+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Mapping Overlapping Constellations: Nature and Technology .../67531/metadc801893/m2/1/high... ·...

Mapping Overlapping Constellations: Nature and Technology .../67531/metadc801893/m2/1/high... ·...

Date post: 06-Sep-2018
Category:
Upload: dokhanh
View: 227 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend
302
MAPPING OVERLAPPING CONSTELLATIONS: NATURE AND TECHNOLOGY IN RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY/TECHNÉ AND ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS Glen Miller Dissertation Prepared for the Degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF NORTH TEXAS May 2015 APPROVED: Adam Briggle, Major Professor Martin D. Yaffe, Committee Member Eugene C. Hargrove, Committee Member Carl Mitcham, Committee Member James Kennedy, Chair of the Department of Philosophy and Religion Studies Costas Tsatsoulis, Interim Dean of the Toulouse Graduate School
Transcript

MAPPING OVERLAPPING CONSTELLATIONS: NATURE AND TECHNOLOGY

IN RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY/TECHNÉ AND ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS

Glen Miller

Dissertation Prepared for the Degree of

DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY

UNIVERSITY OF NORTH TEXAS

May 2015

APPROVED:

Adam Briggle, Major Professor Martin D. Yaffe, Committee Member Eugene C. Hargrove, Committee Member Carl Mitcham, Committee Member James Kennedy, Chair of the Department of

Philosophy and Religion Studies Costas Tsatsoulis, Interim Dean of the

Toulouse Graduate School

Miller, Glen. Mapping Overlapping Constellations: Nature and Technology in

“Research in Philosophy and Technology”/“Techné” and “Environmental Ethics". Doctor of

Philosophy (Philosophy), May 2015, 296 pp., 2 figures, bibliography, 263 titles.

The overlap between the separate fields of philosophy of technology and environmental

philosophy can be investigated using the two longest running flagship journals for each field,

Environmental Ethics (EE) and Research in Philosophy and Technology, which is now published

as Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology (RPT/Techné). By looking at the theoretical

and conceptual ideas on nature and the environment expressed in RPT/Techné, at those on

technology and artifacts expressed in EE, and at the individuals who contributed them using the

principles of social epistemology as developed by Steve Fuller, a stereoscopic view

incorporating the insights from both specializations can be constructed.

The ideas developed in the articles can be charted like stars within constellations, loosely

connected in groupings that are neither clear nor evident. Five constellations can be discerned

from the relevant articles in each journal, and while there is some overlap, there is considerable

difference. The stereoscopic view is developed in three ways: first, by reviewing the

contributions of authors who have published in both journals; second, by utilizing resources in

both specializations to add subtlety and depth to the ideas expressed, starting in this case from

Jacques Ellul’s “Nature, Technique and Artificiality”; and third, by using W. D. Ross’s ethical

theory, which fuses prima facie duties with virtues, to integrate traditional ethical concerns with

those raised by philosophers focused on technology and those concerned with the environment.

ii

Copyright 2015

by

Glen Miller

iii

TABLE OF CONTENTS

Page

LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS ......................................................................................................... v

CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION .................................................................................................. 1

CHAPTER 2. APPROACHING SEPARATE SPECIALIZATIONS ......................................... 15

Steve Fuller’s Social Epistemology as Interpretative Key ............................................... 18

Subsequent Lines of Inquiry ............................................................................................. 30

CHAPTER 3. NATURE (PHYSIS) IN RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY AND

TECHNOLOGY/TECHNÉ ................................................................................................ 33

Nature Seen Historically ................................................................................................... 35

At the Intersection of Nature and Techné ......................................................................... 41

Science, Technology, and Nature ..................................................................................... 52

Religion and Transcendence ............................................................................................. 65

Politics and Policy ............................................................................................................. 68

CHAPTER 4. TECHNOLOGY (TECHNÉ) IN ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS ........................... 76

Techné Seen Historically .................................................................................................. 77

Making and the Natural World ......................................................................................... 80

Science, Technology, Technoscience, and Nature .......................................................... 100

Religion and Transcendence ........................................................................................... 106

Aesthetics of Artworks ................................................................................................... 110

CHAPTER 5. TOWARD A STEREOSCOPIC VIEW OF TECHNÉ AND PHYSIS ............... 114

Longitudinal Interspecialization Analysis ...................................................................... 115

Brief Sketches of Crossover Contributors ...................................................................... 119

iv

Andrew Light: Durbin’s Synthesis Between the Specializations ................................... 147

Weaving Between the Specializations ............................................................................ 151

CHAPTER 6. ROSS’S DUTIES AS A COMPREHENSIVE ETHICAL THEORY ................ 159

Explanation of Ross’s Duty Ethics ................................................................................. 162

Ross and Ethics of Artifacts and the Environment ......................................................... 168

Extending Prima Facie Duties ........................................................................................ 174

Some Contemporary Techno-Environmental Virtues .................................................... 185

CHAPTER 7. EPILOGUE ......................................................................................................... 194

APPENDIX A. EDITORS AND VOLUMES OF RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY AND

TECHNOLOGY/TECHNÉ .............................................................................................. 199

APPENDIX B. ARTICLES IN RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY AND TECHNOLOGY/TECHNÉ,

1979-2014, BY CONTRIBUTOR .................................................................................. 208

REFERENCES ........................................................................................................................... 275

v

LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS

The following abbreviations have been used to refer to the journals cited frequently in this

dissertation:

EE Environmental Ethics

RPT Research in Philosophy and Technology

RPT: Techné The entire collection of publications linked to SPT, which includes

RPT, P&T, JSPT, and Techné: RPT

P&T Philosophy and Technology

SPT Society for Philosophy and Technology

JSPT Journal of the Society for Philosophy and Technology

Techné: JSPT Techné: Journal of the Society for Philosophy and Technology

Techné: RPT Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technolgy

1

CHAPTER 1

INTRODUCTION

Despite the obvious connection between technology and the environment, which is

visible at local, regional, and, in some cases, global levels, and, while popular literature is

increasingly attuned to environmental alterations, relatively little philosophical work has been

done at the intersection between the fields. The distinction between technology and nature has

been made in Western thought since at least the time of Aristotle, who noted that techné differs

from physis in that latter possesses an innate impulse and direction of motion and rest.1 To use

