+ All Categories
Home > Documents > M. H. Abrams Orientation of Critical Theorie s - kleal.com member area pd2 2013/Abrams -...

M. H. Abrams Orientation of Critical Theorie s - kleal.com member area pd2 2013/Abrams -...

Date post: 27-Mar-2018
Category:
Upload: dodang
View: 482 times
Download: 35 times
Share this document with a friend
15
M. H. Abrams Orientation of Critical Theories BOSWELL. 'Then, Sir, what is poetry?7 JOHNSON. 'Why , Sir, it is much easier to say what it is not. We all know what light is ; but it is not easy to tell what it is/ It is the mark of an educated man t o look for precision in each class of things just so far as the nature of the subject admits. —ARISTOTLE, Nicomachean Ethics To pose and answer aesthetic question s in terms of_th e relatio n o f art t o the artist, rather than to external nature, or to the audience, or to the in- ternal requirements of the work itself, was the characteristic tendency of modern criticism up to a few decades ago, and it continues t o be the pro- pensity o t a great many—perhaps th e majority—o t critic s today . This point ot view is very young measured agains t the twenty-flve-hundred - year history of the Western theory of art, for its emergenc e as a compre- hensive approach to art^shared by a large number of critics, dates back not much more than a century and a half. The intention of this book is to chronicle the evolution and (in the early nineteenth century) the triumph, in its divers e forms, of this radical shift t o the artist in the alignment of aesthetic thinking, and to describe the principal alternate theorie s against which this approach had to compete. In particular, I shall be con- cerned with the momentous consequences of these new bearings in crit- icism for the identification, the analysis, the evaluation, and the writing of poetry. The field of aesthetics presents an especially difficult proble m to the historian. Recent theorists of art have been quick to profess that much, if not all, that has been said by their predecessors is wavering, chaotic , phantasmal. 'What has gone by the name of the philosophy of art 7 seemed to Santayana 'sheer verbiage/ D. W. Prall, who himself wrote two excel- lent book s on the subject, commented tha t traditiona l aesthetic s 'i s in fact only a pseudo-science or pseudo-philosophy/
Transcript
Page 1: M. H. Abrams Orientation of Critical Theorie s - kleal.com member area pd2 2013/Abrams - Orientation.pdf · M. H. ABRAMS Orientation of Critical Theories Some Co-ordinates of Art

M. H. Abrams

Orientation of Critical Theories

BOSWELL. 'Then, Sir, what is poetry?7JOHNSON. 'Why, Sir, it is much easier to say what itis not. We all know what light is; but it is not easyto tell what it is/It is the mark of an educated man to look forprecision in each class of things just so far as thenature of the subject admits.

—ARISTOTLE, Nicomachean Ethics

To pose and answer aesthetic question s i n terms of_the relation of art t othe artist, rather than to external nature, or to the audience, or to the in-ternal requirements of the work itself, was the characteristic tendency ofmodern criticism up to a few decades ago, and it continues to be the pro-pensity o t a great many—perhaps the majority—ot critic s today . Thispoint ot view is very young measured agains t the twenty-flve-hundred -year history of the Western theory of art, for its emergence as a compre-hensive approach to art^shared by a large number of critics, dates back notmuch more than a century and a half. The intention o f this book is tochronicle the evolution and (in the early nineteenth century) the triumph,in its diverse forms, of this radical shift t o the artist in the alignment ofaesthetic thinking , and to describe the principal alternate theorie sagainst which this approach had to compete. In particular, I shall be con-cerned with the momentous consequences of these new bearings in crit-icism for the identification, the analysis, the evaluation, and the writingof poetry.

The field of aesthetics presents an especially difficult problem to thehistorian. Recent theorists of art have been quick to profess that much, ifnot all, that has been said by their predecessors is wavering, chaotic ,phantasmal. 'What has gone by the name of the philosophy of art7 seemedto Santayana 'sheer verbiage/ D. W. Prall, who himself wrote two excel-lent books on the subject, commented tha t traditiona l aesthetic s 'i s infact only a pseudo-science or pseudo-philosophy/

Page 2: M. H. Abrams Orientation of Critical Theorie s - kleal.com member area pd2 2013/Abrams - Orientation.pdf · M. H. ABRAMS Orientation of Critical Theories Some Co-ordinates of Art

M. H . ABRAMS

Its subject-matter is such wavering and deceptive stuff a s dreamsare made of; its method is neither logical nor scientific, nor quitewhole-heartedly and empirically matter of fact... withou tapplication in practice to test it and without an orthodoxterminology to make it into an honest superstition o r athoroughgoing, soul satisfying cult. It is neither useful to creativeartists nor a help to amateurs in appreciation.1

And I. A. Richards, in hi s Principles o f Literary Criticism, labeled hi sfirst chapter The Chao s of Critical Theories/ and justified the pejorativeattribute by quoting, as 'the apices of critical theory/ more than a score ofisolated and violently discrepant utterances about art, from Aristotl e tothe present time.2 With the optimism o f his youth, Richards himselfwent on to attempt a solid grounding of literary evaluation in the scienc eof psychology.

It is true that the course of aesthetic theory displays its full measureoi the rEetonc aiTd^IogomacEy^w^h seem an inseparable part o t manes'cjiscourse about all things that reallymatter . But a good deal of our im-patience with th e diversity and seeming chao s in philosophies o f art i srooted in a demand from criticism for something it cannot do, at the costof overlooking many of its genuine powers. We still need to face up to thefull consequence s of the realization that ^ criticism i s not a physical, noreven a psychological, science. By setting out from and terminating in anappeal to the tacts, any good aesthetic theor y is , indeed, empirical inmethod. Its aim, however, is not to establish correlation s between fact swhich will enable us to predict the future by reference to the past, but to^establish principles enabling us to justify order , and clarify our interpre-i principle

id apprais;tation and appraisal ot the aestheticfacts themselves. And as we shall see,these taclS'lum utit'ro have the curious and scientifically reprehensibl eproperty of being conspicuously altered by the nature of the very princi-ples which appeal to them for their support. Because many critical state-ments o f fact ar e thus partially relative to the perspective of the theor ywithin which they occur, they are not 'true/ in the strict scientific sensethat they approach the ideal of being verifiable by any intelligent humanbeing, no matter what his point of view. Any hope, therefore, for the kindof basic agreement in criticisn thatTArfa w Darnedto expect in the exact,sciences is doomed to disappointment.

A good critical theory, nevertheless, has its own kind of validity. Jhecriterion^is not the scientiflcjyeriilability o i its_single prppositions/buttSFscope, precision^jmd coherjgncejpfjLh e insight s tha t it yields into!Ke~"properties>otisingle"works of artjguithejideQ* ^fcj^verselands of art. Such a criteTTonwill r of course, justify not one, bu ta number of valid theories, all in their several ways self-consistent, appli-

Orientation of Critical Theories

cable, and relatively adequate to the range of aesthetic phenomena ; bu tthis diversity is not to be deplored. One lesson we gain from a survey ofthe history of criticism, i n fact, is the great debt we owe to the variety ofthe criticism o f the past. Contrary to Prall's pessimistic appraisal , thesetheories have not been futile, bu t as working conceptions o f the matter ,end, and ordonnance of art, have been greatly effective in shaping the ac-tivities of creative artists. Even an aesthetic philosophy so abstract andseemingly academi c as that o f Kant can be shown to have modified thework of poets. In modern times, new departures in literature almost in-yariably have been accompanied hv novel critical pronouncements, whosevery inadequacies sometimes hel p to form the characteristic qualities ofthe correlated literary achievements, s o that if our critics had not dis-agreed so violently, ou r artistic inheritance woul d doubtles s hav e beenless rich and various. Also, the very fact tha t any well-grounded criticaltheory in some degree alters the aesthetic perceptions i t purports to dis-cover is a source of its value to the amateur of art, for it may open his sen-ses to aspects of a work which othe r theories, with a different focu s anddifferent categorie s o f discrimination, have on principle overlooked , un -derestimated, o r obscured.

The diversity o f aesthetic theories, however , makes th e tas k o f thehistorian a very difficult one. It is not only that answers to such questionsas 'What is art?' or 'What is poetry?7 disagree. The fact is that many the-ories of art canno t readily be compared at all, because they lack a com-mon ground on which to meet an d clash. They seem incommensurabl ebecause stated in diverse terms, o r in identical terms with diverse signi-fication, o r because they are an integral part of larger systems of thoughtwhich diffe r i n assumptions an d procedure. As a result i t is hard to findwhere they agree, where disagree, or even, what the points at issue are.

Our firs t need, then, is to find a frame of reference simple enough tobe readily manageable, yet flexibl e enoug h so that. withouFunciu e vio-lence to any one set of statements about art,Jrwill translate as many setsas possible onto a single plane ot discourseTMost writers bold enough toundertake th e history o f aesthetic theory have achieved this end by si-lently translating the basic terms of all theories into their ow n favoritephilosophical vocabulary , but this procedure unduly distorts its subjectmatter, and merely multiplies th e complications to be unraveled. Themore promising method is to adopt an analytic scheme which avoids im-posing its own philosophy, by utilizing those key distinctions which arealready common to the largest possible number of the theories to be com-pared, and then to apply the scheme warily, in constant readiness to intro-duce such furthe r distinction s a s seern to be needed for the purpose inhand.

Page 3: M. H. Abrams Orientation of Critical Theorie s - kleal.com member area pd2 2013/Abrams - Orientation.pdf · M. H. ABRAMS Orientation of Critical Theories Some Co-ordinates of Art

M. H. ABRAMS Orientation of Critical Theories

Some Co-ordinates of Art Criticism

the total situation of a work of art are discriminated andmade salient, b y one or another synonym, injijjmxps t al l theories whichaim to be comprehensive. First, there is tfeeworA^he artistic product it-self. And since this is a human prpductSaft^artifact, th e second commonelement is the artificer, the^rdst^Third, the work is taken to have a sub-ject which, directly or deviously is derived from existin^jJiiiigS—t o beabout, or signify, o r reflect something wj^icb-eilhei &?m bears some re-lation to. an Qbiectivejtdte of atiairarT'liis third element, whether held toconsist o f people^n^actjj0fT$7idea s an d feelings, materia l things an devents, or super-sepsifile essences , has frequently bee n denoted by thatword-of-all-work^^ature'; but let us use the more neutral and compre^hensive term^/pmVerseNnstead. For the final element we have ti^audi -enceTyhe listenefSTSpectators , or readers to whom the work is addressed,or to whose attention, at any rate, it becomes available.

jOn this framework of artist, work, universe, and audience I wish tospreadout various theories for comparison. To emphasize the artificialityot the device, and at the same lime make it easier to visualize the anal-yses, let us arrange the four co-ordinates in a convenient pattern. A tri-angle will do, with the work of art, the thing to be explained, in the center.

