+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

Date post: 01-Jan-2017
Category:
Upload: dangkien
View: 236 times
Download: 1 times
Share this document with a friend
56
Forthcoming in F. Macpherson and D. Platchais (eds.) Hallucination: Philosophy and Psychology, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. The Philosophy and Psychology of Hallucination: An Introduction Fiona Macpherson Few phenomena have played such a vital role in shaping philosophical theories as hallucination, particularly theories in philosophy of mind, perception, and epistemology. When the ordinary man or woman in the street thinks of hallucination, a drugfueled bizarre perceptual experience is conventionally what springs to mind. The traditional philosophical conception of hallucination encompasses such experience but is broader. The traditional philosophical conception includes perceptual experiences, identical in nature to experiences that could be had whilst perceiving the world, save only that they are had whilst not perceiving. 1 Such experiences might be ones that conform to the conventional conception of hallucination. One might, when hallucinating, have an experience of the sort that one would have were pink and green spiders to be crawling over the text that you are reading. However, they might also be perfectly mundane and be just like the visual experience I expect you are having now when reading this page. This mundane form of hallucination is particularly important in philosophy, as philosophers have often contemplated whether all of one’s perceptual experiences to date could have been hallucinatory. Might you be the subject of mass deception, 1 As I explain in more detail in section one, I use “perceive” as a success verb to indicate perception rather than hallucination, but I use “perceptual experience” to name the kind of state that occurs in both perception and hallucination. Thus note that hallucinations—states not involved in perceiving the world—are nonetheless typically referred to as “perceptual experiences”. I follow that usage in this introduction.
Transcript
Page 1: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

       Forthcoming  in  F.  Macpherson  and  D.  Platchais  (eds.)  Hallucination:  Philosophy  and  Psychology,  Cambridge,  MA:  MIT  Press.    

 

The  Philosophy  and  Psychology  of  Hallucination:  An  Introduction  

Fiona  Macpherson  

 

Few  phenomena  have  played  such  a  vital  role  in  shaping  philosophical  theories  as  

hallucination,  particularly  theories  in  philosophy  of  mind,  perception,  and  

epistemology.  When  the  ordinary  man  or  woman  in  the  street  thinks  of  

hallucination,  a  drug-­‐fueled  bizarre  perceptual  experience  is  conventionally  what  

springs  to  mind.  The  traditional  philosophical  conception  of  hallucination  

encompasses  such  experience  but  is  broader.  The  traditional  philosophical  

conception  includes  perceptual  experiences,  identical  in  nature  to  experiences  that  

could  be  had  whilst  perceiving  the  world,  save  only  that  they  are  had  whilst  not  

perceiving.  1  Such  experiences  might  be  ones  that  conform  to  the  conventional  

conception  of  hallucination.  One  might,  when  hallucinating,  have  an  experience  of  

the  sort  that  one  would  have  were  pink  and  green  spiders  to  be  crawling  over  the  

text  that  you  are  reading.  However,  they  might  also  be  perfectly  mundane  and  be  

just  like  the  visual  experience  I  expect  you  are  having  now  when  reading  this  page.  

This  mundane  form  of  hallucination  is  particularly  important  in  philosophy,  as  

philosophers  have  often  contemplated  whether  all  of  one’s  perceptual  experiences  

to  date  could  have  been  hallucinatory.  Might  you  be  the  subject  of  mass  deception,  

                                                                                                               1  As  I  explain  in  more  detail  in  section  one,  I  use  “perceive”  as  a  success  verb  to  indicate  perception  rather  than  hallucination,  but  I  use  “perceptual  experience”  to  name  the  kind  of  state  that  occurs  in  both  perception  and  hallucination.  Thus  note  that  hallucinations—states  not  involved  in  perceiving  the  world—are  nonetheless  typically  referred  to  as  “perceptual  experiences”.  I  follow  that  usage  in  this  introduction.  

Page 2: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  2  

carried  out  by  an  evil  daemon  or  by  aliens  who  are  artificially  stimulating  your  

brain,  trapping  you  in  a  merely  simulated  world?  In  addition,  this  philosophical  

conception  makes  room  for  experiences  that,  were  the  subject  to  take  them  at  face  

value,  would  seem  to  be  perceptual  experiences  but  could  never  be  had  when  

perceiving,  at  least  when  perceiving  accurately,  simply  because  the  world  could  

never  be  as  the  experience  presents  it  to  be.  For  example,  it  might  be  possible  to  

hallucinate  colours  that  do  not  and  could  not  exist  in  the  world.2  Or  it  might  be  

possible  to  hallucinate  a  geometrically  impossible  spatial  configuration3  

Although  the  consequences  of  the  existence  of  hallucination  have  been  much  

explored  and  debated,  alternatives  to  the  traditional  philosophical  conception  of  

hallucination  have,  until  recently,  received  little  attention.  However,  two  emerging  

strands  of  research  have  brought  to  light  other  conceptions  of  hallucination.  One  of  

these  is  scientific  evidence  about  people  who  actually  hallucinate.  Evidence  from  

psychology,  neuroscience,  and  psychiatry  has  shed  light  on  the  functional  role  and  

physiology  of  actual  hallucinations.  The  second  strand  is  the  development  of  a  

philosophical  theory  of  perception  known  as  disjunctivism.  Some  disjunctivist  

theories  have  as  part  of  their  ontology  a  radically  new  and  different  conception  of  

hallucination.  

                                                                                                               2  See  Crane  and  Piantanida  (1983).  One  might  think  that  such  “novel”  colours  are  not  just  not  actual  but  impossible  if  one  held  an  objective  physicalist  view  of  colours  such  as  that  endorsed  by  Byrne  and  Hilbert.  They  claim,  “The  best  description  of  a  world  with  a  very  different  physics  from  our  own  is  that  in  such  a  world  objects  merely  look  coloured”  (1997,  p.  282,  footnote  8).  Furthermore,  see  ffytche  (this  volume),  who  describes  anecdotally  patients  describing  their  visual  hallucinations  of  colours  as  being  more  vivid  than  those  encountered  in  nonhallucinatory  visual  experience.  3  One  can  have  illusory  experiences  that  seem  to  represent  “impossible  figures”,  such  as  those  frequently  depicted  by  Oscar  Reutersvärd  and  M.  C.  Escher  paintings,  such  as  the  impossible  tribar.  Examples  of  the  kind  of  experience  I  have  in  mind  are  those  had  when  looking  at  specially  created  three-­‐dimensional  objects  that,  viewed  from  the  right  position,  give  one  experiences  that  seem  to  represent  three-­‐dimensional  geometrical  impossibilities.  See  Macpherson  (2010a).  If  one  hallucinated  such  an  object,  it  would  be  an  experience  that  could  not  be  had  when  perceiving  the  world  accurately.  

Page 3: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  3  

  Once  these  different  conceptions  of  hallucination  are  made  clear  we  can  then  

compare  and  contrast  them.  We  can  ask  whether  there  is  or  could  be  any  evidence  

to  think  that  some  of  them,  or  all  of  them,  exist  or  could  exist.  And  we  can  try  to  

determine  whether  the  traditional  debates  about  the  upshot  of  the  existence,  or  

possible  existence,  of  hallucination  are  transformed  by  these  differing  conceptions.  

  Reflection  on  these  different  notions  of  hallucination  has  the  potential  to  

transform  many  traditional  debates  in  philosophy  concerning  the  nature  of  the  

mind,  perception  and  our  knowledge  of  the  world.  It  has  the  potential  to  radically  

alter  our  approach  to,  and  answers  to,  traditional  philosophical  concerns  about  

knowledge  and  the  mind.  In  addition,  clarifying  the  different  conceptions  of  

hallucination  will  be  of  value  to  scientists  when  they  are  trying  to  determine  the  

nature  of  hallucination  in  patients,  and  to  clinical  medics  who  are  trying  to  treat  

them.  The  nature  of  hallucination  is  therefore  of  great  philosophical,  theoretical  and  

practical  importance.  

  These  are  the  issues  that  the  essays  in  this  book  engage  with.  They  are  

written  by  philosophers  of  many  stripes  and  by  scientists.  In  this  introduction,  I  aim  

to  achieve  a  number  of  goals.  I  wish  to  provide  an  introduction  for  scientists,  

philosophers,  and  other  academics  who  want  to  understand  the  philosophical  

debate  about  perception  and  hallucination.  I  aim  to  explicate  a  few  of  the  scientific  

findings  for  philosophers  and  others  unfamiliar  with  the  relevant  empirical  results.  I  

hope  to  add  to  the  debate  by  explaining  how  I  think  the  scientific  results  impact  on  

philosophical  concerns  and  how  philosophical  theory  should  impact  on  the  

interpretation  of  the  scientific  results.  Finally,  I  aim  to  explain  the  fundamental  

difference  between  the  view  of  perception  called  disjunctivism  and  the  more  

traditional  common-­‐kind  view,  and  I  will  explore  reasons  to  favour  one  or  other  of  

two  different  views  of  hallucination:  the  common-­‐kind  conception  and  the  strict  

disjunctive  conception  that  the  theories  advocate.  I  also  explore  other  conceptions  

of  hallucination  and  the  reasons  one  might  have  for  thinking  they  exist.  

Page 4: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  4  

To  that  end,  I  first  outline  the  traditional  conception  of  hallucination  and  

provide  an  overview  of  the  consequences  often  thought  to  follow  from  the  existence  

of  hallucination  conceived  of  in  this  manner.  In  particular,  I  explain  the  constraints  

on  theories  of  perception  and  perceptual  experience  that  have  been  thought  to  

follow  from  the  traditional  conception  of  hallucination,  as  well  as  the  theories  of  

perception  and  perceptual  experience  that  conform  to  these  constraints.  In  addition,  

I  outline  the  challenge  to  empirical  knowledge  that  the  traditional  conception  of  

hallucination  engenders.  I  then  examine  other  notions  of  hallucination  inspired  by  

the  latest  scientific  work  and  by  disjunctivism.  I  consider  to  what  extent  there  is,  or  

could  be,  empirical  evidence  in  favour  of  the  existence  of  the  different  forms  of  

hallucination  or  reasons  to  think  that,  even  if  not  actual,  such  hallucinations  are  

metaphysically  possible.  (Metaphysical  possibility  is  to  be  contrasted  with  

nomological  possibility.  “Nomological  possibility”  refers  to  what  is  possible  given  

that  the  natural  laws  of  this  world  are  held  fixed,  such  as  the  speed  of  light,  the  

strength  of  gravity,  and  so  on.  “Metaphysical  possibility”  refers  to  what  is  possible  

not  only  in  those  circumstances  but  also  in  circumstances  in  which  the  natural  laws  

differ  from  what  they  actually  are.)  I  also  explain  what  consequences  the  existence  

or  possible  existence  of  the  nontraditional  forms  of  hallucination  may  have  on  

further  philosophical  theorizing  about  perception  and  knowledge.  I  finish  by  

considering  the  different  philosophical  commitments  that  underlie  different  views  

of  perception  and  hallucination  and  reasons  to  prefer  one  set  over  another.  

 

1  Preliminaries  

In  this  section  I  outline  some  important  terminological  issues,  conventions,  and  

assumptions  that  are  used  in  philosophy,  which  one  needs  to  appreciate  if  one  is  to  

understand  the  debates  that  follow.  

Page 5: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  5  

  For  the  purposes  of  this  essay,  I  assume  a  realist  framework.  Realism  is  a  

theory  that  makes  both  an  ontological  and  an  epistemological  claim.4  The  

ontological  claim  is  that  there  exists  a  world  that  is  independent  from  the  concepts,  

thoughts,  and  beliefs  that  people  do  or  may  have.  A  slightly  stronger  version  of  the  

claim  is  that  the  world  has  a  structure,  which  thought  and  belief  aim  to  map  or  

represent  with  more  or  less  success.  Thus  with  our  thought  and  language  we  

typically  try  to  refer  to  objects,  properties,  and  events  that  exist  in  the  world  

(although  of  course,  we  sometimes  knowingly  refer  to  objects  that  do  not  exist,  such  

as  round  squares  or  the  fountain  of  youth).  The  realist  epistemological  claim  attests  

to  the  at  least  partial  success  of  the  representation  or  mapping.  We  can  and  do  have  

some  knowledge  of  the  mind-­‐independent  world  and  our  discourse  about  the  world  

can  be  and  is  sometimes  is  true.  

  Contrasting  with  realism,  idealism  in  the  philosophy  of  perception  is  a  view  

that  in  a  strong  form  says  that  the  world  is  mind  dependent,  and  is  simply  composed  

of  one’s  own,  and  perhaps  others’  or  God’s,  perceptual  experiences.  If  one  is  an  

idealist,  then  one  has  to  have  a  rather  idiosyncratic  view  of  hallucination.  Cases  of  

hallucination  involve  having  perceptual  experiences,  and  for  the  idealist,  these  also  

constitute  the  world,  so  there  is  no  question  of  hallucinations  differing  from  

nonhallucinatory  experiences  by  not  matching  the  world  or  by  not  being  linked  to  

the  world  in  the  same  way.  So  for  the  idealist,  the  experiences  that  we  call  

hallucinations  are  simply  the  ones  that  don’t  occur  in  the  regular  patterns  typical  of  

nonhallucinatory  experiences.  For  example,  if  one  had  a  visual  experience  as  of  a  

pink  rat  materializing  in  front  of  one,  and  one  couldn’t  feel  it,  smell  it,  or  hear  it,  and  

no  one  else  who  looked  had  an  experience  of  the  rat,  then  one’s  visual  experience  as  

of  the  pink  rat  would  be  anomalous.  Hallucinatory  experiences,  on  the  idealist  view,  

are  simply  ones  that  do  not  conform  to  certain  patterns  of  regularity,  which  our  

other  experiences  do.  There  is  nothing  over  and  above  this  that  makes  them  

                                                                                                               4  See  Haldane  and  Wright  (1993)  and  Haldane  (1993).  

Page 6: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  6  

different  from  nonhallucinatory  experiences.  According  to  the  idealist,  then,  one  

could  not  be  hallucinating  all  one’s  life  in  a  completely  coherent  and  regular  fashion,  

for  if  one’s  experiences  were  like  that,  then,  according  to  this  theory,  they  would  be,  

by  definition,  not  hallucinations.  However,  I  will  set  aside  idealism  from  here  on.  

Now  that  a  realist  framework  is  assumed,  I  turn  to  consider  some  more  

specific  issues  about  perception.  Consider  the  fact  that  there  are  different  senses.  

One  can  perceive  in  many  different  ways.  One  can  perceive  a  strawberry  by  seeing  it,  

touching  it,  smelling  it,  tasting  it,  and  hearing  it  make  a  dull  thud  when  it  drops  on  

the  floor.  In  philosophy,  the  cases  of  perception  typically  discussed  are  cases  of  

visual  perception  (seeing),  and  when  hallucination  is  discussed,  the  paradigm  case  is  

visual  hallucination.  But,  of  course,  one  can  have  tactile,  auditory,  olfactory,  and  

gustatory  hallucinations  too.  In  fact,  one  can  have  hallucinations  connected  with  all  

the  sensory  modalities,  not  just  the  five  well-­‐known  previously  mentioned  ones.  For  

example,  one  could  have  proprioceptive  or  equilibrioceptive  hallucinations.  In  the  

study  of  perception  in  philosophy,  it  is  frequently  assumed  that  whatever  we  say  

about  the  case  of  vision  can  be  carried  over  unproblematically  to  the  other  

modalities.  This  may  be  true  in  many  cases;  however,  one  ought  to  be  wary  of  this  

assumption.  In  psychology,  visual  and  auditory  hallucinations  are  both  common  

objects  of  study,  but  as  we  will  see,  psychologists  often  provide  different  accounts  of  

visual  and  auditory  hallucinations.  