Aristotle’s terminology, the efficient, teleological, and formal causes for artifacts do not arise in

the being itself but instead are determined or at least influenced by external agents. Like the

word nature does today, though, physis had many different meanings. Aristotle did not just

distinguish physis from techné in Physics. He also contrasted physis with nomos, or convention,

a product of culture, in Nicomachean Ethics.2

Differentiating between the three realms—nature, culture, and technology—is rarely easy

since they are interrelated. On the one hand, technology cannot exist without nature, which

provides its “raw materials” and the external causes (or those that have co-responsibility, to use

Heidegger’s sense of the term), that brings it into existence. Fusing this line of thought with

cosmogenic and evolutionary science and knowledge of the tools used by animals, all technology

is natural: it all arises from the same source. On the other hand, the whole world has been called

technological, in the sense that it has all been impacted by humans. Human constructions are of

a larger scale than ever before—towers in Abu Dabai dwarf the pyramids—and emissions now

1 Aristotle, Physics, translated by Joe Sachs (New Brunswick, New Jersey: Rutgers University Press, 1995),

192b8. 2 Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, translated by Joe Sachs (Newburyport, Massachusetts: Focus Publishing,

2002), 1094b15.

2

change the atmosphere, water, and ground more than they ever have, in part due to the number of

people and their consumption practices. The current age has been called the Anthropocene in

response to this realization.

Moral judgments are influenced by whether technology is thought of as natural. On the

one hand, many environmentalists push for limits to the encroachment of wilderness by human

activities and decry its effects, including air and water pollution, and bemoan the lack of

common knowledge about nature and the minuscule amount of time the average person spends in

it. From this viewpoint, technology should be checked and nature deserves protection or space.

On the other hand, those who see the development and use of all kinds of technology as a natural

part of being human view these complaints as answerable by a sublimated understanding of the

human-technology-nature relationship. According to this view, technology can provide fixes for

whatever ails humans, and perhaps the transformation that is needed is to alter humans so they

can flourish in the new environment.

While both extremes contain a kernel of truth, they also unnecessarily deflate inquiries on

these realms into one dimension, and, in the process, minimize possible philosophical

contributions to the broader discussion. By bracketing inquiry, one of the hallmarks of the

natural and human sciences, clear and distinct results can be determined, but always at the cost of

comprehensiveness. An overarching inquiry, one that spans natural and human sciences, one

that is wrought with conceptual and cultural issues, is precisely the kind of question about which

philosophers should be concerned, in spite of, or perhaps because of, its difficulties and

consequences. Questions about technology and the environment affect our conception of the

good life, especially when the virtue of justice is considered. The connection is particularly

prominent in the environmental justice movement, which addresses procedural and substantive

3

issues involved in the distribution of environmental benefits and burdens among different social

and economic groups. An appeal to justice is often made by those concerned with unequal

access to technologies between different social groups. One example is concern over the Digital

Divide. Other examples of philosophical concepts commonly invoked include the virtue of

prudence, needed to govern human repurposing of natural resources toward technological ends;

the assignment of moral standing, necessary to determine which consequences of technology are

of moral concern; and epistemic uncertainties, involved in our production, use, and subsequent

assessment of the effects of human production and use of technology.

The philosophical community’s response to such issues has regrettably followed a

bifurcation similar to the interest groups in the general public. Philosophy of technology is

considered a separate “field” from environmental philosophy. Each specialization has its own

journals. Institutional support rarely happens in the same department or even university. Few

individuals are members of both intellectual communities, and even fewer have a sophisticated

understanding of both disciplines. The two specializations, which should add depth to public

discourse and nuance to discourse of the other, have been remarkably silent in academic

discourse and in their contributions to popular and political discussions about how one can and

should think about technology and nature, and how one can craft a good life in the material

conditions in which one finds one’s self.

The present inquiry is a step toward healing the division described above by finding

points of overlap in the two longest running journals for each specialization. It is inspired by

Aristotle, who, after noting all the difficulties that accompany distilling physis from nomos,

proceeds to take on that challenge. Here is a brief outline of the project.

4

In the second chapter, I explain the rationale for selecting two longstanding and esteemed

journals, Research in Philosophy and Technology, now published as Techné: Research in

Philosophy and Technology, and Environmental Ethics,3 to provide the a representative look at

each specialization. The direction of the inquiry is shaped by the version of social epistemology

developed by Steve Fuller. While many philosophical inquiries focus solely on concepts or

ideas, social epistemologists emphasize the people and institutions behind ideas that comprise

academic discourse. While I had planned to follow lines of discourse on nature in RPT/Techné

and techné in EE, the lines, when they existed, were too short for analysis. Instead of trying to

force a linear trajectory on the articles, I grouped them as constellations. Constellations require

the viewer to use imagination in order to see the shape formed by the stars, and no one mapping

of the sky can be called objectively right. The task of mapping of the constellations is done in

the third and fourth chapters.

The third chapter maps articles in RPT/Techné that explicitly define or work with the

concept of nature or similar terms into five constellations. Many of the articles were spurred by

two volumes largely dedicated to the theme of “Technology and the Environment” in 1992 and

“Philosophies of the Environment and Technology” in 1998. The first constellation includes

articles that focus on the term “nature” from its Greek origins to the present. The second

constellation is comprised of those articles that look at both nature and technology, and it

includes articles from J. Baird Callicott and Holmes Rolston, luminaries in environmental

philosophy. The third constellation includes articles that consider how science and

technoscience affects nature. The fourth consists of two articles on religion that were both

3 RPT/Techné refers to the entire collection of journals closely associated with the Society for Philosophy

and Technology (SPT). Hereafter, Environmental Ethics is referred to as EE. See the List of Abbreviations for more information.

5

inspired by Lynn White, Jr. The last is composed of articles that discuss politics and policy with

an eye toward conceptual or theoretical detail.

