    source,

    and

    sometimes as

    being

    identical with

    it; moreover,

    in the latter

    case,

    he

    uses

    the terms

    in different contexts and seems to

    attach at least three different meanings to them. This short paper sets

    itself the task

    of

    establishing

    (a)

    the

    philosophical

    sources on which

    Dionysius

    depends

    when

    he

    places

    God above

    ; (b)

    the

    three different

    meanings

    which

    the

    concept

    of

    assumes

    when

    it is

    applied directly

    to

    God,

    as well as their

    philosophical

    and

    patristic

    sources;

    (c)

    the real reason

    why

    Dionysius

    sometimes dis

    tinguishes

    God from

    ,

    nd sometimes identifies him

    with

    it.

    (a)

    The

    passages

    in which

    Ps.-Dionysius places

    his first

    principle

    above

    and

    and

    considers

    it as their

    cause are

    the

    following:

    I.I.

    De

    div. Notn.

    IV,

    X,

    705

    C

    ...

    .

    . .

    ,

    .

    2. De

    div.

    Nom.

    IX, ,

    909

    c

    .

    *

    I wish to thank here Father P.

    Grech, O.S.A.,

    rector of the

    Institutum

    Patristicum

    Augustinianum,

    Rome,

    for

    revising my

    English.

    1

    To the

    evidence about Anaximander

    collected

    by

    H.

    Diels,

    Die

    Fragm.

    der

    Vorsokr.Vorsokr.

    (Berlin, 1951), pp.

    81-90,

    it is

    possible

    to add Clement of

    Alex.,

    Protr.Protr.6, I (I 50, 1416) , .

    6

    (Diels quotes

    the imme

    diately

    following

    lines of

    this

    passage

    of

    Clement

    as

    fragment

    11 of

    Archelaus,

    op.

    cit.

    II

    47, 15).

    On

    Anaximander,

    the

    philosopher

    to whom the

    identification

    of

    with God

    ultimately goes

    back, see,

    for

    instance,

    W.

    Jaeger,

    Die

    TheologieTheologieerfriihen griechischen

    Denker

    (Stuttgart, 1964), pp. 35-49

    and

    229-42,

    and

    G. S.

    Kirk-J.

    E.

    Raven,

    The

    Presocratic

    Philosophers (Cambridge, 1957),

    pp. 99-142

    1

    Three

    inquiries

    on the

    significance

    of this

    concept

    in Greek

    philosophy

    can

    be found in R.

    Mondolfo,

    L'infinite

    nel

    pensiero

    dei

    Greci

    (Firenze,

    1934),

    in

    C.

    J.

    De

    Vogel,

    'La thiorie

    de

    1'

    chez Platon et la tradition

    platonicienne',

    Revueevue

    philos.

    de

    la France et

    de

    I'etranger,

    149 (1959), pp. 21-39,

    and in the

    important

    book

    by

    E.

    Muhlenberg,

    Die Unendlichkeit

    Gottes bei

    Gregor

    von

    NyssaNyssaForsch. zur Kirchen und Dogmengesch. 16, Gottingen, 1966).

    3

    Besides

    Gregory

    of

    Nyssa, Muhlenberg, op.

    cit.,

    draws attention

    to

    Irenaeus

    (p. 69), Tertullian,

    Minucius

    Felix,

    Hilary

    of Poitiers

    (pp. 70-2),

    and the

    Alexandrine

    theologians,

    viz.

    Clement

    and

    Origen (pp.

    73-82).

    This content downloaded from 95.77.230.26 on Fri, 15 Jan 2016 15:27:31 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/25/2019 LILLA, Salvatore R. C., The Notion of Infinitude in Ps.-dionysius Areopagita

    4/12

    NOTES

    AND

    STUDIES

    95

    3De div. Norn. XIII, I, 977 .

    4

    De div. Nom.

    XIII, III,

    980

    C

    ,

    .

    . .

    .

    The

    view

    according

    to

    which

    and

    ,

    though

    being

    the two constitutive

    principles

    of all

    things,

    are nevertheless

    subordinated

    to the

    first,

    divine

    principle,

    goes ultimately

    back

    to

    Presocratic

    philosophy,

    and

    is

    adopted

    and

    developed especially

    by

    Neopythagoreanism

    and

    Neoplatonism.

    As

    Clement of

    Alexandria,

    Protr.Protr.

    6,

    1

    (I 50,

    16-17

    =

    Archelaus,

    fr.

    11

    Diels,

    II

    47, 15)

    tells

    us,

    both

    Anaxagoras

    and his

    pupil

    Archelaus

    placed

    divine

    intelligence

    above

    infinitude,

    .