A  number  of  terminological  points  now  need  to  be  explicated.  First,  it  is  

standard  in  philosophical  discussion  to  use  the  word  “perceive”,  and  its  derivatives  

such  as  “see,”  “touch,”  “hear,”  and  so  on,  as  success  verbs.  For  example,  if  one  

visually  hallucinates  that  there  is  a  dagger  before  one,  one  does  not  see  a  dagger  

before  one.  For  one  to  see  a  dagger,  not  only  would  it  have  to  seem  visually  to  one  as  

if  there  were  a  dagger  before  one,  that  is,  have  a  visual  experience  as  of  a  dagger,  but  

one  must  also,  in  virtue  of  having  that  experience,  be  aware  of  some  real  dagger  that  

exists  (or  possibly,  in  the  case  of  looking  at  very  distant  objects  such  as  stars,  be  

Page 7: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  7  

aware  of  some  object  that  existed).  Thus  when  one  sees  a  dagger  and  when  one  

visually  hallucinates  a  dagger,  one  has  a  visual  experience  as  of  a  dagger.  But  when  

one  visually  hallucinates  a  dagger,  one  does  not  see  a  dagger.  When  one  hallucinates,  

one  might,  of  course,  think  that  one  is  seeing  (although  one  need  not,  if  one  knows  

that  one  is  hallucinating),  and  one  might  claim  that  one  is  seeing  –  but  one  would  be  

wrong,  according  to  this  philosophical  usage  of  the  term.  For  example,  in  the  

Scottish  play,  when  Macbeth  hallucinates  a  bloody  dagger  floating  in  the  air  as  he  

contemplates  killing  Duncan,  he  asks,  “Is  this  a  dagger  which  I  see  before  me?”  The  

correct  philosophical  answer  would  be  “No,  Macbeth.  You  do  not  see  a  dagger.  You  

merely  seem  to  see  one.  You  are  having  a  perceptual  experience  as  of  one,  but  you  

are  hallucinating.”  I  will  abide  by  this  philosophical  convention.  

  A  second  piece  of  terminology  requiring  introduction  is  “veridical  

hallucination”.  Perceptual  experiences  are  often  thought  to  be  more  or  less  accurate.  

Consider,  again,  having  a  visual  experience  as  of  a  dagger.  If  one  is  seeing  a  dagger,  

and  seeing  it  as  it  is,  then  one’s  experience  would  be,  to  this  extent,  accurate.  In  

virtue  of  this,  we  might  say  that  the  experience  accurately  represents  a  dagger.  In  

other  words,  it  is  veridical.5  When  one  thinks  of  visually  hallucinating  a  dagger,  the  

kind  of  case  that  typically  springs  to  mind  is  one  where  one  hallucinates  a  dagger,  

but  there  is  no  dagger  before  one.  In  this  case,  the  visual  experience  had  whilst  

hallucinating  represents  a  dagger,  but  it  is  inaccurate.  How  the  experience  

represents  the  world  to  be  is  not  how  the  world  is.  No  doubt,  the  majority  of  actual  

hallucinations  are  like  this.  

                                                                                                               5  Susanna  Siegel  (2006)  has  explicated  at  length  the  notion  of  accuracy  and  the  notion  of  representation  that  is  concomitant  with  it.  Whether  this  is  the  notion  of  representation  that  everyone  can  agree  experiences  have,  and  whether  there  are  other  notions  of  representation  that  some  people  think  apply  to  experiences,  is  a  topic  of  much  debate  in  modern  philosophy  of  perception.  In  fact  there  is  a  debate  about  whether  representation  can  be  captured  by  accuracy  or  a  seeming  condition.  See  the  essays  in  Hawley  and  Macpherson  (2011),  and  for  an  overview  see  Macpherson  (2011).  See  particularly  Pautz  (2011)  and  Travis  (2004)  for  opposing  views  of  different  kinds  to  Siegel.  

Page 8: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  8  

However,  we  should  be  careful  not  to  define  hallucination  as  inaccurate  

experience  for  two  reasons.  One  is  the  possibility  of  the  existence  of  cases  of  

veridical  hallucination,  which  will  be  discussed  in  this  paragraph.  The  second  is  the  

existence  of  cases  of  illusory  experience,  discussed  in  the  next.  Veridical  

hallucinations  occur  when  one  hallucinates  but  when  one’s  experience  is  accurate.  

For  example,  one  could  hallucinate  a  dagger  as  being  in  front  of  one,  and  completely  

unrelatedly  and  just  by  chance,  there  might  really  be  a  dagger  of  the  very  type  that  

one  is  hallucinating  in  exactly  the  place  where  one  hallucinates  the  dagger  to  be.  Of  

course,  in  normal  circumstances,  the  chances  of  such  a  case  occurring  would  be  

extremely  slim,  but  nothing  rules  out  the  possibility  of  such  a  case.  Indeed,  one  can  

imagine  such  cases  being  deliberately  brought  about.  Suppose  you  are  prone  to  

dagger  hallucinations  and  have  described  to  me  in  detail  what  the  dagger  you  

hallucinate  always  seems  to  look  like.  I  might  procure  such  a  dagger,  and  the  next  

time  you  hallucinate,  I  might  place  the  dagger  in  front  of  you,  thus  making  it  the  case  

that  your  visual  experience  accurately  represents  the  world  in  front  of  you.  

Likewise,  we  can  imagine  a  scenario  in  which  I  place  a  dagger  in  front  of  you  and  

then  cause  you  to  have  a  hallucination  that  exactly  represents  such  a  dagger  by  

feeding  you  a  drug  or  directly  stimulating  your  brain  with  electrodes  or  magnetism  

or  in  some  other  method  that  makes  you  hallucinate  daggers  of  exactly  that  type.  

(While  we  don’t  think  that  neuroscientists  can  at  present  create  such  complex  

hallucinations,  we  do  know  that  they  can  reliably  cause  visual  hallucinations  of  

certain  basic  types  in  people,  and  there  seems  no  reason  to  think  that  in  the  future  

they  will  not  possess  such  abilities.)  These  examples  make  the  possibility  of  

veridical  hallucination  clear.  

A  final  terminological  issue  to  bring  to  the  fore  is  how  the  term  “illusion”  is  

used.  Cases  of  illusion  constitute  the  second  reason  we  have  not  to  define  

hallucinations  as  instances  of  inaccurate  experience.  While  the  case  of  veridical  

hallucination  shows  that  inaccuracy  is  not  a  necessary  condition  for  an  experience  

Page 9: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  9  

to  be  hallucinatory,  illusion  shows  us  that  it  is  not  sufficient.  Illusions  are  typically  

defined  in  philosophy  as  occurring  when  one  sees  the  world,  or  some  object  in  the  

world,  but  one  sees  it  inaccurately  in  some  respect.  For  example,  consider  the  

Müller-­‐Lyer  illusion.  The  figure  produces  illusory  perception  because  it  produces  an  

inaccurate  experience  in  us  of  it.  We  see  the  lines  in  the  figure,  but  we  see  them  

incorrectly.  We  have  an  experience  that  represents  the  top  horizontal  line  as  being  

longer  than  the  bottom  horizontal  line,  whereas  in  fact  they  are  the  same  length.6  A  

frequently  cited  fact  about  such  cases  is  that  the  illusory  experience  persists  even  

when  one  knows  that  the  lines  are  of  equal  length,  and  knows  that  one  is  undergoing  

an  illusion.  As  defined,  when  one  has  an  illusory  experience,  one  is  perceiving  the  

world  –  just  inaccurately  in  one  or  more  respects.  

 

 

Figure  1.1:  The  Müller-­‐Lyer  illusion  

 

In  short,  cases  of  perceptual  experience  can  occur  in  three  different  

conditions:  

                                                                                                               6  This  is,  at  least,  the  standard  view  of  illusions.  An  alternative  view  of  illusions,  inspired  by  a  disjunctivist  view  of  perception,  is  that  in  illusions  we  have  accurate  experience  but  form  inaccurate  beliefs  about  the  world  on  the  basis  of  that  experience.  Bill  Brewer  (2008)  has  articulated  and  defended  this  view,  but  we  will  set  that  view  aside  here.  It  is  not  obvious  that  Brewer’s  view  should  not  be  more  accurately  described  as  one  in  which  there  are  no  illusions,  and  that  cases  typically  classified  as  such  are  ones  in  accurate,  non-­‐illusory  experience  is  involved  in  perceiving  the  world  together  with  inaccurate  belief  formation.  

Page 10: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  10  

(i) veridical  perception:  accurate  perception  of  the  world  

(ii) illusion:  inaccurate  (nonveridical)  perception  of  the  world  

(iii) hallucination:  No  perception  of  the  world.  Hallucinatory  experiences  will  

typically  be  inaccurate  (nonveridical),  but  accurate  (veridical)  hallucinations  

are  possible.  

 And  when  one  is  in  each  of  these  conditions,  it  is  possible  for  one  to  (a)  truly  believe  

that  one  is  in  that  condition,  (b)  falsely  believe  that  one  is  in  that  condition,  and  (c)  

be  agnostic  about  whether  one  is  in  that  condition.  

It  is  worth  noting  that  there  may  be  some  instances  of  having  a  visual  

perceptual  experience  that  are  difficult  to  classify  in  practice.  For  example,  

sometimes  it  will  be  hard  to  know  whether  someone  is  having  an  illusory  

experience,  or  whether  they  are  accurately  perceiving  the  world  but  simply  forming  

false  beliefs  about  it  despite  their  accurate  perceptual  experience.7  Likewise  there  

are  some  cases  where  it  is  not  clear  if  one  should  classify  what  is  taking  place  as  a  

hallucination  or  an  illusory  experience.  For  example,  consider  the  Hermann  grid.  

When  one’s  eyes  roam  across  the  grid,  one  has  an  experience  as  of  grey  squares  

appearing  and  disappearing  on  the  white  intersections  between  the  black  squares.  

Of  course,  one  realises  quickly  that  one’s  experience  is  not  veridical.  But  is  one  

inaccurately  seeing  the  white  intersections  as  grey  –  thus  undergoing  an  illusion  –  or  

is  one  hallucinating  grey  squares,  on  account  of  the  interaction  of  the  grid  with  one’s  

visual  system?  It  is  difficult  to  decide  which  is  the  right  description  of  this  case,  but  

that  difficulty  does  not  stop  the  distinction  between  illusion  and  hallucination  itself  

being  clear.  

                                                                                                               7  See  Macpherson  (2012).  

Page 11: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  11  

 

Figure  1.2:  The  Hermann  grid  

  If  it  is  right  to  think  that  the  grey  squares  experienced  when  looking  at  the  

Hermann  grid  are  hallucinatory,  then  this  case  brings  out  a  feature  of  actual  

hallucinations  not  traditionally  considered  by  philosophers.  When  philosophers  talk  

of  hallucinations,  they  typically  imagine  cases  in  which  one’s  perceptual  experience  

is  completely  hallucinatory.  That  is,  they  imagine  that  one  is  seeing  nothing  and  that  

each  element  of  one’s  perceptual  experience  is  hallucinatory.  In  fact,  in  many  

hallucinations  that  actually  occur,  a  subject’s  experience  is  only  partially  

hallucinatory  in  the  sense  that  some  elements  of  the  perceptual  experience  are  

hallucinatory,  but  others  are  not.  For  example,  a  subject  might  be  seeing  the  room  in  

which  she  sits,  and  doing  so  accurately,  except  for  the  fact  that  she  is  hallucinating  a  

cat  sitting  on  the  carpet.  Another  case  worthy  of  note  is  that  which  is  often  called  

“having  an  afterimage”.  If  one  stares  at  a  patch  of  colour  and  then  looks  at  a  white  

surface,  one  has  an  inaccurate  experience  as  of  a  patch  of  the  same  shape  as  the  one  

stared  at  originally  but  in  the  complementary  colour.  Many  philosophers  would,  I  

think  rightly,  count  such  cases  as  being  cases  of  hallucination.  If  that  is  right  then  

they  are  further  instances  of  partial  hallucinations,  for  one  still  sees  the  world  when  

having  an  afterimage.  While  I  will  mostly  discuss  experiences  that  are  total  

hallucinations,  it  is  worth  bearing  such  partial  hallucinations  in  mind,  in  particular  

Page 12: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  12  

when  one  is  assessing  different  conceptions  of  hallucination  and  the  theories  of  

perception  that  are  associated  with  each  of  them.  

 

2  The  Traditional  View  of  Perception  and  Hallucination  

The  traditional  view  of  hallucination  is  best  explicated  hand  in  hand  with  traditional  

views  of  perception  and  perceptual  experience,  which  have  recently  come  to  be  

known  as  “common-­‐kind”  theories.8  Let  us  start  with  the  basic  scientific  facts  about  

a  typical  case  of  perception,  which  all  philosophical  theories  of  perception  (bar  

idealism)  would  be,  and  should  be,  happy  to  endorse.  

In  a  typical  case  of  seeing,  light  reflects  off  objects  and  enters  our  eyes,  

stimulating  retinal  cells.  These  cells  are  connected  via  the  optic  nerve  to  neurons  in  

the  brain  that  they  in  turn  stimulate.  Although  neurons  in  many  parts  of  the  brain  

are  stimulated  in  this  way,  a  major  neural  pathway  runs  from  the  optic  nerve,  via  the  

lateral  geniculate  nucleus,  to  the  primary  visual  cortex,  located  towards  the  back  of  

the  head  in  the  occipital  lobe.  The  neurons  in  the  visual  cortex  then  go  on  to  

stimulate  neurons  in  a  large  number  of  brain  regions.  During  this  process,  arguably  

when  the  visual  cortex  is  being  stimulated,  a  visual  experience  occurs.9  A  visual  

experience  is  a  conscious  mental  state,  which  is  to  say  that  there  is  “something  that  

it  is  like”  to  be  in  that  state,  to  use  a  well-­‐worn  phrase  coined  by  Thomas  Nagel  

(1974),  and  equivalently,  it  is  to  say  that  the  state  has  phenomenal  character.  

  What  is  the  relationship  between  the  brain  states  and  the  experience?  

Common-­‐kind  theorists  say  different  things.  According  to  some,  brain  states  cause  

distinct  perceptual  experiences  to  come  into  existence  –  experiences  that  are                                                                                                                  8  The  “common-­‐kind”  terminology  has  only  quite  recently  come  to  refer  to  a  class  of  theories  that  share  certain  commitments  that  distinguish  them  from  disjunctivism.  Before  disjunctivism’s  recent  entry  into  the  philosophical  scene,  common-­‐kind  theories  were  the  only  theories  in  the  literature,  and  there  was  no  particular  collective  name  for  them  as  such.  9  See  Crick  and  Koch  (1998).  

Page 13: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  13  

themselves  nonphysical  states.  Such  people  are  committed  to  a  form  of  dualism.  

According  to  others,  some  brain  states  somehow  just  are  experiences.  There  are,  

broadly  speaking,  two  versions  of  this  view.  One  claims  that  the  stuff  that  the  brain  

is  made  of  is  important  in  explaining  how  this  is  so.  Great  disagreement  divides  

theorists  who  advocate  this  sort  of  approach  concerning  what  features  of  physical  

stuff  are  important.  The  second  view  claims  that  mental  states  are  the  states  that  

they  are  in  virtue  of  their  functional  role.  To  cite  an  overly  simplistic  example,  a  pain  

state  might  be  any  state  that  is  typically  caused  by  bodily  damage  and  gives  rise  to  

desires  to  avoid  the  pain  stimulus,  which  in  turn  give  rise  to  avoidance  behaviour.  

Brain  states  have  functional  roles  too,  and  according  to  this  theory,  if  a  mental  state  

plays  the  same  functional  role  as  a  brain  state,  then  we  have  good  reason  to  identify  

the  mental  state  with  the  brain  state  or,  in  a  slight  variant  of  the  view,  to  identify  the  

mental  state  with  the  higher-­‐order  state  of  having  some  physical  state  play  the  role  

in  question.  

  Despite  their  disagreement  about  the  relationship  between  the  experience  

and  the  brain,  common-­‐kind  theorists  agree  on  certain  key  facts:  

(i) A  perceptual  experience  occurs  at  the  end  of  a  causal  chain  that,  in  typical  

cases  of  seeing,  starts  with  light  reflecting  off  an  object  and  then  hitting  

the  eye,  leading  to  various  brain  states  being  instantiated,  leading  to  the  

occurrence  of  a  visual  experience.  

