+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Limits of Empathy

Limits of Empathy

Date post: 01-Dec-2015
Category:
Upload: arubianov
View: 47 times
Download: 1 times
Share this document with a friend
Popular Tags:
20
On the Limits of Empathy Author(s): Juliet Koss Reviewed work(s): Source: The Art Bulletin, Vol. 88, No. 1 (Mar., 2006), pp. 139-157 Published by: College Art Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/25067229 . Accessed: 05/02/2013 17:34 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. . College Art Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Art Bulletin. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded on Tue, 5 Feb 2013 17:34:40 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Transcript
Page 1: Limits of Empathy

On the Limits of EmpathyAuthor(s): Juliet KossReviewed work(s):Source: The Art Bulletin, Vol. 88, No. 1 (Mar., 2006), pp. 139-157Published by: College Art AssociationStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/25067229 .

Accessed: 05/02/2013 17:34

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

.

College Art Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The ArtBulletin.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded on Tue, 5 Feb 2013 17:34:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 2: Limits of Empathy

On the Limits of Empathy

Juliet Koss

After a century of benign neglect and denigration, empathy has been rearing its comforting head in Anglophone cultural

discourse. Seemingly a kinder, gentler model of the aesthetic

response?compared with stringent abstraction, dizzying dis

traction, or harsh estrangement?it has been linked in the

last decade to an unlikely range of subjects, including the art

of Edward Hopper and Adolf Menzel, the architecture of

Frank Gehry, the Surrealist project, and the entire discipline of film.1 The concept has also recently been investigated, and

even explicidy promoted, by the performance artist Karen

Finley and the conceptual artist Barbara Kruger (Fig. I).2

Frequendy conflated with sympathy or compassion, empathy

usually signifies a process of emotional and psychological

projection. More specifically, it can refer to the concept of

Einf?hlung?literally, the activity of "feeling into"?that was de

veloped in late-nineteenth-century Germany in the overlap

ping fields of philosophical aesthetics, perceptual psychology,

optics, and art and architectural history to describe an em

bodied response to an image, object,

or spatial environment.

Simultaneously haptic and optic, Einf?hlung offered a fo

rum for abstract discussions of the active perceptual experi ence of the individual spectator. Like abstraction, distraction,

and estrangement in its wake, it described a potentially

un

comfortable destabilization of identity along the viewer's per

ceptual borders?a sensation at once physical, psychological,

and emotional. Promulgated in a range of disciplines, none

of which was either discrete or fully formed, it underwent

divergent fates in each one. A gradual loss of interest among

art historians (such as Heinrich W?lfflin) and psychologists (such as Theodor Lipps) preceded more forceful rejections

of the concept by Wilhelm Worringer in 1908 and, in the

1930s, Bertolt Brecht, but the concept lingered for decades

within the discourse of modern architecture. Beyond offering a sequence of etymological shifts or discursive trends, the

critical history of Einf?hlung reveals a fracturing of the disci

plines at the turn of the last century; a rejection of narrative,

with the emergence of visual abstraction; and widespread

transformations, with the birth of cinema, in both the objects

of spectatorship and the status of spectators themselves.

Like the recent "return to beauty," the resurgence of em

pathy would seem to signal a backlash against the opposi

tional aesthetics of recent decades?a distancing from the

rigorous intellectualism of poststructuralist discourse and the

allegiances of identity politics.3 The concept's contemporary

appeal may also lie in its interdisciplinary orientation. As a

discussion of spectatorship, it has been applied to art, archi

tecture, literature, film, and theater; it has infused political as

well as aesthetic discourse in the United States, with one

president claiming to feel his nation's pain and the next

advocating "compassionate conservatism." Empathy appears

to promise a constructive theoretical approach that values

emotional, as much as rational, understanding and allows for

the possibility of bridging radically different subject posi tions, both within and across historical periods and geo

graphic zones.4 Within the discipline of art history, Einf?hlung more specifically has garnered scholarly and critical notice in

the last decade.5 Attention to its emergence in late-nineteenth

century Germany and its demise in the ensuing decades reflects

an effort to broaden and complicate the grand narrative of

modernism, question its central tenets, and explore vast

changes in the nature and practice of modern spectatorship.

Aesthetic Empathy The initial theoretical statement concerning Einf?hlung was

made in 1873 by the philosopher Robert Vischer in his

treatise ?ber das optische Formgef?hl: Ein Beitrag zur Aesthetik

(On the Optical Sense of Form: A Contribution to Aesthet

ics). Vischer used the term to describe the viewer's active

perceptual engagement with a work of art. In viewing an

object, he wrote,

I entrust my individual life to the lifeless form, just as I. . .

do with another living person. Only ostensibly do I remain

the same although the object remains an other. I seem

merely to adapt and attach myself to it as one hand clasps another, and yet I am

mysteriously transplanted and mag

ically transformed into this other.6

This reciprocal experience of exchange and transforma

tion?a solitary, one-on-one

experience?created, as it were,

both viewer and object, destabilizing the identity of the

former while animating the latter. Physical, emotional, and

psychological, the process of Einf?hlung placed the spectator at the center of aesthetic discourse.

Devoid of spatial connotations, the German term Ein

f?hlung first appeared in print in 1800 in the work of Gott

fried Herder, whom late-nineteenth-century theorists cited as

a precursor; the concept more generally may be traced to the

writings of Aristode.7 The theme of sympathy broadly speaking evoked the writings of Arthur Schopenhauer and Jean

Jacques Rousseau; one proximate influence was Friedrich

Nietzsche, an acquaintance of Vischer's father, the philoso

pher of aesthetics Friedrich Theodor Vischer. Favoring the

words Mitleid and Miterlebnis over Einf?hlung, Nietzsche nei

ther considered empathy or sympathy in spatial terms nor

discussed the aesthetic response as it literally occurred on the

spectator's skin. Yet his description of this response as a

merger of the self into the work of art that provoked a loss of

speech and the dissolution of individual identity strongly resembles the aesthetic activity that was also described as

Einf?hlung. In 1876, for example, he wrote that the spectator for the Wagnerian Gesamtkunstwerk is led "to a

totally new

understanding and empathy [Verstehen und Miterleben], just as

This content downloaded on Tue, 5 Feb 2013 17:34:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 3: Limits of Empathy

140 ART BULLETIN MARCH 2006 VOLUME LXXXVIII NUMBER 1

1 Barbara Kruger, U empathie peut changer le monde, Strasbourg, France, 1995 (artwork <

Mary Boone Gallery, New York)

Barbara Kruger; photograph provided by

though his senses had all at once grown more spiritual and

his spirit more sensual."8 This aesthetic response also in

volved an element of Selbstent?usserung, or

self-estrangement, as we shall see.

Subsequently developed by such authors as Konrad Fie

dler, Lipps, August Schmarsow, and W?lfflin, the discourse of

Einf?hlung treated vision and the experience of space in

bodily and psychic terms.9 Its interdisciplinary nature re

flected a relative openness among the humanistic and scien

tific disciplines; viewers might "empathize into" anything from everyday objects

or nonreferential markings to works of

fine art, according to the interests of particular theorists and

researchers. Placing the perceiving eye within the viewer's

body, Einf?hlung described a range of relations between this

body and the work of art, including a

tendency to anthropo

morphize and a notion of projection we

might now associate

with Sigmund Freud. The viewer, Vischer wrote, "uncon

sciously projects its own bodily form?and with this also the

soul?into the form of the object. From this I derived the

notion that I call 'Einf?hlung'"10 Pity, sympathy, and compas

sion all appeared within the discourse, and they were not

always (or consistendy) differentiated. W?lfflin's claim, for

example, that "compassion [Mitleiden] ... is psychologically

the same process as aesthetic sympathy [?sthetischeMitf?hlen]" not only had no scientific basis but also contradicted Vi

scher's careful distinctions between Einf?hlung and An

f?hlung, Nachf?hlung, and Zuf?hlung, which may be translated as attentive feeling, responsive feeling, and immediate feel

ing, respectively.11 We are aware of the power of images to elicit a visceral

response; an example would be the discomfort provoked

among the squeamish by depictions of physically painful events.12 Vischer articulated this response to form in abstract

terms, arguing that even simple marks could induce physical

reactions. Vision itself, in fact, was not always central; the

process relied heavily on a network of responses that in

cluded spatial understanding, imagination, emotion, and (in

some cases) "artistic reshaping," or the creative aesthetic

response. "We can often observe in ourselves," he noted, "the

curious fact that a visual stimulus is experienced not so much

with our eyes as with a different sense in another part of our

body."13 This sensation occurred with particular intensity

along the body's surfaces, he argued, usefully providing an

explanation for the mystical shivers and goose bumps of

aesthetic transport. Along with the destabilization of identity and psychic projection, such bodily sensations on the specta

tor's skin produced a

powerful self-awareness. Einf?hlung, in

other words, articulated a loss of self that simultaneously

reinforced a powerful, physical

sense of selfhood.

Vischer primarily used as examples natural or

simple forms

(such as circles, clouds, colors, and lines), a rhetorical model

derived from physiology, optics, and philosophy rather than

This content downloaded on Tue, 5 Feb 2013 17:34:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 4: Limits of Empathy

ON THE LIMITS OF EMPATHY I4I

2 Heinrich W?lfflin, drawing of

Romanesque and Gothic arches. The

Getty Research Institute, Los Angeles, Research Library, 860448

from art history, the discipline he would enter within the

decade. A hazy mixture of projections and impressions, Ein

f?hlung could also be provoked by such three-dimensional

objects as flowers and sculptures. Only in the final pages of

his treatise did he attend to the perception of works of

art?which, he maintained, had the capacity to prompt the

purest optical feeling. In this late-nineteenth-century context,

the representational nature of these objects

was never ques

tioned; his examples include Albrecht D?rer's Eour Apostles.

But in combining psychology, optics, fine art, and the notion

of universal spectatorship, the discourse of Einf?hlung that

Vischer and others developed unwittingly helped set the

terms for the theory and practice of visual abstraction. The

"pure form" of the twentieth century was embedded within

an idea of embodied perception.

According to Vischer, spectators feel physical discomfort

while looking at a single vertical line on a blank page. "A

horizontal line is pleasing because the eyes are positioned

horizontally," he declared, whereas a "vertical line, by con

trast, can be disturbing when perceived in isolation for ... it

contradicts the binocular structure of the perceiving eyes and

forces them to function in a more complicated way."14 Rather

than positing verticality as the visual expression of the up

right human body and horizontality as implying a landscape, Vischer discussed the pure form of a line in relation to the

perceptual faculties of the individual spectator. He under

stood human vision to be simultaneously optical and bodily and described it, crucially,

as binocular. Unlike monocular

vision, which perceives an

image without reference to scale?

the actual size of images seen

through telescopes and micro

scopes is not immediately apparent?binocular vision situ

ates the spectator's body in relation to the image. As objects

that mediate visual experience, moreover, binoculars them

selves create an image by means of bodily perception; held in

the viewer's hands, they present a doubled image that be

comes unified only within the viewer's body.15 Turning dis

tant views into haptic experiences, they allow the individual

spectator to "empathize into" an image.