    In the Platonic

    Philebus

    Socrates,

    after

    maintaining

    that all

    things

    are

    composed

    of limit

    and

    infinitude

    (16 c),

    makes

    it

    clear

    that there is

    a

    cause above

    these two

    principles

    (30

    C

    . . .

    ,,

    ,

    '

    . . .

    ,

    cf.

    23

    D

    .

    .

    .

    ). According

    to

    Syrianus,

    In

    Metaphys. 165,

    35-166,

    2,

    Philolaus

    (under

    whose name is

    probably

    adumbrated

    a

    Neopythagorean

    philosopher,

    just

    as in the

    case of

    Archaenetus

    and

    Brotinus,

    mentioned a few lines

    below, p.

    166,

    4-5)1

    considered

    and

    as

    the

    two

    supreme

    realities deriv

    ing

    directly

    from the first

    principle,

    .

    Plotinus,

    Enn.

    II,

    IV,

    15 (II

    69,

    19-20

    Brehier),

    regards

    infinitude

    as

    being produced by

    the

    one,

    (i.e.

    in the

    one)

    ,2

    and

    brings

    it

    into

    connection

    with the

    inexhaustible

    power

    of

    intelligible being

    (which

    for him

    is one and

    the same

    thing

    with the

    ,

    the

    first

    product

    of the

    one):3

    (i.e.

    the

    intelligible)

    act

    ,,

    ,

    . . .

    Enn.

    VI, V,

    II

    (VI1 211, 23-5);

    . .

    .

    ,

    1

    .

    R. Dodds

    also,

    Proclus,

    The Elements

    of Theology (Oxford, 1933), p.

    247,

    regards

    this

    passage

    of

    Syrianus

    as

    reflecting Neopythagorean

    tradition.

    2

    To

    this

    passage

    of Plotinus

    attention

    has been drawn

    by

    E. R.

    Dodds,

    op.

    cit.

    245

    n.

    3,

    and

    by

    L.

    Sweeney,

    Gregorianum, 38 (1957), p. 718

    n.

    85.

    The

    words

    immediately

    preceding,

    eV

    rijs

    eVos

    del,

    point

    to the

    doctrine

    of the infinite

    generative

    power

    of the

    'one', which,

    in

    Plotinus'

    opinion,

    represents

    the

    only possible interpretation

    of the infinitude

    of the

    'one':

    see

    p.

    100 below.

    For further

    details on the

    doctrine of infinitude

    in

    Plotinus

    see

    Dodds,

    op.

    cit.

    245

    and

    246-7,

    C.

    J.

    De

    Vogel,

    art. cit.

    33-4,

    and

    especially

    L.

    Sweeney,

    'Infinity

    in

    Plotinus',

    Gregorianum, 38 (1957). 515

    35

    and

    713-32

    Cf. for

    instance

    Enn.

    V, III, 5 (V 54, 26-7)

    lv

    .

    8822C78

    This content downloaded from 95.77.230.26 on Fri, 15 Jan 2016 15:27:31 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/25/2019 LILLA, Salvatore R. C., The Notion of Infinitude in Ps.-dionysius Areopagita

    5/12

    96

    NOTES AND

    STUDIES

    ,

    .

    VI, V,

    12

    (VI1

    211,

    5~9) Porphyry

    takes

    up

    the view of his

    teacher.1

    In Proclus the

    doctrine

    of

    an, together

    with

    that

    of

    ,

    assumes a

    very precise

    connotation

    and

    becomes a

    fundamental element

    of

    his

    strongly

    hierarchical

    system.

    In

    keeping

    with

    Neopythagoreism,

    he maintains

    that,

    according

    to

    the

    view set

    forth

    by

    Socrates

    in the

    Philebus,Philebus,

    he first

    principle begets

    both

    and

    :

    iviv

    ,

    Theol.Theol.lat.

    Ill,

    8

    (III

    30,

    19-20

    Saffrey-Westerink);

    the

    and the are for him the two supreme principles of beings,

    subordinated

    only

    to the first 'one'

    {El.

    Theol.

    90-2,

    p.

    82

    Dodds).

    More

    exactly,

    whereas the

    must be

    regarded

    as the second

    'one' which

    originates being,

    the

    represents

    the

    infinite

    generative power

    of

    this second

    'one',

    and is situated between

    being

    and the first

    'one':

    Theol.Theol.lat.

    Ill,

    8

    (III

    31, 18-20)

    '

    (i.e.

    the second

    'one',

    the

    )

    ,

    .