(ii) One  can  cause  a  perceptual  experience  to  come  into  existence  by  

recreating  any  of  the  states  along  that  causal  chain  (so  long  as  they  in  turn  

cause  the  rest  of  the  states  in  the  causal  chain  to  come  into  existence).  In  

particular,  by  stimulating  the  brain  in  the  right  way,  one  can  cause  a  

perceptual  experience  to  occur.  In  this  case,  one  re-­‐creates  the  end  state  

of  the  causal  chain  without  perception  of  the  world  occurring.  This  is  to  

create  a  hallucination.  

Page 14: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  14  

(iii) A  perceptual  experience  caused  by  perception  of  the  world,  and  a  

perceptual  experience  caused  by  merely  stimulating  the  brain  in  the  way  

that  it  would  have  been  stimulated  by  perception  of  the  world,  produce  

experiences  of  the  same  type  in  respect  of  what  they  represent  and  in  

respect  of  their  conscious  nature,  that  is  to  say,  their  phenomenal  

character.  I  will  express  this  idea  by  saying  that  the  experiences  are  of  the  

“same  mental  type.”  These  experiences  are  thus  alike,  bar  the  fact  that  one  

is  had  whilst  perceiving  the  world  and  one  is  had  whilst  hallucinating.  

The  experiences  are  intrinsically  the  same  and  differ  only  in  their  

different  origins  or  in  the  different  casual  relationships  that  they  bear  to  

the  world.  

To  sum  up,  the  traditional  notion  of  hallucination,  what  I  will  call  the  

“common-­‐kind  view  of  hallucination”  arises  from  conceiving  of  perception  in  the  

way  that  common-­‐kind  theorists  do.  Common-­‐kind  theorists  hold  that  states  of  the  

same  mental  type  can  occur  in  perception  and  hallucination.  More  particularly,  they  

hold  that  any  experience  that  could  be  had  when  perceiving  (accurately  or  illusorily)  

could  be  had  when  hallucinating.  This  is  because  any  way  that  the  brain  is  

stimulated  in  a  case  of  perception  could  be  a  way  that  it  is  stimulated  when  no  

perception  occurs,  thus  re-­‐creating  the  same  end  state,  which  they  hold  to  be  

identical  with  one’s  perceptual  experience.  (As  an  aside,  note  that  the  converse  may  

not  be  true.  There  may  be  ways  of  stimulating  the  brain  that  produce  hallucinations  

that  cannot  be  replicated  in  perception.10  However,  from  now  on  I  will  set  that  kind  

of  hallucination  aside  and  focus  only  on  those  hallucinations  that  are  counterparts  of  

experiences  had  while  perceiving.)  The  traditional  common-­‐kind  conception  of  

hallucinations,  therefore,  is  that  they  are  of  the  same  mental  type  as  perceptual  

                                                                                                               10  For  example,  Crane  and  Piantanida  (1983)  induce  experiences  of  novel  colors  that  one  could  plausibly  argue  are  hallucinations,  and  they  speculate  that  such  experiences  cannot  be  caused  by  normal  perceptual  processes  for  those  are  restricted  by  opponent  processing.  

Page 15: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  15  

experiences  had  whilst  perceiving  the  world.  The  difference  between  them  is  simply  

that  hallucinations  are  had  when  not  perceiving.  

We  have  just  seen  how  the  common-­‐kind  view  of  perception  entails  that  one  

can  re-­‐create  the  same  mental  type  of  perceptual  experience  had  during  perception  

without  perception  taking  place.  So  we  have  seen  how  the  common-­‐kind  theory  of  

perception  motivates  the  traditional,  common-­‐kind  conception  of  hallucination.  

However,  as  we  will  now  see,  it  is  often  the  case  that  the  traditional  conception  of  

hallucination  is  assumed  and  then  used  to  argue  for  the  common-­‐kind  view  of  

perception.  Thus  the  common  kind  theory  of  perception  supports  the  common-­‐kind  

conception  of  hallucination,  but  also  vice  versa.  They  are  mutually  supporting.  (Of  

course  this  might  give  rise  to  the  concern  that  there  is  no  independent  motivation  

for  either—a  thought  that  will  be  explored  in  section  four  below.)  

The  famous  “argument  from  hallucination”  is  used  to  motivate  one  particular  

form  of  the  common-­‐kind  theory:  the  sense-­‐data  theory.  I  will  elucidate  that  

argument  before  going  on  to  look  at  a  variant  of  that  argument  that  supports  

another  form  of  the  common-­‐kind  theory  that  is  more  popular  today  than  the  sense-­‐

data  theory:  representationalism.  

The  sense-­‐data  theory  claims  that  when  we  have  a  perceptual  experience—

be  it  one  involved  in  perception  or  hallucination—we  are  immediately  aware  of  

nonphysical,  mind-­‐dependent  objects  called  sense-­‐data.  These  objects  are  such  that  

if  they  appear  to  us  to  be  some  way,  then  those  objects  are  that  way.  While  

nonmental  physical  objects  like  tables  and  chairs  can  seem  to  us  to  be  one  way  and  

yet  be  another,  no  appearance-­‐reality  distinction  exists  when  it  comes  to  sense-­‐data.  

The  sense-­‐data  are  said  to  resemble  and  represent  the  physical  mind-­‐independent  

objects  in  at  least  some  respects—such  as  shape,  size,  and  colour.  In  the  case  where  

we  are  perceiving  the  physical  mind-­‐independent  world,  the  immediate  awareness  

Page 16: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  16  

of  these  sense-­‐data  allows  us  to  be  mediately  aware  of  physical  mind-­‐independent  

objects  in  the  world.  

  Although  the  term  “sense-­‐data”  principally  refers  to  mental  objects,  it  has  

been,  rather  confusingly,  also  used  to  refer  to  the  immediate  objects  of  perception,  

whatever  they  are—for  example,  by  G.  E.  Moore.  When  used  in  this  way,  “sense-­‐

data”  can  refer  to  physical  mind-­‐dependent  objects,  or  to  their  surfaces,  or  to  

patterns  of  light  on  the  retina.  However,  this  latter  usage  has,  for  the  most  part,  lost  

favour,  and  sense-­‐data  are  now  almost  always  taken  to  be  the  postulated  immediate,  

nonphysical,  mind-­‐dependent  objects  of  perception.  This  is  how  I  will  use  the  term  

from  now  on.  Thus  one  should  note  that  sense-­‐data  are  not  to  be  identified  with  the  

patterns  of  light  on  the  retina,  the  early  visual  signals  or  representations  in  the  

brain,  or  brain  states.  Unlike  these,  sense-­‐data  are  nonphysical  objects  in  the  mind  

that  we  are  aware  of.  They  have  many  of  the  properties  that  the  objects  we  typically  

take  ourselves  to  be  aware  of,  like  tables  and  chairs,  have—they  have  shapes  and  

sizes  and  colours—but  not  others,  such  as  the  property  of  being  made  of  wood  or  

being  a  chair.  Although  sense-­‐data  have  properties  like  brownness  and  squareness,  

they  do  not  exist  in  physical  space.  They  inhabit  the  realm  of  each  person’s  mind.  

  Many  people  have  thought  that  a  theory  that  postulates  queer  metaphysical  

entities  like  sense-­‐data  has  a  high  cost  to  bear.  So  why  in  the  past  did  so  many  

people  believe  such  a  theory?  (Sense-­‐data  theory  was  the  dominant  theory  in  the  

first  half  of  the  twentieth  century  and  arguably  for  some  time  before  that.)  The  

answer  is  that  the  argument  from  hallucination  was  thought  to  be  an  exceptionally  

powerful  reason  to  believe  that  it  was  true.  Before  going  on  to  examine  that  

argument,  we  will  consider  briefly  the  distinction  between  mediate  and  immediate  

perception  and  mediate  and  immediate  awareness.  

  What  is  it  to  perceive  immediately,  and  what  is  it  to  perceive  mediately?  If  

one  perceives  an  object  immediately,  then  one  perceives  it  without  perceiving  any  

Page 17: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  17  

other,  intermediary,  object.  And  if  one  perceives  an  object  mediately,  one  perceives  

that  object  in  virtue  of  perceiving  some  other,  intermediary  object.  (The  same  goes,  

mutatis  mutandis,  for  mediate  and  immediate  awareness.)  

  We  typically  think  that  perception  is  immediate.  I  see  tables  and  chairs,  

daggers  and  people,  but  not  in  virtue  of  seeing  other  things.  Thus  it  is  the  notion  of  

mediate  perception  that  requires  further  elucidation.  Are  there  any  examples  of  

mediate  perception  that  we  know  from  everyday  life,  outside  of  philosophical  

theorizing,  which  can  help  us  understand  this  notion?  I  believe  that  there  are.  One  

example  is  perceiving  myself  in  virtue  of  perceiving  my  reflection  in  a  mirror.  A  

second  is  perceiving  Partick  Thistle  football  team  by  perceiving  the  television  screen  

showing  the  match  they  are  playing  in.  Although  in  our  more  reflective  moments  we  

are  aware  that  we  are  not  directly  seeing  our  visage  or  our  team  scoring  a  goal,  we  

often  don’t  give  this  a  second  thought,  and  all  our  attention  is  focused  on  the  

mediate  object.  Likewise  the  sense-­‐data  theorist  will  say  that  normally  we  don’t  

think  about  or  pay  attention  to  our  sense-­‐data,  focusing  only  on  the  mediate  objects  

in  the  physical  world;  but  in  our  more  reflective  moments,  we  can  come  to  

appreciate  that  in  fact  we  are  only  aware  of  such  objects  in  virtue  of  being  aware  of  

sense-­‐data.  

  The  sense-­‐data  theory,  with  its  rich  ontology,  comprising  both  mind-­‐

independent  physical  objects  and  mind-­‐dependent  nonphysical  objects  (sense-­‐

data),  is  motivated  by  the  argument  from  hallucination,  in  which  the  notion  of  

hallucination  in  play  is  the  common-­‐kind  conception.  Recall  that  this  was  that  

hallucinations  are  phenomenally  and  representationally  just  like  experiences  

involved  in  perceiving  the  world,  and  so  are  of  the  same  mental  type.  The  argument  

from  hallucination  can  be  rendered  as  follows:  

  Premise  1   When  I  hallucinate,  I  am  not  aware  of  any  mind-­‐independent,  

physical  object.  

Page 18: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  18  

  Premise  2   When  I  hallucinate,  I  am  nonetheless  aware  of  something.  

  Conclusion  1   When  I  hallucinate,  I  must  be  aware  of  a  mind-­‐dependent,  

nonphysical  mental  object—a  sense-­‐datum.  

  Premise  3   Experiences  that  are  phenomenally  indistinguishable  are  of  

exactly  the  same  type,  qua  mental  state.  

  Premise  4   If  two  experiences  are  of  exactly  the  same  type,  qua  mental  

state,  and  one  involves  being  aware  of  a  mind-­‐dependent,  

nonphysical  object,  then  the  other  also  does.  

  Premise  5   For  every  nonhallucinatory  experience  there  is  a  phenomenally  

identical  hallucinatory  experience.  

  Conclusion  2   All  perceptual  experience,  hallucinatory  and  nonhallucinatory,  

involves  awareness  of  a  mind-­‐dependent,  nonphysical  object—

a  sense-­‐datum.  

The  argument  is  valid  (thus  if  the  premises  are  true,  then  the  conclusion  must  also  

be  true),  but  the  conclusion  is  true  only  if  all  the  premises  are  true.  And  almost  every  

premise  of  this  argument  has  been  questioned,  with  the  possible  exception  of  the  

first.  

Premise  2  is  one  of  the  most  important  premises  in  the  argument.  It  can  be  

challenged  by  claiming  that  although  when  we  hallucinate  we  seem  to  be  aware  of  

something,  perhaps  it  only  just  seems  as  if  we  are  aware  of  something.  Perhaps  we  

are  really  aware  of  nothing.  In  truth  it  can  be  hard  to  decide  between  premise  2  and  

the  thought  that  we  are  aware  of  nothing  in  hallucination,  although  defenders  of  

both  sides  often  loudly  proclaim  that  their  view  is  obviously  correct.  Suppose  that  

you  hallucinate  a  patch  of  red.  You  can  have  such  a  hallucination—of  the  afterimage  

variety—by  staring  at  a  patch  of  green  for  about  a  minute  and  then  blinking  a  few  

times  and  looking  at  a  white  wall,  whereupon  you  should  experience  an  afterimage  

Page 19: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  19  

of  a  red  patch.  The  phenomenal  character  of  such  a  hallucination  can  be  intense  and  

vivid,  particularly  when  one  creates  special  conditions  for  producing  afterimage  

experiences.  For  example,  if  one  creates  a  black  boundary  on  a  white  piece  of  paper  

of  the  right  shape  and  size  so  that  one’s  afterimage  seems  to  fit  perfectly  within  the  

boundary  when  one  faces  it,  then  one’s  afterimage  is  particularly  intense.11  Fixate  on  

the  cross  in  the  centre  of  the  green  patch  in  figure  1.3  for  at  least  one  minute,  then  

blink  a  few  times,  and  then  fixate  on  the  cross  in  the  middle  of  the  white  patch  

surrounded  by  the  black  square.  

 

 

Figure  1.3:  A  stimulus  for  generating  strong  afterimages  

 

From  the  first-­‐person  point  of  view,  it  is  exceedingly  tempting  to  think  that  

you  are  aware  of  a  pink  patch,  particularly  because,  when  having  a  strong  

afterimage,  it  seems  just  like  what  it  is  like  to  be  aware  of  a  pink  patch  when  you  are  

seeing.  (Weaker  afterimages  are  like  seeing  unsaturated  or  slightly  transparent  

patches.)  One  might  think  that  if  there  is  awareness  of  a  patch  of  pink  in  the  case  of  

perceiving  pink,  and  it  seems  to  you  just  exactly  the  same  in  the  hallucinatory  case,  

then  it  involves  awareness  of  a  patch  of  pink  too.  What  more  might  there  be  to  being  

aware  of  a  patch  of  pink  if  not  its  seeming  that  way  to  you?  Moreover,  when  having  

                                                                                                               11  See  Daw  (1962).  

Page 20: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  20  

such  after-­‐images,  people  report  being  aware  of  a  patch  of  pink.  Are  we  to  tell  them  

that  they  are  wrong  about  their  own  minds?  And  how  else  do  we  explain  that  they  

report  a  patch  of  pink,  rather  than  some  other  colour?  However,  one  has  to  

recognise  that  if  such  reports  are  correct,  such  patches  of  pink  are  not  physical,  

mind-­‐independent  patches  of  pinkness.  And  they  are  certainly  not  patches  of  

pinkness  in  the  brain,  which  resolutely  remains  shades  of  grey.  If  there  are  such  

patches  of  pink,  then  they  really  are  peculiar  mental  objects  that  clearly  don’t  

inhabit  physical  public  space.  In  light  of  the  postulation  of  these  metaphysically  

peculiar  objects,  the  opposing  view—that  one  merely  seems  to  be  aware  of  a  patch  

of  pink  in  the  hallucinatory  case—can  start  to  seem  more  attractive.  

  Those  who  believe  that  we  should  reject  premise  2  can  nonetheless  construct  

another  version  of  the  argument  from  hallucination,  which  does  not  have  the  sense-­‐

data  theory  of  perception  as  its  conclusion  but  has  a  claim  consistent  with  the  other  

main  form  of  the  common-­‐kind  theory—a  representationalist  common-­‐kind  

theory—as  its  conclusion.  This  argument  runs  as  follows:  

  Premise  1   When  I  hallucinate,  I  am  not  aware  of  the  mind-­‐independent  

world.  

  Premise  2   When  I  hallucinate,  nonetheless  the  world  perceptually  seems  

to  be  a  certain  way.  

  Premise  3   If  I  am  in  a  state  in  which  the  world  perceptually  seems  to  be  a  

certain  way,  but  I  am  not  aware  of  the  mind-­‐independent  

world,  then  I  am  in  a  state  that  perceptually  represents  the  

world  to  be  a  certain  way.  

  Conclusion  1   When  I  hallucinate,  I  am  in  a  state  that  represents  the  world  to  

be  a  certain  way.  

Page 21: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  21  

  Premise  4   Experiences  that  are  phenomenally  indistinguishable  are  of  

exactly  the  same  type,  qua  mental  state.  