The concept of Einf?hlung suffused the early work of

W?lfflin, whose dissertation, Prolegomena zu einer Psychologie der

Architektur (Prolegomena to a Psychology of Architecture), was completed in 1886 in the Department of Philosophy at

the University of Munich. "Asymmetry," W?lfflin wrote, "is

often experienced as

physical pain, as if a limb were

missing or

injured."16 This psychological understanding of vision as

embedded in the body could be most productively applied, he believed, to the interpretation of works of architecture.17

Representations of architectural form, and architecture itself,

provided an

opportunity for embodied vision. Wolfflin's own

drawings of Romanesque and Gothic arches on a scrap of

paper tucked into his copy of the Prolegomena allow us to test

his claim that "the round arch is generally recognized as

more cheerful to look at than the pointed arch. The former

goes about its task quietly, content with its roundness; the

latter embodies a will and effort in every line" (Fig. 2).18 For W?lfflin at this time, both architecture and its two

dimensional representation were

equally capable of eliciting

Einf?hlung. Schmarsow, however, distinguished between the

two. In a lecture in 1893 marking his inheritance of the art

history chair at Leipzig (a position for which he was chosen in

favor of Vischer and W?lfflin), Schmarsow famously defined

architecture as spatial?rather than structural, material, or

formal?and unique of all the arts in its ability to provoke

Einf?hlung. "Psychologically," he decreed,

the intuited form of three-dimensional space arises

through the experiences of our sense of sight, whether or

not assisted by other physiological factors. . . . [It] consists

of the residues of sensory experience to which the muscu

lar sensations of our body, the sensitivity of our skin, and

the structure of our body all contribute.19

Here again, the psychological parallel between the viewer's

body and that of the work of art (in this case, a building) was

mediated through vision. But while vision was crucial initially,

perception ultimately proved to be a bodily phenomenon:

This content downloaded on Tue, 5 Feb 2013 17:34:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 5: Limits of Empathy

142 ART BULLETIN MARCH 2006 VOLUME LXXXVIII NUMBER 1

3 Adolf Hildebrand, bronze plaque for the grave of Konrad Fiedler, 1895

(artwork in the public domain)

"Every spatial creation is first and foremost the enclosing of a

[human] subject; and thus architecture as a human art differs

fundamentally from all endeavors in the applied arts."20

Schmarsow was not the first to define architecture as spa

tial, but his arguments were particularly significant, given his status and the context in which he spoke.21 Like Vischer and

W?lfflin, he was an art historian who placed architecture at

the center of his work?standard practice in late-nineteenth

century Germany, but rare in the United States today.22 By

publicly registering the concept of Einf?hlung as amenable to

considerations of spatial perception, Schmarsow encouraged its continuation within the discourse of modern architecture

long after it had faded from art historians' attention, a loss of

interest that paralleled that of psychologists after 1900. The uneven fate of Einf?hlung may thus be seen to reflect the

divergence of the two disciplines of art and architecture

history.23 Even as the spatial understanding of architecture

persisted, it was often drained of the emotional content that

Einf?hlung had provided; indeed, the concept itself was not

always named.24

In 1893, however, when the sculptor Adolf Hildebrand

published Das Problem der Form in der bildenden Kunst (The Problem of Form in the Fine Arts), the concept's basic prin

ciples were still considered powerful. "There is a psychology of art," Hildebrand declared in reference to Einf?hlung, "a

clear feeling for the effect of such stimulated movement on

our sensibility

as a whole. Such effects determine whether or

not we breathe freely, for our general sensations are related

to the spatial imagination... ,"25 Like Vischer, he treated the

experience of aesthetic perception as

temporal, spatial, and

embodied. Even spectators who attended to singular, station

ary works of visual art were, implicitiy, mobile creatures,

remaining physically present within their environment. Per

ception was therefore neither static nor entirely dependent on visual cues. "Since we do not view nature simply

as visual

beings tied to a single vantage point but, rather, with all our

senses at once, in perpetual change and motion, we live and

weave a spatial consciousness into the nature that surrounds

us," he asserted; the awareness of space remained "even when

we close our eyes."26

Hildebrand's treatise offered a series of conceptual dichot

omies: the near and the distant view (Nahsicht and Fernsicht),

scanning and seeing (Schauen and Sehen), and inherent and

effective form (Daseinsform and Wirkungsform). Favoring the

second term in each case, he argued that the ideal work of art

united these pairs; framing the effective form of the depicted

object or image, it allowed the viewer to apprehend it as if

from a distance, inspiring within the viewer an intense aes

thetic sensation that he explained in somatic terms: "We

seem, so to speak, to grow larger or smaller to fit the im

age."27 He was primarily concerned with the fine (and not the

applied) arts, writing, for example, that in painting, "of prime

importance is not the appeal of color in itself, as in a carpet,

but its capacity to denote distance."28 Moreover, he advo

cated a particular kind of art, presenting relief sculpture as

the ideal art form, since it spurred the spectator's visual

imagination most strongly into action. His status as a relief

sculptor ensured that his artistic achievements exemplified his

arguments.29 One persistent account of modernism in the visual arts

asserts an increasing reliance on

opticality, ranging chrono

logically from the work of Edouard Manet to the post-paint

erly abstraction of the 1960s. Modernism, as Clement Green

berg explained it, was a matter "of purely optical experience

against optical experience as revised or modified by tactile

associations."30 Facing a work of art, in his account, the

modernist viewer experiences an aesthetic response from the

vantage point of a disembodied eye: a singular perceiving

entity that remained unencumbered by any attachment to

the human body within which it was located. The conceptual

opposition of bodily and optical perception paralleled an

other distinction between traditional representational paint

ing and those works Greenberg described as modernist: "The

Old Masters created an illusion of space in depth that one

could imagine oneself walking into," he argued, "but the

analogous illusion created by the Modernist painter can only be seen into; can be traveled through

... only with the eye."31

The spatial concerns of traditional representational painting

provided the spectator with an opportunity for an embodied

perceptual experience. By contrast, modernist painting was

posited as

essentially flat, optical, and monocular.

The invention of such a notion of opticality is often as

cribed to Fiedler, who famously stated in 1887, "The sole aim

of artistic activity is to be found in the expression of the pure

visibility [Sichtbarkeit] of an object."32 Fiedler's position is

consequendy often taken as antithetical to the concept of

Einf?hlung. Hildebrand, however, developed the ideas for his own book during many years' dialogue with Fiedler. Begin

ning in 1881, Fiedler reviewed several drafts over the course

of a dozen years, a collaboration that suggests a conceptual al

liance between Einf?hlung and opticality. Correspondence be tween the two, demonstrating the extent of Fiedler's influence

on Hildebrand's ideas, lasted from 1870 until Fiedler's death

in 1895, when Hildebrand designed the bronze plaque for his

This content downloaded on Tue, 5 Feb 2013 17:34:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 6: Limits of Empathy

4 Olga Rozanova, Green Stripe (Color

Painting), 1917. Rostov Kremlin State

Museum Preserve (artwork in the

public domain)

if?r.

:.?k

ON THE LIMITS OF EMPATHY I43

:M^f?^'^i'^\ ''7^-y^

^$pf?e?-&t& . ^ ;- \ ,- ;* ;. -?

'X^i^A;.

friend's grave (Fig. 3).33 Vischer's seemingly contradictory

phrase "the optical sense of form" thus captures an essential

claim of Einf?hlung, optical experience occurs with the entire

body. For Vischer, Hildebrand, and Fiedler, opticality was not

"revised or modified by tactile associations," as in Greenberg's

phrase; such associations were there from the beginning. In 1917, almost half a century after Vischer described the

viewer's response to a simple vertical line, the Russian Suprem

atist artist Olga Rozanova made a small painting that consists

of a green vertical stripe on a white background (Fig. 4). "We

propose to liberate painting from its subservience to the

ready-made forms of reality," the artist declared, "and to

make it first and foremost a creative, not a reproductive, art.

The aesthetic value of an abstract picture lies in the com

pleteness of its painterly content."34 Rather than depicting

three-dimensional architectural space or a narrative scene, a

work of art might now demonstrate, with revolutionary clar

ity, the radical act of pure painting. A green vertical line, which theorists of Einf?hlung in late-nineteenth-century Ger

many might have used to measure a viewer's embodied

perception, now stood?in the Soviet Union, following the

October Revolution?as a monument of modernist non

objectivity. Vischer and his cohorts would not have rec

ognized Rozanova's painted line as a work of art, but in

positing and debating the universal response to abstract form

they theorized a perceptual response to visual abstraction

decades before its actual birth.35

Psychological Empathy While historians and theorists of art and architecture com

posed treatises on Einf?hlung that garnered authority from

psychological research?which itself depended on physiolog ical analysis after the late 1870s?psychologists likewise at

tended to the topic, and with particular zeal around the turn

of the twentieth century.36 Prominent among them was

Lipps, who declared in his essay "Einf?hlung und ?stheti

scher Genuss" (Empathy and Aesthetic Pleasure) of 1906

that, in viewing objects, "I necessarily permeate them with . . .

striving, activity, and power. Grasped by reason, they bear

within them, insofar as they

are 'my' objects, this piece of

This content downloaded on Tue, 5 Feb 2013 17:34:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 7: Limits of Empathy

244 ART BULLETIN MARCH 2006 VOLUME LXXXVIII NUMBER 1

myself."37 Without this active contribution on the part of a

spectator, he explained, objects could not be properly con

sidered to exist.38 While a work of art allowed the viewer to

experience Einf?hlung in its purest form, this state of affairs

held true for any object; psychological investigations of Ein

f?hlung were therefore concerned with everyday objects,

treating the viewer as the primary object of analysis and

relying on inductive reasoning and experimentation. Even such aesthetic theories, however, were

coming to be

considered useless without the support of psychological evi

dence. As Lipps himself argued in 1907, "Aesthetics is either

psychological aesthetics or a collection of declarations of

some individual who possesses a sufficiendy loud voice to

proclaim his private predilections or his dependence on

fashion."39 The loud proclamations of individual theorists?

the reference might well have been to Schmarsow, Vischer,

W?lfflin, or Hildebrand?would, ideally, be replaced with

careful scientific analyses that were based on the experiences

of a larger number of people. Rather than theorizing a

universal response to Romanesque and Gothic arches, as

W?lfflin had, Einf?hlung might be used to interpret the data

accumulated from numerous subjects?or at least from the

same one at different moments.40

In testing numerous responses to forms and colors, psycho

logical research on Einf?hlung acknowledged the possibility of perceptual difference. Vischer had noted the reactions of

only one

pair of eyes?his own?and the role of perceptual

research in his writing was minimal. Authority rested in the

body of the author, who presented his experience as univer

sal. Hildebrand's declarations were only theoretically bol

stered by laboratory research; he particularly admired the

work of Hermann von Helmholtz, whose three-volume Trea

tise on Physiological Optics was published between 1856 and

1866.41 "What he says about the laws of the fine arts is

completely in accordance with my thoughts," Hildebrand

wrote to Fiedler, "and proves the correctness of my work?I

always thought that it would find a good reader in Helmholtz

in particular."42 Hildebrand made a bust of Helmholtz in

1891, describing the commission as "a nice opportunity to get

closer to this man."43 And in 1897, three years after the

scientist's death, Hildebrand designed the Helmholtz family grave site.

Addressing individual perception at a universal level, Ein

f?hlung offered a forum for abstract discussions of the view

er's experience, but its conception of spectatorship as indi

vidualistic also prompted its downfall. In the early twentieth

century, psychologists and aesthetic theorists began losing interest in the concept, owing partly

to laboratory research

that discovered perceptual differences among those tested.

According to one source, the British psychologist Edward

Bullough, experiments in 1905 revealed, for example, "the

same subject found oblique straight lines sometimes pleasant and sometimes unpleasant, occasionally

on one and the same

day."44 The changeable nature of individuals was exacerbated

by the unreliability of those in groups; universal and consis

tent characterizations could not confidently be assigned even

to the simplest forms. After testing one hundred viewers,

Bullough himself found "four clearly distinguishable types of

apperception."45 Such discoveries called into question the

accuracy of W?lfflin's universalizing statements regarding

horizontal and vertical lines. "The types appear to be not

merely momentary attitudes of the subject," Bullough wrote,

"but fundamental and permanent modes of apprehending

and appreciating colour."

While only small groups were tested, and viewer categories

remained abstract?differences in class and gender, for ex

ample, were often disregarded?psychological research on

Einf?hlung established the possibility of perceptual differ ence.

"Experimental work on large numbers," Bullough

ar

gued, "would . . . have shown that no single

one of the

explanations championed by different adherents of the the

ory [of Einf?hlung] could claim the monopoly of truth."46

Regardless of how firmly they were based in the theoretical concerns of perceptual psychology, the aesthetic theories of

individual authors were seen to founder on the bedrock of

scientific research. The dissolution of Einf?hlung as an

objec

tive paradigm led Bullough to conclude in 1921: "The great varieties of views and the acrimonious wrangles which took

place at the end of the last century between the upholders of

rival doctrines arose precisely from the generalization of

purely personal introspective evidence."47 Such evidence,

based on the claims of an individual theorist, could not be

generalized into universal truth.

In the late nineteenth century, theorists of Einf?hlung had

described the aesthetic responses of a viewer whom they

extrapolated from their own personal experience. They

treated the spectator as an educated and cultured individual

whose elite status depended

on a presumed superiority to an

uncultured public. Vischer's comment that Einf?hlung "leaves

the self in a certain solitude" meant, ostensibly, that the

process of psychic projection left the viewer feeling emotion

ally and psychologically depleted and, as it were, theoretically

solitary.48 At the same time, it revealed a basic presumption

about the kind of viewer capable of feeling Einf?hlung and

the environment within which it could be experienced. In

articulating a universal aesthetic response to round or

pointed arches, W?lfflin likewise had allowed for a very par ticular viewer: a cultivated and sensitive individual whose soul

might be transported by an exalted experience of art. While

never explicitly described, the empathetic viewer was implic

itiy a man of property whose identity was destabilized within

the confines of a relatively private realm, carefully circum

scribed by the laws of decorum and propriety. The capacity for aesthetic judgment presumed a level of

material comfort and poise exemplified by an undated pho

tograph of W?lfflin (Fig. 5). The well-groomed scholar leans

forward in his chair, gazing intensely at a work of art. His shirt

collar is crisply starched; his jacket formal but not uncom

fortably so; and his face is bathed in a radiant light that

appears to emanate from the work of art itself?or perhaps

from a window at the right. We perceive the work of art in a

three-quarter view: a small painting of a figure set within an

ornate wooden frame. (Is it a religious painting of a woman?

a nude figure? Were we in W?lfflin's privileged position, we,

too, would know.) W?lfflin's own attention to the work is

hap tic in the most literal sense; he holds it in his right hand,

propped against a table, in a

physical gesture that reads,

symbolically, as one of familiarity and potential ownership. The objects

on the table, meanwhile?a vase of flowers, a

sculpture, a stack of books?signify further facets of his ab

This content downloaded on Tue, 5 Feb 2013 17:34:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 8: Limits of Empathy

ON THE LIMITS OF EMPATHY J45

sorbed engagement: beauty, tactility, and erudition. Likewise

brighdy lighted (and, on closer inspection, somewhat awk

wardly held), the art historian's hand appears at the center of

the photograph's lower edge, holding the work of art for

both him and us to see. Anchoring this representation of the

trajectory of Einf?hlung, it also encourages our own gaze to

travel from W?lfflin's attentive eyes down to the painting and

up again to the three-dimensional figure, the flowers, and the

books?and to the radiant world beyond.