    Theol.Theol.

    lat.

    Ill,

    8

    (III 32, 2-5)

    i.e.

    the

    first

    one')

    ,,

    ,.

    El.El.

    heol.

    92 (82, 34)

    (

    ,

    )

    ,

    '

    ),

    .

    Although

    the

    generative

    power {)

    is

    represented,

    in the

    passages

    of the

    Theologia

    Platonica

    quoted

    above,

    as

    belonging

    to the

    and

    as

    originating

    after

    t

    (

    ),

    it

    goes

    nevertheless

    ultimately

    back,

    in Proclus'

    thought,

    to the first one': in El. Theol.

    56

    (54, 8-11)

    Proclus

    clearly

    maintains

    that the

    generative power

    charac

    teristic of the

    inferior

    beings

    derives

    from

    the

    beings

    of the

    upper

    rank,

    . .

    .

    .

    In

    identifying

    with the

    infinite

    generative

    power

    belonging

    to the second

    'one' and

    originating

    from

    the first

    'one',

    Proclus

    does not seem to be

    far

    removed from

    the Plotinian

    conception,

    as

    it

    appears

    in the

    passages

    of the Enneads

    quoted

    above.

    Damascius,

    in Dub.

    et

    Sol.

    45 (I 91,

    1

    Ruelle), places

    the first 'one'

    1

    The first

    part

    of

    Sent.

    40 depends

    on

    Plotinus,

    Enn.

    VI,

    v,

    12: see the

    apparatuspparatus

    fontium

    in E.

    Lamberz, Porphyrii

    sententiae ad

    intellegibilia

    ducentes

    (Leipzig, 1975), p.

    47.

    This content downloaded from 95.77.230.26 on Fri, 15 Jan 2016 15:27:31 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/25/2019 LILLA, Salvatore R. C., The Notion of Infinitude in Ps.-dionysius Areopagita

    6/12

    NOTES

    AND STUDIES

    97

    above

    limit and

    infinitude,

    ;

    and

    in his

    commentary

    on

    the Philebus

    (62,

    3

    Westerink)

    he

    repeats

    the

    same

    view

    referring

    to

    Proclus,

    Se

    ,

    (i.e.

    Proclus).1

    Dionysius'

    doctrine of the subordination

    of

    to God

    and of

    its

    origin

    from him shows

    therefore a

    complete

    agreement

    with

    the

    previous Neopythagorean

    and

    Neoplatonic

    tradition,

    and

    particularly

    with Proclus

    and Damascius:

    passage

    1 must be

    compared

    with

    Syri

    anus,

    In

    Metaphys. 165, 35-166,

    2,

    with

    Plotinus,

    Enn.

    II,

    iv,

    15 (II

    69, 19-20), and with Proclus, Theol. Plat. Ill, 8 (III 30, 19-20);

    passage

    2,

    stressing

    God's transcendence

    with

    respect

    to

    ,

    must

    be understood in the

    light

    of

    El.

    Theol.

    92 (82,

    31-4); passage 3,

    in

    which God is

    represented

    in the act of

    imparting

    a limit

    upon

    ,

    finds also its

    counterpart

    in El. Theol.

    92,

    ,

    ;

    and

    passage

    4,

    in which

    the first one' is

    repre

    sented

    as

    being

    prior

    to

    any

    limit and

    infinitude,

    agrees

    almost verbatim

    with

    Damascius,

    Dub.

    et Sol.

    45 (I 91, 1).

    (b)

    It could not

    escape Dionysius

    that

    Parmenides,

    in

    the first

    hypo

    thesis of

    the

    homonymous

    Platonic

    dialogue

    which so much

    influenced

    the

    theology

    of

    Neoplatonism,2

    calls

    the

    'one'

    also

    (Parm.

    137 d);

    and

    that,

    in the second

    hypothesis,

    he

    brings

    the

    'one' into

    close

    connection

    with

    the

    infinite multitude of

    beings

    {Parm.

    144 a-b).

    And

    since

    Dionysius, adapting

    the

    Neoplatonic

    interpretation

    of

    the

    Parme

    nidesnideso his own

    theology,

    identifies

    his first

    principle

    with

    the

    'one' of

    the

    first two

    hypotheses

    of this

    dialogue,3

    he is inclined

    to call

    God

    himself

    and

    .4

    1

    Another

    passage

    of the

    commentary

    on the Philebus

    (98, 1-6)

    is

    also worth

    noticing:

    rives

    al

    ;

    . . .

    . . .