  Premise  5   If  two  experiences  are  of  exactly  the  same  type,  qua  mental  

state,  and  one  involves  representing  the  world  to  be  a  certain  

way,  then  the  other  does  too.  

  Premise  6   For  every  nonhallucinatory  experience  there  is  a  phenomenally  

indistinguishable  hallucinatory  experience.  

  Conclusion  2   All  perceptual  experience,  hallucinatory  and  nonhallucinatory,  

involves  having  a  perceptual  experience  that  represents  the  

world  to  be  a  certain  way.  

  Conclusion  3   For  every  nonhallucinatory  experience  that  represents  the  

world  to  be  a  certain  way  there  is  a  hallucinatory  experience  

that  represents  it  to  be  that  way  too.  

Common-­‐kind  representationalism  is  perhaps  the  most  widely  held  theory  of  

perception  today.  According  to  that  view,  perceptual  experiences  represent  the  

world  to  be  a  certain  way—where  the  notion  of  representation  is  spelled  out  in  

terms  of  accuracy  conditions  (as  discussed  in  section  1)  or  in  terms  of  how  things  

perceptually  seem  to  a  subject.12  In  addition,  it  says  that  the  same  mental  type  of  

experience  is  had  in  hallucination  and  perception.  (By  calling  this  view  “common-­‐

kind  representationalism,”  I  wish  to  contrast  it  with  a  view  whose  commitment  is  

just  to  the  minimal  claim  that  at  least  some  experiences  represent  the  world.  It  is  

possible  to  hold  such  a  view  and  not  be  a  common-­‐kind  theorist.)  

  Common-­‐kind  representationalism  differs  from  sense-­‐data  theory.  

Although  on  both  views  when  one  has  a  perceptual  experience  the  world  is  

represented,  on  the  common-­‐kind  representationalist  view  an  experience  does  not                                                                                                                  12  See  footnote  5.  

Page 22: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  22  

consist  of  being  aware  of  mental  objects  or  sense-­‐data.  One  particular  variety  of  

common-­‐kind  representationalism,  popular  of  late,  consists  of  the  further  claim  that  

one  is  simply  aware  of  what  the  state  represents:  the  apparent  physical  world  

around  one.  It  claims  that  all  mental  aspects  of  perceptual  experience  are  

representational,  and  thus  perceptual  representation  can  explain  the  nature  of  

phenomenal  character.13  Phenomenal  character  is  taken  to  be  identical  to,  or  to  

supervene  on,  the  representational  content  of  experience.14  So  popular  is  this  view  

that  it,  and  it  alone,  is  sometimes  referred  to  by  the  name  “representationalism”.  It  is  

also  known  as  “strong  representationalism.”  However,  in  this  essay  I  use  

“representationalism”  to  refer  to  the  more  general  type  of  common-­‐kind  theory  that  

may  be  held  with  or  without  these  extra  commitments.  

Contrasting  with  strong  representationalism  is  the  common-­‐kind  

representationalist  view  that  the  phenomenal  character  of  experience  is  at  least  to  

some  degree  independent  of  what  one’s  experience  represents.  One  version  of  this  

view  is  that  phenomenal  character  is  a  property  of  experience  that  one  can  be  aware  

of  in  addition  to,  and  independently  of,  what  the  experience  represents,  for  it  can  

represent  different  things  in  different  circumstances,  and  indeed  in  some  

circumstancs  it  may  not  represent  anything  at  all.  This  view  of  experience  is  quite  

like  that  of  the  sense-­‐datum  view  for  both  posit  awareness  of  something  over  and  

above  what  the  experience  represents.  However,  this  view—sometimes  called  the  

qualia  view—insists  that,  in  addition  to  what  the  experience  represents,  we  are  

aware  only  of  the  properties  of  experience,  that  can  (but  needn’t)  represent  the  

                                                                                                               13  Recent  proponents  of  this  view  include  Tye  (1995),  Dretske  (1995)  and  Lycan  (1996).  See  also  Macpherson  and  Platchias  (forthcoming).  14  Supervenience  is  a  metaphysical  relation  that  comes  in  different  specific  kinds,  but  common  to  all  is  the  idea  that  if  one  group  of  properties  supervenes  on  another,  then  there  can  be  no  difference  in  the  supervenient  properties  without  a  difference  in  those  that  they  supervene  on  –  the  subvenient  properties.  Sometimes  it  is  also  specified  that  the  supervenient  properties  must  in  some  way  be  dependent  on  the  subvenient  properties  and  not  vice  versa.  

Page 23: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  23  

physical  world.  This  is  unlike  the  sense-­‐data  view  according  to  which  we  are,  in  

addition,  aware  in  experience  of  mental  objects  and  their  properties.  

Common-­‐kind  representationalists  can  hold  a  variety  of  positions  concerning  

the  relation  between  experiential  states  and  physical  brain  states.  They  can  be  

physicalist  or  dualist.  However,  a  perceived  virtue  of  the  theory  is  that  it  is  possible  

for  it  to  be  compatible  with  physicalism.  Among  the  physicalist  versions  of  the  view  

are,  on  the  one  hand,  those  that  hold  the  mental  states  of  a  person  are  determined  

by  the  intrinsic  nature  of  that  person’s  brain  and,  on  the  other,  those  that  hold  that  

the  relations  that  brain  states  bear  to  things  outside  the  body  is  vital.  This  latter  

view  arises  because  many  theories  of  representation  claim  that  what  a  brain  state  

represents  is  determined  crucially  by  causal,  counterfactual,  historical,  or  

evolutionary  relations  that  a  type  of  brain  state  bears  to  the  things  that  it  

represents,  and  that  it  is  what  the  brain  state  represents  that  determines  what  kind  

of  mental  state  it  is.  

  This  second  argument  from  hallucination  seems  more  plausible  than  the  first.  

The  first  two  premises  appear  to  be  true.  The  third  premise  is  a  common  definition  

of  perceptual  representation,  although  not  agreed  on  by  all  (see  note  5).  The  most  

serious  attempt  to  undermine  the  conclusion,  I  believe,  comes  from  denying  the  

truth  of  premise  4.  This  is  the  premise  that  disjunctivists  deny.  I  will  explore  that  

position  in  section  4.  

  To  summarise  this  section,  common-­‐kind  theories  of  perception  hold  that  the  

experiences  had  in  perception  are,  qua  mental  states,  exactly  the  same  type  as  those  

had  in  hallucination.  The  difference  between  them  is  just  that  one  is  had  when  

hallucinating,  and  the  other  when  perceiving.  The  sense-­‐data  theory  form  of  the  

common-­‐kind  theory  takes  these  perceptual  experiences  to  consist  in  a  direct  

awareness  of  nonphysical,  mind-­‐dependent  objects  that  represent  the  world.  Sense-­‐

data  theorists  therefore  take  perceptual  experiences  to  be  nonphysical  mental  states  

Page 24: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  24  

that  are  caused  by  brain  states.  They  are  dualists,  for  they  believe  that  there  are  

distinctive  mental  and  nonmental  (physical)  objects  or  properties.  The  

representationalist  version  of  the  common-­‐kind  theory  takes  experiences  to  consist  

in  perceptual  states  that  represent  the  world.  These  representational  states  are  

often  held  to  be  identical  to  brain  states,  thus  allowing  representationalists  to  resist  

dualism  and  hold  a  physicalist  view.  One  can  see  that  whether  or  not  one  agrees  

with  common-­‐kind  theories,  the  motivation  for  them  stems  from  the  common-­‐kind  

conception  of  hallucination  –  that  hallucination  is  the  same  kind  of  perceptual  

experience,  qua  mental  state,  that  is  had  when  perceiving  the  world.  

  The  common-­‐kind  theories  therefore  explain  the  difference  between  cases  of  

perception  and  cases  of  hallucination  not  by  reference  to  the  nature  of  the  

perceptual  experiences  had  in  each  but,  typically,  by  means  of  the  differing  origin  of  

the  experiences  or  their  relation  to  the  world.  The  most  well-­‐known  theory  that  

explains  the  difference  in  this  manner  is  the  causal  theory  of  perception,  which  is  

very  frequently  used  to  supplement  the  common-­‐kind  theory.  The  causal  theory  

claims  that  

A  subject  S  sees  an  object  O  if  and  only  if  

(1)  S  has  a  visual  experience  E  that  represents  O,  and  

(2)  E  is  caused  in  an  appropriate  manner  by  O.  

Much  philosophical  labour  has  gone  into  spelling  out  to  what  extent  accurate  

representation  of  O  is  required  and  what  account  of  suitable  causation  can  be  

given.15  But  we  can  ignore  the  details  of  this  debate  for  our  purposes.  We  turn  now  

to  consider  the  epistemological  implications  of  the  common-­‐kind  conception  of  

hallucination.  

                                                                                                                 15  See  e.g.  Lewis  (1980).  

Page 25: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  25  

3  The  Epistemological  Upshot  of  the  Common-­‐Kind  Conception  of  

Hallucination  

The  common-­‐kind  conception  of  hallucination  has  been  used  to  motivate  skepticism.  

Indeed,  the  argument  that  uses  this  notion  of  hallucination  is  perhaps  the  most  

famous  argument  in  all  philosophy.  Descartes,  in  his  meditations,  entertains  the  

thought  that  an  evil  dæmon  or  genius  “of  the  utmost  power  and  cunning  has  

employed  all  his  energies  in  order  to  deceive  me”.  He  imagines  that  at  least  as  part  

of  this  deception,  the  dæmon  has  been  deceiving  his  senses  by  causing  him  to  

hallucinate.  At  the  same  time,  we  are  asked  to  consider  that  these  hallucinations  

may  not  correspond  to  the  way  reality  really  is.  In  consequence,  Descartes  asks  us  to  

consider  how  we  know  that  the  world  around  us  is  as  we  believe  it  to  be.  How  do  we  

know  that  we  are  not  merely  hallucinating  the  existence  of  such  a  world,  for  couldn’t  

we  undergo  the  same  perceptual  experience  when  hallucinating  that  we  do  when  

perceiving?  Modern  philosophical  versions  of  the  idea  consider  whether  we  might  

be  a  brain  in  a  vat  stimulated  into  hallucinating  by  an  evil  scientist.  Versions  of  this  

idea  also  occur  in  popular  culture,  notably,  for  example,  in  the  film  The  Matrix.  

  Philosophers  have  formulated  Descartes’s  arguments  in  many  ways.  One  way  

is  as  follows:  

Premise  1   When  I  perceive  and  when  I  hallucinate,  I  have  the  same  type  

of  perceptual  experience,  qua  mental  state.  

Premise  2   My  hallucination  doesn’t  give  me  knowledge  of  how  the  world  

is  around  me.  

Premise  3   If  two  perceptual  experiences  are  the  same,  qua  mental  states,  

and  one  cannot  give  you  knowledge  of  the  world  around  you,  

then  the  other  cannot.  

Page 26: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  26  

Conclusion     My  perceptual  experience  involved  in  perception  cannot  give  

me  knowledge  of  the  world  around  me.  

Skepticism  of  the  sort  engendered  by  the  common-­‐kind  notion  of  hallucination  at  

play  in  these  arguments  has  been  challenged  in  many  ways.  Premise  3  has  been  

challenged  by  externalists,  who  claim  that  having  one  type  of  mental  state  on  some  

occasions  can  fail  to  give  one  knowledge,  yet  having  the  same  type  on  other  

occasions  can  provide  knowledge.  Differing  claims  about  the  circumstances  in  which  

having  a  mental  state  provides  knowledge  yield  different  forms  of  externalism.  

One  externalist  view,  for  example,  is  known  as  “sensitivity”.  According  to  this  

view,  an  experience  can  give  one  knowledge  only  if  it  leads  to  the  formation  of  a  

belief  that  is  true  and  is  sensitive,  in  a  particular  way,  to  the  truth  and  falsity  of  what  

is  believed.  To  explain  in  what  way  your  true  belief  must  be  sensitive,  imagine  a  

range  of  circumstances  that  are  not  too  different  from  those  that  obtain  in  the  actual  

world,  and  imagine  that  in  those  circumstances  what  you  actually  believe  is  false.  If,  

in  all  those  not  too  different  circumstances,  you  would  no  longer  hold  the  belief  in  

question,  then  your  belief  is  sensitive  to  the  truth  or  falsity  of  what  is  believed,  and  

in  the  actual  world,  you  know  what  you  believe.  If  you  aren’t  sensitive  in  that  way,  

then  you  don’t  know.  Philosophers  would  express  this  thought  by  saying  that  your  

belief  is  sensitive  if,  in  the  nearest  possible  worlds  in  which  what  is  believed  is  false,  

you  would  no  longer  hold  the  belief.  Another  externalist  view  is  “safety”,  which  

claims  that  an  experience  can  give  one  knowledge  only  if  it  leads  to  the  formation  of  

a  belief  that  is  such  that  in  most  of  the  nearby  possible  worlds  in  which  one  holds  

the  belief,  the  belief  is  true.16  We  can  now  see  why  these  views  reject  premise  3.  In  

both  of  these  views,  one  instance  of  a  particular  kind  of  belief—for  example,  the  

kind  of  belief  that  involves  holding  it  to  be  true  that  there  is  tea  in  the  teapot—could  

be  safe  and/or  sensitive  and  hence  amount  to  knowledge  while  another  instance  

would  fall  short.  Suppose  now,  as  is  plausible  on  the  common-­‐kind  view,  that                                                                                                                  16  For  a  survey  of  such  positions,  see  Pritchard  (2008).  

Page 27: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  27  

instances,  qua  mental  state,  of  the  same  kind  of  experience  caused  these  beliefs—

such  as  the  visual  experience  as  of  steam  rising  from  the  teapot’s  spout.  One  

instance  of  that  experience  would  not  provide  knowledge,  but  the  other  would.  

Externalists  often  claim  that  I  can  know  something  even  if  I  don’t  know  that  I  

know  it  because  I  can’t  rule  out  that  I  am  hallucinating.  They  claim  that  requiring  

that  I  know  that  I  know  something,  and  hence  requiring  that  I  know  that  I  am  not  

hallucinating,  is  too  strong  a  condition  to  place  on  the  conditions  required  for  

knowledge  and  that  a  sensitivity  or  safety  condition  is  all  that  is  required.  

  Some  people  have  wished  to  resist  skepticism  but  are  unsatisfied  with  the  

ways  in  which  externalism  does  so.  Fortunately,  for  such  people,  alternative  views  of  

hallucination  offer  a  chance  of  showing  other  ways  to  resist  the  skeptical  conclusion.  

 

4  Disjunctivism  and  Alternative  Views  of  Hallucination  

Recall  the  common-­‐kind  conception  of  hallucination,  according  to  which  

hallucination  involves  having  exactly  the  same  kind  of  perceptual  experience,  qua  

mental  state,  as  one  has  in  perception.  As  we  saw  in  section  2,  backing  for  this  view  

comes  from  the  thought  that  perceptual  experiences  involved  in  perceiving  occur  at  

the  end  of  a  causal  chain  of  events—and  you  could  create  the  same  perceptual  

experiences  by  re-­‐creating  the  conditions  at  the  end  of  the  chain.  One  could  do  this  

either  by  directly  creating  just  those  end  conditions  or  by  creating  any  intermediate  

step  in  the  chain.  The  evidence  that  is  often  cited  for  thinking  that  this  is  true  is  (a)  

the  nomological  possibility  of  such  cases  and  (b)  the  actual  existence  of  

hallucinations,  which  for  the  traditional  philosopher  will  include  the  following:  

§ clinical  hallucinations  (hallucinations  that  occur  in  nonnormal  subjects  

suffering  from  recognised  psychological  abnormalities,  such  as  people  with  

Page 28: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  28  

Parkinson’s  disease,  schizophrenics,  and  people  suffering  from  delusions  of  

various  kinds)    

§ dream  experiences  

§ afterimages  

But  does  the  existence  of  these  kinds  of  cases  really  back  up  the  traditional  common-­‐

kind  view  of  hallucination?  One  might  argue  not.  One  might  argue  that  they  do  so  

only  if  you  take  a  very  particular  view  of  them.  This  is  how  “experiential  

disjunctivists”  argue.  They  claim  that  only  if  one  accepts  the  common-­‐kind  theory  of  

perception  will  one  be  tempted  to  adopt  the  common-­‐kind  conception  of  

hallucination.  Thus  one  doesn’t  have  to  hold  that  hallucination  involves  the  very  

same  type  of  perceptual  experience  that  one  has  in  veridical  perception.  And  one  

may  even  go  on  to  try  to  deny  the  nomological  or  metaphysical  possibility  of  cases  of  

hallucination  as  the  common-­‐kind  theorist  conceives  of  them.  