For his part, Worringer affectionately described W?lfflin as

"this bourgeois aristocrat of Switzerland (or should I say: this

aristocratic bourgeois)," adding that "in W?lfflin's case, the

expression 'le style c'est l'homme'is really of the most convinc

ing accuracy."49 Lipps himself clearly articulated the privi

leged status of the empathetic viewer?or, more accurately,

that of the theorist o? Einf?hlung?when he wrote in 1906:

But that one should know what aesthetic contemplation

means, that one should have had experience in this aes

thetic contemplation, in brief: that one should know that

aesthetic experience is to be absolutely clearly distin

guished from all the experience of things that occur in the

real world. . . . All of this must first be demanded of any

one who speaks of empathy and wants to join the discus

sion of the question of empathy.50

Like the theorists themselves, the viewer that the concept

posited was implicitly a bourgeois man of property: a viewer

who might sit comfortably at home, holding the object of his

aesthetic engagement between his hands. His subjectivity could be destabilized within the confines of a relatively pri vate realm; his cultural and intellectual background (and,

indeed, his gender) remained so consistent as to be taken for

granted; and his elite status depended in part on his superi

ority to an uncultured public.

With the expansion of middle-class leisure, the explosion

of mass media, and the unprecedented growth in the audi

ence for culture in the last decades of the nineteenth century,

this cultivated individual?and the Einf?hlung he theoreti

cally experienced?was increasingly difficult to maintain as a

universal model. Introduced in Berlin (as in Paris) in 1895, film gathered viewers into audiences that engaged in a kind

of spectatorship that the writings of Lipps, Vischer, and

W?lfflin had not addressed.51 A photograph taken at a cin ema in Berlin in 1913 shows an audience absorbed in this new form of spectatorship (Fig. 6). Men, women, and chil

dren are together in one room, which they have been allowed

to enter after paying a

relatively small entrance fee. Rather

than owning the work that they view, in other words?or

emulating this established model of aesthetic perception, as

museum visitors do?they have gained access to it tempo

rarily by means of a commercial transaction, and the terms of

their engagement have changed. Strangers sit among strang

ers, together watching the images that flicker on the giant, flat screen before them. This screen is distant, intangible; the

spatial depth displayed on it depicts a narrative that, to use

Greenberg's words, "can be traveled through . . .

only with

the eye." Here, spectators cannot hold an image in their hands.

This kind of optical experience, however, long remained

outside the realm of aesthetic discourse, an omission reflect

ing, among other things, the popularity of cinema among

lower- and middle-class spectators.52 As Erwin Panofsky would

later reminisce, movies in Berlin around 1905 were projected

in a few small and dingy cinemas mostiy frequented by the

"lower classes" and a sprinkling of youngsters in quest of

adventure. . .. Small wonder that the "better classes" when

they slowly began to venture into these early picture the

aters, did so . . . with that characteristic sensation of self

conscious condescension with which we may plunge . . .

into the folkloristic depths of Coney Island. .. .53

The rapid growth and rising social status of cinema audiences

after 1910 made film increasingly prominent both in German

society and aesthetic debate. While they were not explicidy mentioned in analyses of the viewer's relation to the work of

art, new audiences hovered in the background, challenging

the narrow parameters of aesthetic discourse.

Psychologists' differentiation of viewer types ostensibly re

sulted from laboratory experimentation. The phenomenon

also reflected a profound shift in the conception of specta

torship, one that was linked to a revised understanding of the

status of the spectator that, in turn, reflected sociological

changes among European audiences. Theorists of aesthetic

Einfuhling had sought to base their claims on psychological foundations, but the emerging discipline of psychology had

proved insufficient to describe a universal aesthetic response.

Difficulties arose in translating individual claims into univer

sally applicable statements, as well as in negotiating the terri

tory between objects of fine art and mass cultural experiences.

Early-twentieth-century research into psychological aesthetics

demonstrated not only that a viewer could feel Einf?hlung in

the absence of a work of art but also that an aesthetic response

might occur with no accompanying experience of Einf?hlung

Empathy and Abstraction

If the demise of Einf?hlung was already under way among

psychologists and aesthetic theorists at the beginning of the

twentieth century, its death knell was rung in 1908, when

Worringer used it as a conceptual foil in Abstraktion und

Einf?hlung (Abstraction and Empathy). Embraced as the bi

ble of twentieth-century aesthetic theory even before its pro

fessional publication, this book catapulted its author to fame

and was reprinted almost annually in subsequent decades.54

Conflating the experiences of the artist, spectator, and histo

rian?as well as the attributes of the work of art?Worringer

argued that all aesthetic activity could be traced to a dialec

tical formulation comprising the two concepts in his book's

tide. For Worringer, following Alois Riegl, artistic will, not

ability?the Kunstwollen, and not the Kunstk?nnen?governed

artistic creativity.55 Borrowing a rhetorical model from The

Birth of Tragedy, in which Nietzsche had divided Greek art into

the duality of Apollonian and Dionysian impulses, he posited

empathy and abstraction as two creative urges that, together,

constituted the Kunstwollen.56

Adhering to the requirements for the doctorate in his day,

Worringer published copies of his dissertation in 1907, dis

tributing them to those he thought might prove sympathetic. One recipient

was the writer Paul Ernst, who, unaware that

the book had not been published professionally, reviewed it

This content downloaded on Tue, 5 Feb 2013 17:34:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 9: Limits of Empathy

146 ART BULLETIN MARCH 2006 VOLUME LXXXVIII NUMBER 1

S'

5 W?lfflin, photograph, n.d.

in the journal Kunst und K?nstler. "The litde book deserves to

be closely heeded," he announced; "it contains nothing less

than a program for a new aesthetics."57 Providing a

synopsis

and an assessment of Worringer's argument, Ernst's review

sparked enough interest to prompt its publication the follow

ing year. "For a long time in our art as well as in our art

appreciation we have remained under the influence of Greek

antiquity and the Renaissance," Ernst wrote in summary of

the book. "But there are people and ages who had completely different artistic feelings and expressed these in their works.

As a rule, we interpret these today

as achievements of a de

ficient ability [K?nnen], when in reality they are the achieve ments of a differendy directed will [ Wollen]."58 Works from be

yond the borders of Renaissance Italy and ancient Greece were

also worth investigating, in other words; they merely required a new

conceptual framework with which to be understood.

Worringer's understanding of the latest psychological re

search and theoretical discourse regarding Einf?hlung was

better than he acknowledged. His main source for empathy

theory, he noted, was a dissertation completed in Munich in

1897 by Paul Stern (a student of Lipps, and Worringer's friend) and published a year later.59 But while Worringer

frequendy cited the work of Hildebrand, Riegl, Schopen hauer, Gottfried Semper, and W?lfflin, he generally ignored the particular claims offered by Lipps?an omission that is

striking given that his argument throughout the first of his

book's three chapters revolved around a formula taken from

Lipps's work. Having attended Lipps's lectures at the Univer

sity of Munich in 1904-5, Worringer would also have been aware of his professor's

own recent shift away from the psy

chological understanding of Einf?hlung.60 In his book, how

ever, he played down the importance of Lipps's major works as well as three decades of debate on the topic of Einf?hlung.

"Modern aesthetics," Worringer grandly announced in his

book's opening pages, "culminates in a theory that can be

described with a general and broad name as the doctrine of

empathy."61 Like the psychologists, Worringer argued that

this doctrine did not apply universally; rather, it governed

only the artistic naturalism of ancient Greece and Renais

sance Italy?art that was made by, and for, people who were

at ease in their environment and who found psychic repose in

aesthetic activity. Art from other eras and cultures was gov

erned by an "urge to abstraction [Abstraktionsdrang]," which

reflected discomfort on the part of both viewer and artist, and which he associated with ornament and with the notion

of style. More specifically, abstraction expressed a "spiritual aversion to space [geistige Raumscheu]," a horror vacui repre

sented on the cover of the book's ninth edition in 1916 by an

ornamental motif, its abstraction mitigated by the elaborate

twists of stylized snakes (Fig. 7) .62

Worringer based his arguments around what he initially

put forward as a condensed formula for the theory of Ein

f?hlung: "Aesthetic enjoyment is objectified self-enjoyment," or a

pleasurable sensation rendered in the form of an object.

His source was an essay published by Lipps in 1906; Worrin

ger chose to make rhetorical use of this formula rather than

engage more fully with a range of writings about Einf?hlung.

Lipps's "aesthetic system," he explained, "shall serve pars pro

toto as a foil for the following explanations."63 That system, in

turn, was encapsulated in this one formula, which Worringer

stated (without the use of quotation marks) five times in his

book's first chapter, each time to slighdy different effect.64 By its fifth and final appearance, Worringer had dislodged Ein

f?hlung from its pedestal to set a complementary theory of

abstraction beside it. Perhaps more significandy, he had

placed discomfort at the heart of the aesthetic experience. After a summary of Einf?hlung that reads as an endorse

ment, Worringer repeated Lipps's phrase: aesthetic enjoy

ment is objectified self-enjoyment. Immediately, however, he

asserted that his own book's very purpose was to demonstrate

that "with this theory of empathy, we stand helpless in the

face of the artistic creations of many ages and peoples."65

While Einf?hlung operated as the theoretical basis for the

naturalist art of ancient Greece and the Renaissance, the

This content downloaded on Tue, 5 Feb 2013 17:34:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 10: Limits of Empathy

ON THE LIMITS OF EMPATHY I47

6 Berlin cinema audience, 1913

happy and wholesome relation to the outside world it re

flected could not be universally applied; the art of all other

cultures was based on the urge to abstraction, which he

posited as both a fundamental, universal urge and the result

of highly developed cultures. "[W]ith primitive peoples, as it

were, the instinct for the 'thing in itself is at its strongest," he

argued, positing a

primitive man who was Kantian by

na

ture.66 Abstraction conflated a basic artistic urge on the part

of primitive cultures with the modern theories produced by the most advanced intellects of Western Europe: "What was

once instinct is now the ultimate product of knowledge."67

The third appearance of Lipps's formula indicated neither

agreement nor dissent. "What modern man calls beauty,"

Worringer explained, "is a satisfaction of that inner need for

self-affirmation that Lipps sees as the prerequisite of the

empathy process. In the forms of a work of art, we enjoy ourselves. Aesthetic enjoyment is objectified self-enjoy

ment."68 A beautiful object was, in effect, created by the

spectator's perception of it; the spectator relocated his enjoy able experience of self-affirmation within the object. The

activity of aesthetic contemplation thus provided an experi ence of psychic repose; the aesthetic object offered a repos

itory for the emotions it inspired.

Crucially, for Worringer aesthetic activity did not necessar

ily entail comfort. He first suggested as much with a passing reference to Lipps's distinction between positive and negative

Einf?hlung, or between a sense of freedom and one of reluc

tance felt in the face of the work of art.69 But even "negative

Einf?hlung did not sufficiendy articulate the profound sense

of unease that Worringer wished to discuss. Such a sensation

could be felt, he believed, both while contemplating a par ticular work of art and as a general existential condition.