The fourth chapter organizes articles in EE that address techné and similar terms into five

clusters. Unlike articles in RPT/Techné, the articles in EE were the work of the contributors:

there was no directive from the journal editor or an associated society. Three of the five

constellations are similar to what was found in RPT/Techné, but the other two are composed of

creative and novel contributions that deserve more attention from philosophers who focus on

technology. One constellation includes a couple of historical inquiries into technology. A

second constellation consists of articles that have to do with understanding how the natural world

is affected by art or craft, which differs significantly from the almost exclusive focus on modern

technology in RPT/Techné. A third constellation is comprised of articles that investigate science,

technology, and nature, which is similar to the third constellation in RPT/Techné. A fourth

constellation also has a counterpart in RPT/Techné: the papers in it consider aspects of religion,

technology, and nature that arose from White’s “The Historical Roots of Our Ecologic Crisis.”

The fifth constellation, which includes articles that reflect on artifacts and natural things through

the perspective of aesthetics, has no analogue in RPT/Techné.

After building the individual images of techné and nature in RPT/Techné and EE,

respectively, the next task is to bring them into focus, to comprehend both at the same time. I do

this first by looking at yearly publication numbers, then by reviewing the twenty-four

contributors who published at least one article in both journals. Paul T. Durbin’s history of

philosophy of technology, which locates the intersection between the specializations in the work

of Andrew Light, one of the dual contributors, sets the originality of this project into relief. The

chapter ends with a sketch of the interrelated concepts of freedom, evolution, and ecology that is

6

informed by the history and depth of both specializations, starting from an RPT article by

Jacques Ellul.

The penultimate chapter proposes an amended version of W. D. Ross’s prima facie duties

as a suitable theory that can integrate environmental and artifactual issues. The amendments that

are necessary are to extend concerns to a global population and future generations, to address

non-human organisms, and to address the non-organic environment, broadly understood to

include ecosystems and the built environment. All but the last are incorporated by extending the

scope of the duties, while the last is addressed by supplementing the intellectual and moral

virtues that Ross recognized. While there are some minor issues with the extension, it is

relatively successful when it is assessed according to the aim of providing a flexible structure

that provides space, but not prescriptions, for concerns traditionally associated with ethics and

issues of technology and the environment.

Before starting on the project, however, let me sketch out a few hurdles in the way of

such work.

A powerful force hindering integration of philosophical issues associated with technology

and the environment is the trend toward increasing disciplinization of academic work. New

disciplines originated in the human and natural sciences to address the exponential growth of

information and to manage a multiplicity of methods. New disciplines form when the amount of

important information in a discipline exceeds the grasp of its average practitioner. New modes

of analysis can lead to novel disciplines or specializations if they are complex enough to demand

nearly exclusive attention or are suited to a subset of objects that were at one time all studied in a

discipline. Philosophy, originally the master science that encompassed all others, changed

7

similarly: many philosophers became “scholars and specialists themselves,” “brought back

under the domination of science.”4

The development of philosophy of technology and environmental philosophy into

separate social groups and separate specializations is one such example of a narrowing of scope.

It is, in a sense, subservience, freely chosen. The majority of intellectuals in both groups, it

seems, have been more attuned to their standing in the eyes of those practicing philosophy in its

traditional spheres of metaphysics, epistemology, ethics, and logic than in how their work related

to their counterparts pursuing a specialization that, at first glance, appears to be properly

excluded from their concerns. This is wrong, though: the other specialization should be

considered complementary.

The chasm between philosophy of technology and environmental philosophy arose in

spite of their contemporaneous origins that had similar philosophical foundations. Over time,

each specialization developed its own body of literature and technical jargon, in large part

through their respective journals. On the one hand, the specialization is not particularly

surprising. Both fields were trying to deal with a motley crew of contributors from philosophy

and a range of other fields, such as Science and Technology Studies, law, politics, and certain

sciences: just to attain consistency within the specialization required ongoing effort. On the

other hand, the processes of specialization began to create impediments that prevented

individuals from coherently considering both aspects of philosophical concern.

The burdens erected by fragmentation are paired by a related impediment, the celebration

of depth, rather than breadth, in academic research. To the extent that journal publications are an

accurate measure of what is valued in academic research, adding a slightly new perspective or a

4 Friedrich Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil, translated by Judith Norman, edited by Rolf-Peter Horstmann

and Judith Norman (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002), §204.

8

minor extension of an argument is surely the best “return for investment” on research efforts for

an individual scholar. The benefits of such corrections, the theory goes, are aggregated as

academic discourse progresses. Yet one result of my inquiry is that adding a minor contribution

to an academic debate may be of limited or no value: at worst, it may be ignored by other

scholars, or, more commonly, perfunctorily cited in the third or fourth paragraphs of future

publications, without any evidence of a serious evaluation of its arguments or how they would

affect the argument put forth in the new paper.5 The tendency toward depth and rigor,

especially to the extent that the latter is understood to demand at least a superficial understanding

of all other writings on a particular topic, even to the point of learning new languages to fully

understand a few paragraphs, has two negative consequences for discourse.

The first consequence is that the emphasis on specialization and depth can lead to a

trained incapacity, to use the noted phrase of social critic Thorstein Veblen that was later

popularized by Kenneth Burke, among its practitioners. To the extent that these values are

elevated over others, academics are dissuaded, and may even lose their ability to conduct,

general, interdisciplinary inquiries necessary to participate in discourses on topics that do not

neatly fall within disciplinary boundaries, which themselves expand far beyond a particular

specialization. If the values of specialization, depth, and rigor are reinforced in young scholars

from the beginning of graduate school until they have earned tenure, the values may become so

ingrained that they will determine the research projects the academics undertake for the

remainder of their careers.

A second consequence of the demanding burdens of depth and rigor is that philosophical

contributions often only see the light of day so far after general impressions have already formed

that they function as “academic exercises,” in the most pejorative sense of the term, drawing

5 Exceptions exist, and they are often the supreme achievements of academic discourse.

9

little interest and having less influence outside of the specialization, or perhaps the discipline, if

the author is lucky or slightly more timely. Tardy contributions also impoverish academic

discourse because they are not evaluated by a wider range of intellectuals, so they are less likely

to be tested and developed to the greatest possible extent.