  According  to  experiential  disjunctivists,  a  different  conception  of  

hallucination  has  been  overlooked.  This  alternative  is  that  when  one  hallucinates,  

one  goes  into  a  state  wherein  it  is  not  possible  to  know,  by  introspection  alone,  that  

one  is  not  veridically  perceiving—but,  qua  mental  state,  that  is  all  that  is  the  case.  

When  one  is  in  such  a  state,  one  is  said  to  be  in  a  state  that  possesses  the  “negative  

epistemic  property”.  The  reason  for  saying  that  in  hallucination  it  is  not  possible  to  

know  by  introspection  alone  that  one  is  not  veridically  perceiving  is  to  allow  for  the  

existence  of  some  cases  of  hallucination  where  we  come  to  know  by  other  means  

that  we  are  hallucinating.  In  such  cases,  we  may  come  to  know  because  someone  

tells  us  –  perhaps  a  trusted  doctor.  Or  we  may  notice  anomalies  among  our  

experience.  For  example,  we  may  be  unable  to  touch  the  dagger  that  visually  seems  

to  us  to  be  floating  in  midair.  Or  we  may  notice  bizarre  features  of  our  experience  

that  we  think  are  better  explained  by  hallucination  than  by  the  fact  that  the  world  

has  changed  to  allow  such  things  to  be  possible—for  example,  so  that  daggers  can  

hover  in  midair.  In  these  cases  we  are  not  using  introspection  alone  in  coming  to  

Page 29: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  29  

know  that  we  are  hallucinating.  We  are  using  it  together  with  general  knowledge  of  

the  way  the  world  is  and  the  way  experiences  ought  to  be  consistent  and  so  forth.  

Such  cases  can  still  count  as  hallucinations  for  the  disjunctivist.  for  these  cases  could  

still  be  ones  where  reflection  on  the  nature  of  the  experience  alone,  without  

additional  general  knowledge  of  contingent  facts  about  the  world,  is  such  that  it  is  

not  possible  for  the  subject  to  know  that  he  or  she  is  not  perceiving.  

The  lynchpin  of  the  disjunctive  theory  is  that  one  does  not  go  into  the  same  

perceptual  experiential  state,  qua  mental  state,  when  hallucinating  that  one  would  

go  into  were  one  perceiving  what  one  seems  to  be  perceiving.  Of  course,  the  state  

that  one  goes  into  when  one  perceives  the  world  also  has  the  negative  epistemic  

property,  but  it  has  other  mental  properties  besides  that,  which  the  hallucination  

state  lacks.  The  nonhallucinatory  state  is  a  state  of  perceiving,  and  it  is  also  a  state  

that  has  a  certain  phenomenal  character,  and  depending  on  what  else  one  thinks,  it  

may  mental  properties  as  well.  The  hallucinatory  state  lacks  those  properties.17  

Moreover,  according  to  experiential  disjunctivism,  hallucinatory  states  would  

not  be  the  same  type  of  state,  qua  mental  state,  as  states  involved  in  perceiving,  even  

if  the  brain  states  involved  in  perception  and  hallucination  were  identical.  This  is  

because,  according  to  the  disjunctivist,  perception  doesn’t  happen  when  you  have  

the  right  causal  connections  between  an  appropriate  perceptual  experience  and  the  

world.  Perceptual  experience  is  not  the  end  state  in  a  causal  chain.  Rather,  one’s  

perceptual  experience  comprises  the  whole  process:  what  goes  on  in  your  head,  the  

things  in  the  world  seen,  and  any  causal  connections  between  the  latter  and  the  

former.  So  even  if  the  whole  brain  is  in  the  very  same  state  when  hallucinating  as  it  

is  when  perceiving,  the  occurrence  of  this  brain  state  does  not  constitute  conditions  

sufficient  for  perceptual  experience.  

                                                                                                               17  See  Martin  (2004,  2006)  and  Fish  (2008).  

Page 30: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  30  

Many  philosophers  who  hold  the  common-­‐kind  view  don’t  just  disagree  with  

experiential  disjunctivism—they  find  it  extremely  unpalatable.  One  reason  that  may  

explain  this  is  that  it  is  not  easy  to  form  an  intuitively  appealing  picture  of  

perception  and  hallucination  as  the  disjunctivist  conceives  it.  In  part  this  may  be  

because  the  common-­‐kind  view  of  perception  has  a  strong  intuitive  pull  and  has  

deep  roots  within  traditional  Western  philosophy.  Thus,  to  give  experiential  

disjunctivism  as  much  plausibility  as  possible,  I  will  try  to  paint  as  appealing  and  

clear  a  picture  of  perception  and  hallucination,  as  the  experiential  disjunctivist  

conceives  of  it,  by  means  of  elaborating  on  a  metaphor  concerning  the  role  of  the  

brain  in  perception.  

The  common-­‐kind  theorist  could  think  of  the  brain  as  a  machine  that  has  the  

task  of  producing  perceptual  experiences,  and  it  is  by  having  these  experiences  that  

we  can  be  aware  of  the  world,  at  least  in  certain  circumstances,  namely,  when  the  

brain  is  producing  the  right  kind  of  experience  and  is  causally  connected  to  the  

world  in  the  right  way.  The  disjunctivist  views  the  brain’s  role  differently.  One  might  

think  of  it  as  a  machine,  but  not  one  that  produces  experiences  as  output.  Rather,  the  

brain  can  be  thought  of  as  the  machinery  required  to  focus  and  attune  a  lens  in  

order  to  allow  us  to  see.  The  nature  of  the  machinery  and  the  lens  is  highly  complex  

because  not  only  does  what  we  see  change  all  the  time,  but  the  conditions  for  seeing  

change  too,  and  the  best  adjustment  of  the  lens  for  seeing  different  things,  and  for  

seeing  the  same  things  in  different  conditions,  varies.  Thus  the  brain  is  constantly  

adjusting  itself  in  response  to  the  way  the  world  is  based  on  its  principles  of  

operation.  When  the  brain  adjusts  itself  in  the  right  way  in  response  to  the  world,  

then  the  brain  provides  a  transparent  window  onto  the  world—a  lens—allowing  the  

person  whose  brain  it  is  to  see  the  world.  In  this  situation,  one  sees  the  world  

directly;  there  is  nothing  else  of  which  one  is  aware,  no  representational  

intermediary,  no  machinery  of  the  brain,  no  lens.  In  this  situation,  one  has  a  

perceptual  experience  of  the  world,  but  that  experience  comprises  the  objects  and  

Page 31: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  31  

properties  that  you  directly  see  together  with  the  relationship  that  you  bear  to  

them—the  perceptual  relation.  The  perceptual  relation  obtains  because  the  lighting  

conditions  are  appropriate  and  because  the  brain  is  doing  what  it  needs  to  do  to  

allow  you  access  to  the  world.  

Of  course,  sometimes  the  brain  does  not  manage  this  extraordinary  feat.  

Sometimes  the  lens  is  not  focused  properly,  and  our  window  onto  the  world  distorts  

our  view  of  the  world.  When  we  see  in  a  distorted  manner,  we  are  undergoing  an  

illusion.  On  other  occasions  the  window  on  the  world  remains  opaque.  In  such  cases  

we  don’t  see.  But  during  some  of  these  occasions,  the  brain  is  in  a  configuration  that  

fools  us.  It  fools  us  by  putting  us  into  a  state  such  that  we  can’t  distinguish  that  state,  

by  introspection  alone,  from  veridical  perception.  In  other  words,  we  hallucinate.  

We  are  seeing  nothing,  but  the  configuration  of  our  brain  prevents  us  from  detecting  

this  by  introspection  alone.  18  

  This  view  is  experiential  disjunctivism.  As  it  is  sometimes  put,  the  view  is  

that  the  experience  in  the  “good  case”  (perception)  and  the  experience  in  the  “bad  

case”  (hallucination)  are  not  the  same  type  of  experience,  qua  mental  state.  One  is  an  

experience  of  seeing  the  world;  the  other  is  an  experience  that  involves  not  being  

able  to  know,  by  introspection  alone,  that  one  is  not  perceiving.  Experiential  

disjunctivists  hold  that  when  one  is  hallucinating  one’s  experience  lacks  

phenomenal  character  altogether,  for  all  there  is  in  common  between  the  

hallucination  and  its  perceptual  experiential  counterpart,  is  the  negative  epistemic  

fact.  The  idea  is  that  when  one  sees,  the  phenomenal  character  of  one’s  experience—

what  it  is  like  to  have  that  experience—is  constituted  by  the  properties  of  the  

objects  that  one  sees.  The  phenomenal  character  of  one’s  experience  when  one  

accurately  sees  a  red  teapot  (the  phenomenal  redness,  say)  is  constituted  by  (is  

simply)  a  property  of  the  physical  surface  of  the  teapot.  In  the  bad  case,  there  is  no  

physical  patch  of  red  in  objective  space  that  one  is  aware  of,  and  so  one’s  experience                                                                                                                  18  I  owe  this  metaphor  to  Imogen  Dickie,  who  suggested  a  form  of  it  in  conversation.  

Page 32: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  32  

cannot  have  that  phenomenal  character,  in  fact,  it  has  none  at  all.  This  is  why  the  

disjunctivist  often  emphasises  the  idea  that,  when  hallucinating,  all  there  is  to  being  

in  that  state  is  being  unable  to  tell  (by  introspection  alone)  that  one  is  not  

perceiving.  One  is  not  having  an  experience  with  the  phenomenal  character  that  one  

would  have  in  the  good  case.  

We  are  now  in  a  position  to  see  what  the  motivations  for  experiential  

disjunctivism  are.  First,  the  view  allows  that  perception  of  the  world  can  be  direct  

and  immediate.  Second,  some  believe  that  it  allows  us  to  give  a  naturalistic  account  

of  phenomenal  character:  phenomenal  character  is  identical  with  the  properties  of  

physical  objects  in  public  space.19  

A  third  motivation,  according  to  some  (but  not  all),  is  that  the  view  allows  us  

to  overcome  skepticism.  We  can  sketch  how  this  view  might  be  thought  to  do  by  

considering  that  as  the  experiences  in  the  good  case  and  the  bad  case  are  held  not  to  

be  the  same  in  all  mental  respects,  then  there  is  some  reason  to  think  that  the  

experiences  do  not  possess  the  same  epistemic  properties.20  Thus  one  can  think  that  

the  perceptual  experience  in  the  good  case  can  give  one  knowledge  of  the  world  

even  though  the  experience  in  the  bad  case  cannot.  Attributing  these  different  

epistemic  properties  to  the  experiences  might  seem  unproblematic,  for  on  this  view,  

the  mental  states  themselves,  qua  mental  states,  are  very  different.  Thus  epistemic  

differences  are  grounded  in  experiential  mental  differences,  and  an  important  

                                                                                                               19  Fish  (2009)  argues  for  this  view.  20  In  fact,  one  can  hold  an  epistemic  disjunctivst  view  without  being  an  experiential  or  phenomenal  character  disjunctivist  simply  by  holding  that  the  experiences  in  the  good  and  the  bad  case  have  different  epistemic  value.  However,  to  my  mind,  epistemic  disjunctivism  is  better  motivated  if  one  grounds  the  epistemic  difference  in  an  experiential  difference  or  difference  in  phenomenal  character,  because  then  one  has  an  explanation  for  the  different  epistemic  value  one  is  attributing  to  the  experiences,  and  one  needn’t  become  an  externalist  to  reply  to  skepticism  in  this  manner.  For  more  details  of  types  of  disjunctivism  and  their  relation,  see  Haddock  and  Macpherson  (2008b)  and  the  essays  in  Haddock  and  Macpherson  (2008a).  

Page 33: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  33  

internalist  requirement  is  met:  there  is  no  epistemic  difference  without  a  difference  

in  one’s  mental  life.  

  Of  course,  one  can  think  that  disjunctivism  does  not  deliver  the  goods.  Many  

complaints  against  it  have  been  made.  One  is  that  disjunctivism  does  not  explain  

how  direct  perception  and  awareness  come  about.  One  might  think  that  

disjunctivism  fails  to  provide  a  naturalistic  explanation  of  how  one  can  come  to  be  

aware  of  properties  of  the  external  world  in  perception,  even  if  it  has  a  naturalistic  

account  of  those  properties  to  proffer.  Another  is  that  it  cannot  provide  a  plausible  

account  of  cases  of  illusion  and  cases  of  partial  hallucination—cases  that  seem  to  

require  partial  direct  access.  A  third  is  that  the  view  does  not  make  good  the  notion  

of  “not  being  able  to  know  (by  introspection  alone)  that  one  is  not  perceiving”.  All  

these  issues  have  been  explored  at  length—see,  for  example,  the  essays  in  Haddock  

and  Macpherson  (2008a)  –  and  fall  outside  the  scope  of  this  introduction.  

  Last,  one  might  think  that  disjunctivism  does  not  promise  a  novel  and  

satisfying  reply  to  skepticism.  This  is  because,  although  the  theory  claims  that  the  

experiences  in  the  good  and  bad  cases  are  different,  these  differences  are  not  

manifest  to  the  subject  of  those  experiences,  and  thus  one  might  think  that  any  

epistemological  difference  between  the  states  is,  in  truth,  a  mere  externalist  one.  

One  could  think  that  the  subjects  themselves  cannot  have  different  reasons  available  

to  them  to  think  that  the  two  cases  are  different—no  reason  even  in  principle.  Thus  

the  theory  does  not  promise  a  good  nonexternalist  response  to  skepticism.  

  Debates  concerning  whether  disjunctivism  is  a  good  theory  are  ongoing.  (See  

the  essays  in  part  II  of  this  volume.)  For  the  purposes  of  this  introduction,  however,  

we  leave  this  debate  behind.  We  now  have  enough  of  an  understanding  of  

disjunctivism  to  see  how  reflection  on  the  view,  and  its  varieties,  opens  up  a  few  

different  conceptions  or  models  of  hallucination,  which  could  be  held  independently  

of  a  commitment  to  disjunctivism.  

Page 34: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  34  

  I  began  the  previous  section  by  outlining  the  common-­‐kind  view  of  

hallucination,  which  is  of  a  state  that  is  the  same  in  all  mental  respects  to  its  

nonhallucinatory  counterpart  perceptual  state,  in  particular  having  the  same  

phenomenal  character.  The  second  view  of  hallucination,  which  we  have  just  

encountered  when  considering  disjunctivism,  is  that  when  hallucinating,  one  lacks  

an  experience  with  phenomenal  character,  and  in  addition,  one  is  simply  unable  to  

know  in  principle,  by  reflection  alone,  that  one  is  not  perceiving.  Call  this  the  “strict  

disjunctive  conception”  of  hallucination.  

  A  third  view,  not  held  by  disjunctivists,  but  a  possible  view  of  hallucination  

inspired  by  modifying  the  strict  disjunctive  conception,  can  now  be  discerned.  It  is  

that  in  hallucination  one  lacks  an  experience  with  any  perception-­‐like  phenomenal  

character  but  believes  that  one  is  having  a  perceptual  experience  with  phenomenal  

character,  although  in  principle  one  could  come  to  know  otherwise,  by  reflection  

alone.  For  example,  it  could  be  that  were  one  to  pay  attention  to  one’s  mental  life  in  

the  right  way,  one  would  be  able  to  tell.  One  would  be  able  to  notice  that  really  one  

was  not  in  an  experiential  state  with  perceptual  phenomenal  character.  Call  this  the  

“contingent  disjunctive  conception”  of  hallucination.  