Perhaps the true flaw of Einf?hlung was its failure to account

properly for psychic discomfort; what Worringer termed the

"urge to abstraction"?an urge that led artists to create ab

stract images and viewers to contemplate them?may be seen

as an attempt to theorize this condition. Worringer proudly

acknowledged the influence on his thinking of Georg Sim

mel, whose lectures he had attended in Berlin. In the fore

word to the 1948 edition of the book, he even wrote of

glimpsing the famous professor while visiting the Trocad?ro

Museum in Paris as an art history student and conceiving of

his dissertation topic later that day.70 With the fourth appearance of Lipps's formula, Worringer

finally stated his own position: "aesthetic enjoyment" and

"objectified self-enjoyment" were not equivalent, but op

posed. The former described the urge to abstraction; the

latter stood for empathy. Abstraction was now associated with

unease: an aesthetic enjoyment encompassing the experi

ence of its own interference. Empathy, by contrast, implied the comfortable relation between the viewer and the work of

art by means of which aesthetic enjoyment was delightfully rendered in the form of an object. More important than their

differences was the element of discomfort they shared: both

the urge to abstraction and the urge to empathy, Worringer wrote, "are only degrees of a common need that is revealed

to us as the deepest and ultimate essence of all aesthetic

experience: that is the need for self-estrangement [Selbstent

?usserung]," or a distance measured within the self.71

As if to emphasize the insufficiency of Lipps's formula,

Worringer repeated it once more, reiterating that even Ein

f?hlung entailed an experience of self-estrangement. In this

psychic transfer, he wrote, the spectator invested the work of

art with a portion of his self, sacrificing his autonomy as an

individual in order to exist, momentarily and aesthetically, within the work. "Insofar as we

empathize this urge to activity

into another object," he explained,

This content downloaded on Tue, 5 Feb 2013 17:34:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 11: Limits of Empathy

148 ART BULLETIN MARCH 2006 VOLUME LXXXVIII NUMBER 1

7 Cover of Wilhelm Worringer, Abstraktion und Einf?hlung 9th ed. (Munich: R. Piper, 1916)

we exist in the other object. We are delivered from our

individual being as

long as we ... are absorbed into an

external object, in an external form. We feel, as it were,

our individuality flow into fixed boundaries, as opposed to

the boundless differentiation of the individual conscious ness. In this self-objectification lies a self-estrangement [In dieser Selbstobjektivierung liegt eine Selbstent?usserung].72

The empathetic spectator, letting down his emotional guard,

permits himself to dissolve into the work of art. Such a

process of absorption, Worringer maintained, entailed a loss

of self that was felt as estrangement, not comfort.

To prove his point, Worringer quoted Lipps himself?this

time, notably, from his two-volume Aesthetics. "In empathizing

I am not the real I," Lipps had argued, "but rather am set free

from this inner I; that is, I am set free from everything that I am outside of the observation of form. I am only this ideal, this observing I."7? Even the ultimate authority on Einf?hlung, it would seem, had acknowledged the viewer's bifurcated

subjectivity?a distancing from the self, as it were?as central

to the perceptual process. (Daily speech could likewise be

mobilized to prove the existence of estrangement within the

aesthetic response, Worringer maintained: "popular usage

speaks with striking accuracy of 'losing oneself in the con

templation of a work of art.")74 Abstraction and Einf?hlung existed at opposite extremes along

an existential continuum

of emotional discomfort. The universal impulse to self-es

trangement played itself out formally in one, while an indi

vidualistic urge to self-estrangement appeared in the guise of

the other. Meeting at the edges of their continuum, the two

perceptual experiences were not always distinguishable. Like the theorists of Einf?hlung, Worringer presented his

claims in Abstraction and Empathy in terms of emotional sen

sations and psychological drives. At the same time, his book

shifted the terms of aesthetic debate in several significant ways. While refusing to acknowledge that Einf?hlung was ab

stract?insofar as it described a viewer's basic physiological response to pure form?he transposed its universalizing

claims to the concept of abstraction, even though such claims

had long been part of the internal critique that had crumbled

the authority of Einf?hlung. Beyond this, he reconfigured

Einf?hlung in his text as a general emotional identification,

ignoring its spatial orientation, thus further separating the

visual and applied arts from the discipline of architecture.

Finally, he placed discomfort at the heart of the aesthetic

response, thereby constructing a

conceptual hinge between

Einf?hlung and the articulations of estrangement that would

describe the communal aesthetic experience of the mass

audience in the 1920s and 1930s.

Self-Estrangement and the Fear of Space The conceptual opposition of Einf?hlung and abstraction in

Worringer's book thus masked a more profound claim: one

could trace "all aesthetic enjoyment, and perhaps the entire

human sensation of happiness generally, in its deepest and

ultimate essence, to the impulse of self-estrangement [Selbst

ent?usserung] ."75 The articulation of this impulse, sometimes

translated as self-distanciation or self-alienation, fundamen

tally reworked the status of comfort in the conception of the

aesthetic response. If aesthetic enjoyment, at its core, en

tailed an experience of self-estrangement, then discomfort

could be, in some essential way, pleasurable. By bringing the

notion of aesthetic distance into the body of the viewer,

Worringer provided a link between the idea of an individual

loss of self that had been fundamental to the late-nineteenth

century discourse of Einf?hlung and that of collective alien

ation, which would become central to the discourse of es

trangement, or Brechtian Verfremdung.

Worringer's analysis of spectatorship in terms of self-es

trangement derived in part from Nietzsche, who in 1876 had

described the activity of spectatorship almost as a form of

aesthetic schizophrenia. Writing of Richard Wagner's music

dramas, the philosopher explained that a spectator

is from time to time compelled ... to ask himself: what

would this nature have with you? To what end do you really

exist??Probably he will be unable to find an answer, and

will then stand still, amazed [befremdet] and perplexed at

his own being. Let him then be satisfied to have experi enced even this; let him hear in the fact that he feels alienated [entfremdet] from his own being the answer to his

question. For it is precisely with this feeling that he par

ticipates in Wagner's mightiest accomplishment, the cen

This content downloaded on Tue, 5 Feb 2013 17:34:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 12: Limits of Empathy

ON THE LIMITS OF EMPATHY I49

tral point of his power, the demonic transmissibility and

self-estrangement [Selbstent?usserung] of his nature. . . ,76

For Nietzsche, aesthetic perception in its most heightened form?the engagement with Wagner's music dramas at Bay

reuth, in the inaugural year of the festival theater there?

entailed a depletion of the spectator's

sense of self. The

experience was both liberating and disturbing, a conflation

of two sensations: a paralyzing loss of self and an active

engagement in the art object. The simultaneous presence of

detachment and absorption, estrangement and identifica

tion, defined both artistic creation and aesthetic reception.77

While the discourse of Einf?hlung had, in the nineteenth

century, treated the aesthetic response to spatial

as well as

visual form, Worringer attended primarily to two-dimen

sional creations in 1908. "Space is the greatest enemy of all

efforts at abstraction," he asserted, "and must therefore be

the first thing to be suppressed in the representation."78 Like

Hildebrand, he posited relief sculpture as the epitome of

artistic creation, insofar as it transformed spatial depth into

planar relations.79 But whereas Hildebrand had associated

two-dimensionality with the notion of distance on the

grounds that flat images resulted, literally, from distant views,

Worringer linked two-dimensionality with the emotional dis

tance felt within the spectator's body. He described this

psychic unease as "a tremendous spiritual aversion to space,"

likening it to "physical agoraphobia."80 As a result of this sen

sation, he argued, both artists and viewers were led to create,

or seek out, images of abstract purity: approximations of visual

planarity that soothed both eye and soul in a process reminis

cent, ironically, of his initial presentation of Einf?hlung.

According to Worringer, "the urge to abstraction is the

result of man's great inner unease, caused by the phenomena

of the outside world."81 This "primitive fear" persisted in the

modern era among "people of oriental cultures [orientalische

Kulturv?lker]," he asserted?those who had, over the course of

many centuries, managed to resist the civilizing influences of

the West.82 Abstraction, that is, was both the ultimate achieve

ment of advanced civilizations and a basic human urge: ex

otic and foreign, it remained the most fundamental form of

creativity. While cautioning against generalizing about prim

itive people on the grounds that the term covered disparate cultures of varying levels of artistic talent, Worringer himself

privileged human instinct in a manner that today reads as

Freudian. The fear of space was universal and was felt by both

artists and viewers, but the "rationalistic development of man

kind represses this instinctive fear, which is caused by man's

lost position in the world."83 Nonetheless, it was to be found

both among "primitives" and among those contemporary

Europeans who had been rendered fearful by the very process of civilization. This logic, although perverse, was prevalent in

early-twentieth-century European culture, making it possible

for Worringer to argue that to acknowledge the urge to

abstraction was to confront human instinct on its own terms,

stripped of the repressive forces of Western civilization.

Worringer characterized the urge to abstraction?both for

creative artists and those who viewed their creations?as "the

attempt to rescue the single object of the outside world from

its connection with and dependence on other things,

to

snatch it from the course of events, to render it absolute."84

As a process of spectatorial engagement, Einf?hlung was asso

ciated, fundamentally, with temporality. Developed in an era

of representational art, it was also linked to narrative; scenes

might literally be depicted within a painting, or they might

simply be implied, as with a portrait or a still life. Insofar as it

had been used to discuss the spectator's experience of archi

tecture, Einf?hlung suggested a movement through space that

necessarily occurred in time. By contrast, abstraction en

tailed, in Worringer's view, an effort to arrest temporality

itself?to detach the "single object of the outside world" from

other objects and from this world. For both artist and viewer, abstraction represented "the consummate ...

expression of

emancipation from the chance and temporality of the world

picture."85 This creative urge was manifested as a universal hu

man need to free particular objects from the existential terror of

the three-dimensional and of the dimension of time itself?a

fear that could be allayed only through aesthetic activity. A passing reference made by Hildebrand to "the agonizing

quality of the cubic [das Qu?lende des Kubischen]" had helped construct, in The Problem of Form, a theoretical justification of

ancient Greek sculptural relief; Worringer appropriated the

claim to justify even flatter artistic creations?as well as those

from all historical eras and geographic locations.86 All the

same, relief sculpture remained central to Worringer's argu

ment, a stance he derived from Hildebrand and Riegl. In

Stilfragen (Problems of Style), published in 1893, Riegl had

portrayed the history of world art as a grand trajectory from

three-dimensional objects to two-dimensional representation:

If we ignore concrete examples for a moment and try in a

purely deductive way to reason out abstracdy which of

them came first in the development, then we will find

ourselves forced ... to conclude that three-dimensional

sculpture is the earlier, more primitive medium, while

surface decoration is the later and more refined.87

Like Riegl, Worringer celebrated flatness, ornament, and

non-Western cultural artifacts. Unlike Riegl, he presented his

arguments succincdy and polemically. Avoiding the archaeo

logical detail that made Problems of Style so intimidating, he

reinforced its claims with arguments rooted in psychological

discourse.88

Again following Riegl, Worringer held that abstraction was

epitomized by the flat style of Egyptian vegetal ornament.

The urge to abstraction now operated

as the theoretical

apparatus ushering the creations of overlooked ages and

peoples into aesthetic discourse.89 Even while arguing for an

expansion of the art historical canon, Worringer showed little

interest in the expanding art audience; he described univer

sal vision within the framework of an aesthetic discourse that

had been in place since Immanuel Kant, leaving intact the

conception of the spectator as a cultivated individual. Like

the discourse of Einf?hlung itself, Worringer's book offered, at the level of the individual viewer, a theoretical understand

ing of a universal, visceral response to art. Where researchers

in psychology laboratories had begun to point to the possi

bility of larger audiences comprising varied individuals, Wor

ringer theorized their experience within the field of aesthet

ics. In conflating the psychic experience of the Egyptian artist

and the contemporary European spectator, and in identify

This content downloaded on Tue, 5 Feb 2013 17:34:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 13: Limits of Empathy

150 ART BULLETIN MARCH 2006 VOLUME LXXXVIII NUMBER 1

8 Gabriele Munter, M?dchen mit Puppe (Girl with DoU), 1908-9. Milwaukee Art Museum, Gift of Mrs. Harry Lynde Bradley

(artwork ? 2005 Artists Rights Society [ARS], New York / VG Bild-Kunst, Bonn)

ing the work of art as both cause and effect of this experi ence, he allowed for the possibility that untrained eyes? those not belonging to cultivated Europeans, for example?

might likewise be capable of aesthetic experience.

Worringer set the duality of Einf?hlung and abstraction

parallel to that of naturalism and style, linking Einf?hlung with naturalist depiction, and his arguments were

easily un

derstood in relation to recent cultural developments in Mu

nich. Two decades earlier, that city's most advanced artistic

creations had fallen under the rubric of naturalism, but by the early twentieth century artists, art theorists, writers, and

dramatists considered that approach to be outmoded.90 Pri

marily in drama, but in other fields as well, naturalism had come to stand for an obsessive imitation of reality and the

abandonment of true creativity. Rather than simply denigrat

ing naturalism for its mimetic capacities, however, Worringer historicized it, declaring it an artistic tendency that, by 1908, was on the wane. In so doing, he distinguished it from

imitation, which (like the urge to abstraction) existed, he

maintained, in every era and among all cultures. "The drive

to imitation, this elemental human need, stands outside aes

thetics proper," he argued; "in principle its satisfaction has

nothing to do with art."91

Despite Worringer's efforts to distinguish naturalism and

imitation, the two were clearly linked in early-twentieth-cen

tury German artistic discourse; artists and designers engaged in the rejection of the former had for years been disparaging the latter. In 1900, the architect Peter Behrens had written, for example: "It's not difficult for a man with a talent for

imitation to put on a mask and represent a well observed

character; even if not everyone can do this, that does not

make it art."92 True art required a level of creativity beyond the simple craft of imitation; the sinuous Jugendstil tendrils

Behrens himself designed at the turn of the century did not

reproduce plant forms but, rather, expressed in abstract vi

sual terms the force of vegetal growth. By 1908, even Behrens

had abandoned his Jugendstil roots. "We have in the fine arts

as in poetry reached the outermost point of Naturalism,"

Ernst asserted in his review of Abstraction and Empathy that

year; "the pendulum will now swing to the other side, and it

is Worringer's achievement to have explained this process

historically and philosophically."93 As the aesthetic pendulum swung toward abstraction, nat

uralism and imitation came to be associated with feminine

creativity. Using the terms laid out in Worringer's book, one

might theoretically have assigned abstraction, and the notion

of decorative ornament with which it was associated, to the

province of women. But while Worringer linked ornament to

the artistic creations of primitive people [Naturv?lker] and

with children's scribbles, he did not present the concept in

gendered terms.94 Those who did, meanwhile, such as the art

critic Karl Scheffler, associated women not with abstraction

and ornament but, instead, with empathy, naturalism, and

imitation. In Die Frau und die Kunst (Woman and art), also

published in 1908, Scheffler labeled the woman artist "the

imitatrix par excellence ... who sentimentalizes and trivial

izes manly art forms."95 True creativity and aesthetic original

ity remained the province of men; women functioned essen

tially as copyists. This distinction between male and female

creative impulses also held true among viewers, in Scheffler's

view: "Woman looks at a work of art in terms of the nature

contained within it; abstraction remains foreign to her."96

Such an association of Einf?hlung with passivity, imitation, and feminine creativity would hold sway for decades.