    2

    On the

    theological

    interpretation

    of

    the

    Parmenides in

    Neopythagoreism

    and

    Neoplatonism

    see

    particularly

    E. R.

    Dodds,

    'The Parmenides of

    Plato and

    the

    Origin

    of the

    Neoplatonic

    "One"',

    Class.

    Quarterly,

    22

    (1928),

    pp.

    129-42;

    E.

    Corsini,

    II trattato De

    divinis

    nominibus dello

    pseudo-Dionigi

    e i

    commenti

    neoplatonicineoplatonici

    l Parmenide

    (Torino, 1962),

    pp.

    115-20;

    H. D.

    Saffrey-L.

    G.

    Westerink, Proclus, Theologie platonicienne,

    i

    (Paris, 1968), pp.

    lxxxv-lxxxix.

    3

    This has been

    rightly

    seen

    by

    E.

    von

    Ivanka,

    'Der

    Aufbau der

    Schrift

    "De divinis nominibus"

    des Ps.

    Dionysios',

    Scholastik,

    15

    (1940), pp.

    392-3

    (=lato(=lato(=

    lato

    Christianus, Einsiedeln,

    1964, pp. 234-5)

    and

    by

    E.

    Corsini,

    op.

    cit.,

    pp.

    43

    and 120-1. On

    the

    dependence

    of the De

    divinis

    nominibus on

    the

    Parmenidesarmenides

    see

    particularly chapter

    III

    of Corsini's

    book,

    II De divinis

    nominibus

    ee l

    Parmenide,

    pp.

    77-111.

    4 It may be worth noticing that Clement of Alexandria also calls his God

    -,,

    n

    Strom.

    V

    81,

    5-82,

    (II 380,20-5)

    he is

    no

    doubt under the influence

    of

    a

    Neopythagorean

    speculation

    on

    the first

    hypothesis

    of the Parmenides .

    (

    .

    .

    .

    ,

    This content downloaded from 95.77.230.26 on Fri, 15 Jan 2016 15:27:31 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/25/2019 LILLA, Salvatore R. C., The Notion of Infinitude in Ps.-dionysius Areopagita

    7/12

    98

    NOTES AND

    STUDIES

    The identification of God with

    and

    gives origin,

    in

    Dionysius' thought,

    to

    three different

    ideas. God is

    infinitude

    or infi

    nite since

    (1)

    he

    comprehends

    all

    things

    in

    himself;

    (2)

    he is endowed

    with a

    generative

    power

    which knows no

    end;

    (3)

    he is

    completely

    in

    comprehensible

    to the

    human

    mind.

    Infinitude

    becomes

    thus

    practically

    identical

    (1)

    with God's

    property

    of

    enclosing everything

    in

    himself;

    (2)

    with his infinite

    generative

    power; (3)

    with his total

    unknowability.

    (1)

    That for

    Dionysius

    God is infinitude because he

    comprehends

    everything

    in

    himself is

    clearly

    shown

    by

    the

    following

    evidence:

    5.

    De div. Norn.

    Ill,

    I 680

    .

    6. De div. Notn.

    V, ,

    825

    .

    ..

    e

    div.

    Nom.

    V, X,

    825

    >

    []

    ..

    . .

    .

    .1

    8.

    De div. N0ttl.

    IX,

    III,

    912

    .

    .

    .

    . .

    .

    .

    It is one of

    the

    main features

    of the

    theology

    both

    of

    Dionysius

    and of

    Neoplatonism

    to

    consider

    all

    beings

    as

    proceeding

    from

    the 'one'

    by

    means

    of a

    process

    of

    emanation:

    the

    'one'

    is the source of all

    beings

    in

    so far

    as

    they

    pre-exist

    already

    in some

    wayi.e.

    without

    being

    distinct

    from one

    anotherin

    the

    'one',

    which contains

    all of them and

    brings

    them

    forth.2

    This

    is the

    underlying

    idea of a

    passage

    of

    Plotinus,

    Enn.

    ,

    Sc

    ,

    oil

    ,

    ,

    .

    All

    these

    concepts

    go

    back

    to the first

    hypothesis

    of

    the

    Parmenides.

    On this

    passage

    see also

    Muhlenberg, op.

    cit., pp. 75-6;

    I

    very

    much

    regret

    not to

    have drawn atten

    tion

    to

    this

    important

    point

    in

    my

    book on Clement

    (see particularly p.

    219).

    1

    is

    my

    own

    restoration;

    I

    also

    thought

    it

    proper

    to

    cut out

    the

    which

    immediately

    follows. E.

    R.

    Dodds,

    Proclus.

    The Elements

    of

    Theology,

    p.