The present inquiry tries to bridge the aim for rigor—itself valuable in moderation and

one characteristic of academic work that gives it gravitas and traction—with the desire to

develop a research style that avoids the traps associated with it. While it at first appears to be

subject to the preceding critique of narrowness—a study based on two journals, EE and

RPT/Techné, each focused on a specialization, seems to be a niche of a niche—its scope is

actually much broader due to the interdisciplinary nature of both journals.6 It is an effort toward

development of a stereoscopic view of the world that fuses together insights from both

specializations while pointing out blind spots and obstructions that have arisen through their

separate development.

The present inquiry aims to make progress in three dimensions. Most obviously, it is

intended to be a theoretical contribution to the body of scholarly discourse. More narrowly, it is

a trail in interdisciplinary inquiry that may show the potential of such efforts: it seems to me the

best way to promote the erosion of disciplinary boundaries is to write outside of them. I hope to

follow Augustine in this effort: I write so that I might progress, and I progress by writing.

I also seek to make progress in a more practical dimension, at a personal level. I see

issues of technology and the environment as important concerns that must be addressed in asking

the fundamental question of ethics, as understood by Aristotle, namely, what it means to live a

6 The interdisciplinary spirit of both magazines was aptly expressed by Eugene Hargrove, reflecting on the

submissions to the journal, who bemoaned the lack of submissions on “economics, business, biology, public policy, health, environmental standards, environmental impact assessment, law, population, and future generations—and

10

good life for a human. To be sure, Aristotle elevated contemplation as the culmination of human

being, but by it he did not mean separation or inactivity. Humans were meant for a polis, he

reasoned, and to only talk about philosophical issues without actively living virtuously is like

hearing a doctor’s guidance but not following it.7

I also expect the effort to succeed in the pedagogical dimension, by increasing my ability,

and that of my readers, to lead students through the complicated issues that affect technology and

the environment that bother and interest them, informed by the best of academic research at that

intersection. While the pedagogical dimension is important in my own intellectual development,

it is essential to the success of the broader enterprise of the university. While pedagogy is often

undervalued at public universities in the United States, who are shifting their priorities toward

research, shorting the pedagogical position obstructs the case for public funding of universities

during an era when accountability is a growing tagline.

Lest I be accused of mercenary philosophizing, the importance I place on the pedagogical

dimension is more than a response to market or political forces. It also rehabilitates a split that

has arisen between the freedom to teach (Lehrfreiheit) and the freedom to learn (Lernfreiheit).

These two freedoms were balanced in the German instantiation of the university, which most

closely resembles the structure and social expectations of its current form.8 Under Wilhelm van

Humboldt’s guidance, the topics that instructors can teach as experts are selected in concert with

students. Tendencies of researchers to explore increasingly abstract and detailed inquiries, by

which professors develop expertise and sustain intellectual interest, are checked in two ways.

Professors have to be able to find an interested group of students to take their classes, and to do

even this list is far from being exhaustive” in “New Directions,” EE 3, no. 4 (Winter 1981): 291, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics1981341.

7 Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 1097b10, 1105b10-15. 8 Steve Fuller, Sociology of Intellectual Life (London: Sage, 2009), 40.

11

so they have to develop the ability to convey their research in a way that can be understood by

non-experts. By pairing Lehrfreiheit and Lernfreiheit, universities can claim a legitimate social

function, one that contributes to the flourishing of free societies of socially and economically

mobile citizens. They create social capital through their research function, and they distribute or

democratize this capital through their teaching function.9

Even though the present formulation of this project is intended for an academic

audience—not for students or for the broader public—its design and execution have been shaped

with the balance between Lehrfreiheit and Lernfreiheit in mind. An impetus for the project was

my students’ meager responses when faced with the interwoven nature of environmental issues

and how they related to technology. They often exhibited an intellectual paralysis, one that may

have resulted from intimidation at the interdisciplinary nature of the problems that was further

exacerbated by a university education that emphasizes the importance of the sciences.

The outline of the contours of the intersection between the two specializations may be of

interest to other scholars whose research and instruction involve both fields but who were trained

in one and lack the time to learn the other. In addition, I hope to add personal and institutional

awareness to the history of ideas of each specialization, which I think will be especially

important to those who teach in this area or who contribute to extra-academic discourses.

Further, just as both journals seek to engage a range of contributors and readers that include

academic philosophers and those with interest in those topics, I also have attempted to write with

as little jargon and as few footnotes as possible. The aim of doing so is to give non-specialists a

vocabulary and theoretical structure rich enough to understand and address the social and ethical

concerns faced at the present without the accompanying burden of mastering the expertise in

9 Fuller, Sociology of Intellectual Life, 4. Fuller and Collier use the term “prolescience” to evaluate

“research in terms of its teachability” (31).

12

both specializations, though such simplification is not always possible except at the expense of

an unacceptable loss of meaning.

Keeping scholarly, personal, pedagogical, and public goals in mind while integrating the

two specializations should yield ancillary benefits for the academic profession. By attending to

student concerns, I am preparing to participate in extra-academic discourse that shapes political

attitudes, government and corporate policies, and individual practices more than intra-academic

discourse does. The profession may be able to take some credit for an improvement in the

quality of public discourse, which may result in more thoughtful development of political

identities. Moreover, the concerns I expect to raise will most likely lead to conflicts between my

positions and those of powerful interests, providing evidence of the importance of tenure, which

will likely need to be repeatedly justified because those outside academia see no reason that

professors get job security that few others have.

In addition to the contributions of faculty at Colorado School of Mines, the University of

North Texas, and the University of Twente, this dissertation owes its existence and form to

several specific individuals. Carl Mitcham introduced me to John Staudenmeier’s Technology’s

Storytellers, a bibliometric analysis of the journal Technology and Culture, as a way to manage

an overwhelming amount of literature on a broad set of topics.10 Robert Figueroa taught me the

value of focusing on a specific journal through a term paper he assigned in a graduate seminar in

Environmental Ethics that I took early in my studies at the University of North Texas. Martin

Yaffe’s studied assessment of Lynn White, Jr. and Aldo Leopold in his introduction to Jewish

Environmental Ethics boosted an inclination I already had to look critically at inherited

knowledge, even in a field as “subversive” as environmental ethics, which itself is not immune to

10 Mitcham’s scholarly disposition, one of humility and curiosity, also helped shape my own intellectual

self, though perhaps not as much as it should have.