Artists and writers in 1908, particularly in Munich, wel

comed Worringer's book, which they took as support for

their own rejection of artistic naturalism. While Worringer demonstrated no interest in contemporary European art, his

book encouraged Wassily Kandinsky and Gabriele M?nter, as

well as other future members of the Blaue Reiter, to investi

gate painterly abstraction.97 The flat, unmodeled planes of

color in Munter's M?dchen mit Puppe (Girl with Doll, 1908-9), its forms composed of abstracted expanses of color within

heavy black oudines, reflect several sources, including the

paintings of Henri Matisse and the Jugendstil emphasis on

planarity and flatness (Fig. 8), but she acknowledged her

debt to Worringer direcdy. "We have known each other since

the beginnings of the postimpressionist development of art," the artist reminded Worringer in a letter written on the

occasion of his seventieth birthday, a development "for which

you prepared the intellectual ground. I still have from those

early years the original copy of your book Abstraction and

Empathy, which had at the time such a profound effect."98 As

This content downloaded on Tue, 5 Feb 2013 17:34:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 14: Limits of Empathy

ON THE LIMITS OF EMPATHY \^\

9 Wassily Kandinsky, Composition IV, 1911. Kunstsammlung Nordrhein-Westfalen, D?sseldorf (artwork ? 2005 Artists Rights Society [ARS], New York / ADAGP, Paris)

one critic stated that same year, there existed "hardly a

single

member of the avant-garde of modern art who was not deeply

excited by this book."99 In ?ber das Geistige in der Kunst ( Concerning the Spiritual in

Art), first published in 1911, Kandinsky, too, advocated uthe

rejection of the third dimension, that is to say, the attempt to keep the

picture on a

single plane."100 His Composition IV of that year, an

image on the threshold of abstraction, likewise demonstrates

the resonance of Worringer's ideas (Fig. 9). Subtided Battle, the painting shows three figures standing at its center, with

white robes, red caps, and two long, vertical spears. On the

left, three groups of parallel black lines become the spears of

advancing armies visible over the hilly horizon, and on the

right, two large figures lean backward in the foreground. The

image requires the viewer's effort in order to become repre

sentational. As Kandinsky explained it,

The more abstract form is, the more clear and direct its

appeal... . The more an artist uses these abstract forms,

the deeper and more confidendy will he advance into the

kingdom of the abstract. And after him will follow the

viewer ... who will also have gradually acquired a greater

familiarity with the language of that kingdom.101

Painterly abstraction offered a realm of purity and directness, a kingdom of unknown riches awaiting discovery by the bold

est artists and art lovers of the early twentieth century. Those

who dared navigate such territory would create truly universal

works of art that, at least theoretically, would be equally accessible to all. Formal clarity would deepen the interaction

between artist, object, and spectator; bypass the limitations of

linguistic difference; and ignore national boundaries, both

within Europe and beyond.

Empathy, Distraction, Estrangement In 1925, the art critic Franz Roh identified "the art of the

nineteenth century, including impressionism," as an era of

Einf?hlung, one that had since been replaced?first by ab

straction, in the early twentieth century, and subsequentiy by what he very hesitandy termed "magic realism."102 In associ

ating the demise of Einf?hlungv?th the birth of a new form of

visual art, Roh conflated a theory of aesthetic perception?a form of spectatorship?with the visual style of the art objects

with which its theoretical spectator engaged. Such a confla

tion reveals, above all, the impossibility of disengaging aes

thetic discourse from the kinds of objects it describes. Both

the birth of abstract painting and the reconfiguration of

architecture as a spatial

art around the turn of the last cen

tury appeared to detach narrative, spatial depth, and tempo

rality from the realm of the visual arts. The emergence of

film, meanwhile, and its extraordinary ability to conjure three-dimensional space?precisely what Worringer had

called the greatest enemy of all efforts at visual abstrac

tion?as well as the growing presence of crowds in cinemas

and the interest of particular historians and critics in watch

This content downloaded on Tue, 5 Feb 2013 17:34:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 15: Limits of Empathy

152 ART BULLETIN MARCH 2006 VOLUME LXXXVIII NUMBER 1

absorption, unlike that of the cultured spectators of the

nineteenth century, was treated as wholly passive.

It was this model of spectatorship?shallow, passive, weak

willed?that Brecht opposed with such vehemence when, in

1936, he promulgated the theory of Verfremdung (estrange ment or alienation) after many years' work with the unnamed

concept. The technique of estrangement, he explained,

could be used to combat the "empathy theater [einf?hlungs

theater]" that relied on the suspension of disbelief.107 The use

of Einf?hlung, according to Brecht, existed only for bourgeois entertainment: it encompassed

an experience of psychologi

cal and emotional identification that encouraged spectators

to lose control of their own identities and prevent the possi

bility of critical thought. In Brecht's writings, the concept had

litde to do with the active experience of embodied spatial

perception that the theorists o? Einf?hlung had debated in the

last quarter of the nineteenth century. Psychological and

emotional, it was devoid even of the element of self-estrange

ment that Worringer, following Simmel, had placed within its

shallow domain. For Brecht, Einf?hlung provided a useful foil

for estrangement, the conceptual tool that was to reinstate

spectators' self-control, critical awareness, and political en

gagement both within the auditorium and, potentially, be

yond its walls.

Despite his public condemnations of the concept, Brecht

confided to his journal that Einf?hlung could be useful as "a

rehearsal measure"; in performances, he wrote, ideally "two

different methods are used: the technique of empathy and

the technique of estrangement [die einf?hlungstechnik und die

Verfremdungstechnik].,"108 This alternation of distancing and

absorption was in fact necessary, he explained, insofar as

neither technique could exist without the intermittent pres

ence of the other. In ajournai entry of 1940, Brecht elabo

rated on their theoretical relation:

in this new method of practicing art empathy would lose

its dominant role, against that the alienation effect (a

effect) will need to be introduced, which is an artistic

effect too and also leads to a theatrical experience, it

consists in the reproduction of real-life incidents on the

stage in such a way as to underline their causality and

bring it to the spectator's attention, this type of art also

generates emotions; such performances facilitate the mas

tering of reality; and this it is that moves the spectator.109

Here, again, theoretical techniques were conflated with the

art forms that were to produce them. The realism of nine

teenth-century visual art had been linked to "an era of Ein

f?hlung" a

perceptual experience that, according to both

Lipps and Worringer, involved a bifurcated sense of self.

Contrary to his own highly publicized claims on the subject, the theatrical realism Brecht hoped to create in the 1930s

required the occasional use of Einf?hlung. At different histor

ical moments?and with regard to radically different model

subjects?both empathy and estrangement described the

viewer's potentially uncomfortable destabilization of identity.

Despite the arguments of Brecht and others, it is not always

possible to make a clear distinction between passive and

10 Heinrich Hoffmann, audience listening to Adolf Hitler,

possibly Weimar, photograph. The Getty Research Institute, Los Angeles, Research Library, 920024

ing movies, all challenged the status of Einf?hlung as a dom

inant theory of aesthetic perception.

The reign of Einf?hlung was, indeed, over. Yet, Roh's de

cree notwithstanding, the concept remained central to the

understanding of spectatorship throughout the twentieth

century, and was merely reworked to accommodate shifts in

the status of spectators and the objects to which they at

tended. It continued to surface as a conceptual foil, a femi

nine weakness, and the ingredient of a populist

art history.103

Given the concept's reconfiguration, it is particularly striking

that three of the most important theorists of Einf?hlungin the

1920s were women: Vernon Lee, Clementine Anstruther

Thomson, and Edith Stein, a student of Edmund Husserl.104

The intense experience of absorbed spectatorship also took

on other terminological guises. Siegfried Kracauer's assertion

in 1929, for example, that films "drug the populace with the

pseudo-glamour of counterfeit social heights, just as

hypno

tists use glittering objects to put their subjects to sleep,"

posited a visual, psychological, and emotional absorption that

had been reconfigured as feminine, passive, and communal

for the Weimar mass audience.105 Visiting the new picture

palaces, Kracauer maintained, moviegoers?especially the

"little shopgirls" on their evenings off?diverted their atten

tion from the dull routine of daily employment.106 Their

distraction was figured

as a form of attention: an intense

absorption in the narratives they followed on-screen. This

This content downloaded on Tue, 5 Feb 2013 17:34:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 16: Limits of Empathy

11 Hider at the premiere of Morgenrot,

Ufa-Palast, 1933, photograph. The

Getty Research Institute, Los Angeles, Research Library, 920024

ON THE LIMITS OF EMPATHY \^

wm w tw.

v*^^Mm?;

"X*

active spectatorship, or between observation and participa

tion. While Brecht was developing the theory of estrange ment, it was becoming increasingly difficult, in Germany and

elsewhere, to distinguish the role of the individual spectator within the communal audience. Brecht was concerned less

with the passive aesthetic response per se than with the

potential political ramifications of such passivity in the audi

ences of the 1930s. His concerns may be represented with two

contemporaneous photographs (Figs. 10, 11). The first, taken by Heinrich Hoffmann, shows an audience attending to Adolf Hider and others on a theater stage. Crowded into

three tiers of an auditorium, men and women appear fully

absorbed in the performance they are

watching; the camera,

positioned just above the speakers to emphasize Hider's

bowed head in the lower left corner of the image, faces the

attentive crowd and centers on the banner hung from the

royal box: a flat canvas that displays a swastika. Brecht's

mistrust of Einf?hlung stemmed from a horror of passive, communal spectatorship and a fear of the uncritical accep

tance of Nazi claims that was already widespread. Without

mentioning Vischer, Lipps, or Worringer (his own reference

point was Aristode), he criticized the kind of spectatorship that entailed a loss of self and an overidentification with the

object of attention. The swastika at the center of the image

suggests, too, that National Socialist visual language might be

associated as much with abstraction as with Einf?hlung?or that the Einf?hlung Brecht decried had litde to do with the

concept as it was discussed in the nineteenth century.110 A second photograph shows Hider and his cohorts sitting

in the balcony at the cinema, attending a film premiere at the

Ufa-Palace in Berlin in 1933. As if absorbed in the perfor mance, they stare out beyond the space of the image?all but

one, who looks directiy, and quizzically, at the camera lens.

The generic gesture of a disembodied hand, at the right,

indicates the existence of an empty seat at the bottom of the

photograph, complete with a program booklet laid out on

the balustrade before it. The real actors, here, would seem to

be the political figures on view within the photograph, and

not those whom they are

watching on the silver screen. Hider

himself, his arms crossed and his head turned slightiy toward

the camera, appears as aware of the photographer who is

taking his picture as of the film he is meant to be watching. In Germany in the 1930s, the mass audience seemed to be

equally absorbed by the movies and the political rallies of

National Socialism; Brecht characterized their absorption as

passive and labeled such passivity Einf?hlung. Never one to shy from conceptual contradiction?or the

performance of passivity, or gender bending, for that mat

ter?Andy Warhol can serve both to personify the conflation

of empathy and estrangement and to demonstrate the ex

traordinary reach of these two theoretical models. A photo

graph from 1971 shows Warhol and other spectators engaged in rapt absorption at the Invisible Cinema, constructed that

year by the avant-garde filmmaker Peter Kubelka for the

Anthology Film Archives in New York (Fig. 12). Permitting a

form of spectatorship simultaneously individual and commu

nal, the construction allowed each spectator to see the movie

screen, but not the other spectators. Dismanded owing to

difficulties with air circulation in the room (heating and

air-conditioning proved impossible), it combined the private

activity of individual spectatorship with the communal activity of movie going. Here, a

solitary spectator could attend to a

film in a manner that approximated the individualistic expe rience of Einf?hlung, as it had been described almost a cen

tury earlier with regard to representational works of art,

objects in nature, and abstract forms. And who could say if

these spectators felt empathy or estrangement, sitting sepa

rately, together, within a communal audience?