    248,

    in

    quoting

    this

    passage,

    puts

    after

    in,

    without

    making

    it clear

    that the

    word

    represents

    a

    restoration,

    since it occurs

    neither

    in

    the

    Migne

    edition nor

    in

    the

    manuscripts.

    I,

    however,

    prefer

    to

    write

    ,

    which

    I

    regard

    as

    dependent

    on

    .

    *

    It

    must be

    remembered

    that

    in

    passages

    58

    of

    Dionysius,

    as well as in

    analogous

    passages

    of

    Plotinus,

    Proclus,

    and

    Damascius,

    the 'one'

    comprehends

    all

    things

    in itself

    potentially,

    i.e. before

    bringing

    them forth

    by

    means of its

    emanation.

    This

    concept

    must not

    be

    confused

    with the

    other

    idea

    according

    to

    which

    the divine

    principle,

    thanks

    to its

    power,

    embraces

    ()

    and holds

    together () the whole sensible universe. This idea, which goes ultimately

    back

    to

    Presocratic

    philosophy,

    occurs

    in Plato's

    conception

    of the

    world-soul,

    becomes

    fundamental

    in the

    Porch,

    and

    is inherited

    by

    Philo,

    Clement of

    Alex.,

    Gregory

    of

    Nyssa,

    Middle

    Platonism,

    Neoplatonism,

    and

    Dionysius

    himself:

    This content downloaded from 95.77.230.26 on Fri, 15 Jan 2016 15:27:31 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/25/2019 LILLA, Salvatore R. C., The Notion of Infinitude in Ps.-dionysius Areopagita

    8/12

    NOTES

    AND STUDIES

    99

    V,

    III,

    15 (V 70, 29-3 )

    7

    .

    . . '

    .

    In his

    commentary

    on

    the Parmenides

    Proclus,

    prob

    ably

    having

    Aristotle in

    mind,

    brings

    the

    infinitude

    of

    the first 'one'

    into

    close

    connection

    with

    its

    property

    of

    possessing

    everything

    in advance:

    Inn

    Farm. VI

    (73,

    11-12

    Cousin)

    ...

    el

    ,

    7

    ,

    .1

    Inn

    Parm.

    VI

    (7316-17)

    .

    Damascius also

    maintains that the 'one'

    comprehends

    everything:

    Dub.Dub.t Sol. I

    (I 3, 1-2)

    '

    .

    Dub.Dub.

    t

    Sol. 2

    (I 5, 2-3)

    .

    . .

    '

    . . .

    .

    Dub.Dub.

    t

    Sol.

    25 (I

    42, 27)

    .

    Ps.-Dionysius'

    dependence

    on

    Neoplatonism

    even

    in

    terminology

    is

    therefore

    evident:

    the

    of

    passages

    5

    and 8

    is

    already

    used

    by

    Proclus and

    Damascius;

    and the

    of

    passage

    7

    must be com

    pared

    with the

    expression

    which occurs

    in

    Plotinus,

    Enn.

    V, III,

    15 (V

    70,

    29-30).

    (2)

    God's infinitude

    is

    also connected with his

    generative

    power,

    which is infinite in so

    far

    as it never ceases to

    produce

    an infinite

    number of

    powers

    and never

    runs short.

    This idea occurs in

    the

    two

    following

    passages:

    9.

    De div. Nom.

    VIII,

    11,

    889

    D

    . .

    .

    157j57,

    2

    .

    see,

    for

    instance,

    Anaximenes 2

    (Diels I,

    95)

    and W.

    Jaeger's

    important

    remarks

    on the use of the term

    on the

    part

    of some

    Presocratic

    philo

    sophers, op.

    cit.

    42

    and n.

    39,

    pp.

    232-3;

    Plato,

    Tim.

    36 e;

    SVF

    I

    530,

    II

    439,

    440, 441, 447;

    Philo, De

    Fuga

    et Inv. 112, De

    Conf. Ling.

    137,

    De Post. C.

    7,

    DeDe

    Migr.

    Abr.

    182,

    De Sobr.

    63,

    De

    Somn.

    I

    63

    and

    185;

    Clement of Alex.

    Strom.Strom.

    I, 5, 4,

    II, 6, 2, V,

    73, 3,

    V, 81,

    3; Gregory

    of

    Nyssa,

    De

    Profess.

    Christ.

    139,39, 3-4

    Jaeger;

    Plutarch,

    De An. Procr. in Tim.

    1023 a;

    Atticus,

    fr. VIII

    Baudry;

    Alcinous,

    Did.