UNIVERSE

tOR

/ \K/ \T AUDIENC Eall fou rAlthough any reasonably adequate, theory takes

(dements, almost_^lJjlieones^swe jhall see, exhibitsentation toward one only. That.isf a critic tends tn ^priVP frforms hi s principaTcateffories fo r defining, classifying , and analyzing

work of artr as wellasliteHrnajor Ggkerrajg^hich he judges its value. Aj>plication of this analytic scheme, therefore, will sortlittempts to explainthe nature and worth of a work of art into four broad classes. Three willexplain the work of art principally by relating it to another thing: the uni-verse, the audience, or the artist. The fourth will explain the work by con-sidering it in isolation, as an autonomous whole, whose significance andvalue are determined without any reference beyond itself.

To find the major orientation of a critical theory, however, is only thebeginning of an adequate analysis. For one thing, these four co-ordinates

rnr|stantsf hut variables: they differ in significance according tothe theory in which they occur. Take what I have called the universe as anexample. In any one theory, the aspects of nature which an artist is saidto imitate, o r is exhorted to imitate, may be either particulars or types,and they may be only the beautiful o r the moral aspects of the world, orelse any aspect without discrimination . I t may be maintained tha t th eartist's world is that of imaginative intuition, o r of common sense, or ofnatural science; and this world may be held to include, or not to include,gods, witches , chimeras , an d Platonic Ideas. Consequently, theorie swhich agree in assigning to the represented universe the primary controlover a legitimate work of art may vary from recommending the most un-compromising realism to the most remote idealism. Each of our otherterms, as we shall see, also varies, both in meaning and functioning, ac-cording to the critical theory in which it occurs, the method of reasoningwhich the theorist characteristicall y uses, and the explicit or implicit'world-view' of which these theories are an integral part.

It would be possible, of course, to devise more complex methods ofanalysis which, even in a preliminary classification, would make moresubtle distinctions.3 By multiplying differentiae, however, we sharpen ourcapacity to discriminate a t the expense both of easy manageability andthe ability to make broad initial generalizations . For our historical pur-pose, the scheme I have proposed has this important virtue, that it wil lenable us to bring out the one essential attribute which most early nine-teenth-century theorie s had in common: th e persistent recourse to thepoet to explain the nature and criteria of poetry. Historians have recentlybeen instructed t o speak only of 'romanticisms/ in the plural, but fro mour point of vantage there turns out to be one distinctively romantic crit-icism, although this remains a unity amid variety.

Mimetic Theories

The mimetic orientatio n — the explanation of art a s essentially a n imi-tation o f aspects of the universe — was probably the most primitive aes-thetic theory, but mimesis is no simple concept by the time it makes itsfirst recorded appearance in the dialogues of Plato. The arts of p^ntin^,poetry, mus^, dn r>r^r>g, fllld sculpture, Socrates says, are all imitations.4, , , ,'Invitation' is a relational term, signifying two items and some correspon-dence between them. But although in many later mimetic theories every-thing is comprehended in two categories, the imitable and the imitation,the philosopher in the Platonic dialogues characteristically operates withthrge categories. The first category is that of the eternal and unchangingdeas; the second, reflecting this, i s the world of sense, natural or artifi-

Page 4: M. H. Abrams Orientation of Critical Theorie s - kleal.com member area pd2 2013/Abrams - Orientation.pdf · M. H. ABRAMS Orientation of Critical Theories Some Co-ordinates of Art

M. H. ABRAM S

cial; and the third category, in turn reflecting the second, comprises suchthings as shadows, images in water and mirrors, and the fine arts.

Around this three-stage regress— complicated stil l further b y var-ious supplementary distinctions, as well as by his exploitation of the poly-semism of his key terms— Plato weaves his dazzling dialectic.5 But fromthe shifting arguments emerges a recurrent pattern, exemplified in the fa-mous passage in the tenth book of the Republic. In discussing the natureof art, Socrates makes the point that there are three beds: the Idea which'is the essence of the bed' and is made by God, the bed made by the car-penter, and the bed found in a painting. How shall we describe the painterof this third bed?

I think, he said, that we may fairly designate him as theimitator of that which the others make.

Good, I said; then you call him who is third in the descent fromnature an imitator?

Certainly, he said.And the tragic poet is an imitator, and therefore, like all other

imitators, he is thrice removed from the king and from the truth?That appears to be so.6

From the initial position tha t ar t imitates th e world of appearanceand not of FnS.seriasJlfollows that works nf nrt hnyp^jjo\^status in"theorder^ksdoting •febiqgs.JurthermQre, since the realmof Ideas is the liltl-mate locus not only of reality but of value, the determination that art i sat second remove from th e truth automaticall y establishes its equa l re-moteness from th e beautiful and good. Despite the elaborate dialectic—or more accurately, by means of it— Plato 's^emains a philosophy of 3 sin-gle standard; for allthings, including'art, areultimately judged bvlhe^e-criterion of theirrelation to tne same Ideas. On these grounds, thepoet isinescapably me competitor ot the artisan, the lawmaker, and the moral-ist; indeed, any one of these can be regarded as himself the truer poet, suc-cessfully achievin^haH^^ th e traditional'poetattempts under conditions dooming him tolailure. Thus the lawmaker isable to reply to the poets seeking admission t o his city , 'Bes t o f strang-ers —

we also according to our ability are tragic poets, and our tragedy isthe best and noblest; for our whole state is an imitation of the bestand noblest life, which we affirm t o be indeed the very truth oftragedy. You are poets and we are poets . . . rivals and antagonists inthe noblest of dramas . . . 7

And the poor opinion of ordinary poetry to which we are committed onthe basis of its mimetic character, is merely confirmed when Plato pointsout that its effect s on its auditors are bad_because it represents appear-

Orientation of Critical Theories

ance rather than truth, and nourishes their feelings rather than their rea-j>omjor by demonstrating that the poet in composing (as Socrates jockeyspoor obtuse Ion into admitting) cannot depend on his art and knowledge,but must wait upon the divine afflatus and the loss of his right mind.8

The Socratic dialogues, then, contain no aesthetics proper, for neitherthe structure ot Plato's cosmos ppr the pattern nf his rMfller.tir permits usto consider poetry as poetry—as a special kind of product having its own

' criteria lild reason for being. In the dialogues there is only one directionpossible, and one issue, that is , the perfecting of the social state and thestate of man; so that the question of art can never be separated from ques-tions of truth, justice, and virtue. Tor great is the issue at stake/ Socratessays in concluding his discussion of poetry in the Republic, 'greater thanappears, whether a man is to be good or bad/9

Aristotle in the Poetics also defines poetry as imitation. 'Epic poetryand tragedy, as also Comedy, Dithyrambic poetry, and most flute-playingand lyre-playing, are all, viewed as a whole, modes of imitation'; and 'theobjects th e imitato r represent s are actions .. . /1 0 But the differenc e be -tween the way the term 'imitation' functions in Aristotle and in Plato dis-tinguishes radically their consideration of art. In the Poetics, as in the Pla-tonic dialogues , th e ter m implie s tha t a work of art i s constructe daccording tn prior models in the nature of things^but since Aristotle hasshorn away the other world of criterion-Ideas, there is no longer anythinginvidious in that fact . Imitation i s also made a term specific to the arts,distinguishing thes e fro m everythin g else in th e universe , an d therebyfreeing them from rivalry with other human activities. Furthermore , inhis analysis of the fine arts, Aristotle at once introduces supplementarydistinctions according to the objects imitated, the medium of imitation,and the manner—dramatic, narrative, or mixed, for example—in whichthe imitatio n i s accomplished . By successive exploitatio n o f these dis-tinctions in object, means, and manner, he is able first to distinguish po-etry from othe r kinds of art, and then to differentiate th e various poeticgenres, such as epic and drama, tragedy and comedy. When he focuses onthe genre of tragedy, the same analytic instrument i s applied to the dis-crimination o f the parts constituting the individual whole: plot , charac-ter, thought , and so on. Aristotle's criticism, therefore , is not only criti-cism of art as art independen t of statesmanship, being, and morality, butalso of poetry as poetry, and of each kind of poem by the criteria appropri-ate to its particula r nature. As a result o f this procedure, Aristotle be-queathed an arsenal of instruments for technical analysis of poetic formsancl their elements which have proved indispensable to critics ever sincie,however diverse the uses to which these instruments have been put.