This content downloaded on Tue, 5 Feb 2013 17:34:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 17: Limits of Empathy

154 ART BULLETIN MARCH 2006 VOLUME LXXXVIII NUMBER 1

12 Andy Warhol at Peter Kubelka's Invisible Cinema at the

Anthology Film Archives, New York, 1971 (photograph by Michael Chikiris, reproduced by permission of Anthology Film

Archives)

Juliet Koss is assistant professor of art history at Scripps College, Claremont. Her work has appeared in The Art Bulletin, Assem

blage, Grey Room, Kritische Berichte, and elsewhere; she is

currently completingThe Total Work of Art: Modernism, Spec

tatorship, and the Gesamtkunstwerk [Department of Art History,

Scripps College, Claremont, Calif 91711, [email protected]].

Notes Portions of this material were delivered at Columbia University, February 2004; Yale University, February 2004; Johns Hopkins University, April 2004;

Scripps College, April 2005; the College Art Association Conference, New

York, February 2000 and February 2003; the Association of Art Historians'

conference, London, April 2003; and the Society of Architectural Historians'

conference, Providence, April 2004. My thanks go to all of those who invited me to speak and to my audiences and interlocutors at each event My research on Einf?hlung was carried out at the Getty Research Institute, Los Angeles, during a residential fellowship in 1998-2000; further support for my research came from a Summer Stipend from the National Endowment for the Human

ities, 2002; a sabbatical research fellowship from Scripps College, 2002-3; and a Humboldt Foundation Research Fellowship, 2002-4. I am deeply grateful for all of these, and to the Bergemanns for their hospitality in Nuremberg. Finally, my thanks to those who have generously read and commented on

earlier incarnations of this essay: Lory Frankel, Marc Gotlieb, Sandy Isenstadt,

Lutz Koepnick, Helga Lutz, Erik Wegerhoff, and the two anonymous (and

mutually contradictory) readers for The Art Bulletin. All translations are my own, except where otherwise noted; once again, I am

grateful to Steven Lindberg for checking them over but retain the responsi bility for any errors that might remain. Throughout the text I have left the term Einf?hlung untranslated where it refers specifically to the late-nine

teenth-century discourse in an effort to distinguish the concept from more

amorphous understandings of empathy.

1. Claims for a critical empathetic approach deriving from "a surrealist

tradition, an alternative twentieth-century modernist tradition ... that has to do with psychology, emotion, surprise and scariness" are found in Herbert Muschamp, "How the Critic Sees: Conversation with Her

bert Muschamp," Architecture New York 21 (1998): 16-17. On Hopper, see Alain de Botton, The Art of Travel (London: Hamish Hamilton,

2002), 53-54 and passim; on Menzel, see Michael Fried, Menzel's Real ism: Art and Embodiment in Nineteenth-Century Berlin (New Haven: Yale

University Press, 2002); and on Gehry, see Christian Hubert, "Outside/ In: Frank Gehry and Empathy" (lecture, School of Architecture, Uni

versity of Toronto, November 8, 2001). According to the cultural histo rian Alison Landsberg, "technologies of mass culture," film especially, "are a preeminent site for the production of empathy." Landsberg, Pros thetic Memory: The Transformation of American Remembrance in the Age of Mass

Culture (New York: Columbia University Press, 2004), 47. Finally, an in

dependent film entitled Empathy, directed by Amie Siegel, produced by Mark Ranee, and released in 2002, addressed the relation between psycho analysis, documentary filmmaking, and modern architecture and design.

2. Karen Finley's performance at the Cutting Room, New York, in July 2002 (a work in progress "which explores the emotions of New Yorkers

after September 11th," according to its promotional material) was enti tled "The Distribution of Empathy." Barbara Kruger's empathy project exists in several versions and at least three languages; Einf?hlungsver m?gen kann die Weh ver?ndern (The Capacity for Empathy Can Change the World), for example, was installed on advertising billboards in

Wuppertal, Germany, in 1990.

3. In this context, see Suzanne Perling Hudson, "Beauty and the Status of

Contemporary Criticism," October, no. 104 (Spring 2003): 115-30; Alex ander Alberro, "Beauty Knows No Pain," Art Journal 63, no. 2 (Summer

2004): 36-43; Elaine Scarry, On Beauty and Being Just (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999); and Dave Hickey, The Invisible Drag on: Four Essays on Beauty (Los Angeles: Art Issues Press, 1993). The link between beauty and empathy was made by Carl Jung, who argued (cit

ing Theodor lipps): "The form into which one cannot empathize is ...

ugly." C. G. Jung, Psychological Types, or The Psychology of Individua

tion, trans. H. Godwin Baynes (1923; reprint, London: Pantheon

Books, 1964), 360, emphasis in the original; translation modified.

4. "The most fruitful research developed in the afterlife of Warburg's contributions," the historian Michael S. Roth has argued, for example, "will be work that explores specific intersections of memory and empa

thy in the visual domain, work that tries to understand the past as part of the history of the present. This is to be distinguished from simply projecting the present back on to the past?an exercise in narcissism, not empathy." "Why Warburg Now?" (paper presented at the College Art Association Conference, New York, 2000).

5. Scholarly interest in Einf?hlung has been prompted by the translation and publication of selected primary documents in Empathy, Form and

Space: Problems in German Aesthetics, 1873-1893, ed. and trans. Harry Francis Mallgrave and Eleftherios Ikonomou (Santa Monica: Getty Cen ter Publications, 1994). Other relevant recent works include Georges

Didi-Huberman, L'image survivante: L'histoire de l'art et temps des fant?mes selon Aby Warburg (Paris: ?ditions de Minuit, 2002), 400-413; Juliet

Koss, "Empathy and Abstraction in Munich," in The Built Surface, vol. 2, Architecture and the Pictorial Arts from Romanticism to the TxvenfyFirst Century, ed. Karen Koehler (London: Ashgate, 2002), 98-119; and Nina Rosen

blatt, "Empathy and Anaesthesia: On the Origins of a French Machine

Aesthetic," Grey Room 2 (Winter 2001): 78-97. The call for papers for a

session devoted to empathy at the Society of Architectural Historians' conference in 2004 referred to the concept as a "dominant theory."

6. Robert Vischer, ?ber das optische Formgefuhl: Ein Beitrag zur Aesthetik

(Leipzig: Credner, 1873), 20.

7. On the link between Einf?hlung and Aristotle's notion of eleos in the

Rhetoric, see Walter Kaufmann, Tragedy and Philosophy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1968), 44-48; see also Gottfried Herder,

KaUigone: Vom Angenehmen zum Sch?nen (Leipzig: J. F. Hartkoch, 1800). For a history of Einf?hlung from Immanuel Kant through German Ro manticism to the late nineteenth century, see Mallgrave and Ikono

mou, introduction to Empathy, Form and Space, 1-85; as well as David

Morgan, "The Enchantment of Art: Abstraction and Empathy from German Romanticism to Expressionism," Journal of the History of Ideas

57, no. 2 (1996): 317-41; and Richard A. Etlin, "Aesthetics and the

Spatial Sense of Self," Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 56, no. 1

(Winter 1998): 1-19. Brief essays on empathy theorists and related fig

This content downloaded on Tue, 5 Feb 2013 17:34:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 18: Limits of Empathy

ON THE LIMITS OF EMPATHY J55

ures, from Gustav Fechner and Charles Darwin to Wilhelm Worringer, appear in Moshe Barasch, Modern Theories of Art, vol. 2, From Impression ism to Kandinsky (New York: New York University Press, 1998), 84-187.

8. Friedrich Nietzsche, "Richard Wagner in Bayreuth" (1876), in Untimely Meditations, trans. R. J. Hollingdale, ed. Daniel Breazeale (New York:

Cambridge University Press, 1997), 239, translation modified. The Ger man is found in Nietzsche, "Richard Wagner in Bayreuth," in Unzeitge m?sse Betrachtungen IV, reprinted in Nietzsche Werke: Kritische Gesamtaus

gabe IV, ed. Giorgio Colli und Mazzino Montinari (Berlin: Walter de

Gruyter, 1967), 61.

9. Other important discussions of empathy include Karl Groos, Einleitung in die ?sthetik (Giessen: Ricker, 1892) and Der ?sthetische Genuss (Gies sen: Ricker, 1902); and Johannes Volkelt, Der Symbol-Begriff in der neuesten ?sthetik (Jena: Dufft, 1876) and ?sthetische Zeitfragen (Munich: Beck, 1895).

10. Vischer, ?ber das optische Formgefuhl, vii; trans, in Mallgrave and Ikono

mou, Empathy, Form and Space, 92. A mutual interest in the work of Arthur Schopenhauer links the empathy theorists to Freud; see Mail

grave and Ikonomou, introduction, 8-10.

11. Heinrich W?lfflin, Prolegomena zu einer Psychologie der Architektur (Berlin: Gebr?der Mann, 1999), 14. Vischer's distinctions are found in ?ber das

optische Formgefuhl, 24-25. "Feeling" here describes an active, physical sensation, as in the phrase "I feel the ground beneath my feet."

12. One image that can provoke a visceral response appears on the cover

of Jonathan Crary, Techniques of the Observer: On Vision and Modernity in the Nineteenth Century (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1990). Crary's

work on embodied perception in the nineteenth century denies the

place of Einf?hlung within this history, owing partly to a focus on

French material. "The whole neo-Kantian legacy of a disinterested aes

thetic perception," Crary has written elsewhere, "from Konrad Fiedler ... to more recent 'formalisms,' has been founded on the desire to

escape from bodily time and its vagaries." Crary, Suspensions of Percep tion: Attention, Spectacle, and Modern Culture (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT

Press, 1999), 46. Placing Einf?hlung within this escapist camp, he calls its model viewer "constructed ... to counter the claims of an antihu

manist stimulus-response psychology or behaviorism." Ibid., 158. Ein

f?hlung was often deeply engaged with stimulus-response psychology, however; it treated embodied, temporal perception theoretically, as

opposed to empirically.

13. Vischer, ?ber das optische Formgefuhl, 10; trans, in Mallgrave and Ikono

mou, Empathy, Form and Space, 98.

14. Vischer, ?ber das optische Formgef?hl, 8; trans, in Mallgrave and Ikono

mou, Empathy, Form and Space, 97.

15. In this context, see the discussion of Adolf Menzel's Moltke's Binoculars

(1871), The Opera Glass (ca. 1850), and Lady with Opera Glasses (ca. 1850) in relation to embodied vision in Fried, MenzeVs Realism, 46-47, 101.

16. W?lfflin, Prolegomena, 22; trans, in Mallgrave and Ikonomou, Empathy, Form and Space, 155.

17. "We judge every object by analogy with our body," he asserted two

years later, "and should not architecture participate in this unconscious animation? It participates in the highest possible measure." Heinrich

W?lfflin, Renaissance und Barock (Munich: F. Bruckmann, 1907), 56.

Compare Vischer, ?ber das optische Formgef?hl, 10; trans, in Mallgrave and Ikonomou, Empathy, Form and Space, 98: "In rooms with low ceil

ings our whole body feels the sensation of weight and pressure. Walls that have become crooked with age offend our basic sense of physical stability."

18. W?lfflin, Prolegomena, 35; trans, in Mallgrave and Ikonomou, Empathy, Form and Space, 177. Further analysis of W?lfflin's dissertation appears in Mallgrave and Ikonomou, introduction, 39-47.

19. August Schmarsow, Das Wesen der architektonischen Sch?pfung (Leipzig: Karl W. Hiersemann, 1894), 10-11; trans, in Mallgrave and Ikonomou,

Empathy, Form and Space, 286.

20. Schmarsow, Das Wesen, 15; trans, in Mallgrave and Ikonomou, Empathy, Form and Space, 288.

21. Mitchell Schwarzer has traced the shift to a spatial understanding of architecture to an essay by the Viennese architect Hanns Auer, "The

Development of Space in Architecture" (1883). Schwarzer, German Ar chitectural Theory and the Search for Modern Identity (New York: Cambridge

University Press, 1995), 192.

22. This disciplinary divergence is legible in Michael Podro's remark that "there is something strained about the way he [W?lfflin] yokes paint ing and architecture." It is also worth noting Podro's reference to "the

basic and rather primitive theory of empathy." Podro, The Critical Histo rians of Art (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1982), 98, 100.

23. Insofar as it addresses an aesthetic response to space as well as visual

form, Einf?hlung has remained central to the canon of architectural

theory, while fading from that of art history. Its central texts are still

assigned in methods courses in doctoral programs in architecture his

tory in the United States, for example, while generally remaining ab sent from their counterparts in art history.

24. See, for example, Siegfried Giedion, Space, Time and Architecture (Cam

bridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1941); L?szl? Moholy-Nagy, "The Concept of Space" (1925-28), Bauhaus 1919-1928, ed. Herbert

Bayer et al. (New York: Museum of Modern Art, 1938), 122; and Bruno

Zevi, Architecture as Space: How to Look at Architecture (1948; reprint, New

York: Horizon Press, 1957), 188-93.