  Finally,  by  considering  the  idea  behind  the  contingent  disjunctive  conception,  

that  of  a  misidentified  state,  I  can  conceive  of  a  fourth  kind  of  hallucination.  This  is  

not  a  conception  of  hallucination  that  differs  from  the  counterpart  nonhallucinatory  

perceptual  experience  in  virtue  of  lacking  perception-­‐like  phenomenal  character;  it  

is  one  where  it  has  a  different  perception-­‐like  phenomenal  character  to  the  

counterpart  nonhallucinatory  perceptual  experience,  and  moreover,  the  subject  of  

the  state  does  not  appreciate  that  it  so  differs.  According  to  this  notion  of  

hallucination,  when  subjects  hallucinate,  they  don’t  have  a  perceptual  experience  of  

the  sort  that  they  would  have  were  they  perceiving  what  they  are  hallucinating.  

Instead  the  subject  is  in  another  mental  state  that  has  some  perception-­‐like  

phenomenal  character.  Candidate  mental  states  are  perceptual  imaginings  or  

Page 35: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  35  

perceptual  rememberings.  To  focus  on  the  case  of  visual  hallucination,  the  idea  is  

that  the  subject  is  visually  imagining  or  visually  remembering  but  goes  wrong  by  

identifying  that  state  as  being  a  perceptual  experience  when  it  is  not.  Visual  

imaginings  and  visual  rememberings  are  thought  to  be  different  from  perceptual  

experience  at  least  in  respect  of  their  liveliness  or  vivacity  of  phenomenal  character,  

which  is  said  to  be  weaker  than  that  of  perceptual  experience.21  They  may  be  

different  in  other  respects  too.  These  hallucinations  could  be  such  that  although  the  

subject  misidentifies  the  nature  of  their  experience  by  introspection,  it  might  not  be  

in  principle  impossible  for  the  subject  to  come  to  notice  the  misidentification  solely  

by  reflection  on  the  nature  of  the  subject’s  mental  state.  Call  this  conception  of  

hallucinations  the  “imagery/memory”  one.  

  With  these  three  further  conceptions  of  hallucination  now  articulated,  in  

addition  to  the  common-­‐kind  conception,  we  can  see  why  someone  might  say  that  

the  existence  of  the  following  cases  of  actual  hallucinations  does  not  show  that  

hallucinations  of  the  common-­‐kind  variety  exist:  

§ clinical  hallucinations  (hallucinations  that  occur  in  nonnormal  subjects  

suffering  from  recognised  psychological  abnormalities,  such  as  people  with  

Parkinson’s  disease,  schizophrenics,  and  people  suffering  from  delusions  of  

various  kinds)    

§ dream  experiences  

§ afterimages.  

This  is  because  these  could  be  cases  of  the  strict  disjunctive  conception,  the  

contingent  disjunctive  conception,  or  the  imagery/memory  conception.  Given  that,  

the  reason  to  believe  that  instances  of  common-­‐kind  hallucinations  are  possible  

should  not  be,  as  I  believe  it  has  sometimes  been,  the  existence  of  actual  instances  of  

                                                                                                               21  This  idea  was  famously  proffered  by  of  one  of  Auld  Scotia’s  favourite  sons,  David  Hume,  and  although  most  people  agree  that  intuitively  this  seems  right,  spelling  out  exactly  what  liveliness  and  vivacity  amounts  to  is  a  difficult  task.  I  will  not  undertake  it  here.  

Page 36: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  36  

hallucination.  Thus  we  now  simply  seem  to  be  in  the  position  of  having  four  

different  accounts  of  the  nature  of  actual  hallucinations  on  the  table,  without  reason  

to  choose  one  over  the  other.  

  One  way  forward  at  this  point  would  be  to  debate  the  merits  and  demerits  of  

the  common-­‐kind  and  disjunctive  theories.  However,  another  possibility  would  be  

to  see  if  psychology  and  neuroscience  can  be  of  assistance,  for  these  disciplines  have  

started  to  investigate  actual  hallucinations.  Moreover,  they  claim  that  they  have  

evidence  that  shows  the  existence  of  different  sorts  of  hallucination.  Clearly  this  

evidence  might  be  relevant  to  the  philosophical  debate.  In  turn,  the  four  conceptions  

of  hallucination  that  we  have  identified  via  philosophical  theorizing  might  be  of  

interest  to  psychologists  and  neuroscientists  because,  to  my  knowledge,  scientists  

have  not  considered  all  four  conceptions—only  two  of  them.  Thus  scientists  should  

welcome  the  elucidation  of  conceptions  of  hallucination  in  addition  to  those  they  

have  thus  far  considered,  for  those  conceptions  are  potentially  the  right  ones  of  

some  actual  hallucinations.  If  scientists  want  to  be  able  to  determine  the  nature  of  

particular  instances  of  actual  hallucinations,  then  they  should  make  sure  that  their  

evidence  rules  out  all  but  one  of  the  four  models  of  hallucination  that  I  have  just  

articulated.  

 

5  The  Role  of  Psychology  and  Neuroscience  

Consider  again  the  four  conceptions  of  hallucination  that  I  have  identified:  

(1) the  common-­‐kind  conception  

(2) the  strict  disjunctive  conception  

(3) the  contingent  disjunctive  conception  

(4) the  imagery/memory  conception  

Page 37: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  37  

I  believe  that  when  scientists  and  clinical  medics  have  considered  the  nature  of  

hallucinations  to  date,  they  have  considered  only  conceptions  (1)  and  (4).  And  they  

have  tried  to  determine  whether  instances  (or  certain  classes)  of  hallucinations  are  

of  type  (1)  or  type  (4).  I  know  of  no  accounts  of  hallucination  in  the  scientific  

literature  that  consider  other  conceptions.  When  I  have  explained  models  (2)  and  

(3)  to  scientists  and  clinicians  in  papers  delivered  at  conferences,  their  reaction  has  

confirmed  this.22  In  fact,  some  clinicians  expressed  moral  distaste  for  conceptions  

(2)  and  (3),  on  grounds  I  will  explain  later  in  this  section.  

  One  psychologist  who  argues  for  the  existence  of  the  common-­‐kind  

hallucination  is  Dominic  ffytche  (this  volume).  He  claims  that  hallucinations  in  

Charles  Bonnet  syndrome,  namely,  visual  hallucinations  found  in  subjects  soon  after  

serious  deterioration  in,  or  complete  loss  of,  their  vision,  are  of  type  (1).  These  

hallucinations  are  often  rich  and  detailed  and  have  bizarre  content.  In  line  with  my  

earlier  claim  that  scientists  consider  only  conceptions  (1)  and  (4)  of  hallucination,  

ffytche  considers  whether  Charles  Bonnet  hallucinations  are  instances  of  visual  

imagery  or  visual  memory,  which  he  claims  are  known  to  be  linked  to  activity  in  the  

frontal  and  parietal  lobes,  or  instances  of  visual  experiences,  which  he  claims  are  

known  to  be  linked  to  activity  in  visual  cortical  areas.  He  presents  evidence  that  the  

brain  activity  underlying  these  hallucinations  is  spontaneous  activity  in  the  visual  

cortex,  which,  by  his  lights,  provides  evidence  for  these  hallucinations  being  

instances  of  perceptual  experiences,  rather  than  visual  imagery.  

  If  one  is  confident  that  one  can  correlate  perceptual  experiences—or,  more  

plausibly,  perceptual  experiences  in  a  certain  modality—with  activity  in  one  area  of  

the  brain  and  instances  of  perceptual  imagery/memory  in  that  modality  with                                                                                                                  22  Macpherson,  F.  (September  2010),  “On  the  Origin  of  Hallucination:  Philosophical  Perspectives,”  invited  paper,  symposium  entitled  “On  the  Origin  of  Hallucination,”  2nd  Meeting  of  the  Federation  of  the  European  Societies  of  Neuropsychology  (FESN),  Amsterdam,  Netherlands;  and  Macpherson,  F.  (April  2010)  “Hallucinations:  A  Philosophical  Perspective,”  invited  paper  at  a  European  Science  Foundation  workshop  on  the  neural  and  cognitive  basis  of  hallucinations,  University  of  Granada,  Spain.  

Page 38: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  38  

activity  in  a  different  part  of  the  brain,  then  one  can  empirically  determine  which  

type  of  hallucinations  are  occurring  on  certain  occasions  by  determining  what  brain  

activity  is  occurring.  I  will  return  to  the  question  of  whether  one  is  right  to  think  that  

one  can  establish  such  correlations.  For  now,  note  that  this  is  a  common  

methodology  adopted  by  psychologists  when  trying  to  determine  whether  certain  

hallucinations  are  of  type  (1)  or  type  (4).  

Richard  Bentall  and  Filippo  Varese  (this  volume)  look  for  this  type  of  

evidence  in  auditory  hallucinations  –  a  type  of  hallucination  that  frequently  occurs  

in  schizophrenia.  They  want  to  determine  whether  auditory  hallucinations  consist  of  

auditory  experiences  of  voices  or  of  misattributions  of  people’s  own  inner  speech,  

which  they  classify  as  being  a  kind  of  auditory  imagery.  While  some  brain  imaging  

studies  favour  of  the  latter  view,  namely,  that  type  (4)  hallucinations  are  occurring,  

overall  the  results  are  unclear.  Bentall  and  Varese  attribute  the  lack  of  clear  

evidence  to  “methodological  challenges  and  oversimplistic  thinking  about  the  

nature  of  inner  speech.”  I  suspect  that  they  believe  that  while  inner  speech  and  brain  

activity  have  not  been  accurately  correlated  to  date,  such  correlations  could  be  

established  with  further  effort  and  then  clearer  results  could  be  obtained.  

Given  that  those  correlations  (if  indeed  they  exist)  have  not  yet  been  

identified,  Bentall  and  Varese  investigate  another  way  to  determine  whether  

auditory  hallucinations  are  of  type  (1)  or  type  (4):  by  using  behavioural  evidence.  

They  find  that,  compared  to  people  who  lack  auditory  hallucinations,  people  who  

have  auditory  hallucinations  are  (a)  more  likely  to  report  that  an  external  voice  is  

present  when  none  is  there  during  presentation  of  certain  stimuli,  such  as  white  

noise;  (b)  less  good  at  recalling  whether  certain  words  were  generated  by  

themselves,  by  others,  or  by  neither;  and  (c)  less  good  at  identifying  distorted  

versions  of  their  own  voice,  especially  when  the  content  of  the  speech  is  derogatory.  

This  suggests  that  hallucinators  are  less  good  at  determining  whether  or  not  an  

experience  is  generated  by  themselves.  This  is  known  as  “source  monitoring”.  The  

Page 39: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  39  

lack  of  good  source  monitoring  in  auditory  hallucinators  provides  some,  although  

not  conclusive,  evidence  for  the  view  that  auditory  hallucinations  arise  on  account  of  

a  failure  to  identify  auditory  imagery—in  these  cases,  self-­‐generated  inner  speech—

as  being  just  that.  At  least  it  provides  evidence  for  that  view  over  the  hypothesis  that  

the  patients  are  undergoing  perceptual  auditory  experiences  of  the  sort  they  would  

have  if  hearing  another  person  speak  out  loud.  

  To  summarise,  on  the  assumption  that  we  are  only  trying  to  decide  between  

(1),  the  common-­‐kind  conception  of  hallucination,  and  (4),  the  imagery/memory  

conception  of  hallucination,  two  possible  sorts  of  evidence  might  weigh  in  favour  of  

one  rather  than  the  other:  evidence  from  what  brain  state  the  person  is  in  and  

behavioural  evidence.  The  scientific  evidence  to  date  suggests  that  if  choosing  

between  these  two  options,  then  in  some  cases  we  should  favour  (1),  in  others  (4).  

Note,  in  addition,  that  if  there  are  hallucinations  of  type  (4),  then  a  particular  

method  of  treatment  for  such  hallucinations  becomes  worth  investigating:  teaching  

people  to  be  better  at  introspecting  their  experience  and  determining  whether  it  is  

imagery  and/or  whether  such  imagery  is  self-­‐generated.  Whether  such  a  treatment  

would  be  effective  for  type  (4)  hallucinations  is  an  empirical  matter,  but  in  principle,  

it  could  not  be  used  to  treat  type  (1)  hallucinations.23  

  As  the  attentive  reader  will  have  noted,  I  have  stressed  that  the  evidence  and  

methodologies  of  scientists  used  to  determine  the  nature  of  hallucinations  work  

                                                                                                               23  This  is  not  to  say  that  other  introspective  methods  might  not  be  able  to  give  subjects  insight  into  when  they  were  having  type  (1)  hallucinations,  dependent  on  the  contingencies  of  the  world.  For  example,  suppose  it  turned  out  that  a  person’s  hallucinations  were  all  Lilliputian  hallucinations,  that  is,  hallucinations  of  little  people.  (In  fact,  scientists  claim  that  there  are  subjects  who  have  just  these  hallucinations.  See  e.g.  Chand  and  Murthy  (2007).)  Such  a  person  might  be  able  to  learn  what  was  real  and  what  was  hallucinated  by  learning  that  her  hallucinations  were  only  of  little  people,  and  knowing  that  she  was  unlikely  to  be  in  an  environment  that  contained  such  little  people.  Note,  of  course,  that  this  kind  of  evidence  that  subjects  might  have  that  they  were  hallucinating  would  not  come  from  reflection  on  the  nature  of  their  experiences  alone  (unlike  the  knowledge  that  type  (4)  hallucinators  are  said  to  lack).  It  would  come  from  reflection  plus  the  knowledge  that  their  experiences  of  little  people  occurred  when  and  only  when  they  were  hallucinating.  

Page 40: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  40  

only  when  one  is  deciding  in  a  forced  choice,  whether  the  hallucination  is  of  type  (1)  

or  type  (4).  But  we  have  seen  that  philosophers  have  identified  four  conceptions  of  

hallucination.  Suppose  that  we  are  trying,  as  we  should,  to  determine  whether  a  

hallucination  is  of  type  (1),  (2),  (3),  or  (4).  Can  we  do  so?  And  can  the  evidence  and  

methodologies  of  science  we  have  considered  here  be  used  to  do  so?  

  To  consider  this  question,  let  us  temporarily  set  aside  type  (2)  conceptions  of  

hallucination.  Therefore  consider,  in  the  first  instance,  the  following  question:  can  

we  determine  whether  a  hallucination  is  of  type  (1),  type  (3),  or  type  (4),  supposing  

that  those  are  the  only  conceptions  of  hallucination  that  we  were  choosing  between  

(in  other  words,  in  a  forced  choice  between  these  alternatives)?  I  think  that  the  

answer  to  this  question  is  contingent.  There  are  some  ways  that  the  world  might  

turn  out  to  be  that  would  allow  us  to  have  such  evidence,  but  we  may  be  unfortunate  

and  the  world  might  not  turn  out  that  way.  I  will  first  demonstrate  what  evidence  

would  be  informative,  before  illustrating  how  the  world  may  not  provide  us  with  

evidence  one  way  or  the  other.  

  Evidence  in  favour  of  type  (3)  hallucinations,  rather  than  type  (1)  or  type  (4),  

could  be  found  if  one  area  of  the  brain  correlated  with  conscious  visual  experience,  

and  one  area  of  the  brain  correlated  with  visual  imagery,  and  one  knew  this,  and  one  

found  that  neither  of  these  regions  was  active  when  a  subject  was  hallucinating.  In  

particular,  it  would  be  persuasive  if  one  had  evidence  that  a  part  of  the  brain  

typically  associated  with  believing—perhaps  consciously  occurrently  believing—

was  active.  It  would  be  evidence  in  favour  of  the  only  alternative  that  we  are  

supposing  there  to  be  on  the  table,  namely,  that  the  subject  lacks  a  state  with  

perceptual-­‐like  phenomenal  character  but  believes  himself  or  herself  to  be  in  such  a  

state,  although  the  subject  could  come  to  know  otherwise  by  introspection  alone—a  

type  (3)  hallucination.  

Page 41: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  41  

One  might  question  whether  there  could  ever  be  such  evidence  by  

questioning  whether  one  could  ever  establish  what  the  neural  correlate  of  just  

visual  experience  was,  as  opposed  to  the  correlate  of  the  following  disjunction:  

either  having  visual  experience  or  having  a  type  (3)  hallucination.  Likewise,  one  

could  question  whether  one  could  find  the  neural  correlate  of  conscious  visual  

imagery  as  opposed  to  a  type  (3)  hallucination.  