13

repressing history. Adam Briggle’s patience, encouragement, and way he practices philosophy

also encouraged me to attempt a less conventional project.

More generally, my project was prompted by my respect for the intellectual efforts of the

eminences grises, especially Mitcham, Eugene Hargrove, and J. Baird Callicott, whose

encyclopedic knowledge of each specialization made my graduate studies a joy and whose

anecdotes introduced me to the personalities behind the ideas. My instructors who encouraged

careful readings of “old” texts taught me a robust distrust of the search for novelty, a distrust that

has been reinforced by comments of my own students. Another inspiration is my curiosity in the

role of journals in academic publishing and in the functioning of the university as institution.

Because my scholarly work began after searchable databases had become common, I wanted to

see how a medium with continuity that arises from a community of scholars—at least in

principle—had been transformed into one vein in a large pool from which individual articles on a

particular topic could be accessed. The change has much in common with the transition from

extended record albums to the rise of the single song, which has transformed the music industry.

My review also sets the stage for a better understanding of the forward-looking side of the Janus-

face of the journal environment, that is, the future of academic journals operating in a rapidly

changing media environment providing content to readers with differing interests and

affiliations, and who consume content from a variety of sources and through a variety of media.

Interests in the changing space of journal production evoked curiosity in a broader topic,

the consideration of how the structure of knowledge production and distribution in academia and

in general is structured now and will be structured in the future. I have already discussed

concerns about increasing disciplinization and specialization in academia, which arises in part as

a way to manage information. As argued earlier, many pressing societal problems cannot be

14

solved, or even conceptualized, through the lens of a single discipline. While the

interdisciplinary breadth of EE and RPT/Techné meant that my inquiry escaped disciplinary

boundaries from its origin, both still followed the general trend of disconnecting individuals from

their ideas. The peer review process, an attempt to avoid bias and to maintain quality, is “blind”

by design. While author information is published along with the articles, it is always in the

background, either buried in a footnote or a short section at the front or back of the volume, and

it is always terse. Subsequent citations of an article omit this information entirely. At the same

time, the chronological nature of journals in general obscures patterns of discourse, when volley

and response can be separated by years or even decades. Attending to these aspects of scholarly

participation offers the promise of opening up promising lines inquiry and illuminating barriers

to progress.

These concerns inspired me to amend my provisional inquiry to include more than a

comparative history of ideas. The history of ideas, as understood in Arthur O. Lovejoy’s classic

work into the interrelations and shifts of meanings of the Great Chain of Being, is the

fundamental model for the third and fourth chapters, which map the discourse on relevant

articles from philosophy of technology and environmental philosophy. The chapters do more

than that, though: they supplement the disembodied ideas with information about the thinkers

themselves. The chapters are intermediaries between a disembodied history of ideas and an

intellectual history that considers what the authors think or say, who they are, and what they do.

Yet my primary concentration is on the philosophical aspects of the two specializations, not just

a historical review. To provide an overarching framework for the inquiry, I have employed

Steve Fuller’s version of social epistemology.

15

CHAPTER 2

APPROACHING SEPARATE SPECIALIZATONS

My analysis concentrates on two journals, EE and RPT/Techné in order to overcome the

hurdles discussed previously that arise from an exponential growth in literature and terminology

in each specialization. It can be understood as a second-order complement to the essays from

each journal, which are the primary sources that possess the customary depth and rigor for

academic work. My analysis can be understood in a second way, as revealing and adding

texture, a third dimension, to the intellectual tapestry of both specializations.

Out of many quality journals in both fields, EE and RPT/Techné are the best

representatives of their respective specializations for several reasons. Both are well-respected,

flagship journals. Their reputations increase the likelihood that important themes, approaches,

and topics that have been discussed in each specialization are included in the journals, and that

the contributions flowed from the pens of distinguished scholars. Both journals emerged at the

same time, in the late 1970s, which makes them proper subjects for a comparative analysis. Both

have been published longer than most other journals concerned with these topics, which makes

them ideal candidates for a longitudinal study.

Both journals have rejected disciplinary boundaries. EE is subtitled “An Interdisciplinary

Journal Dedicated to the Philosophical Aspects of Environmental Problems.” When RPT:

Techné transitioned to a quarterly journal, its editors explicitly sought contributions from those

who were not academic philosophers "as long as their work meets the standards of some

philosophical perspective.”11 Seemingly counterintuitively, by focusing on a particular kind of

being—nature or technology—both journals managed to de-discipline philosophy, to grant it the

11 Paul T. Durbin, “Introduction to the New Journal,” JSPT 1, no. 1-2 (Fall 1995): 2, doi:

10.5840/techne199511/21 (italics in original).

16

breadth it had possessed until modern times, and to enlist the participation from those outside of

the confines of academic philosophy.

While the journals have much in common, they also diverge in significant ways, as a

quick look at their histories shows. EE has been under the hand of editor Eugene Hargrove since

its founding in 1979. Hargrove has traced its genesis even earlier, to 1977 “at about 10:30 AM

on April 29, somewhere between the tenth and fifteenth floors on an elevator in the Sheraton-

Chicago Hotel” at the Western Division Meeting of the American Philosophical Association.12

Initial institutional support was provided by the John Muir Institute, the University of New

Mexico, the American Conservation Association, and Chevron USA. In the first issue, Hargrove

identified two purposes for the journal: “first, as a forum for diverse interests and attitudes, and,

second, as a means towards the establishment of an environmental ethics institute, by creating

the technical material which will make such an institute possible.”13

Hargrove quickly achieved the second goal with the founding of Environmental

Philosophy, Inc., a non-profit that served as the holding company for the publication of the

journal, in September 1980. In the summer of 1981, Hargrove moved the journal to the

University of Georgia, where he had accepted a faculty position in the Department of Philosophy

and Religion at the University of Georgia. The journal was published at the University of

Georgia until 1990, when Hargrove moved to the University of North Texas. Since then, the

journal has been published there, and the Center for Environmental Philosophy, established by

Environmental Philosophy, Inc. in 1989, has also been located there. Hargrove is currently a

faculty member in the Department of Philosophy and Religion Studies.