A salient quality of the Poetics is the way it considers a work of artin various of its external relations, affording each its due function as one

Page 5: M. H. Abrams Orientation of Critical Theorie s - kleal.com member area pd2 2013/Abrams - Orientation.pdf · M. H. ABRAMS Orientation of Critical Theories Some Co-ordinates of Art

10 M. H. ABRAMS

of the 'causes' of the work. This procedure results in a scope and flexibil-ity that makes the treatise resist a ready classification into any one kindof orientation. Tragedy cannot be fully defined , fo r example, nor can th etotal determinants of its construction be understood, without taking intoaccount its proper effect on the audience: the achievement of the specifi -cally 'tragic pleasure/ which is 'that of pity and fear/11 It is apparent, how-ever, that th e mimeti c concept—th e reference of a work to the subjec tmatter which it imitates—is primary in Aristotle's critical svstem^evenif i t i s primus inter pares. Their character as an imitation o f human ac-tions is what defines the arts in general, and the kind of action imitatedserves as one important differentia o f an artistic species. The historica lgenesis of art is traced to the natural human instinct for imi tati HIL atRJhmthe natural tendency to find pleasure in seeing imitations. Even the unityessential to any work ot art is mimetically grounded, since 'one imitationis always of one thing/ and in poetry 'the story, as an imitation o f action,must represen t one action, a complete whole ... /1 2 And the 'form ' o f awork, the presiding principle determining the choice and order and inter-nal adjustments of all the parts, is derived from the form of the object thatis imitated. It is the fable or plot 'that is the end and purpose of tragedy/its 'life and soul, so to speak/ and this because

tragedy is essentially an imitation not of persons but of action andlife... We maintain that Tragedy is primarily an imitation of action,and that it is mainly for the sake of the action that it imitates thepersonal agents.13

If we refer again to our analytic diagram, one other general aspect ofthe Poetics presses on our attention, particularly when we have the dis-tinctive orientation of romantic criticism in mind. While Aristotl emakes a distribution (though an unequal one) among the objects imi-tated, the necessary emotional effects on an audience, and the internal de-mands of the product itself, as determinants o f this or that aspect of apoem, he does not assign a determinative function to the poet himself .The poet *V jjuHicp^ncoKU pfflripnt cause , the agent whof b y his skill .extracts the form fro m natura l thingsaodLingoses it upon anjirufkia lmedium; bu t his personal faculties, feelings/or desires are not called onto explain the subject matter or form of a poem. In the Poetics, the poet isinvoked only to explain the historical divergenc e of comic from seriou sforms, an d to be advised of certain aids toward the construction o f plotand the choice of diction.14 In Plato, the poet is considered from the pointof view of politics, not of art. When the poets make a personal appearanceall the major ones are dismissed, with extravagant courtesy, from th eideal Republic; upon later application, a somewhat greater number are ad-mitted to the second-best state of the Laws, but with a radically dimin-ished repertory.15

Orientation of Critical Theories 11

'Imitation' continued to be a prominent item in the critical vocabu-lary Tor a long time after Aristotle—al l the way through the eighteenthcentury, in fact. The systematic importance given to the term differe dgreatly from critic to critic; those objects in the universe that art imi-tates, or should imitate, were variously conceived as either actua l or insome sense ideal; and from the first, there was a tendency to replace Ar-istotle's 'action' as the principal object of imitation with such elementsas human character , or thought, o r even inanimate things . Bu t particu-larly after the recovery of the Poetics and the great burst of aesthetic the-ory in sixteenth-century Italy, whenever a critic was moved to get downto fundamentals and frame a comprehensive definition oi art, the predi-cate usually included the word 'imitation.' or^lse one of those parallelterms which, whatever differences they might imply, all faced in the samedirection: 'reflection / 'representation. ' 'counterfeiting/ 'feigning / 'copy /

image.'_>. •• •Through most of the eighteenth century, the tenet that art is an imi-

tation seemed almost too obvious to need iteration or proof. As RichardHurd said in his 'Discourse on Poetical Imitation/ published in 1751, 'AllPoetry, to speak with Aristotle and the Greek critics (if for so plain a pointauthorities be thought wanting) is, properly, imitation. It is, indeed, thenoblest and most extensive of the mimetic arts; having all creation for itsobject, and ranging the entire circuit of universal being.'16 Even the reput-edly radical proponents of 'original genius' in the second half o f the cen-tury commonly found that a work of genius was no less an imitation forbeing an original. 'Imitations,' Youn g wrote in his Conjectures o n Orig-inal Composition, 'are of two kinds: on e of nature, one of authors. Thefirst we call Originals ... ' The original genius in fact turn s out to be akind of scientific investigator: 'Th e wide field of nature lies open beforeit, where it may range unconfined, make what discoveries it can... as faras visible nature extends... '17 Later the Reverend J. Moir, an extremist inhis demand for originality in poetry, conceived genius to lie in the abilityto discover 'a thousand new variations, distinctions, and resemblances' inthe 'familiar phenomena of nature/ and declared that original genius al-ways gives 'the identical impression it receives.'18 In this identification.pL,the pnet/s frisk as novelty of discovery and particufanty ot description weEave moved a long way from Aristotle's conception oFmimesis, except in ~mis respect, that criticism still looks to one or another aspect oFthegivefT'world forjhe essentia l source atld"subject matter ot poetry

Instead of heaping up quotations, i t will be better to cite a few eigh .teenth-century discussions o f imitation tha t ar e of specialintgrest. Myfirst example is the French critic,Uiarles tfatteUX, whose LesBeaux Artsreduits a un meme principe (1747) found some favor in England and hadimmense influenc e in Germany, as well as in his native country. Therules of art, Batteux thought, which are now so numerous, must surely be

Page 6: M. H. Abrams Orientation of Critical Theorie s - kleal.com member area pd2 2013/Abrams - Orientation.pdf · M. H. ABRAMS Orientation of Critical Theories Some Co-ordinates of Art

12 M. H. ABRAMS

reducible to a single principle. 'Le t us/ he cries, 'imitate the true physi-cists, who assemble experiments and then on these found a system whichreduces them to a principle/

That Batteux proposes for his procedure 'to begin with a clear anddistinct idea'—a principle 'simple enough to be grasped instantly, and ex-tensive enough to absorb all the little detailed rules7—is sufficient cluethat he will follow in method not Newton, the physicist, but rather Euclidand Descartes. In pursuance of his clea r and distinct idea, he burrowedindustriously throug h the standard French critics until , h e says ingen-uously, 'it occurred to me to open Aristotle, whos e Poetics I had heardpraised/ Then came the revelation,- all details fell neatly into place. Thesource of illumination?—none other than 'th e principle of imitatio nwhich the Greek philosopher established for the fine arts/19 This imita -tion, however, is not of crude everyday reality, but of 'la belle nature7; thatis, 'le vrai-semblable,7 formed by assembling traits taken from individualthings to compose a model possessing 'all the perfections it is able to re-ceive/20 From this principle Batteux goes on, lengthily and with greatshow of rigor, to extract one by one the rule s of taste—both the generalrules for poetry and painting and the detailed rules for the special genres.For

the majority of known rules refer back to imitation, and form a sortof chain, by which the mind seizes at the same instantconsequences and principle, as a whokLperfertly joined, in which allthe parts are mutually sustained^1

Next to this classic instance of a priori and deductive aesthetics Ishall set a German document, Lessing7s Laokoon, published in 1776 .Lessing undertook to undo the confusion in theory and practice betweenpoetry and the graphic and plastic arts which, he believed, resulted fro man uninquisitive acceptance of Simonides7 maxim that 'painting is dumbpoetry and poetry a speaking painting/ His own procedure, he promises,will be continually t o test abstrac t theory agains t 'the individual in -stance/ Repeatedly he derides German critics for their reliance on deduc-tion. 'We Germans have no lack of systematic books. We are the most ex-pert o f any nation in the world at deducing, from a few given verbalexplanations, and in the most beautiful order, anything whatever that wewish/ 'How many things would prove incontestable in theory, had not ge-nius succeeded in proving the contrary in fact!722 Lessing7s intention ,then, is to establish aesthetic principles by an inductive logic which is de-liberately oppose d to the procedur e of Batteux. Nevertheless, lik e Bat-teux, Lessing concludes that poetry, no less than painting, is imitation.The diversity between these arts follows from thei r difference i n me-

Orientation of Critical Theories 13

dium, which imposes necessary differences i n the objects each is com-petent to imitate. But Although poetry consists of a sequence of articulatesounds in time rather than of forms and colors fixed in space , and aT-though, instead of being limited, like painting t o a static bu t pregnantmoment, its special power is the reproduction of progressive action, Less-ing reiterates to r it the standard formula: 'Nachahmung ' is still tor thepoet the attribute 'which constitutes the essence of hisjnt/2^

As the century drew on, various English critics began to scrutinizethe concept of imitation very closely, and they ended by finding (Aristotleto the contrary) that differences in medium between the arts were suchas to disqualify all but a limited number from being classed as mimetic ,in any strict sense. The trend may be indicated by a few examples. In 1744James Harris still maintained, in 'A Discourse on Music, Painting, andPoetry,7 that imitation wa s common to all three arts . 'They agree, bybeing all mimetic o r imitative. The y differ , a s they imitate by differentmedia . . . /24 In 1762 Kames declared that 'of all the fine arts, painting onlyand sculpture are in their nature imitative7; music, like architecture, 'isproductive of originals, and copies not from nature7; while language cop-ies from nature only in those instances in which it 'is imitative of soundor motion/25 And by 1789, in two closely reasoned dissertations prefixe dto his translation of the Poetics, Thomas Twining confirmed this distinc-tion between arts whose media are 'iconic7 (in the later terminology of theChicago semiotician, Charle s Morris), in that the y resemble what theydenote, and those which are significant only by convention. Only worksin which the resemblance between copy and object is both 'immediate7

and 'obvious,7 Twining says, can be described as imitative in a strictsense. Dramatic poetry, therefore, in which we mimic speech by speech,is the only kind of poetry which is properly imitation; musi c must bestruck from the list of imitative arts ; and he concludes by saying thatpainting, sculpture, and the arts of design in general are 'the only arts thatare obviously and essentially imitative/26

The concept that art is imitation, then, played an important par t inneoclassic aesthetics; bu t closer inspection shows that it did not, in mosttReTmes, play the"3ominant part. Artit was commonly said, is anUon— but an imitation whic h is onlyinstrumental toward producing ef-fects upon an audience. In iact, the near-unanimity with which post Ren-aissance critic s lauded and echoed Aristotle's Poetics is deceptive. Thefocus of interest ha d shifted^ and , on our diagram, this later criticism i sjirimarily nriprfled, not from work to universe, but from work to audience.The nature and consequences of this change of direction is clearly ihdi-cated by the firs t classic of English criticism, written sometim e i n th eearly 15807s, Sir Philip Sidney's The Apologie for Poetry.