However,  in  reply,  I  think  that  one  could  establish  the  neural  correlate  of  just  

visual  experience  and  just  visual  imagery  if  certain  conditions  existed.  One  would  

need  to  be  able  to  discriminate  between  the  presence  of  both  visual  experience  and  

visual  imagery  from  the  presence  of  type  (3)  hallucination.  If  the  world  was  

conveniently  set  up  so  that  behavioural  differences  existed  between  the  states  in  

question,  of  the  kind  one  would  expect  given  the  natures  of  those  states,  then  one  

might  be  able  to  tell  these  states  apart.  For  example,  on  some  occasions  when  

hallucinating  someone  might  change  their  mind  about  whether  they  were  having  a  

perceptual  or  perceptual-­‐like  experience,  perhaps  when  prompted,  whilst  on  other  

occasions  they  would  not.  Such  behavioural  evidence  would  be  evidence  that  itself  

helped  one  decide  whether  a  hallucination  was  of  type  (1),  type  (3),  or  type  (4).  But,  

in  addition,  it  might  allow  one  to  correlate  different  brain  activity  with  each  type  of  

hallucination,  allowing  one  thereafter  to  determine  via  brain  scanning  alone  which  

type  of  hallucination  was  present  on  a  given  occasion,  and  to  provide  confirmation,  

or  lack  thereof,  of  the  behavioural  evidence.  As  said  previously,  whether  one  could  

actually  do  any  of  this  is  a  contingent  matter.  It  would  be  no  great  surprise  if  the  

behaviour  associated  with  type  (3)  hallucinations  was  rather  similar,  or  indeed  

identical,  to  that  of  type  (1)  and  type  (4)  owing  to  the  likelihood  of  both  states  

producing  the  same  beliefs  in  subjects.  However,  psychologists  are  experts  at  

teasing  apart  rather  similar  states,  so  perhaps  some  measures  could  be  found.  

It  is  worth  noting  that  someone  changing  her  mind,  from  believing  that  she  

has  a  perceptual  experience  to  believing  that  she  does  not,  will  not  guarantee  that  

Page 42: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  42  

the  person  is  having  a  type  (3)  hallucination.  This  is  because  someone  who  is  having  

a  common-­‐kind  hallucination  could  (falsely)  change  her  mind  about  whether  she  is  

having  a  perceptual  experience.  Such  belief  change  could  be  a  response  to  myriad  

factors.  Therefore,  evidence  about  subjects’  brains  and  behavior  on  occasions  when  

we  are  confident  that  they  are  not  having  visual  or  visual-­‐like  experiences,  and  

when  we  are  confident  that  they  are  having  beliefs  about  visual  experiences,  may  be  

the  key  to  seeking  firmer  evidence  of  the  appropriate  sort.  

Now  let  us  consider  whether  we  could  determine  whether  a  hallucination  is  

of  type  (1),  (2),  (3),  or  (4).  One  can  imagine  finding  such  evidence.  Let  me  provide  

some  examples.  First,  suppose  that  it  has  been  established  that  some  hallucinations  

occur  when  the  visual  cortex  is  active  (which  leads  us  to  suspect  that  these  are  type  

(1)  hallucinations),  and  some  hallucinations  occur  when  the  frontal  and  parietal  

lobes  are  active  (which  provides  some  evidence  that  these  are  type  (4)  

hallucinations),  and  some  occur  when  only  a  part  of  the  brain  associated  with  

conscious  belief  is  active  (supporting  the  suggestion  that  these  are  type  (3)  

hallucinations).  If  we  then  found  that  some  hallucinations  occurred  when  a  very  

different  pattern  of  brain  activity  occurred,  then  this  would  provide  evidence,  albeit  

rather  weak,  that  these  hallucinations  were  different,  and  if  type  (2)  hallucinations  

are  the  only  other  candidate  type,  then  perhaps  we  might  be  tempted  to  identify  

these  as  type  (2)  hallucinations.  Likewise,  if  we  found  behavioural  markers  for  type  

(1),  (3),  and  (4)  hallucinations  and  then  found  hallucinations  with  a  different  

behavioural  profile,  then  this  again  might  lead  us  to  suspect  that  they  were  of  type  

(2).  In  short,  some  type  (2)  hallucinations  could  have  a  distinct  brain  correlate  and  

could  produce  measurable  behavioural  differences  from  types  (1),  (3),  and  (4).  Thus  

it  is  possible  that  we  could  produce  positive  evidence  in  favour  of  type  (2)  

hallucination  being  present,  although  whether  the  world  is  as  it  would  need  to  be  for  

such  evidence  to  be  present  is  another  matter.  

Page 43: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  43  

However,  unfortunately,  although  we  have  just  seen  that  there  could  be  

positive  evidence  in  favour  of  type  (2)  hallucinations,  there  is  good  reason  to  believe  

that  we  could  never  have  evidence  to  rule  out  that  a  type  (2)  hallucination  is  

occurring.  For  example,  suppose  a  person’s  brain  was  active  in  just  the  way  it  would  

be  were  the  person  perceiving.  When  I  considered  whether  one  could  decide  

between  types  (1),  (3),  and  (4),  supposing  that  those  were  the  only  possibilities,  

then  perception-­‐identical  brain  activity  and  perception-­‐identical  behaviour  counted  

in  favour  of  the  presence  of  type  (1)  hallucination,  rather  than  (3)  or  (4).  However,  

when  we  also  consider  the  possibility  of  type  (2)  hallucinations,  the  situation  

changes.  If  perception-­‐identical  brain  activity  occurs,  but  not  perception,  then  how  

could  we  determine  whether  a  type  (1)  or  a  type  (2)  hallucination  was  occurring?  

According  to  the  common-­‐kind  theory,  being  in  the  same  kind  of  brain  state  that  one  

is  in  when  one  perceives  causes  one  to  have  a  perceptual  experience  with  the  same  

phenomenal  character  that  one  would  have  were  one  perceiving—a  type  (1)  

hallucination.  But  recall  that,  according  to  the  disjunctivist,  this  is  not  the  case.  

According  to  the  disjunctivist,  if  a  person  is  in  the  very  same  brain  state  as  he  would  

have  been  in  when  perceiving,  he  is  simply  in  a  state  in  which  it  is  not  possible  for  

him  to  know  that  he  is  not  perceiving  by  means  of  introspection  alone.  He  is  not  in  a  

state  with  phenomenal  character.  He  is  having  a  type  (2)  hallucination.  Thus  upon  

discovery  that  the  brain  is  undergoing  perception-­‐like  activity  in  the  absence  of  

perception,  there  is  no  evidence  from  the  brain  state  alone  that  could  determine  

whether  the  hallucination  is  of  type  (1)  or  type  (2).  Therefore,  which  type  one  thinks  

is  occurring  will  depend  on  one’s  high-­‐level  theoretical  commitments  about  the  

nature  of  perception  and  hallucination—one’s  commitments  to  either  the  common-­‐

kind  or  the  disjunctive  theory  of  perception.  Thus  the  existence  of  hallucinations  in  

which  the  brain  is  active  in  the  same  way  as  it  is  in  perception  could  never  tell  in  

favour  of  the  common-­‐kind  type  (1)  conception  of  hallucination  over  the  strict  

disjunctivist  type  (2)  conception.  Indeed,  given  that  a  disjunctivist  could  believe  that  

any  pattern  of  brain  activity  associated  with  hallucinatory  states  that  a  person  might  

Page 44: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  44  

have  is  compatible  with  that  person  having  a  type  (2)  hallucination,  it  would  seem  

that  there  is  no  evidence  about  brain  activity  which  could  rule  out  the  possibility  

that  a  type  (2)  hallucination  is  occurring  on  any  occasion.  

Moreover,  disjunctivists  will  think  that  the  same  behavior  could  be  present  

whether  the  subject  was  having  a  type  (2)  hallucination  or  one  of  the  other  types  of  

hallucination.  Thus  they  could  think  that  no  behavioural  test  could  tell  apart  type  (2)  

hallucinations  from  any  of  the  other  kinds.  

In  short,  we  can  never  in  principle  be  in  a  position  to  rule  out  that  a  type  (2)  

hallucination  is  occurring,  rather  than  one  of  the  other  types  of  hallucination,  on  the  

basis  of  empirical  evidence.  However,  if  we  set  type  (2)  hallucinations  to  one  side  

and  suppose  that  we  are  just  trying  to  determine  whether  a  hallucination  is  of  type  

(1),  (3)  or  (4),  then  it  is  possible  that  we  could  find  brain  and  behavioural  evidence  

that  tells  us  which  it  is,  in  the  manner  that  we  have  seen  psychologists  actually  do  

and  in  the  manner  that  I  outlined  earlier  in  this  section.  

Given  these  reflections,  it  is  perhaps  no  surprise  that  psychologists,  

neuroscientists,  and  clinicians  have  not  acknowledged  hallucinations  of  type  (3),  

and,  more  particularly,  of  type  (2).  The  relative  ease  with  which  one  can  determine  

whether  a  type  (1)  or  type  (4)  hallucination  is  occurring,  if  those  are  the  only  two  

possible  options,  is  marked,  compared  to  that  required  when  we  broaden  the  

choices  to  include  type  (3)  and  type  (2).  However,  as  we  have  just  seen,  all  four  

conceptions  of  hallucinations  seem  possible.  Thus,  determining  which  sort  of  

hallucination  is  occurring  is  more  difficult  than  scientists  have  heretofore  

acknowledged,  and  looks  to  be  impossible  if  we  wish  to  find  empirical  evidence  that  

rules  out  that  a  hallucination  of  type  (2)  is  occurring.  

Another  reason  that  may  explain  why  scientists  have  not  considered  

hallucinations  of  type  (2)  or  (3)  lies  in  the  response  of  a  clinician  when  I  asked  him  

why  he  had  never  considered  whether  hallucinations  of  these  types  were  occurring  

Page 45: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  45  

in  his  patients.  He  replied  that  to  do  so  seemed  morally  repugnant.  He  noted  that  it  

would  involve  disbelieving  his  patients’  reports  about  their  own  experience—

disbelieving  them  about  their  own  minds.  The  clinician  would  have  to  raise  the  

possibility  to  his  patients  that  what  they  were  saying  about  the  nature  of  their  own  

minds  was  false.  They  were  not  having  perceptual  or  perceptual-­‐like  experiences  on  

occasions  when  they  claimed  that  they  were.  

  One  might  wonder  why  he  found  that  so  repugnant.  After  all,  there  are  

occasions  when  clinicians  tell  their  patients  that  they  are  not  perceiving  the  world  

when  they  think  and  claim  that  they  are.  Clinicians  do  inform  their  patients  that  they  

are  hallucinating.  If  it  is  morally  acceptable  to  do  that,  which  clinicians  take  it  to  be  

at  least  in  some  cases,  why  would  it  be  wrong  to  go  further  and  tell  the  patients  that  

they  were  not  even  having  perceptual  experiences?  After  all,  one  need  not  suppose  

that  one’s  patients  are  lying  in  this  situation.  They  might  be  trying  to  report  

truthfully  on  the  nature  of  their  mental  life  but,  due  to  circumstances  beyond  their  

control,  be  getting  it  wrong.  That  too  could  be  explained  to  these  patients.  

There  are  deep  issues  here  to  do  with  the  authority  that  we  grant  others  

about  the  nature  of  their  own  mental  lives.  This  kind  of  issue  can  be  brought  out  by  

considering  a  related  case:  the  case  of  pain.  Suppose  that  someone  went  to  the  

doctor  complaining  of  terrible  pain  in  his  knee.  If  the  doctor  did  some  tests  and  then  

told  the  patient  that  she  had  good  news  that  he  was  not  in  fact  suffering  pain  at  all  

and  should  therefore  go  home,  we  might  think  that  something  very  wrong  had  

occurred.  You  might  think  that  the  patient  is  the  expert  on  his  mental  state,  not  the  

doctor,  whatever  the  empirical  tests  say.    

These  considerations  bring  out  a  key  feature  that  separates  the  common-­‐

kind  theory  of  perception  from  the  disjunctive  theory  of  perception.  This  feature  is  a  

significant  and  important  philosophical  difference  that  divides  the  theories.  The  

common-­‐kind  view  of  perception  must  insist  that  there  are  some  hallucinations  of  

Page 46: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  46  

type  (1)  or  that  such  hallucinations  are  at  least  possible.  Their  theory  of  perception  

requires  such  a  commitment.  They  can  also  allow  the  actuality  and  possibility  of  

types  (3)  and  (4).  And,  although  in  theory  they  could  allow  for  type  (2)  

hallucinations  to  be  possible,  in  practice,  I  believe  that  many  will  want  to  deny  their  

existence,  for  doing  so  provides  one  reason  to  favour  the  common-­‐kind  theory  over  

the  disjunctive  position,  as  I  will  explain  shortly.  The  disjunctive  theory  of  

perception  endorses  the  possibility  of  type  (2)  hallucinations  and  can  allow  that  

hallucinations  of  type  (3)  and  (4)  may  occur.  However,  they  must  insist  that  

hallucinations  of  type  (1)  do  not  and  cannot  occur.  Given  that  no  possible  empirical  

evidence  would  settle  whether  hallucinations  of  type  (1)  are  occurring  or  are  

possible,  rather  than  type  (2),  we  must  turn  to  theoretical  philosophical  reasons  for  

thinking  about  which  types  of  hallucination  are  possible,  rather  than  to  science.  

What  we  find  when  we  do  so  is  that  the  theoretical  reasons  that  underpin  thinking  

one  kind  of  hallucination  rather  than  the  other  is  possible  amount  to  fundamentally  

different  worldviews:  different  sets  of  initial  starting  assumptions  on  which  one  

builds  to  construct  the  rest  of  one’s  philosophical  view—different  sets  of  

fundamental  assumptions  that  the  common-­‐kind  and  the  disjunctivist  theories  are  

based  on.  So  it  is  to  these  assumptions  that  we  must  now  turn  to  understand  what  at  

core  differentiates  the  common-­‐kind  view  from  disjunctivism  and  on  what  grounds  

we  should  accept  one  view  rather  than  the  other.  

The  common-­‐kind  conception  of  the  world  is  Cartesian  in  a  certain  respect.  

According  to  the  Cartesian  view,  doubts  may  arise  as  to  the  nature  of  the  external  

world  and  our  knowledge  of  it,  but  serious  doubts  cannot  arise  as  to  whether  we  

know  that  we  are  conscious  and  know  the  nature  of  our  mental  states.  Although  

Descartes  said,  “I  think,  therefore  I  exist”,  a  modern  Cartesian  might  replace  this  

with  “I  am  conscious,  therefore  I  exist”.  Knowledge  of  one’s  own  consciousness  –  of  

one’s  own  phenomenal  character  –  is  bedrock.  It  is  the  foundational  truth—the  

place  where  our  knowledge  is  certain.  The  Cartesian  and  the  common-­‐kind  theorist  

Page 47: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  47  

take  it  that  we  know  our  own  mind.  We  know  that  we  have  conscious  mental  states,  

and  what  phenomenal  character  they  have.  

I said “serious” doubts cannot arise about our knowledge of these matters, for the

Carteisan can allow that on occasion we may make mistakes. We may not be paying

enough attention, or we may make a snap decision unguided properly by introspection, or

circumstances may arise in which we make contingent trivial errors; we are not infallible.

But when suitably focused, and when we set aside trivial errors, such as inadvertent word

or concept choice, we cannot be wrong about the nature of our own mental experience, in

particular we cannot be wrong regarding the basic question of whether we have it. Thus

the natural view for the Cartesian is that when hallucinating (and not realizing that we are

hallucinating rather than perceiving) we are right that we are having perceptual

experience, just wrong about the way that the world is (or if having a veridical

hallucination we would be right about the way that the world was but we would not know

how it was based on our experience). Thus, type (1) hallucinations fit well with the

Cartesian view.

Although hallucinations of type (3) and type (4) do not sit at ease with the

Cartesian position, the Carteisan and common-kind theorist can try to allow for them.