25. Adolf Hildebrand, Das Problem der Form in der bildenden Kunst (1893; re

print, Baden-Baden: Heitz, 1961), 28-29; trans, in Mallgrave and

Ikonomou, Empathy, Form and Space, 247-48.

26. Hildebrand, Das Problem der Form, 19; trans, in Mallgrave and Ikono

mou, Empathy, Form and Space, 239.

27. Hildebrand, Das Problem der Form, 33; trans, in Mallgrave and Ikonomou,

Empathy, Form and Space, 253. Hildebrand's distinction of Sehen and

Schauen (42) may also be found in Vischer, ?ber das optische Formgefuhl, 1-2. On the relation of Hildebrand's and Vischer's arguments, see Mallgrave and Ikonomou, introduction to Empathy, Form and Space, 36-37.

28. Hildebrand, Das Problem der Form, 30; trans, in Mallgrave and Ikono

mou, Empathy, Form and Space, 250.

29. Antagonism to space and the interest in relief (and in notions of sculp tural shallowness and visual flatness, more generally) pervaded the the

ory and practice of the visual arts in Germany at the time. See also

Schmarsow, "Reliefkunst," in Grundbegriffe der Kunstwissenschaft: Ab ?ber

gang vom Altertum zum Mittelalter (1905; Berlin: Gebr?der Mann, 1998), 263-78. It should be noted that relief sculpture is technically more dif ficult to produce than sculpture in the round. On the link between relief sculpture and narrative, with reference to Hildebrand, see Rosa lind E. Krauss, Passages in Modern Sculpture (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT

Press, 1977), 12-15. On opticality and embodiment in the work of

Roger Fry, see Krauss, The Optical Unconscious (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT

Press, 1993), 138ff.

30. Clement Greenberg, "Modernist Painting" (1960), in Collected Essays and Criticism, ed. John O'Brien, vol. 4 (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1993), 89.

31. Ibid., 90.

32. Konrad Fiedler, "Der Ursprung der k?nstlerischen Th?tigkeit (1887),

quoted in Francesco Dal Co, Figures of Architecture and Thought: German Architecture Culture, 1880-1920 (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1990), 114. "In the following investigations," Fiedler explained in his book's

opening pages, "'artistic activity' always refers only to the activity of the fine artist." Fiedler, "Der Ursprung der k?nstlerischen Th?tigkeit," in Konrad Fiedlers Schriften ?ber Kunst, ed. Hans Marbach (Leipzig: S. Hir

zel, 1896), 185.

33. As W?lfflin put it, "without Fiedler, Hildebrand might very well not

have written his Problem ofForm.n W?lfflin, quoted in Henry Schaefer

Simmern, introduction to On Judging Works of Visual Art, by Konrad Fied

ler, trans. Schaefer-Simmern (1876; Los Angeles: University of Califor nia Press, 1978), xii. See also G?nther Jachmann, ed., Adolf von Hilde brands Briefwechsel mit Conrad Fiedler (Dresden: Wolfgang Jess, 1927).

34. Olga Rozanova, "Extracts from Articles" (1918), in Russian Art of the Avant-Garde: Theory and Criticism, trans, and ed. John E. Bowlt (New York: Thames and Hudson, 1988), 148.

35. By contrast, the vertical zips of Barnett Newman might be read in rela tion to Einf?hlung?albeit watered down, over the decades, in its trans fer to the United States. On Newman's critique of Worringer's argu

ments (which the artist knew only through paraphrases provided by T. E. Hulme), see Karlheinz Barck, "Worringers Stilpsychologie im Kon text der Stilforschung," in Wilhelm Worringers Kunstgeschichte, ed. Hannes

B?hringer and Beate S?ntgen (Munich: Wilhelm Fink, 2002), 31. For a

discussion of Newman's zips with regard to the phenomenological con cerns of Maurice Merleau-Ponty, see Yve-Alain Bois, "Perceiving New

man," in Painting as Model (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1990), 194-96.

36. The birth of experimental psychology within the domain of philosophy is usually taken to be the establishment of Wilhelm Wundt's laboratory in Leipzig in 1879. See Stuart Danziger, Constructing the Subject: Histori cal Origins of Psychological Research (New York: Cambridge University

Press, 1990), 17-38; John Fizer, Psychologism and Psychoaesthetics: A His torical and Critical View of Their Relations (Amsterdam: John Benjamins, 1981), 45-57; Mark Jarzombek, The Psychologizing of Modernity: Art, Archi

tecture, History (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2000), 37-72; Martin Jay, "Modernism and the Specter of Psychologism," Modernism/

Modernity 3, no. 2 (1996): 93-111; and David E. Leary, "The Philosophi cal Development of the Conception of Psychology in Germany," Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences 14 (1978): 113?21. See also Crary, Techniques of the Observer, 69 and passim.

37. Theodor Lipps, "Einf?hlung und ?sthetischer Genuss," Die Zukunft 54

(1906): 108. An English translation (mistakenly dated 1905) is found in

This content downloaded on Tue, 5 Feb 2013 17:34:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 19: Limits of Empathy

156 ART BULLETIN MARCH 2006 VOLUME LXXXVIII NUMBER 1

Lipps, "Empathy and Aesthetic Pleasure," in Aesthetic Theories: Studies in the Philosophy of Art, trans. Karl Aschenbrenner, ed. Aschenbrenner and

Arnold Isenberg (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1965), 409.

38. Lipps, "Einf?hlung und ?sthetischer Genuss," 106: "It is a basic fact of

psychology and even more so of aesthetics that a 'sensuously given ob

ject,' strictly speaking, is an absurdity?something that does not exist and never can exist."

39. Lipps, "Psychologie und Aesthetik," Archiv f?r die gesamte Psychologie 9

(1907): 117, quoted in Fizer, Psychologism and Psychoaesthetics, 224 n. 15.

40. At the same time, those whose work had been steeped in Einf?hlung had moved away from its theoretical claims. On the methodological shifts in W?lfflin's work, for example, see Martin Warnke, "On Hein rich W?lfflin," Representations 27 (1983): 172-87.

41. See Hermann von Helmholtz, Handbuch der physiologischen Optik (Leipzig: Voss, 1867).

42. Hildebrand to Fiedler, July 24, 1892, in Bernhard Sattler, ed., Adolf von

Hildebrand und seine Welt: Briefe und Erinnerungen (Munich: Georg D. W.

Callwey, 1962), 384. Fiedler viewed this common ground more warily, warning his friend, "If you were ever to publish your research, people would be able to say in some instances that Helmholtz has already touched upon it." Fiedler to Hildebrand, August 6, 1892, in ibid., 385.

43. Hildebrand to Nikolaus Kleinenberg, February 11, 1891, in ibid., 359. See also two letters from Hildebrand to Fiedler of April 9 and 16, 1891, and one from Helmholtz to Hildebrand of December 26, 1891, in ibid., 362, 374. The bust is now in the Academy of Sciences in Berlin.

44. Edward Bullough, "Recent Work in Experimental Aesthetics," British

Journal of Psychology 12 (1921): 93.

45. Bullough, ibid., 86, labeled these "objective," "physiological," "associa

tive," and "character."

46. Ibid., 78.

47. Ibid.

48. Vischer, ?ber das optische Formgef?hl, 26.

49. Worringer, lecture on W?lfflin, n.d., in Worringer Archive, Germani sches Museum, Nuremberg, folder ZR ABK 146, p. 160a/93, emphasis in the original.

50. Lipps, "Einf?hlung und ?sthetischer Genuss," 113.

51. For a treatment of German socioeconomic transformation between 1870 and 1918, see Fritz K. Ringer, The Decline of the German Mandarins: The German Academic Community, 1890-1933 (London: Wesleyan Univer

sity Press, 1990), 42-61.

52. See Anton Kaes, "Mass Culture and Modernity: Notes toward a Social His

tory of Early American and German Cinema," in America and the Germans: An Assessment of a Three-Hundred-Year History, ed. Frank Trommler and

Joseph McVeigh, vol. 2 (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press,

1985), 320; as well as idem, "The Debate about Cinema: Charting a Con

troversy (1909-1929)," New German Critiqued (Winter 1987): 7-33. Film

theory itself, one might argue, emerged in part from the discourse o? Ein

f?hlung with the publication in 1916 of Hugo M?nsterberg, The Photoplay: A Psychological Study. Trained in Wundt's psychology laboratory and well versed in Einf?hlung M?nsterberg moved to the United States at the turn

of the twentieth century, soon becoming director of the experimental psy

chology laboratory at Harvard University. See M?nsterberg, Hugo M?nster

berg on Film: The Photoplay; A Psychological Study and Other Writings, ed. Allan

Langdale (New York: Routledge, 2001), 45-162; as well as Juliet Koss, "Re flections on the Silent Silver Screen: Advertising, Projection, Reproduc tion, Sound," Kritische Berichte: Zeitschrifl f?r Kunst und Kulturwissenschaften 32, no. 2 (July 2004): 53-66.

53. Erwin Panofsky, "Style and Medium in the Motion Pictures," in Three

Essays on Style, ed. Irving Lavin (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1995), 93-94.

54. Begun in 1905, Abstraktion und Einf?hlung: Ein B?trag zur Stilpsychologie was first published as a dissertation (Neuwied, 1907) and subsequently as a book (Munich: R. Piper, 1908; reprint, Amsterdam: Verlag der

Kunst, 1996). It did not appear in English until 1953, as Abstraction and

Empathy: A Contribution to the Psychology of Style, trans. Michael Bullock

(Chicago: Elephant Paperbacks, 1997). See Geoffrey C. W. Waite,

"Worringer's Abstraction and Empathy: Remarks on Its Reception and

the Rhetoric of Criticism," in Invisible Cathedrals: The Expressionist Art

History of Wilhelm Worringer, ed. Neil H. Donahue (University Park, Pa.:

Pennsylvania State University Press, 1995), esp. 16-20; Mary Gluck, "In

terpreting Primitivism, Mass Culture and Modernism: The Making of

Wilhelm Worringer's Abstraction and Empathy," New German Critique 80

(Spring-Summer 2000): 149-69; as well as Siegfried K. Lang, "Wilhelm

Worringers Abstraktion und Einf?hlung. Entstehung und Bedeutung," in

B?hringer and S?ntgen, Wilhelm Worringers Kunstgeschichte, 81-117. Wor

ringer's work entered Anglophone criticism through that of Joseph Frank and T. E. Hulme, with its absorption into art history accom

plished primarily by Rudolf Arnheim and Herbert Read. Its postwar

reception was affected by Worringer's political and biographical cir

cumstances, which may be gleaned from a lecture in 1924 concerning what he termed "the eternal cultural struggle on two fronts in the midst of which we Germans, as people of the European center, are

placed." Worringer, Deutsche Jugend und ?stlicher Geist (Bonn: Friedrich

Cohen, 1924), 5; I thank Margaret Olin for sharing this text with me. See also Helga Grebing, "Bildungsb?rgerlichkeit als Lebenssinn: Sozio

biographische Ann?herungen an Wilhelm und Marta Worringer," in

B?hringer and S?ntgen, Wilhelm Worringers Kunstgeschichte, 204-8.

55. Again following Riegl, Worringer, Abstraktion und Einf?hlung, 42, pre sented the Kunstwollen as Riegl's critique of the materialist followers of

Gottfried Semper. Riegl had argued: "Technical factors surely played a

role as well .. . but it was by no means the leading role that the sup

porters of the technical materialist theory of origin assumed. The impetus did not arise from the technique but from the particular artistic impulse." Riegl, Problems of Style: Foundations for a History of Ornament, trans. Evelyn Kain (1893; Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992), 30.

56. His argument overthrew the tyranny of ancient Greece and the Renais

sance, while remaining under Nietzsche's spell. The reference here is to E. M. Butler, The Tyranny of Greece over Germany: A Study of the Influ ence Exercised by Greek Art and Poetry over the Great German Writers of the

Eighteenth, Nineteenth, and Twentieth Centuries (Boston: Beacon Press,

1935). One might argue that with Problems of Style, Riegl offered a theo retical justification of Jugendstil ornament while still perpetuating the

tyranny of Greece.

57. Paul Ernst, review of Worringer, Abstraktion und Einf?hlung, in Kunst und K?nstlern (September 1908): 529. Worringer referred to "the poet Paul Ernst" in the foreword to the 1948 edition of his book; the art critic Karl Scheffler cited "the dramatist Paul Ernst, who may be de scribed as the leader of the neoclassical school in Germany." Scheffler, "B?hnenkunst," Kunst und K?nstler 5 (March 1907): 222.

58. Ernst, review of Worringer, Abstraktion and Einf?hlung, 529.

59. Paul Stern, Einf?hlung und Association in der neueren ?sthetik: Ein Beitrag zur Psychologischen Analyse der ?sthetischen Anschauung (Empathy and As sociation in the New Aesthetics: A Contribution to the Psychological

Analysis of Aesthetic Representation) (Hamburg, 1898); see Worringer, Abstraktion und Einf?hlung, 136 n. 2.