Page 7: M. H. Abrams Orientation of Critical Theorie s - kleal.com member area pd2 2013/Abrams - Orientation.pdf · M. H. ABRAMS Orientation of Critical Theories Some Co-ordinates of Art

14 M. H. ABRAM S Orientation of Critical Theories 15

Pragmatic Theories

Poesy therefore [said Sidney] is an arte of imitation, for so Aristotletermeth it in the word Mimesis, that is to say, a representing,counterfetting, or figuring foorth — to speake metaphorically, aspeaking picture: with this end, to teach and delight.27

In spite of the appeal to Aristotle, this is not an Aristotelian formu-lation. To Sidney, poetry, by definition, has a purpose— to achieve certaineffects in an audience, it imitates only as a means to the proximate end ofpleasing, and pleases, it turns out, only as a means to the ultimate end o£teaching; tor 'right poets7 are those who 'imitate both to delight and teach,and delight to move men to take that goodnes in hande, which withou tdelight they would flye as from a stranger ... /28 As a result, throughoutthis essay the needs of the audience become the fertile grounds for criticaldistinctions an d standards. In order 'to teach and delight/ poets imitatenot 'what is, hath been, or shall be/ but only 'what may be, and should be/so that the very objects of imitation becom e such as to guarantee themoral purpose. The poet is distinguished from , p1pvatp£rahnvpjKh e

Amoral philosopher and the historian by his capacity to movehis auffitp? sAmore tnrretn ilk

JosopherwitTPthe particular exampleing his doctrin e i n a taler he -

e he couples 'the general

aware, into the love of goodness, 'as if they tooke a medicine o t Cherries/ofThe genres of poetry are discussed an d ranked from the point ot view

the moral and social effect eac h is suited to achieve: the epic poem thusdemonstrates itsel f t o be the king of poetry because it 'mos t inflameththe mind with desire to be worthy/ and even the lowly love lyric is con-ceived as an instrument for persuading a mistress o f the genuineness ofher lover's passion.29 A history of criticism could be written solely on thebasis of successive interpretations o f salient passages from Aristotle's Po-etics. In this instance, with no sense of strain, Sidney follows his Italianguides (who in turn had read Aristotle through the spectacles o f Horace,Cicero, and the Churc h fathers) i n bending one after anothe r of the keystatements of the Poetics to fit his own theoretical frame. 30 ^ ^

For convenience we may name criticism that , like Sidney's, i^or-dered toward the audienc^^pragmatic theo7y^( since it looks at the wor.of arrdbieHy as a me"ans"to an endf ar T somethingcbnef and tends to judge its value according to its success in achieving thataim. There is, of course, the greatest variance in emphasis and detail, but

°f the p^S^ r rritir : ifi to conceive a poem as some-thing made in order to effect requisite responses in its readers;the author from the point of view of the powers and training he must havein order to achieve this end; to ground the classification and anatom^Tjo f

poems in large part on the special effect s eac h kind and component isrnmppfpnt f n arVnPVP j on H r n HpriVP ffa norms of the DOetJ C art and

canons of critical appraisal from the needs and legitimate demands of theaudience to whom the poetry is addressed."* Th e perspective, much of the basic vocabulary, and many of the chlT^acteristic topic s of pragmatic criticism originated in the classical theoryof rhetoric. For rhetoric had been universally regarded as an instrumen tfor achieving persuasiofi in an audience, an d most theorists agreed withCicero that in order to persuade, the orator must conciliate, inform , andmove the minds of his auditors.31 The great classical exemplar of the ap-plication of the rhetorical point of view to poetry was, of course, the Ar sPoetica of Horace. As Richard McKeon points out, 'Horace's criticism i sdirected in the main to instruct the poet how to keep his audience in theirseats until the end, how to induce cheer s and applause, how to please aRoman audience, and by the same token, how to please all audiences andwin immortality'32

In what became for later critics th e focal passage of the Ars Poetica,Horace advised that 'th e poet's aim i s either to profit o r to please, or toblend in one the delightful and the useful.' The context shows that Horaceheld pleasure to be the chief purpose of poetry, for he recommends the prof-itable merely as a means to give pleasure to the elders, who, in contrast tothe young aristocrats, 'rai l at what contains no serviceable lesson.'33 Butprodesse and delectare, to teach and to pleaser together with another term

*rr>rn . served for centuries to collectunder three heads the sum of aesthetic effect s on the reader. The balanceBetween these terms altered in the course of time. To the overwhelmingmajority o f Renaissance critics, a s to Si r Philip Sidney, the moral effec twas the terminal aim, to which delight and emotion were auxiliary. Fromthe time of the critical essays of Dryden through the eighteenth century,pleasure tended to become the ultimate end, although poetry withou tprofit wa s often hel d to be trivial, an d the optimistic moralis t believedwith James Beattie that if poetry instructs, it only pleases the more effec -tually34

Lookin g upon a poem as a 'making/ a contrivance for affecting an au-dience, the typical pragmatic critic is engrossed with formulating themethods—the 'skill, o r Crafte o f making' as Ben Jonson called it—fo rachieving the effects desired. These methods, traditionally comprehendedunder the term poesis, or 'art' (in phrases such as 'the art of poetry'), areormulated a s precepts and rules whose warrant consists either in thei rbeing derived from the qualities of works whose success and long survivalhave proved their adaptatio n t o human nature , o r else in thei r beinggrounded directly on the psychological laws governing the responses o fmen in general. The rules, therefore, are inherent in the qualities of each

Page 8: M. H. Abrams Orientation of Critical Theorie s - kleal.com member area pd2 2013/Abrams - Orientation.pdf · M. H. ABRAMS Orientation of Critical Theories Some Co-ordinates of Art

16 M. H. ABRAM S Orientation of Critical Theories

excellent wor k of art, and when excerpted and codified these rules serveic artist in making and the critics in judging any future

product. 'Dryden, ' sai d Dr. Johnson, 'may be properly considered as thefather of English criticism, as the writer who first taught us to determineupon principles th e meri t o f composition/35 Dryden's method o f estab-lishing those principles was to point out that poetry, like painting, has anend, which is to please; that imitation o f nature is the general means forattaining this end; and that rules serve to specify th e means for accom-plishing this end in detail:

Having thus shewn that imitation pleases, and why it pleases in ILjf \h these arts, it follows, that some rules of imitation are \(*\v

necessary to obtain the end; for without rules there can he no art,any more than there can be a housFWilhuut a door to conduct youinto it.36

Emphasis on the rules and maxims of an art is native to all criticismthat grounds itself in the demands of an audience, and it survives today inthe magazines and manuals devoted to teaching fledgling authors 'how towrite stories that sell / But rulebooks based on the lowest common de-nominator of the modern buying public are only gross caricatures of thecomplex and subtly rationalized neo-classic ideals of literary craftsman-ship. Through the earlv part of the eighteenth century, the poet conld rp1yconfidently on the trained taste and expert connoisseurship o f a limitedcircle of readers, whether these were Horace's Roman contemporaries un-der Emperor Augustus, or Vida's at the papal court of Leo X, or Sidney'sfellow-courtiers under Elizabeth, or the London audience of Dryden andPope; while, i n theory , the voices even of the best contemporary judgeswere subordinated t o the voice of the ages. Some neo-classic critics werealso certain tha t the rules of art, though empirically derived , were ulti-mately validate d b y conforming to that objective structure o f norms^whose existence guaranteed the rational orde r and harmony of the uni-verse^ In a strict sense, as |ohn JJennis made explicit what was often im-plied, Nature 'is nothing but that Rule and Order, and Harmony, which wefind in the visible Creation'; so 'Poetry, which is an imitation of Nature,'must demonstrate the same properties. The renowned masters among theancients wrote not

to please a tumultuous transitor y Assembly, or a Handful of Men,who were call'd their Countrymen; They wrote to their Fellow-Citizens of the Universe, to all Countries, an d to all Ages ... Theywere clearly convinc'd, tha t nothing could transmit thei r ImmortalWorks to Posterity, but something like that harmonious Orderwhich maintains the Universe ...37

Although the y disagreed concerning specifi c rules, and althoug^many English critics repudiated such formal French requisites as the utx_ity of time and place, and the purity of comedy and tragedy, all but a fe\eccentrics amon g eighteenth-century critic s believe d in the validity

set o f universal rules . At about rnid-^ptnry, i t became populaF7«~*Ttemonstrate and expound all the major rules for poetry, or even for art 1^general, in a single inclusive critical system. 1 he"paHe o* the pragmai rteasonirig usually employed may conveniently be studied in such a con .pendious treatment as James Beattie's Essay on Poetry and Music as theyaffect th e Mind (1762), o r more succinctly still , i n Richard Hurd's 'Di^_sertation o f the Idea of Universal Poetry' ( 1766). Universal poetry, no mat-ter what the genre, Hurd says, is an art whose end is the maximum po$_sible pleasure. 'When we speak of poetry, as an art, we mean such a wqyor method of treating a subject, as is found most pleasing and delightfulto us. ' And this idea 'if kept steadily in view, will unfold to us all the mys.teries o f the poetic art. There needs but to evolve the philosopher's ide a^and to apply it, as occasion serves.' From this major precise Hurd evolv^sthree properties, emeriti al to 3 11 pgetnjf i t is to efFle delight: figurativ e language , 'fiction' (that is to say, a departure frwhat is actual, or empirically possible! , and versification** 1 l*e mode adegree in wJucn these three universal qualities are to be combined ione species o f poetry, however, will depend on its peculiar end, becau§eeach poetic kind must exploit that special pleasure which it is genericallyadapted to achieve. 'For the art of every kind of poetry is only this genei:aiart so modified as the nature of each, that is, its more immediate and su^.ordinate end, may respectively require.'