    170,

    3-5

    (on

    the

    right spelling

    of the name of

    the author

    of the

    Didaskalikos,

    who must

    be

    distinguished

    from

    Albinus,

    the

    pupil

    of

    Gaius,

    see now

    J.

    Whittaker, Phoenix,

    28

    (1974), pp. 450-6);

    Plotinus,

    Enn.

    IV,

    3, 9

    (IV 76,

    36-7)

    and

    V, 1,

    2

    (V 17,

    29-30); Ps.-Dionysius,

    De div. Nom.

    IV,

    iv

    697

    c, 700

    a-b,

    VIII,

    11

    892 a,

    XI,

    949 a, XI,

    11

    949

    c.

    1

    Proclus' words

    eVo's

    may

    have

    been influenced

    by

    Aristotle's

    definition

    of

    ,

    ot 8e

    17780

    ,

    Phys.

    Ill

    207a8-9-

    As to

    the

    idea

    according

    to which infinitude

    comprehends

    everything

    in

    itself,

    cf.

    Aristotle,

    Phys.

    Ill

    207a1821, ye 1, nepicgfiv

    1,

    '

    .

    2

    The

    expression ?

    is Procline: see for instance

    El.

    Theol.

    (2,

    10-11),

    Theol. Plat.

    II,

    1

    (II

    4,

    22-3),

    In Parm. VI

    (75,

    16 and

    19).

    This content downloaded from 95.77.230.26 on Fri, 15 Jan 2016 15:27:31 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/25/2019 LILLA, Salvatore R. C., The Notion of Infinitude in Ps.-dionysius Areopagita

    9/12

    100

    NOTES AND

    STUDIES

    10. De

    div. Norn.

    VIII, 11,

    889

    D-892

    A

    in'

    .

    Plotinus also had

    interpreted

    the

    infinitude of the

    'one'

    in

    this

    way:

    the

    'one' is unlimited

    (Enn.

    IV

    ill, 8,

    pp. 74, 38

    6

    ,,

    f.

    Enn.

    V, V, II,

    p. 103, 34

    "'

    ^

    and

    Enn.

    VI, V,

    4>

    202,

    13-14

    ,

    ),

    but its

    infinitude must be

    under

    stood as

    referring

    not to its

    physical

    dimensions

    (from

    this

    point

    of

    view the 'one' is neither limited nor unlimited, Enn. V, v, 10,

    p. 103,

    18-20 '

    . . .

    '

    '

    )

    but

    only

    to its

    inexhaustible

    power:1

    Enn.Enn.Enn.

    I,

    4,

    15

    (II

    69,

    19)

    Enn.Enn.

    V,

    III,

    8

    (IV 74> 3^~7) V

    TV

    ,

    ..

    Enn.Enn.

    , V,

    (V 103,

    212)

    '

    ..

    Enn.Enn.

    I, V,

    \ (VI1

    202,

    1314)

    "

    ,

    '

    ,

    ;

    Enn.Enn.

    I, ,

    6

    (VI2

    11210

    )

    eivai

    )

    and

    is

    severely

    condemned

    by

    Justinian

    for this

    reason: cf. the references

    produced

    by

    P. Koetschau in the

    apparatus

    fontium, p.

    164.

    For

    a

    discussion

    of

    this

    passage

    cf.

    Muhlenberg,

    op.

    cit.,

    pp. 78-82,

    This content downloaded from 95.77.230.26 on Fri, 15 Jan 2016 15:27:31 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/25/2019 LILLA, Salvatore R. C., The Notion of Infinitude in Ps.-dionysius Areopagita

    10/12

    NOTES AND STUDIES

    101

    The same view is shared

    by

    Damacius,

    who

    in

    Dub. et Sol.

    178

    (II 55,

    22)

    uses

    the term

    which occurs in

    passage 9

    of Ps.

    Dionysius:

    .1

    (3)

    In two

    passages

    Dionysius brings

    nto close

    connection

    with the total

    unknowability

    of the first

    principle.

    God is

    and,

    is therefore too

    superior

    to

    the limited

    faculties

    of

    the human

    mind,

    which is not

    capable

    of

    comprehending

    him:

    II.II. De div. Norn.

    I,

    I

    588

    . . .

    2

    . . .

    .

    12. De div. Nom.

    I, 11,

    588

    C

    .3

    The doctrine of

    the

    absolute

    unknowability

    of

    the first

    principle

    is

    fundamental in

    Neoplatonism:

    as E.