12 Eugene Hargrove, “From the Editor: How, When, Where, Why,” EE 1, no. 1 (Spring 1979): 1, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics1979111. 13 Ibid., 1.

17

The simple history of EE stands in contrast to what has occurred at RPT/Techné, which

has had a series of editors over the course of its existence and has been published by several

different entities under a handful of names. It was first published as an annual series called

Research in Philosophy and Technology (RPT) in 1978 by JAI Press. The first editor was Paul

T. Durbin, who shepherded the journal as the official publication of the Society for Philosophy

and Technology (SPT) until 1985. Durbin was a longtime professor at the University of

Delaware. Due to a dispute between JAI and SPT that arose with Durbin’s initiation of the series

Philosophy and Technology, published by Kluwer, that built off of two earlier volumes in the

Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science series, and its promotion as the official publication

of SPT, Frederick Ferré was brought on as editor. RPT was published from 1989 through 1994,

it was published under the editorial hand of Ferré, a longtime professor at the University of

Georgia who also contributed to environmental philosophy literature. From 1995 to 2002,

publication continued under the general editorship of Carl Mitcham, who at the time was a

professor of philosophy and of science and technology studies at Pennsylvania State

University.14

Nine volumes (the third through the eleventh volumes) of Philosophy and Technology

were published between 1987 and 1994. Concern over the price of the volumes led the board of

SPT to create a quarterly electronic journal, first published in 1995 as the Journal of the Society

for Philosophy and Technology (JSPT). Durbin returned at the helm for three years, until 1997.

Peter Tijmes, a Dutch philosopher, served as editor from 1997 through 1999. The journal was

renamed in 2000 as Techné: Journal for the Society of Philosophy and Technology. From 2000

until 2007 it was edited by Davis Baird, at the present the chief academic officer for Clark

University. Joseph C. Pitt, a philosophy professor at Virginia Tech, published the journal from

14 Several editions had guest editors. A list of the volumes is included in Appendix A.

18

the fall of 2007 until the spring of 2014. The journal changed names again in 2008, becoming

Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology. The online journal is currently edited by

Neelke Doorn of Delft Univeristy and Diane P. Michelfelder of Macalester College and is

published three times a year.

Steve Fuller’s Social Epistemology as an Interpretative Key

While epistemology has usually not been concerned with specific individuals—instead

asking questions about how a person can justifiably claim to know something, or whether there

are limits to what a person can know, for example—social epistemology takes a different

approach. Social epistemology does not presume that knowledge is an absolute good that can

potentially be grasped by all individuals. Instead, it primarily understands knowledge as a social

product that gains validity based on consensual agreement more so than its coherence with

“objective truth.” Correspondingly, the validity of knowledge depends to some extent on the

breadth of contributors and the diversity of their outlooks. The appeal of consensus, the aim to

universal assent, has a counterbalance, however. Knowledge is power when it is held by some

but not others. To put it another way, knowledge is a relative social good.

The term social epistemology gained currency in the late 1980s, largely through the work

of Steve Fuller, who studied history and philosophy of science at the University of Pittsburgh.

He had encountered the term in Marc De Mey’s The Cognitive Paradigm (1982), but it was Fred

Schmidt’s call for papers for Synthese that Fuller calls the “proximate cause” of his inquiry.15

Fuller “took up the issues that arise from having to make decisions in the present, the

justification of which must be drawn from past cases while, at the same time, setting precedent

15 Steve Fuller, “Social Epistemology: A Quarter-Century Itinerary,” Social Epistemology: A Journal of

Knowledge, Culture and Policy 26, no. 3-4 (October 2012): 267-283. doi: 10.1080/02691728.2012.714415.

19

for future judgment.”16 His target was the common understanding that scientists were esteemed

judges of facts put before them. Their methodical judgment transforms a subjective position to

be universally binding on their colleagues. The commonly accepted scientific paradigm gains a

“objective validity” in this process. Fuller subscribed to the Edinburgh School of the sociology

of scientific knowledge, which challenged this viewpoint. He argued that this understanding of

science ignored its “repressed history,” and recognition of its history would “challenge the

epistemic monopoly of the dominant paradigm.”17 Fuller’s social epistemology rejects any

account that does not ask “how the agents came to be as they are, facing the problems that they

do, which in turn calls forth some sort of explicit epistemic activity.”18

Work in social epistemology has extended beyond Fuller’s initial interest in science and

of scientists, most notably by Fuller himself. One particularly impressive effort is Randall

Collins’s Sociology of Philosophies, which, as the title indicates, follows philosophers rather

than scientists, and, as the subtitle indicates, attempts an expansive goal of providing “a global

theory of intellectual change.”19 My dissertation can be seen as an extension and a hybrid of

Fuller’s original study of scientists and Collins’s work over histories of philosophies. Some

relevant articles in RPT/Techné and EE are written by scientists or technologists, others by

policy experts, and still others by philosophers. My effort tests several of Collins’s theories, and

it seeks to shed light on the history of the two specializations.

Repression is often unintentional and, despite its common connotation, may not be

negative. All histories, including all intellectual histories, are “repressive” to a degree, since

16 Ibid., 267-268. 17 Ibid., 268. Fuller’s version of social epistemology differs from analytic social epistemology, such as the

kind practiced by Alvin Goldman. Goldman’s version restricts its attention to “reliable processes for arriving at the truth” (269), a position that implies that truth can be disembodied and decontextualized, a position that Goldman’s fellow analytic social epistemologist William Alston criticized as being fit for androids, not humans.

18 Ibid., 279-280.

20

only some facts can be included and these must be contextualized, even if the rationale for

inclusion is left unstated. As the two specializations in which I am interested pass into their

second intellectual generation,20 histories become codified. This transition point is a good time

to look for underappreciated articles.