For the name of poem will belong to every composition/ whoseprimary end is to please, provided it be so constructed as to affor dall the pleasure, which its kind or sort will permit-38

On the basis of isolated passages from hi s Letters on ChivalryRomance, Hurd is commonly treated as a 'pre-romantic' critic. But insummation of his poetic creed in the 'Idea of Universal Poetry/ the ri gdeductive logic which Hurd employs to 'unfold' the rules of poetry froi^ aprimitive definition , permitting 'th e reason of the thing7 to override t^eevidence of the actual practice of poets, brings him as close as anyone jnEngland to the geometric method of Charles Batteux, though without t atcritic's Cartesian apparatus . The difference i s that Batteu x evolves srules from the definition of poetry as the imitation of la belle nature, andHurd, from its definition as the art of treating a subject so as to afford thereader a maximum pleasure; and this involves his assuming that he p0s.sesses an empirical knowledge of the psychology of tbe reader. For i f the

Page 9: M. H. Abrams Orientation of Critical Theorie s - kleal.com member area pd2 2013/Abrams - Orientation.pdf · M. H. ABRAMS Orientation of Critical Theories Some Co-ordinates of Art

18 M. H. ABRAM S

\rv

V

end of poetry is to gratify the mind of the reader, Hurd says, knowledge ofthe laws of mind is necessary to establish it s rules , which are 'but somany MEANS, which experience finds most conducive to that end/39 SinceBatteux and Hurd, however, are both inten t on rationalizing wha t i smainly a common body of poetic lore, it need not surprise us that, thoughthey set out from differen t point s of the compass, their paths often coin-cide.40

But to appreciate the power and illumination o f which a refined andflexible pragmatic criticism is capable, we must turn from these abstractsystematizers of current methods and maxims to such a practical critic asSamuel Johnson. Johnson's literary criticism assume s approximately theframe o f critical reference I have described, but Johnson , who rtistmstsrigid and abstractto specific literary pyaniples fipfprprjp e t o the opinions of other readers,but ultimately, reliance on his own expert responses to the text. As a re-sult Johnson's comments on poets and poems have persistently afforde da jumping-off poin t tor later critics whose frame of reference and particu-]jir judgments differ radically from hisjpwn. For an instance o t lohnson'sprocedure which is especially interesting because it shows how the no-tion of the imitation o f nature is co-ordinated with the judgment of po-etry in terms of its end and effects, consider that monument of neo-classiccriticism, Johnson' s Preface t o Shakespeare.

Johnson undertakes in hi s Preface t o establish Shakespeare' s rankamong poets, and to do so, he is led to rate Shakespeare's native abilitiesagainst the general level of taste and achievement in the Elizabethan age,and to measure these abilities in turn 'by their proportion to the generaland collective ability of man.'41 j>ince the powers and excellence of an au_ -thor, however, can only be inferred from the nature and excellent n^ f^pworks he achieves, Tohnson addresses himself to a general examination ofShakespeare's dramas. In this systematic appraisa l of the works them-selves, we lind that mimesis retain s for Johnson a measure of authorityas criterion. Repeatedl y Johnson maintains tha t 'this therefore is thepraise of Shakespeare, that his drama is the mirrour oHifg,' and of inani-mate nature as well: 'He was an exact surveyor of the Inanimate world . . .Shakespeare, whether life or nature be his subject, shews plainly, that hehas seen with hi s own eyes . . . /42 But, Tohnson also claims. 'Th e end of.writing is to instruct; the end of poetry is to instruct by pleasing.'43 It is tothis function of poetry, and to the demonstrated effect o f a poem upon itsaudience, that Johnson awards priority as aesthetic criterion. I f a poemfails to please, whatever its characte r otherwise, it i, snothing; though Johnson insists, wit h a strenuous moralism tha t mus talready have seemed old-fashione d to contemporary readers, it mii splea^ejwithout violatin g the standards of truth an d virtue. Accordingly,

Orientation of Critical Theories 19

Johnson discriminates those elements in Shakespeare's plavs which wer£introduce J to appeal to the local and passing tastes of the rather barbarousaudience ot his own time ('H e knew/ said Johnson, 'how he should mostplease7!.44 from those elements which are proportioned to the tastes ot thecommon readers of all time. And since in works 'appealing wnollv to ob-servation and experience, no other test can be applied than length of du-ration and continuance of esteem,' Shakespeare's long survival as a poet'read without any other reason than the desire for pleasure' is the best ev-idence for his artistic excellence. The reason for this survival Johnson ex-plains o n the subsidiary principle that 'nothin g can please many, aqdplease long, but jus t representations of general nature.' Shakespeare ex-hibits the eternal 'species' of human character, moved by 'those generalpassions an d principles bv which al l minds are agitated.'45 Thus Shake -speare's excellence in holding up the mirror to general nature turns out,In the long run, to bejustmed by the superior criterion of the appeal thisachievement holds for the enduring tastes ot the generalliterary public.—-

A number o f Johnson's individual observations and judgments ex-hibit a play of the argument between the tw o principles of the nature ofthe world the poet must reflect , an d the nature and legitimate require -ments of the poet's audience. For the most part the two principles co-op-erate toward a single conclusion. For example, both the empirical natureof the universe and of the universal reader demonstrate the fallacy of thosewho censure Shakespeare for mixing his comic and tragic scenes. Shake-speare's plays , Johnson says, exhibit 'the real state of sublunary nature,which partakes of good and evil, joy and sorrow, mingled with endless va-riety.' In addition, 'the mingled drama may convey all the instruction oftragedy or comedy' by approaching nearer 'to the appearance of life'; whilethe objection that the change of scene 'wants at last the power to move'isa specious reasoning 'received as true even by those who in daily experi-ence fee l i t t o be false.'46 Bu t when the actua l state o f sublunary affair sconflicts with the poet's obligation to his audience, the latter is the courtof final appeal. It is Shakespeare's defect, says Johnson,

that he seems to write without anv moral purpose H e makes nojust distribution of good Qr^evil, nor is always careful to shew in thevirtuous a disapprobation of the wicked... It is always a writer'sllutv to make the world better, and justiceTsTatime or place/*7

The pragmatic orientation, orderin g the aim o f the artis t an d thethe work to the nature, the needs, and the springs of pleasure

jii the audience, characterized by far thegreatest part of criticism from thetime of Horace through the eighteenth century. Measured either by its du-fation o r the nnrnb^ r ™ f it s adherents , therefore, th e pragmatic view,

Page 10: M. H. Abrams Orientation of Critical Theorie s - kleal.com member area pd2 2013/Abrams - Orientation.pdf · M. H. ABRAMS Orientation of Critical Theories Some Co-ordinates of Art

20 M. H. ABRAMS

hro^lvmnceived."

a esthetic attitude of the West-."Bunnherent in this systemwereTthe elements o f its

ent rhetoric had bequeathed to criticism not only its stress onaffecting the audience but also (since its main concern was with educat-ing the orator ) its detaile d attention t o the powers and activities o f thespeaker himself— his 'nature/ o r innate power s and genius, a s distin-guished from hi s culture and art, and also the process of invention, dis -position, and expression involved in his discourse.48 In the course of time,and particularly afte r th e psychologica l contribution s o f Hobbes andLocke in the seventeenth century , increasing attention was given to themental constitution o f the poet, the quality and degree of his 'genius/ andthe play of his facultie s in th e ac t of composition. Through most o f theeighteenth century, the poet's invention and imagination were made thor-oughly dependent for their materials — their ideas and 'images' — on th eexternal universe and the literary models the poet had to imitate,- whilethe persistent stres s laid on his need for judgment and art — the mentalsurrogates, in effect , o f the requirements o f a cultivated audience — heldthe poet strictly responsible to the audience for whose pleasure he exertedhis creative ability. Gradually, however, the stress was shifted more andmore to the poet's natural genius, creative imagination, an d emotionalspontaneity, at the expense of the opposing attributes of judgment, learn-ing, and artful restraints. As ajpsnlt the audience gradually receded intotj2£Wkgrn^ndr givin g place to the poet himseJT and his own mentalpowers and emotional ri f H«j as thp predominant causeand eventlge^Lar»rl tf^ f n f nit , Ry this time other developments, which we shall haveoc-casion to talk about later, were also helping to shift th e focus of criticalinterest fro m audienc e to artist and thus to introduce a new orientationinto the theory of art.

Expressive Theories

'Poetry/ Wordsworth announced in his Preface to the Lyrical Ballads of1800, 'is the_spontaneous overflow of powerful feelings/ He thought wellenough of this formulation to use it twice in the same essay, and on this,as the ground-idea, he founded his theory of the proper subjects, language,effects, and value of poetry. Almost all the major critics of the English ro-mantic generation phrased definitions or key statements showin g a par-allel alignment fro m wor k to poet. Poetry is the overflow, utterance^Qi ,.projection of the thought andfeelings~ot tJ^poet^orelse^jin the chief var-

ipnfpoetry"is^eflned i n terms oTEE e imaginative process '[synthesizes the images, thoughts, andjgelin^s

of thinking, in which theartis

Orientation of Critical Theories 21

jnrelgpient generating both the artistic product and the criteria by whichitTigtobe judged, I shall call the expressive theory"of art. \g the date at which this point of view became^predominant in

critical theory, like marking the point at which orange becomes yellow inthe color spectrum, must be a somewhat arbitrary procedure. As we shallsee, an approach to the expressive orientation, though isolated in historyand partial in scope, is to be found as early as Longinus' discussion of thesublime style as having its main sources in the thought and emotions ofthe speaker,- and it recurs in a variant form in Bacon's brief analysis of po-etry as pertaining to the imagination and 'accommodating the shows ofthings to the desires of the mind/ Even Wordsworth's theory, it will ap-pear, is much more embedded in a traditional matrix of interests and em-phases, and is, therefore, less radical than are the theories of his followersof the 1830's . The year 1800 is a good round number, however, and Words-worth's Preface a convenient document , b y which t o signalize the^Es^placement ot the mimetic an d pragmatic by the expressive viewjDFarOhEnglish criticism. ~ " " ~ ~ ~ "~~ I n general terms, the centra l tendency of the expressive theory may

be summarized in this way: A work of art is essentially the internal madeexternal, resulting from a creative process operating under the impulse offeeling, and embodying the nnmh|]ied product of the poet's perceptions^thoughts, and feelings. The primary source and subject matter ot a poem/therefore, are the attributes and actions of the poet's own mind; or if as-pects of the external world, then these only as they are convertedlTomfactto poetry by the feelings and operations of the poet's mind. ['Thus the Po-etry ... ' Wordsworth wrote, 'proceeds whence it ought to do, from th esoul of Man, communicating its creative energies to the images of the ex-ternal world/) 49 The paramount cause of poetry is not, as in Aristotle, aformal cause , determined primarily by the human actions and qualitie simitated; nor, as in neo-classic criticism, a final cause, the effect intendedUpon the audience, - but instead an efficient cause—th e impulse withi nthgj>oet of feelings and desires seeking expression, or the compulsion!)?flST'creative' imagination whicn . like irod the creator, has its interna lsource of motion. Th e propensity is to grade the arts b y the exten t t owhich their media are amenable to the undistorted expression of the feel-ings or mental powers of the artist , and to classify th e species of an art,and evaluate their instances, b y the qualities or states of mind of whichthey are a sign. Of the elements constituting a poem, the element of dic-tion, especially figures of speech, becomes primary,- and the burnin gquestion is, whether these*are the natural utterance of emotion and imag-ination or tlie deliberate aping of poetic conventions. The fir<^ test anypoem must pass is no longer. 'Is it true to nature?' or 'Is it appropriate tothe requirements either of the best judges or the generality of mankind?'