    R. Dodds has

    shown,

    it derives

    from

    the

    theological

    interpretation

    of the 'one' of the

    first

    hypothesis

    of

    Plato's Parmenides.4

    And since Parmenides calls this

    'one'

    (Parm.(Parm.37 d)

    and

    comes

    to

    the

    conclusion that it

    cannot be the

    object

    of any speech, scientific knowledge, or opinion (Parm. 142 a), it must

    not have been difficult

    for

    Dionysius

    to

    bring

    these two

    negative

    properties

    of

    the

    first

    one'

    (that

    of

    being

    infinite and

    that of

    being

    completely unknown)

    into connection

    with

    each other and

    to define

    consequently

    his God

    as an

    which lies

    far

    beyond

    the reach

    of

    the human mind.

    But

    Dionysius

    did not find

    this close

    connection

    between

    and

    God's

    unknowability

    in

    the Parmenides itself or in

    Neoplatonism:

    the

    'one'

    of

    the first

    hypothesis

    of

    the Parmenides

    is

    represented

    as

    being

    completely

    unknown not because

    it

    is

    ,

    but because

    it

    partakes

    in no way of being (Parm. 141 e ), and

    1

    In

    the

    Elements

    of Theology

    Proclus

    applies

    the

    term

    not to

    the first

    principle,

    but to

    the

    intelligible beings

    deriving

    from

    and

    :

    see El. Theol.

    84 (78, 5),

    86

    (80, 12), 89 (82, 2), 92 (82,

    31).

    In the

    Commentary

    onn the

    Timaeus

    also

    (see

    Diehl, Index,

    vol.

    iii,

    397)

    the

    term

    is not

    applied

    to the first

    principle.

    The

    expression

    en'

    in

    passage

    10 of

    Dionysius

    should be

    compared

    with

    Damascius,

    Dub. et Sol.

    178

    (II 55,

    18)

    en'

    .

    22

    In

    my opinion,

    the

    varia

    lectio

    ,

    which occurs in some

    manuscripts,

    is better than

    , accepted

    in the

    Migne

    edition.

    3

    The term

    which occurs in De cael. Hier.

    II,

    iii,

    140

    D

    is also con

    nected with

    God's

    incomprehensibility:

    ..

    4

    Cf. Class.

    Quarterly,

    22

    (1928).

    133i

    and

    especially

    the

    Appendix

    I,

    'The

    unknown God in

    Neoplatonism',

    in his

    Proclus,

    The

    Elements

    of Theology

    (Oxford

    1933), 310-13.

    This content downloaded from 95.77.230.26 on Fri, 15 Jan 2016 15:27:31 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/25/2019 LILLA, Salvatore R. C., The Notion of Infinitude in Ps.-dionysius Areopagita

    11/12

    102 NOTES

    AND

    STUDIES

    in

    spite

    of the

    strong emphasis

    laid on

    the

    doctrine of

    the

    unknowability

    of

    the first

    'one',

    Neoplatonism

    does not seem to

    regard

    this

    unknow

    ability

    as

    a

    result

    of

    .

    As we

    have

    seen

    (pp. 95-7

    above),

    for

    Plotinus, Proclus,

    and

    Damascius

    is the

    product

    of the first

    ,one',

    but

    not identical

    with

    it;

    and when

    they

    call this 'one'

    infinite,

    they

    think either of its

    property

    of

    containing

    all

    beings

    in itself

    potentially,

    or

    of

    its

    generative

    power

    which

    knows no

    end.1

    The

    con

    ception

    of

    God's

    unknowability

    as

    a

    direct result of

    has come

    to

    Dionysius

    not

    from

    Neoplatonism

    but from a Patristic

    source,

    namely

    Gregoiy of Nyssa, and goes ultimately back to the Aristotelian doctrine

    of

    71/)>.

    .

    Muhlenberg

    has

    devoted

    a

    detailed

    inquiry

    to the notion of

    both

    in

    Gregory

    of

    Nyssa

    and in

    previous

    Greek

    thought,2

    and has

    also hinted

    at the

    way

    in which

    Dionysius interprets

    this doctrine of the

    Cappadocian

    father.3

    We shall here limit

    ourselves to

    drawing

    attention

    to some

    passages

    of

    Gregory

    and of

    Aristotle which

    may

    be of

    some

    importance

    for our

    point.

    That

    Gregory

    of

    Nyssa regards

    as a

    negative

    attribute

    of God

    and

    as the

    main cause of his

    unknowability

    appears

    clearly

    from the

    following evidence:

    Contraontra Eunom. II

    (I 246,

    16-22

    Jaeger)

    i.e.

    )

    . .

    . .

    ,

    '

    ,,

    '

    .*

    Contraontra

    Eunom.

    Ill

    (II 58,

    268

    Jaeger)

    55

    ,

    .