They can say that these arise in conditions where the kind of errors outlined in the

previous paragraph occur such as lack of attention, and snap judgments not based on

proper introspection. The empirical evidence suggests that there may be many

hallucinations of type (4). A weak point of this theory is that it is highly debatable

whether the kinds of error posited to explain this type of hallucination would explain the

persistence of these hallucinations in individuals who have them. What would be

stopping these individuals from realizing that they were not having perceptual

experiences by simply paying more attention and taking more time to make their

judgments, and thus curing themselves of their hallucinations?

The main point, however, that I wish to make about the Cartesian and common-

kind theory is that to maintain the epistemological view that their theory has regarding

Page 48: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  48  

the mental realm—that knowledge of the existence of our own consciousness is

foundational and close to infallible—Cartesians and common-kind theorists will want to

deny that hallucinations of type (2) could occur. The common-kind theorist will want to

maintain this epistemological view because the evidence of the existence of type (1)

hallucinations, and hence evidence in favor the common-kind view, comes from

introspective knowledge that we allegedly have that we can have perceptual experience at

times that we nonintrospectively know that we are not perceiving the world, such as when

dreaming and having after-images. Type (2) hallucinations involve “serious” errors as to

whether a mental state is conscious and has perceptual phenomenal character. In many

such cases one will think or judge that one is having a perceptual experience but one will

be wrong. (In some cases one may not do any thinking or judging.) Indeed it is not

possible for one to know though introspection alone that one is not perceiving, so it is not

possible for one to know though introspection that one is not having a perceptual

experience. This is precisely the kind of error that the Cartesian will want to deny is

possible, as will common-kind theorists who wish to maintain the Cartesian view of our

knowledge of our own minds. For the possibility of making such error—and as the

disjunctivist would have it, making such errors in every instance of hallucination—casts

doubt on our claim to know that perceptual experience is possible in the absence of

perception of the world.

In contrast, the disjunctivist conception of perception begins with an

epistemological “modesty,” to use M. G. F. Martin’s term, about our knowledge of our

own experience.24 It does not presuppose that we can tell that we are having a conscious

perceptual experience. It does not presuppose that when we are in a mental state, we can

know whether that state has perceptual phenomenal character. In this respect,

disjunctivism seems to make less strong assumptions about our knowledge than the

Cartesian and common-kind view, and this may seem like a reason to favor this position.

However, it also begins with a strong claim about the external world that the Cartesian

and common-kind theorist do not presuppose, namely, “that some at least of our sensory                                                                                                                24  Martin  (2004,  38)  

Page 49: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  49  

episodes are presentations of an experience-independent reality.”25 This is an expression

of Martin’s commitment to naive realism—the view that at least on some occasions we

immediately perceive the world. This view is likely to be accompanied by the further

view that many disjunctivists would endorse, namely, that when immediately perceiving

the world we are in a position, at least, to come to have knowledge about it. (See

McDowell 1994 and, for an overview, Haddock and Macpherson 2008b.)

Thus we are faced with the choice of starting by taking it for granted that we are

in a strong epistemological position with respect to knowledge of our own mental lives,

in particular the facts concerning whether we are having perceptual experiences, or of

starting by taking it for granted that we sometimes accurately perceive a mind-

independent reality, and are thereby in a position to know about the world. It is hard to

adjudicate between these positions and therefore with what basic assumptions one should

make at the point of beginning to theorize about the nature of perception and the world.

M.G. F. Martin (2004, 2006) argues at length in favor of the disjunctive starting

point—one reason in its favor being its claimed epistemological modesty. But one might

resist this. For example, opponents of disjunctivism could claim that it fails to provide a

plausible account of phenomenal character. Recall that disjunctivists claim that though

two experiences may be such that in principle there is no way for the subject to tell apart

the states just by introspection, nonetheless these states can have different phenomenal

characters. This is just the epistemic modesty that they are keen to avow: there will be

cases where we can’t tell apart cases of perception that involve perceptual experiences

with phenomenal character from cases of hallucination in which there is no phenomenal

character. They hold a view where either phenomenal character is not to be identified

with “what it is like” for the subject (for that is the same in the good case and the bad

case, while phenomenal character is not the same) or, if it is, then “what it is like” must

be distinguished from “what it seems like” (for in the good case there is something that it

is like, while in the bad there merely seems to be something that it is like). But one might

                                                                                                               25  See  Martin  (2004,  38).  

Page 50: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  50  

balk at any theory with this consequence. One might think that the theoretical role of

phenomenal character is to capture “what it is like” where this is one and the same as

“what it seems like.” Surely that is the notion of our mental life that concerns us—as

illustrated in the example considered earlier of the inappropriateness of the hypothetical

doctor’s reaction to someone claiming to be in pain, namely, that they should go home for

they merely think that they are in pain.

Further, one may hold that the epistemically modest view raises a skeptical worry

that far outstrips the Cartesian skeptical worry, which is that we may not know anything

about the external world. Surely epistemic modesty—the possibility of error with respect

to our judgment that we are in a state with phenomenal character—raises the specter that

we never know whether we are having perceptual experiences with phenomenal

character, and that we never are. Might we not always just think that we are? Thus might

we be experiential zombies? Faced with the threat of such radical skepticism about our

internal mental lives, one reaction would be to think that we should reject the possibility

of type (2) hallucinations and, with them, disjunctivism.

In my own opinion, it is possible to allow for the possibility of type (2)

hallucinations but fend off the skeptical challenge concerning one’s knowledge of

whether one is in a state with phenomenal character. One can think that cases can exist in

which a person seems to be judging that he is in a state with phenomenal character when

he is not in a phenomenal state and, further, that the person is not be able to know by

reflection alone that he is not in a state with phenomenal character. Yet one might think

that such cases do not show that there cannot be cases in which someone has knowledge

that they are in a state with phenomenal character, when indeed they are, and know that

they know this. If one adopts a disjunctive theory of introspection (not of perception),

then one can think that when one is in a state with phenomenal character, one can have

direct access to, or acquaintance with, that character and, by virtue of that access, know

that one is in such a state (and know that one knows). And this can be so even if there can

be states in which one is not in a position to know whether one is in a state with

Page 51: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  51  

phenomenal character, and indeed one makes a false judgment about whether one is. To

draw an analogy here, one might think that it is possible in some circumstances to know

that one is sober (and know that one knows it), such as, on certain occasions when one is

sober and otherwise clear minded, even though in other cases it may not be possible for

one to know that one is not sober, for example, when one reaches a certain level of

drunkenness, even when in that state one falsely judges that one is sober. It is common to

believe that the circumstances that one finds oneself in can alter one’s ability to know

things. Typically these circumstances are thought to consist in the way the world is

around one. However, in the cases I am considering, we can see that the state that one’s

mind is in can alter one’s ability to know things and one’s ability to discriminate between

the obtaining of different situations. On this view, one need not advocate epistemically

modesty—at least all the time. Sometimes we may not be able to tell whether we are in a

state with phenomenal character, but sometimes we can tell and we do know. This view is

argued for in more detail in Macpherson (2010b).

My view lacks enough modesty vis-à-vis introspection to align it with the

common-kind view, though it is more modest than the traditional versions of that view.

According to my view, there could be type (1) hallucinations. It is possible for one to be

having a perceptual experience—be in a state with phenomenal character—and know it,

and yet one may merely be hallucinating. This secures commitment to the common-kind

theory of perception. Yet, on my view, there can also be type (2) hallucinations, for one

can be in a position where one doesn’t know by introspection alone whether or not one is

in a state with phenomenal character. Like both the traditional common-kind view and

disjunctivism, my position also allows for there to be type (3) and type (4) hallucinations.

However, it does not face the pressure that the common-kind view faced with respect to

these hallucinations. My view is not committed to the idea that if one paid enough

attention or was careful enough in introspection one should be able, when having such

hallucinations, to realize that that is what they are. My view also shares a modesty with

the traditional common-kind views, that disjunctivism lacks, namely, the need not to

assume that we do ever perceive the world rather than hallucinate it. The view is also

Page 52: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  52  

modest inasmuch as it need not assume that any type of hallucination is not possible. All

are possible according to this view and that, I believe, is a reason to recommend it.26

I leave the reader to consider the common-kind view, disjunctivism, and my own

view, which I take to be a new variant of the common-kind view, and the four kinds of

hallucination I have discussed in this essay, and to weigh the reasons for deciding

between the theoretical positions outlined herein.

 

6  Conclusion  

This  is  an  interesting  time  to  be  conducting  research  on  the  nature  of  perception  

and  hallucination.  Within  philosophy,  disjunctivism,  a  view  opposing  the  dominant  

common-­‐kind  theories,  is  being  increasingly  worked  out  and  articulated.  The  debate  

and  disagreement  between  the  two  camps  is  becoming  clearer.  How  can  we  make  

further  progress  in  deciding  between  these  two  views?  It  is  time  for  scientists  to  

become  familiar  with  this  debate  and  to  start  to  think  about  the  disjunctive  

conception  of  hallucination.  They  should  consider  all  possible  sorts  of  hallucinations  

in  their  reflections  on  what  their  empirical  data  show.  In  addition,  I  believe  that  they  

should  think  about  whether  the  philosophers  are  right    in  their  claim  that  there  is  no  

way  to  empirically  test  between  the  common-­‐kind  theory  and  disjunctivism,  or  their  

respective  conceptions  of  hallucination.  Scientists  in  the  past  have  disproved  many  

long-­‐standing  philosophical  claims  with  ingenious  experimentation,  although  I  

doubt  that  it  is  possible  in  this  case.  Within  psychology  itself,  empirical  work  on  the  

brain  mechanisms  underlying  hallucination  proceeds  apace  with  the  invention  and  

spread  of  the  latest  scanning  techniques.  Will  scientists  discover  further  conceptions  

of  hallucinations  that  will  have  an  impact  on  philosophical  theorizing?  That  remains  

                                                                                                               26  Instances  of  when  type  (2)  hallucinations  might  actually  arise,  namely  in  Anton’s  syndrome—a  syndrome  in  which  people  who  are  blind  claim  that  they  can  see—which  is  usually  classified  as  a  monothematic  delusion,  are  given  and  discussed  at  length  in  Macpherson  (2010b).  

Page 53: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  53  

to  be  seen,  but  it  seems  to  me  to  be  a  serious  possibility.  I  hope  that  this  volume  will  

accelerate  the  pace  of  research  on  these  important  and  fascinating  topics.  

The  essays  in  this  book  continue  various  strands  of  the  debate  that  I  have  

outlined  in  this  essay.  An  overview  of  the  specific  contents  of  those  essays  forms  the  

following  chapter  of  this  volume.  

 

Acknowledgements  

I  would  like  to  thank  Clare  Batty,  Jon  Bird  and  Dimitris  Platchias  for  their  helpful  

comments  on  drafts  of  this  essay.  

 

References  

Brewer,  B  (2008)  “How  to  Account  for  Illusion”  in  A.  Haddock  and  F.  

Macpherson  (eds.)  Disjunctivism:  Perception,  Action,  Knowledge,  Oxford:  Oxford  

University  Press.  

Chand,  P.  K.  and  Murthy,  P.  (2007)  “Understanding  a  Strange  Phenomenon:  

Lilliputian  Hallucinations”,  German  Journal  of  Psychiatry,  10:  21-­‐4.  

Crane,  H.  D.  and  Piantanida,  T.  P  (1983)  "On  Seeing  Reddish  Green  and  

Yellowish  Blue",  Science,  221:  1078-­‐80.  

Crick,  F.  and  Koch,  C.  (1998)  “Consciousness  and  Neuroscience”,  Cerebral  

Cortex,  8:97–107.  

Dow,  N.  W.  (1962)  “Why  Afterimages  are  not  Seen  in  Normal  Circumstances”,  

Nature,  196:  1143—5  

Dretske,  F.  (1995)  Naturalizing  the  Mind,  Cambridge,  MA.:  MIT  Press.  

Page 54: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  54  

Fish,  W.  (2008)  “Disjunctivism,  Indistinguishability  and  the  Nature  of  

Hallucination”,  in  A.  Haddock    and  F.  Macpherson  (eds.)  Disjunctivism:  Perception,  

Action  and  Knowledge,  Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press.  

Fish,  W.  (2009)  Perception,  Hallucination,  and  Illusion,  New  York:  Oxford  

University  Press.  

Haddock,  A.  and  Macpherson,  F.  (2008a)  (eds.)  Disjunctivism:  Perception,  

Action,  Knowledge,  Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press.  

Haddock,  A.  and  Macpherson,  F.  (2008)  "Introduction:  Varieties  of  

Disjunctivism",  in  A.  Haddock  and  F.  Macpherson  (eds.)  Disjunctivism:  Perception,  

Action  Knowledge,  Oxford  University  Press.  

Haldane,  J.  (1993)  "Mind-­‐World  Identity  Theory  and  the  Anti-­‐Realist  Challenge",  in  J.  Haldane  and  C.  Wright  (eds.)  Reality,  Representation  and  Projection,  Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press.  

Haldane,  J.  and  Wright,  C.  (1993)  "Introduction",  in  J.  Haldane  and  C.  Wright  (eds.)  Reality,  Representation  and  Projection,  Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press.  

Hawley,  K.  and  Macpherson,  F.  (2011)  (eds.)  The  Admissible  Contents  of  Experience,  Wiley-­‐Blackwell.  

Lewis,  D.  (1980)  “Veridical  Hallucination  and  Prosthetic  Vision”,  Australasian  Journal  of  Philosophy,  58(3):  239-­‐249.  

Lycan,  W.  (1996)  Consciousness  and  Experience,  Cambridge,  M.A.:  MIT  Press.  

Macpherson,  F.  (2010a)  "Impossible  Figures",  in  E.  B.  Goldstein  (ed.)  the  SAGE  Encyclopedia  of  Perception,  Thousand  Oaks,  CA:  Sage.  

Macpherson  F.  (2010b)  "A  Disjunctive  Theory  of  Introspection:  A  Reflection  on  Zombies  and  Anton's  Syndrome",  Philosophical  Issues,  20(1):  226-­‐265.  

Page 55: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  55  

Macpherson,  F.  (2011)  “The  Admissible  Contents  of  Experience”  in  K.  Hawley  and  F.  Macpherson  (eds.)  The  Admissible  Contents  of  Experience,  Chichester,  West  Sussex:  Wiley-­‐Blackwell.  

Macpherson,  F.  (2012)  "Cognitive  Penetration  of  Colour  Experience:  Rethinking  the  Issue  in  Light  of  an  Indirect  Mechanism",  Philosophy  and  Phenomenological  Research,  84  (1):  24-­‐62.  

Macpherson,  F.  and  Platchais,  D.  (forthcoming)  Representationalism,  Cambridge,  MA.:  MIT  Press.  

Martin,  M.  G.  F.  (2004)  “The  Limits  of  Self-­‐Awareness”,  Philosophical  Studies,  120:  37-­‐89.  

Martin,  M.  G.  F.  (2006)  “On  Being  Alienated”,  in  T.  S.  Gendler  and  J.  Hawthorne  (eds.)  Perceptual  Experience,  Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press.  

McDowell,  J.  (1994)  Mind  and  World,  Cambridge,  Mass.:  Harvard  University  Press.  

Nagel,  T  (1974)  “What  Is  It  Like  To  Be  a  Bat?”,  The  Philosophical  Review,  83  (4):  435-­‐50.  

Pautz,  A.  (2011)  “What  Are  The  Contents  Of  Experiences?”,  in  K.  Hawley  and  

F.  Macpherson  eds.  The  Admissible  Contents  of  Experience,  Chichester,  West  Sussex:  

Wiley-­‐Blackwell.  

Pritchard,  D.  (2008)  “Sensitivity,  Safety,  and  Anti-­‐Luck  Epistemology”,  in  J.  

Greco  (ed.)  The  Oxford  Handbook  of  Scepticism,  Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press.  

Siegel,  S.  (2006)  “Which  Properties  Are  Represented  in  Perception?”,  in  T.  

Szabo  Gendler  and  J.  Hawthorne  (eds.)  Perceptual  Experience,  Oxford:  Oxford  

University  Press.  

Travis,  C.  (2004)  “The  Silence  of  the  Senses”,  Mind,  113  (449):  59-­‐94.  

Page 56: Macpherson Hallucination Introduction web.docx copy

  56  

Tye,  M.  (1995)  Ten  Problems  of  Consciousness,  Cambridge,  MA.:  MIT  Press.  


Recommended