Page 11: M. H. Abrams Orientation of Critical Theorie s - kleal.com member area pd2 2013/Abrams - Orientation.pdf · M. H. ABRAMS Orientation of Critical Theories Some Co-ordinates of Art

22 M. H. ABRAMS Orientation of Critical Theories 23

but a critprinn 1Qn1fing in A different direction, - namely, Is it sincere? Is itgenuine? Does it match the intention, the feeling, and the actual state ofmind of the poet while composing;?7 The work ceases then to be regardedas primarily a reflection of nature, actual or improved; the mirror held upto nature becomes transparent and yields the reader insights into th e' an d heart of the poet himself. JThe exploitation ot literature as an

indextS^TKcm^tiTy^rst m itsel f in the early nineteenth century;it is the inevitable consequence of the expressive point of view.

The sources , details , an d historical result s o f this reorientatio n ofcriticism, i n its various forms, wil l be a principal concern of the rest ofthis book. Now, while we have some of the earlier facts fresh in mind, letme indicate what happened to salient elements of traditional criticism i nthe essay s 'What Is Poetry?' and The Tw o Kinds of Poetry/ written byJohn Stuart Mill in 1833. Mill relied in large part on Wordsworth's Prefaceto the Lyrical Ballads, but in the intervening thirty years the expressivetheory had emerged from th e network of qualifications in which Words-worth had carefully placed it, and had worked out its own destiny unhin-dered. Mill's logic in answering the question, 'What Is Poetry?' is notmore geometrico, like that o f Batteux, nor stiffly formal , like RichardHurd's; nonetheless, his theory turns out to be just as tightly dependentupon a central principle as theirs. Fo r whatever Mill's empirical preten-sions, his initial assumption about the essential nature of poetry remainscontinuously thoug h silently effective i n selecting, interpreting , an d or-dering the facts to be explained.

The primitive proposition of Mill's theory is: Poetr y is "the expres-sion or uttering forth n f feeljp g /5 ° Exploration of the data of aestheticsfrom this starting point leads, among other things, to the following drasticalterations in the great commonplaces of the critical tradition:

(11 Th e poetic kinds. Mil l reinterpret s and inverts th e neo-classi cranking of the poetic kinds. As the purest expression of feeling, lyric po-etry is 'more eminently and peculiarly poetry than any other . . .' Otherforms are all alloyed by non-poetic elements, whethe r descriptive, didac-tic, or narrative, which serve merely as convenient occasions for the po-etic utterances of feeling either by the poet or by one of his invented char-acters. To Aristotle, tragedy had been the highest form of poetry, and th eplot, representing the action being imitated, had been its 'soul'; whilemost neo-classic critics had agreed that, whether judged by greatness ofsubject matter or of effect, epi c and tragedy are the king and queen of po-etic forms. It serves as an index to the revolution in critical norms to no-tice that to Mill, plot becomes a kind of necessary evil. An epic poem 'inso far as it is epic (i.e. narrative)... is not poetry at all/Tmt only a suitableframe for the greatest diversity of genuinely poetic passages; while the in-terest in plot and story 'merely as a story' characterizes rude stages of so-

ciety, children, and the 'shallowest and emptiest' of civilized adults.51Similarly with the other arts; in music, painting, sculpture, and architec-ture Mill distinguishe s between that which i s 'simple imitation or de-scription' and that which 'expresses human feeling' and is, therefore, po-etry.52

(2) Spontaneity a s criterion. Mill accepts the venerable assumptionthat a man's emotiona l susceptibilit y i s innate, bu t his knowledge andskill—his art—are acquired. On this basis, he distinguishes poets intotwo classes: poets who are born and poets who are made, or those who arepoets 'by nature,' and those who are poets 'by culture.' Natural poetry isidentifiable because it 'is Feeling itH^ pr np1ny^nf Though t only as the"medium of its utterance' ; on the other hand, the poetry of 'a cultivate dbut not naturally poetic mind/ is written with 'a distinct aim/ andjpJtthe thought remain s th e conspicuous object , however surrounded by/ahalo ot feeling/ Natura l poetry, it turns out , is 'poetry in a far highers'ense, than any other; sinc e .. . that which constitute s poetry, human^feeling, enters far more largely into this than into the poetry of culture.'Among tJie moderns, Shelley represents the poet born and Wordsworththe poet made; and with unconscious irony Mill turns Wordsworth's owncriterion, 'th e spontaneous overflo w of feeling,' agains t it s sponsor .Wordsworth's poetry 'has little even of the appearance of spontaneous-ness: th e well is never so full that it overflows.' 53

(3) The external world. In so far as a literary product simply imitatesobjects, it is not poetry at all. As a result, reference of poetry to the exter-nal universe disappears from Mill's theory, except to the extent that sen-sible objects may serve as a stimulus or 'occasion for the generation of po-etry/ and then, 'the poetry is not in the object itself/ bu t 'in the state ofmind' in which it is contemplated. When a poet describes a lion he 'is de-scribing the lion professedly, but the state of excitement o f the spectatorreally/ and the poetry must be true not to the object. butJaaJtbf *

d From the external world, the objects signifiedby^a poem tend to be regarded as no more than a projected equivalent— an

articulated symbol — for the poet's inner state of mind. Po-etry, said Mill, i n a phrasing which anticipates T. E. Hulme and lays thetheoretical groundwork for the practice of symbolists from Baudelairethrough T. S. Eliot, embodies 'itself in symbols, which are the nearest pos-sible representations of the feeling in the exact shape in which it exists inthe poet's mind.'55 Tennyson, Mill wrote in a review of that poet's earlypoems, excels in 'scene-painting, in the higher sense of the term'; and thisis

not the mere power of producing that rather vapid species ofcomposition usually termed descriptive poetry . . . but the power ofcreating scenery, in keeping with some state of human feeling; so

Page 12: M. H. Abrams Orientation of Critical Theorie s - kleal.com member area pd2 2013/Abrams - Orientation.pdf · M. H. ABRAMS Orientation of Critical Theories Some Co-ordinates of Art

24 M. H. ABRAMS

fitted to it as to be the embodied symbol of it, and to summon upthe state of feeling itself, with a force not to be surpassed byanything but reality56

And as an indication of the degree to which the innovations of the roman-tics persist as the commonplaces of modern critics — even of those whopurport t o found thei r theor y on anti-romantic principles — notice howstriking is the parallel between the passage above and a famous comment

. S. Eliot:g emotion in the form of art is by findingin other words, a set of objects, a

situation, a chain of events which shall be the formula of thatparticular emotion,- such that when the external facts, which mustterminate in sensory experience, are given, the emotion isimmediately evoked.57

audience. No less drastic is the fate of the audience. Accord-ing toMill, 'Poetry is feeling, confessing itself to itself in moments of sol-itude . . . ' The poet's audience is reduced to a single member, consistingof the poet himself 'Aljjpoetry^ as"Mill puts it. 'is ot the nature ot squy.' The purpose of producing effects upon other men, which for centu-ries Had been the defining character of the ar t o f poetry, now serves pre-cisely the opposite function: i t disqualifies a poem by proving it to berhetoric instead. When the poet's

act of utterance is not itself the end, but a means to an end — viz. bythe feelings he himself expresses, to work upon the feelings, or uponthe belief, or the will, of another, — when the expression of hisemotions ... is tinged also by that purpose, by that desire of makingan impression upon another mind, then it ceases to be poetry, andbecomes eloquence.58

There is, in fact, something singularly fatal to the audience inthe romantic point of view. Or, in terms of historical causes, itmight be conjectured that the disappearance of a homogeneous anddiscriminating readin g public fostered a criticism which onprinciple diminished the importance of the audience as adeterminant of poetry and poetic value. Wordsworth still insistedthat 'Poets do not write for Poets alone, but for Men/ and that eachof his poems 'has a worthy purpose7; even though it turns out thatthe pleasure and profit of the audience is an automatic consequenceoTthe poet's spnntnneOUV overflo w of feeling, provided that the, pappropriate associations between thoughts and feelings have beenestablished by the poe t in advance^ 59 Keats , however affirme d ~roundly that 'I never wrote one single line of Poetry with the leastShadow of public thought/60 'A poet is a nightingale/ according toShelley, 'who sits in darkness and sings to cheer its own solitude

Orientation of Critical Theories 25

with sweet sounds; his auditors are as men entranced by themelody of an unseen musician . . . '61 For Carlyle, the poet utterlyreplaces the audience thp gpnpratnr nf

On the whole, Genius has privileges of its own,- it selects an orbitfor itself; and be this never so eccentric, i f it is indeed a celestialorbit, we mere star-gazers must at last compose ourselves; mus t

J ceas e to cavil at it, and begin to observe it, and calculat e its laws. 62

I Th e evolution is complete, from the mimetic poet, assigned the minimalI rol e of holding a mirror up to nature, through the pragmati c poet who,I whateve r his natural gifts, is ultimately measured by his capacity to sat-

isfy the public taste, t o Carlyle's Poet as Hero, the chose n one who, be-;, | caus e he is 'a Force of Nature/ writes as he must, and through the degree

of homage he evokes, serves as the measur e of his reader's piet y and\63

Objective Theories

All types of theory described so far, in their practical applications, getdown to dealing with the work of art itself, in its parts and their mutualrelations, whethe r the premises on which these elements are discrimi-nated and evaluated relate them primarily to the spectator, the artist, orthe world without. But there is also a fourth procedure, the 'objective ori-entation/ which on principle regards the work of art in isolation from allthese externa l points of reference, analyzes it a s a selt-sutilcien t entity If

rirconstituted by its parts in their internal relationsTand sets ouTtcnsolely bv criteria intrinsic to its own mode of being.