    Quoduod

    non sint tres dii

    (52, 1520 Miiller)

    ,

    .

    ,

    .6

    1

    As to the

    interpretation

    given by

    E.

    Muhlenberg

    of the

    passage

    of

    Enn.

    VI, IX,

    6

    quoted

    above

    (p. 100)

    see the

    footnote

    p.

    100 n.

    3

    above.

    2

    Cf.

    p. 94

    n. 2 above.

    Op.

    cit.

    142-3:

    '. .

    . dad er

    [Gregor

    of

    Nyssa]

    nicht einfach

    sagt,

    das

    MaB

    Gottes

    sei seine

    Unbegreiflichkeit.

    So haben die

    mystischen

    Theologen, ange

    fangen

    bei

    Dionysius Areopagita, Gregor

    von

    Nyssa

    verstanden.'

    4

    This

    passage

    is discussed at some

    length

    by

    Muhlenberg, op.

    cit.,

    p. 142.

    5

    The same verb SioJ s used by Dionysius in passage 2 quoted above

    (P- 94)

    6

    Another

    passage

    of

    Gregory

    of

    Nyssa

    about divine

    infinitude,

    De An. et

    Res.

    (P.G.

    46. 97

    a

    3-8),

    is also worth

    noticing, although

    there is no

    mention in

    This content downloaded from 95.77.230.26 on Fri, 15 Jan 2016 15:27:31 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/25/2019 LILLA, Salvatore R. C., The Notion of Infinitude in Ps.-dionysius Areopagita

    12/12

    NOTES AND STUDIES 103

    The last sentence

    of this

    passage,

    which

    traces the

    unknowability

    of

    divine

    nature

    back to

    the

    impossibility

    of

    giving

    any

    definition

    of

    pov,pov,

    s based

    on the Aristotelian

    doctrine

    according

    to

    which

    is

    completely

    unknown:

    Phys.Phys.Phys.

    187b 7

    el

    fj

    .

    Phys.Phys.

    ll

    207"

    25-6

    fj

    .

    Rhet.Rhet.ll I048b 27-8

    (c)

    It is now

    necessary

    to

    point

    out that there is

    no real contradiction

    between

    Dionysius'

    view

    which

    places

    the

    first

    principle

    above

    and considers the latter

    as a

    product

    of the former and his

    tendency

    to

    identify

    with God himself.

    If we take into account

    a funda

    mental law

    of

    Dionysius' systemnamely

    the

    law

    of

    and

    ,

    the two distinct

    stages

    of

    God's

    existenceand

    are aware of

    the

    philo

    sophical background

    of both

    views about

    ,

    we

    are able to

    under

    stand

    what

    Ps.-Dionysius really

    meant and to

    appreciate

    the intimate

    coherence of his

    thought.

    For

    Dionysius

    there can be no confusion between

    the

    which

    is

    produced by

    God and is inferior to him and

    the

    which

    is

    identical

    with

    him:

    whereas the former is the

    expression

    of divine

    emanation or

    ,

    and is

    only

    one of the

    two

    constitutive

    prin

    ciples

    of

    beings

    which Plato

    places

    under the first

    cause and which

    both Plotinus

    and

    Proclus

    regard

    as an

    emanation

    of the first ,one'

    (cf.

    pp. 95-6

    above),

    the latter

    must be referred to

    God's

    ,

    viz. to that

    stage

    of God's existence in which he has not

    yet

    come out of

    himself,

    and

    becomes then one of his main

    negative

    attributes. As we

    have seen

    (pp. 97

    and 101

    above),

    it was the

    Neoplatonic interpretation

    of

    the

    first

    two

    hypotheses

    of Plato's Parmenides that led

    Dionysius

    to

    identify

    with

    God;

    and the three different

    ways

    in which he

    interpreted

    it were

    suggested

    to him

    by

    Neoplatonism

    and

    by Gregory

    of

    Nyssa.

    Salvatore R. C. Lilla

    it of God's

    unknowability:

    '

    .

    .

    .

    )

    -

    ,

    .

    1

    On

    the notion of

    in

    Aristotle

    see also

    Muhlenberg, op.

    cit.,

    pp. 43

    if.

    who, however,

    does not draw

    enough

    attention to the

    unknowability

    of the

    Aristotelian

    .

    In the

    passage

    of Clement of

    Alexandria,

    Strom. V

    81,

    6

    quoted above (footnote 4, p. 97 above) there also seems to be a closer connection

    between

    the

    infinitude of the 'one' and its

    unknowability:

    . .

    .

    .


Recommended