60. He also had included in the bibliography appended to his dissertation the two volumes of Lipps's Aesthetics, published in 1903 and 1906, re

spectively. See Worringer, Abstraktion und Einf?hlung, 170 n. 3. On

Lipps's abandonment of psychologism following criticism from Ed mund Husserl, see Fizer, Psychologism and Psychoaesthetics, 224 n. 18; on

Worringer's productive misreading of Lipps, see Waite, "Worringer's Abstraction and Empathy,

" 23-28.

61. Worringer, Abstraktion und Einf?hlung, 36.

62. Ibid., 49.

63. Ibid., 36.

64. Theodor Lipps, quoted in Worringer, Abstraktion und Einf?hlung, 37, 40, 48, 58, 59: "Aesthetischer Genuss ist objectiver Selbstgenuss."

65. Worringer, Abstraktion und Einf?hlung, 40.

66. Ibid., 52.

67. Ibid.

68. Ibid., 48.

69. See ibid., 39.

70. See ibid., 9-13. For an analysis of this tale as "empathetic discourse in the crudest sense," see Waite, "Worringer's Abstraction and Empathy,

" 30.

71. Worringer, Abstraktion und Einf?hlung, 59.

72. Ibid., 59-60, emphasis in the original.

73. Lipps, quoted in ibid., 60.

74. Ibid.

75. Ibid.

76. Friedrich Nietzsche, "Richard Wagner in Bayreuth" (1876), in Untimely Meditations, translation modified, emphasis in original. The German is found in Nietzsche, "Richard Wagner in Bayreuth," in Nietzsche Werke, 38. Wagner himself had linked sympathy to something akin to self

alienation, describing the hybrid aesthetic experience of "a thorough stepping out of oneself into unreserved sympathy with the joy of the

beloved, in itself." Wagner, Das Kunstwerk der Zukunft (Leipzig: Otto

Wiegand, 1850), 160.

77. Describing an artist viewing the subject for a painting, Nietzsche re

ferred to "that aesthetic phenomenon of detachment from personal interest with which a painter sees in a stormy landscape with thunder and lightning, or a rolling sea, only the picture of them within him, the phenomenon of complete absorption in the things themselves... ."

Nietzsche, "On the Uses and Disadvantages of History for Life" (1873), in Untimely Meditations, 91.

This content downloaded on Tue, 5 Feb 2013 17:34:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 20: Limits of Empathy

ON THE LIMITS OF EMPATHY I57

78. Worringer, Abstraktion und Einf?hlung, 75-76. Introducing the reissued

English edition of Worringer's book in 1997, Hilton Kramer presents the author as a proto-Greenbergian: "what remains central to Abstrac tion and Empathy is the essential distinction it makes between art that takes pleasure in creating some recognizable simulacrum of three dimensional space . . . and art that suppresses that spatial illusion in favor of something flatter, more constricted and abstract." Kramer, in troduction to Abstraction and Empathy, ix.

79. See Worringer, Abstraktion und Einf?hlung, 59, 76, and passim.

80. Ibid. On spatial anxiety in architectural discourse, see Anthony Vidler, The Architectural Uncanny: Essays in the Modern Unhomely (Cambridge,

Mass.: MIT Press, 1992); and idem, "Agoraphobia: Psychopathologies of

Urban Space," in Warped Space: Art, Architecture, and Anxiety in Modern

Culture (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 2000), 25-50.

81. Worringer, Abstraktion und Einf?hlung, 49.

82. Ibid., 50.

83. Ibid.

84. Ibid., 55-56.

85. Ibid., 81.

86. What Hildebrand had labeled "the agonizing quality of the cubic,"

Worringer, ibid., 58, argued "is ultimately nothing else than a remnant

of that agony and unease that governed mankind in the face of the

things of the outside world in their unclear connection and interplay; it is nothing else than a final memory of the point of departure for all artistic creation, namely of the urge to abstraction." See also Worringer, review of Gesammelte Aufs?tze by Hildebrand (Strassburg: Heitz und M?n

del, 1909), in Monatshefte f?r Kunstwissenschafi, vol. 3 (Leipzig: Klinkhardt und Biermann, 1910), 212. The task of sculpture, Hildebrand had actu

ally written, is to offer a "visual image and thus to remove what is dis

turbing from the cubic form." Hildebrand, Das Problem der Form, 37, trans, in Mallgrave and Ikonomou, Empathy, Form and Space, 258.

87. Riegl, Problems of Style, 14.

88. "It's certainly very welcome that Dr. Wilhelm Worringer, Professor of Art History in Bern [sic], has undertaken to portray and to develop further the basic principles of his [Riegl's] view of art," the critic Egon Friedeil declared in a review of Abstraction and Empathy in 1920; Riegl's work was important, but "not in the least accessible," and Worringer helped the reader to navigate "the oppressive fullness of purely archae

ological detail ... to get at the genial thoughts at the core." Friedell, "Der Sinn des Expressionismus," Neues Wiener Journal, June 25, 1920;

quoted in Neil H. Donahue, Forms of Disruption: Abstraction in Modern German Prose (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1993), 32 n. 10.

89. See Worringer, Abstraktion und Einf?hlung, 78, 106-8; and Riegl, Prob lems of Style, 51-83. For a discussion of the symbolic value of Egyptian

art in the work of Riegl and Worringer in relation to early silent film, see Antonia Lant, "Haptical Cinema," October, no. 74 (Fall 1995): 45 73. Two decades later Worringer wrote a book on Egyptian art, ?gyp tische Kunst: Probleme ihrer Wertung (Munich: R. Piper, 1927).

90. On the naturalist movement in Munich at the end of the nineteenth

century and its demise two decades later, see Peter Jelavich, Munich and Theatrical Modernism: Politics, Playwriting, and Performance, 1890-1914

(Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985), 26-52.

91. Worringer, Abstraktion und Einf?hlung, 44.

92. Peter Behrens, Feste des Lebens und der Kunst, eine Betrachtung des Theaters als h?chsten Kultur-Symboles (Leipzig: Diederichs, 1900), 22, emphasis in the original.

93. Ernst, review of Worringer, Abstraktion und Einf?hlung, 529.

94. Worringer, Abstraktion und Einf?hlung, 92-93. He was not averse to sex

ist generalizations, however, and elsewhere referred to the "feminine

receptivity to the appearances of life" that dominated nineteenth-cen

tury architecture, arguing that "this feminine self-resignation is synony mous with the will to the loss of self...." Worringer, "Zum Problem der modernen Architektur," Neudeutsche Bauzeitung 7 (1911): 496.

95. Karl Scheffler, Die Frau und die Kunst (Berlin: Julius Bard, 1908), 4.

96. Ibid., 38.

97. Worringer's engagement with contemporary art increased after the publi cation of Abstraction and Empathy in 1908. See Geoffrey Perkins, Contempo rary Theory of Expressionism (Frankfurt: Herbert Lang, 1974), 47-48.

98. Gabriele Munter to Wilhelm Worringer, January 13, 1951, Worringer Archive, folder ZR ABK 146, pp. 377-80.

99. Werner Haftman, "Gruss an Wilhelm Worringer," Die Neue Zeitung, Jan uary 9, 1951, in Worringer Archive, folder 3R ABK 146, p. 278. In a

memorial speech, Hans Sedlmeyer referred to Abstraction and Empathy as "a bestseller of art history," saying, "Even in the twenties, every edu cated person who wanted to speak about art had to have read it, much like?a bit earlier?Simmel's writings." Sedlmeyer (memorial speech,

Ostfriedhof Crematorium, Munich, April 2, 1965), in Worringer Ar

chive, folder ZR ABK 146, pp. 486-88.

100. Wassily Kandinsky, Concerning the Spiritual in Art, trans. M. T. H. Sadler

(New York: Dover, 1977), 44, emphasis in the original; the German is found in Kandinsky, ?ber das Geistige in der Kunst (1911; reprint, Bern:

Benteli, 1952), 110. According to Peg Weiss, Kandinsky was "not likely to have seen the book [Abstraction and Empathy] in any case before

1909, when his own ideas .. . were already well formulated." Weiss,

Kandinsky in Munich: The Formative Jugendstil Years (Princeton: Prince ton University Press, 1979), 159.

101. Kandinsky, Concerning the Spiritual in Art, 32; the German is found in

Kandinsky, ?ber das Geistige in der Kunst, 75-76. For his part, Worrin

ger's response to Kandinsky's book was polite, but distant. With refer ence to the artist's famous description of art as a large, upwardly mov

ing triangle, he wrote: "Briefly formulated, this is my position with

regard to your book: I am not standing at the same point, but I find

myself in the same triangle." Worringer to Kandinsky, January 7, 1912, in Hilmar Frank, "Die Missverstandene Antithese: Zur Logischen Struktur von Abstraktion und Einf?hlung," in B?hringer and S?ntgen,

Wilhelm Worringers Kunstgeschichte, 75.

102. Franz Roh, Nach-Expressionismus, Magischer Realismus: Probleme der neuesten Europ?ischen Malerei (Leipzig: Klinkhardt und Biermann,

1925), 40, emphasis in the original. In 2002, Michael Fried, Menzel's

Realism, 253, made a similar claim: modern Western culture between 1840 and 1880 may be viewed within the theoretical framework of Ein

f?hlung, he wrote, citing the following individuals: "Kierkegaard, Helmholtz, Ruskin, Marx, Courbet, Millet, Thoreau, Whitman,

Melville, Flaubert, Baudelaire, Dickens, Wagner, C?zanne, the first decade of Eakins's activity as a painter, [and] early Hardy."

103. The history of empathy in the twentieth century?a subject beyond the parameters of this essay?would treat the concept's Anglophone afterlife, which began in 1904 with the translation into English of

Wundt's Principles of Physiological Psychology by E. B. Titchener, Wundt's former student and later the head of the psychology labora

tory at Cornell University. Notably, contemporary German speakers use the term Empathie, not Einf?hlung, to describe the generic experi ence of empathy. Universalizing art historical claims based on per sonal observation, legitimized by psychological insight, and deriving from Einf?hlung, have appeared most famously in the work of Rudolf

Arnheim and Ernst Gombrich; see especially Arnheim, "Wilhelm Wor

ringer on Abstraction and Empathy," in New Essays on the Psychology of Art (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1986), 50-62.

104. See Vernon Lee, with Clementine Anstruther-Thomson, Beauty and

Ugliness and Other Studies in Psychological Aesthetics (New York: Lane,

1912); idem, The Beautiful: An Introduction to Psychological Aesthetics

(New York: Putnam's, 1913); and Edith Stein, Zum Problem der Ein

f?hlung (On the Problem of Empathy) (Halle: Buchdruckerei des

Waisenhauses, 1917). Muschamp's association (in "How the Critic Sees,"

16) of the current "opportunity for empathy" with the achievements of

late-twentieth-centuiy feminism is therefore especially dubious, given that

empathy has often been considered girlish since the 1920s.

105. Siegfried Kracauer, The Salaried Masses: Duty and Distraction in Weimar

Germany (1930), trans. Quintin Hoare (New York: Verso, 1998), 94. See also idem, "The Mass Ornament" (1927), in The Mass Ornament:

Weimar Essays, trans, and ed. Thomas Y Levin (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1995), 75-86.

106. Kracauer, "The Little Shopgirls Go to the Movies" (1927), in The Mass

Ornament, 76 and passim. On the early-twentieth-century cultural cod

ing of mass culture as feminine, see Andreas Huyssen, "Mass Culture as Woman: Modernism's Other," in After the Great Divide: Modernism,

Mass Culture, Postmodernism (Bloomington: University of Indiana Press,

1986), 44-62; on the recoding o? Einf?hlung in Weimar German aes

thetic discourse as passive and feminine, see Juliet Koss, "Bauhaus Theater of Human Dolls," Art Bulletin 75 (December 2003): 735-36.

107. Bertolt Brecht, "Alienation Effects in Chinese Acting" (1936), in Brecht on Theatre: The Development of an Aesthetic, trans, and ed. John Willett

(New York: Hill and Wang, 1994), 91-99.

108. Bertolt Brecht, entries for January 11 and February 1, 1941, Journals 1934-1955, trans. Hugh Rorrison, ed. John Willett (New York: Rout

ledge, 1996), 124, 131.

109. Brecht, entry for August 2, 1940, ibid., 81-82.

110. A contemporaneous discussion of the link between the rise of mass

culture, new modes of perception, and "efforts to render politics aes

thetic" appears in Walter Benjamin, "The Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction," in Illuminations: Essays and Reflections,

trans. Harry Zohn, ed. Hannah Arendt (New York: Schocken, 1969), 241 and passim. Brecht's public mistrust of Einf?hlung has been inher ited by art historians who ignore his treatment of the concept in his

journals and fail to distinguish between the Einf?hlung he discussed and that of the nineteenth century.

This content downloaded on Tue, 5 Feb 2013 17:34:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions


Recommended