This point of view has been comparatively rare in literary criticism.The one early attempt at the analysis of an art form which is both objec-tive and comprehensive occurs in the central portion of Aristotle's Poet-ics. I have chosen to discuss Aristotle's theory of art unde r the heading ofmimetic theories, because it sets out from, and makes frequent referenceback to the concept of imitation. Such is the flexibilit y o f Aristotle's pro-cedure, however, that after he has isolated the species 'tragedy/ and estab-lished its relation to the universe as an imitation o f a certain kind of ac-tion, and to the audience through its observed effect o f purging pity andfear, his method becomes centripetal, and assimilates these external ele-ments into attributes of the work proper. In this second consideration oftragedy as an object in itself, the actions and agents that are imitated re-enter th e discussion a s the plot, character , and thought which, togethe rwith diction, melody, and spectacle, make up the si x element s o f a trag-edy; and even pity and fear ar e reconsidered as that pleasurable quality

Page 13: M. H. Abrams Orientation of Critical Theorie s - kleal.com member area pd2 2013/Abrams - Orientation.pdf · M. H. ABRAMS Orientation of Critical Theories Some Co-ordinates of Art

26 M. H. ABRAMS

proper to tragedy, to be distinguished from the pleasures characteristic ofcomedy and other forms.64 The tragic work itself can now be analyzed for-mally as a^self-determining whole made up of parts, all organized aroundthe r.nntrnliin g part; the tragic pint — itself a unity in which the compo-nent incidents ar e integrated bv the internal relations of "necessity orprobability/

As an all-inclusive approach to poetry, the objective orientation wasjust beginning to emerge in the late eighteenth and early nineteenth cen-tury. We shall see later on that some critics were undertaking to explorethe concept of thejpoem as a heterocosm, a world of its own, independentof the world into which we are born, whose end is not to instruct or pleasebut simply to exist. Certain critics, particularly in Germany, were ex-panding~upon Kant's formula that a work of art exhibits Zweckmdssig-keit ohne Zweck (purposiveness without purpose), together with his con-cept that the contemplation of beauty is disinterested and without regardto utility, while neglecting Kant's characteristic reference of an aestheticproduct to the mental faculties of its creator and receptor. The aim to con-sider a poem, as Poe expressed it, as a 'poem per se ... written solely forthe poem's sake/65 in isolation fro m externa l cause s and ulterioi^ends,came to constitute on e element of the diverse doctrines usually huddledtogether by historians under the heading 'Art for Art's Sake/ And with dif-fering emphases and adequacy, and in a great variety of theoretical con-texts, the objective approach to poetry has bernr^ rmp nf thpinent element s i n th e innovativ e criticis m o f the las t tw o cm-thre e^c^es. 1. S. EllOf'S dictum of 1928, that 'when we~are considering poetrywemust consider it primarily as poetry and not another thing7 is widelyapproved, however far Eliot's own criticism sometimes departs from thi sideal; and it is often joined with MacLeish's verse aphorism, 'A poemshould not mean But be/ The subtle and incisive criticism of criticism bythe Chicag o Neo-Aristotelians and thei r advocacy of an instrumen tadapted to dealing with poetry as such have been largely effective towarda similar end. In his 'ontological criticism/ John Crowe Ransom has beencalling for recognition of 'the autonomy of the work itself as existing forits own sake';66 campaigns have been organized against 'the personal her-esy/ 'the intentional fallacy / and 'the affective fallacy' ; th e widely influ-ential handbook , The Theory o f Literature, written by Rene Wellek andAustin Warren, proposes that criticism dea l with a poem qua poem, in-dependently of 'extrinsic' factors; and similar views are being expressed,with increasing frequency, no t only in our literary but in our scholarlyjournals. In America, at least, some form of the objective point of view hasalready gone far to displace its rivals as the reigning mode of literary crit-icism.

Orientation of Critical Theories 27

According to our scheme of analysis, then, there have been four majororientations, each one of which has seemed to various acute minds ade-quate for a satisfactory criticis m o f art i n general. And by and large thehistoric progression, from the beginning through the early nineteenthcentury, has been from th e mimetic theor y of Plato and (in a qualifiedfashion) Aristotle, through the pragmatic theory, lasting from the confla -tion o f rhetoric with poeti c in the Hellenistic an d Roman era almos tthrough the eighteenth century , to the expressive theory of English (andsomewhat earlier, German) romantic criticism.

Of course romantic criticism, lik e that of any period, was not uni -form in its outlook. As late as 1831 Macaulay (whose thinking usually fol-lowed traditional patterns) still insists, as an eternal rule 'founded in rea-son and in the nature of things/ that 'poetry is, as was said more than twothousand years ago, imitation/ and differentiates between the arts on thebasis of their diverse media and objects o f imitation. Then , i n a n essaypacked with eighteenth-century catch-lines, he ungratefully employs themimetic principle to justify his elevation of Scott, Wordsworth, and Col-eridge over the eighteenth-century poets because they imitate naturemore accurately, and attacks the neo-classic rules of correctness o n th eground that they 'tend to make ... imitations les s perfect than they oth-erwise would be ... ' 67 The mode of criticism which subjects art and theartist to the audience also continued to flourish, usually in a vulgarizedform, among influential journalists such as Francis Jeffrey, wh o deliber-ately set themselves to voice the literary standards of the middle class andto preserve unsullied wha t Jeffrey called 'the purity of the female charac-ter/68

But these are not the innovative critical writings which contribute dto the predominant tempe r of what Shelley , in his 'Defenc e of Poetry/called 'the spirit of the age'; and the radical difference between the char-acteristic points of view of neo-classic and romantic criticism remain sunmistakable. Tak e such representative production s of the 1760' s and70's a s Johnson's Preface t o Shakespeare, Kames's Elements o f Criti-cism, Richard Hurd's 'On the Idea of Universal Poetry/ The Art o f Poetryon a New Plan (o f dubious authorship), Beattie's Essays o n Poetry an dMusic, and the firs t eight Discourses of Sir Joshua Reynolds. Place thesenext to the major inquiries into poetry and art of the romantic generation:Wordsworth's Prefaces and collateral essays, Coleridge's Biographia Lit-eraria and Shakespearean lectures, Hazlitt's 'On Poetry in General' andother essays, even Shelley's Platonistic 'Defenc e o f Poetry',- then add tothis group such later documents as Carlyle's 'Characteristics' and earlyliterary reviews, J. S. Mill's tw o essay s on poetry, John Keble's Lectureson Poetry, and Leigh Hunt's 'What Is Poetry?'. Whatever the continuity of

Page 14: M. H. Abrams Orientation of Critical Theorie s - kleal.com member area pd2 2013/Abrams - Orientation.pdf · M. H. ABRAMS Orientation of Critical Theories Some Co-ordinates of Art

28 M. H. ABRAMS

certain terms and topics between individual members of the tw o eras ,and however important the methodological and doctrinal difference swhich divide the members within a single group, one decisive changemarks off the criticism in the Age of Wordsworth from that in the Age ofJohnson. The poet has moved into the cente r of the critical system andtaken over many of the prerogatives which had once been exercised by hisreaders, the nature of the world in which he found himself, and the inher-ited precepts and examples of his poetic art .

NOTES

1. Forewor d to Philosophies o f Beauty, ed. E. F. Carritt (Oxford, 1931) , p. ix .2. (5t h ed.; London, 1934), pp. 6-7 Richards ' later change of emphasis is indi-

cated by his recent statemen t tha t ' "Semantics" which began by findingnonsense everywhere may well end up as a technique for widening under-standing7 (Modern Language Notes, LX, 1945, p. 350).

3. Fo r a subtle and elaborate analysis of diverse critical theories, se e RichardMcKeon, 'Philosophic Bases of Art an d Criticism/ Critics and Criticism,Ancient and Modern, ed. R. S. Crane (The University of Chicago Press, Chi-cago, 1952).

4. Republic (trans. Jowett) x. 596-7; Laws ii. 667-8, vii. 814-16.5. Se e Richard McKeon, 'Literary Criticism an d the Concep t of Imitation i n

Antiquity/ Critics and Criticism, ed. Crane, pp. 147-9. The article exhibitsthose multipl e shift s i n Plato' s use o f the ter m 'imitation 7 which havetrapped many later commentators as successfully as they once did the rashspirits who engaged Socrates in controversy.

6. Republic x. 5977. Laws vii. 8178. Republic x. 603-5; Ion 535-6; cf. Apology 22.9. Republic x. 608.

10. Poetics (trans. Ingram Bywater) 1 . 144 7a, 1448 a. On imitation i n Aristotle' scriticism see McKeon, 'The Concept of Imitation/ op. cit. pp. 160-68.

11. Poetics 6. 1449 b, 14. 1453b.12. Ibid . 8. 145K13. Ibid . 6. 1450a-1450b.14. Ibid . 4. 1448 b, 17 1455a- 1455b.15. Republic iii. 398, x. 606-8; Laws vii. 81716. Th e Works o f Richard Hurd (London , 1811) , 11 , 111 -12.17. Edwar d Young, Conjectures on Original Composition, ed . Edith Morley

(Manchester, 1918) , pp. 6, 18 . See also William Duff, Essay on Original Ge-nius (London, 1767) , p. 192n. John Ogilvie reconciles creative genius andoriginal invention with 'the great principle of poetic imitation' (Philosoph-ical and Critical Observations on the Nature, Characters, and Various Spe-cies of Composition, London, 1774 , 1, 105-7). Joseph Warton, familiar pro-ponent of a 'boundless imagination/ enthusiasm, an d 'the romantic, the

Orientation of Critical Theories 29

wonderful, an d the wild/ still agrees with Richard Hurd that poetry is 'anart, whose essence is imitation/ and whose objects are 'material or animate,extraneous or internal7 (Essay o n the Writings and Genius of Pope, London,1756, 1 , 89-90). Cf. Robert Wood, Essay on the Original Genius and Writ-ings of Homer (1769), London, 1824, pp. 6-7, 178.