The gold standard of the discovery that can be done in cross-specialization or cross-

discipline review can be found in the work of Don R. Swanson. Swanson was an information

scientist, who proposed, and, in that sense, “discovered,” that fish oil could cure Raynaud’s

syndrome.21 Swanson had no medical training and ran no experiments to arrive at this

discovery. Instead, his research consisted of reviewing articles from specializations that rarely

cross-pollinated, that is, rarely cited each others work, but yet were concerned with related

topics. In the process, Swanson debunked the prevailing wisdom that uncited articles were of

little importance and highlighted the importance of working across specializations. Later, in an

ASIST Award of Merit acceptance speech, he made a radical claim: “the connection explosion

may be more portentous than the information explosion.”22

While the possible outcomes of my research address a far less corporeal concern and are

concerned with philosophical rather than scientific research, I wanted to investigate whether

similar opportunities may exist in the connection of two specializations of my inquiry.23 To do

so required two lacunae of knowledge to be filled. The first was the gap between my

19 Randall Collins, The Sociology of Philosophies: A Global Theory of Intellectual Change (Cambridge,

Massachusetts: Belknap Press, 1998). 20 This concept, developed by Randall Collins, is discussed in more detail later in the text. 21 Swanson’s landmark discovery was published in 1986 in two journals, as “Undiscovered Public

Knowledge” in Library Quarterly 56, no. 2: 103-118, and "Fish Oil, Raynaud's Syndrome, and Undiscovered Public Knowledge” in Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 30, no. 1: 7-18.

22 Swanson, Don R. “On the Fragmentation of Knowledge, the Connection Explosion, and Assembling Other People’s Ideas,” Bulletin of the American Society for Information Science and Technology 27, no. 3 (February/March 2001), http://www.asis.org/Bulletin/Mar-01/swanson.html.

23 Swanson proposes that his approach may work in the humanities as well in “Undiscovered Public Knowledge,” 104.

21

understanding of each specialization, especially compared to the eminences grises, who knew

minor works in each specialization of which most young scholars were unaware. The second

lacuna was a systematic and comprehensive inquiry into how each specialization handled the

other. Since each was at least slightly “off-topic” to the other, it is reasonable to expect that both

may have suffered neglect on this account. I address the first gap, as best as possible, in the

histories in the third and fourth chapters. The second gap was the lack of a comprehensive

comparison between the two specializations, which I address to a degree in the fifth chapter, by

comparing the results found in the third and fourth chapters, which are supplemented by sketches

of individuals who contributed to both journals based on their articles.

While Fuller’s work provides the foundational structure for my inquiry, Collins’s magnus

opus provided several concepts and theories that guided the practical aspects of my inquiry.

Collins posited that the proper period of analysis of academic works is the timeframe of an

intellectual generation, roughly a third of a century, which is the current age of both EE and

RPT/Techné. While identifying intellectual epochs becomes more difficult as a specialization or

discipline develops, the designation seems particularly appropriate during the first generation. In

the case of both EE and RPT/Techné, the timeframe is personified: the first editors of each

journal are approaching the end of their academic careers, yet both are still active participants in

scholarly discourse. Durbin, however, already does so from an emeritus position, and Ferré, an

editor of RPT in the 1990s, has died. The passing of an intellectual generation marks a possible

inflection point, i.e., a change of direction of the specialization. At the same time, it seems likely

that the transition entails a loss of historical knowledge.

Collins argued that philosophical advances always take the form of dialogical moves.

Successors in a scholarly discourse, he says, respond to earlier works by either saying “yes, and”

22

or “no, but,” that is, either amending by addition or by positing a different line of argument.

Collins makes the even bolder claim that these responses can be predicted if one can

conceptualize the historical trajectory of the field, at least over a longer period of time. My

project tested whether his theory could predict movements in each specialization in the short

term and found it lacking. The binary structure that he observed, which may have been an

artifact constructed by the historians of philosophy who wrote the histories on which his analysis

was based, was a poor framework for organizing articles from RPT/Techné and EE.

Collins’s methodology has been rightly criticized by Fuller for excluding informal and

non-philosophical voices while purporting to provide a “global theory of intellectual change.”24

Because Collins’s theories arose from analyzing standard philosophical histories, intellectual life

appears “both self-organizing and self-oriented.”25 Fuller warns that “the fact that academics are

the premier producers of intellectual histories means that sociologists of knowledge need to take

extra care to ensure that the ultimate contributions of non-academic intellectuals are not

underestimated.”26 My project was designed to include the viewpoints of those who did not

pursue academic careers, whose contribution would most likely be ignored in a “repressed” and

simplified history of the field, though as far as I can tell, only a couple of contributors fall into

this category. My second claim for success on this front arises from the interdisciplinary nature

of both journals. Both journals explicitly invite contributions from those who are not academic

philosophers. Yet my review is still limited to those seeking an academic journal as a forum for

discourse, which excludes public intellectuals, journalists, policy-makers, and many others. The

ethical orientation most clearly present in EE but also common in RPT/Techné mitigates against

the risk that I will overemphasize philosophical research on metaphysics and epistemology, a

24 Fuller, Sociology of Intellectual Life, 45. 25 Ibid., 47.

23

charge Fuller levies against Collins’s study on account of the predilection of historians of

philosophy toward those areas of inquiry.27

The simplification or “repression” that arises by necessity in extensive academic histories

of philosophy can be seen in the two specializations that I am investigating as primary texts are

condensed into topical histories. Evidence of repression is the repeated use of the same

quotations or basic summaries in most later articles. While it can be the case that a pithy phrase

can summarize an entire argument, the “stock” citations often seem to fulfill a requirement

without giving any indication that the rest of the article or book was understood, and, in some

cases, even read.

Fuller gives two more reasons such quotation conformity should cause concern. First, it

supports the status quo by further elevating the “relevance,” at least in terms of citations, of

dominant voices in a field and by minimizing others. Quantitative tools often utilized in the

early stages of research function as designed when they exclude outlying viewpoints. The

increasing use of such metrics by tenure committee and administrators exacerbates these

concerns. Second, the practice “fosters a dependency culture whereby academics are rewarded

for feats of ventriloquism, that is, an ability to speak through the authority of others. The result

is institutionalized cowardice.”28 Regardless of whether Fuller is right about the consequence,

the shorthand used for such references often serves as a barrier to those who do not have formal

training in a field. Further, few references take adequate account of the material and social

conditions in which a statement is made, and even fewer adequately explain the perspective of

the contributors.