18. 'Originality / Gleanings (London, 1785) , 1 , 10 109.19. Charle s Batteux, Les Beaux Arts reduits a un memeprincipe (Paris , 1747) ,

pp. i-viii.20. Ibid . pp. 9-2721. Ibid . p. xiii. For the important place of imitation in earlier French neo-classic

theories, se e Rene Bray, L a Formation de la doctrine classique en France(Lausanne, 1931), pp. 140ff .

22. Lessing , Laokoon, ed. W. G. Howard (New York, 1910) , pp. 23-5, 42 .23. Ibid . pp. 99-102, 64.24. Three Treatises, in Th e Works o f James Harris (London , 1803) , 1 , 58. Cf .

Adam Smith, 'O f th e Nature of that Imitation which Takes Place in WhatAre Called the Imitative Arts/ Essays Philosophical and Literary (London,n.d.), pp. 405ff .

25. Henr y Home, Lord Kames, Elements of Criticism (Boston, 1796), 11,1 (chap,xviii).

26. Thoma s Twining, ed., Aristotle's Treatise o n Poetry (London , 1789) , pp. 4,21-2,60-61.

27. Si r Philip Sidney, 'An Apology for Poetry/ Elizabethan Critical Essays, ed .G. Gregory Smith (London, 1904) , 1 , 158.

28. Ibid . 1,159.29. Ibid . 1,159, 161-4, 171-80, 201.30. See , e.g., his use of Aristotle's statement tha t poetry is more philosophical

than history (1, 167-8), and that painful things can be made pleasant by im-itations (p. 171); and his wrenching of Aristotle's central term, praxis—theactions which are imitated by poetry—to signify the moral action which apoem moves the spectator to practise (p. 171).

31. Cicero , De oratore 11. xxviii.32. Th e Concep t of Imitation/ op. cit. p. 173.33. Horace , Ars Poetica, trans. E. H. Blakeney, in Literary Criticism, Plato to

Dryden, ed . Allan H. Gilbert (New York, 1940) , p. 139.34. Essays on Poetry and Music (3d ed.; London, 1779), p. 10.35. 'Dryden / Lives of the English Poets, ed. Birkbeck Hill (Oxford, 1905) , 1 , 410.36. 'Paralle l of Poetry and Painting' (1695), Essays, ed. W. P. Ker (Oxford, 1926) ,

11, 138. See Hoyt Trowbridge, 'The Place of Rules in Dryden's Criticism/Modern Philology, XLIV (1946), 84ff .

37. Th e Advancement an d Reformation o f Modern Poetry ( 1701), in Th e Criti-cal Works of John Dennis, ed. E. N. Hooker (Baltimore, 1939), 1 , 202-3. ForDennis' derivation of specific rules from the end of art, which is 'to delightand reform the mind/ see The Grounds of Criticism in Poetry ( 1704), ibid,pp. 336ff .

38. 'Dissertatio n on the Idea of Universal Poetry/ Works, 11 , 3-4, 25-6 , 7 For aparallel argument see Alexander Gerard, An Essay on Taste (London, 1759) ,p. 40.

Page 15: M. H. Abrams Orientation of Critical Theorie s - kleal.com member area pd2 2013/Abrams - Orientation.pdf · M. H. ABRAMS Orientation of Critical Theories Some Co-ordinates of Art

30 M. H. ABRAM S

39. 'Ide a of Universal Poetry / Works, 11 , 3-4. O n the rationale underlying thebody of Hurd's criticism, see the article by Hoyt Trowbridge, 'Bishop Hurd:A Reinterpretation/ PMLA, LVII I (1943), 450ff .

40. E.g. , Batteux 'deduces' from the idea that poetry is the imitation, no t of un-adorned reality, but of la belle nature, that its end can only be 'to please, tomove, to touch, in a word, pleasure' (Les Beaux Arts, pp. 81, 151) . Conversely,Hurd infers from th e fac t that the end of poetry is pleasure that the poet'sduty is 'to illustrate and adorn' reality, and to delineate it 'in the most takingforms' ('Idea of Universal Poetry/ Works, 11 , 8) . For purposes of a specializedinvestigation int o the evidences for plagiarism among poets, Hurd himself,in another essay, shifts his ground, and like Batteux, sets out from a defini-tion o f poetry as an imitation , specifically , of 'the fairest form s o f things '('Discourse on Poetic Imitation/ Works, 11 , 111).

41. Johnson on Shakespeare, ed. Walter Raleigh (Oxford, 1908) , pp. 10 , 30-31.42. Ibid . pp. 14 , 39. Cf . pp. 11 , 31, 33, 37, etc.43. Ibid . p. 16.44. Ibid . pp. 31-3, 41.45. Ibid . pp. 9-12.46. Ibid . pp. 15-17 See also Johnson's defense o f Shakespeare for violating the

decorum of character-types, by the appeal to 'nature' as against 'accident';and for breaking the unities o f time and place, by the appeal both to the ac-tual experience of dramatic auditors, and to the principle that 'the greatestgraces of a play, are to copy nature and instruct life ' (ibid. pp. 14-15, 25-30).Cf. Rambler No. 156.

47. Ibid. pp. 20-21. The logic appears even more clearly in Johnson's early paperon 'works of fiction / in Rambler No. 4,1750 (The Works o f Samuel Johnson,ed. Arthur Murphy, London, 1824, IV, 23): 'It is justly considered as the great-est excellency of art, to imitate nature; but it is necessary to distinguishthose parts of nature which are most proper for imitation/ etc. For a detailedanalysis of Johnson's critical methods, se e W. R. Keast, 'The TheoreticalFoundations of Johnson's Criticism/ Critics and Criticism, ed. R. S. Crane,pp. 389-407

48. Se e the masterly precis of the complex movements within English neo-clas-sic criticism b y R. S. Crane, 'English Neoclassical Criticism/ Critics andCriticism, pp. 372-88.

49. Letters of William an d Dorothy Wordsworth: Th e Middle Years, ed . E. deSelincourt (Oxford, 1937) , 11 , 705; 18 Jan. 1816.

50. Early Essays b y John Stuart Mill, ed. J. W. M. Gibbs (London, 1897) , p. 208.51. Ibid . pp. 228, 205-6, 213, 203-4.52. Ibid . pp. 211-1753. Ibid . pp. 222-31.54. Ibid . pp. 206-755. Ibid . pp. 208-9. Cf. Hulme, 'If it is sincere in the accurate sense... the whole

of the analogy is necessary to get out the exact curve of the feeling or thingyou want to express...' ('Romanticism and Classicism/ Speculations, Lon-don, 1936, p. 138).

Orientation of Critical Theories 31

56. Review , written i n 1835 , o f Tennyson's Poems Chiefly Lyrical (1830) andPoems (1833), in Early Essays, p. 242.

57. 'Hamlet / Selected Essays 1917-32 (London, 1932), p. 145.58. Early Essays, pp. 208-9. Cf. John Keble, Lectures o n Poetry (1832-41),

trans. E. K. Francis (Oxford, 1912) , 1 , 48-9: 'Cicer o is always the orator' be-cause 'he always has in mind th e theatre, th e benches, th e audience';whereas Plato is 'more poetical tha n Homer himself''because 'he writes toplease himself, not to win over others.'

59. Prefac e to the Lyrical Ballads, Wordsworth's Literary Criticism, ed . N. C.Smith (London, 1905), pp. 30, 15-16.

60. Letters, ed. Maurice Buxton Forman (3d ed.; New York, 1948), p. 131 (to Rey-nolds, 9 Apr. 1818).

61. 'Defenc e of Poetry/ Shelley's Literary and Philosophical Criticism, ed. JohnShawcross (London, 1909), p. 129.

62. 'Jea n Paul Friedrich Richter' (1827) , Works, ed . H. D. Traill (London, 1905) ,XXVI, 20.

63. Se e Heroes, Hero-Worship, an d th e Heroic in History, in Works, v , esp. pp.80-85, 108-12. Cf. Jones Very's indignant denia l o f the inference that be-cause the general ear takes delight in Shakespeare, 'his motive was to please... We degrade those whom the world has pronounced poets, when we as-sume any other cause of their song than the divine and original action of thesoul in humble obedience to the Holy Spirit upon whom they call' ['Shake-speare' (1838), Poems and Essays, Boston and New York, 1886, pp. 45-6].

64. 'No t every kind of pleasure should be required of a tragedy, but only its ownproper pleasure. The tragic pleasure is that o f pity and fear . . .' (Poetics 14.1453b).

65. Th e Poeti c Principle/ Representative Selections, ed. Margaret Alterton andHardin Craig (New York, 1935), pp. 382-3.

66. Se e John Crowe Ransom, Th e World's Body (Ne w York, 1938) , esp. pp .327ff., an d 'Criticism as Pure Speculation/ Th e Intent o f the Critic, ed .Donald Stauffer (Princeton , 1941) .

67. 'Moore' s Life o f Lord Byron,' in Critical and Historical Essays (Everyman'sLibrary; London, 1907), 11, 622-8.

68. Edinburgh Review, VIII (1806), 459-60. On Jeffrey's us e o f an elaborate as-sociationist aesthetic s in order to justify the demand that an author or artisthave as his aim 'to give as much [pleasure] and to as many persons as possi-ble/ and that he 'fashion his productions according to the rules of taste whichmay be deduced' from a n investigation o f the most widespread public pref-erences, see his Contributions t o the Edinburgh Review (London, 1844) , 1,76-8, 128 ; 111 , 53-4. Fo r contemporary justifications, on sociological andmoral grounds, for instituting a petticoat governmen t ove r the republic ofletters, see, e.g., John Bowring's review of Tennyson's Poems, in Westmins-ter Review, XIV (1831), 223; Lockhart's Literary Criticism, ed . M. C. Hild-yard (Oxford, 1931) , p. 66; Christopher North (John Wilson), Works, ed . Fer-rier (Edinburgh and London, 1857), IX, 194-5, 228.


Recommended