26 Ibid., 52. 27 Ibid., 44-45. Proof of this is that Collins’s study gives short shrift to someone like Machiavelli. In

addition, Fuller points out that Collins’s bias in favor of metaphysics and epistemology at the expense of value theory is a rejection of the positions of Leo Strauss and Quentin Skinner, one that Collins leaves unjustified.

24

Fuller’s inspiration led me to test the hypothesis that philosophy of technology and

environmental philosophy are mistakenly understood if they are not thought of as products of a

social processes, rather than as disembodied and decontextualized history of ideas as they appear

in academic journals. My study is a first step in considering the agents who have contributed to

each specialization in order to make sense of how they choose and approach their topics.

Surveys of discourse in which the contributors are situated in various disciplines, as EE and

RPT/Techné contributors are, are at risk of serious distortion if these factors are not taken into

account.

My inquiry also exemplifies both ways that Fuller claims that philosophy can relate to

interdisciplinarity. Fuller calls the first way normal interdisciplinarity, which posits philosophy

as a store of all knowledge, and the adjudicator of its disciplinary and specialization divisions. In

this sense, all intellectual work is philosophy, just as Newton called his laws natural philosophy,

not natural science. Philosophy regains its pre-disciplined precedence. Each journal is

interdisciplinary to an extent, and, a fortiori, so is my inquiry.

My inquiry also interdisciplinary in a deviant sense, to use Fuller’s terminology. He says

“philosophy itself may be the site for the production of interdisciplinary knowledge, understood

as a kind of second-order understanding of reality that transcends the sort of knowledge that the

disciplines provide left to their own devices.”29 By design, I seek a second order understanding,

though my comparative analysis works between specializations, not disciplines, that are usually

considered part of philosophy. It is a measure of the hyperspecialization present in the

contemporary academic environment that an approach intended to bridge disciplines can work

within one. It is all the more troubling that this is true within philosophy, which has historical

28 Ibid., 86. 29 Fuller, “Social Epistemology,” 273.

25

resources that can counteract tendencies toward fragmentation that have accompanied other

disciplines since they were founded.

There is at least one important difference between my approach in this inquiry and what

Fuller argues for. My research has been primarily inductive, not deductive. It seeks to be more

responsive to what has been said than the “trying” of a preconceived argument or position. My

intention is to work with an attitude of curiosity associated with the philosophy of the ancient

Greeks. According to both Plato and Aristotle, “the source and spring of philosophy is wonder

or curiosity,”30 which differs character from an approach that is active and agent-oriented, where

knowledge and power are cojoined. Fuller argues—at least in the sciences—for “belief by

decision” rather than “belief by evidence,” i.e., to assert and test a hypothesis rather than letting,

as the phrase goes, “the facts speak for themselves.” Fuller first argues for the former in science

and social epistemology, but his “proactionary” principle that bridges epistemic and moral values

extends “belief by decision” to philosophical and ethical questions themselves.31

Let me briefly summarize the ways in which my study relates to Collins and Fuller.

First, whereas Fuller focused on scientists, Collins concentrated on philosophers, who

contributed the majority of relevant articles to RPT/Techné and EE. Second, the theoretical debt

for the longitudinal structure of the inquiry and its appropriateness at the present time is owed to

Collins, though obviously my aims—two specializations over a single “intellectual life span”—

are but a fraction of his global theory that extends over recorded philosophical history. Third,

my inquiry can be seen as a test of his theory that intellectual discourse can be characterized as

“yes, and” or “no, but,” which, prima facie, seemed appealing yet overly simplistic. Fourth, my

30 W. K. C. Guthrie, A History of Greek Philosophy: The Earlier Presocratics and the Pythagoreans, vol. 1

(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1962), 30. 31 Fuller, “Social Epistemology,” 278.

26

attempt to delineate contributors to the two specializations through their discourse patterns tests

Collins’s theories developed from his sociological analysis.

Important differences exist between Collins’s work and the present inquiry. One

difference is that I foreground the progression of ideas rather than people. It is first a history of

ideas, then a sociology, the reverse of Collins. A second difference is that my research is based

on a review of the works of the authors themselves. As Fuller pointed out in his criticism,

Collins used commonly available histories of philosophies, separated by tens if not hundreds of

degrees from the original intellectuals and their works. A third difference is that my comparative

inquiry uses the parallel social and intellectual progression of the specializations with the goal of

identifying promising future research projects, a more sophisticated synthesis than the binary

“yes, and”/“no, but” structure proposed by Collins.

My approach has several limitations. The greatest is that it further exaggerates the

impact of a few editors and reviewers and the limited intellectuals who chose to contribute to the

journals. Also, focusing on two journals excludes a priori many important articles and books

that have shaped intellectual inquiry on the relation of humans to their technology and to the rest

of the world, including the environment. Since EE and RPT were started, moreover, the

academic publishing space has become more fragmented. My study excludes newer offshoots,

including journals such as Environmental Values and Philosophy and Technology, that deal with

similar issues, and other publications that focus first on policy or science. Furthermore, any

second-order analysis includes the risk of misinterpreting or of treating articles superficially

because it is an analysis based on an individual’s summarization of the primary texts. If the first

step is flawed, the second will be, too.

27

Analyzing EE, which now has all of its issues online, had its difficulties. Many early

articles were assigned keywords that most likely would be different today, after thirty years of

development of each specialization. In addition, the secondary nature of philosophical issues

relating to technology in a journal targeting the environment meant that a simple keyword

analysis for technology, artifact, or techné was inadequate. I compiled an initial set of relevant

articles by searching the Philosopher’s Index for EE articles that mentioned technology, built

environment, design, artifact, and art in abstracts and titles. The relevant words were developed

by starting with artifact and technology and, in the course of research, discovering articles that

should have been included but had not been, and then revising the search to include the relevant

keywords used for those articles. This results of this search were overly broad, and some of the

articles were rejected after review because they did not investigate any philosophical aspects of

technology.

My hopes of analyzing the articles through a quantitative analysis were frustrated for

several reasons. First, the quality of the abstracts varied significantly. Generally, abstracts from

early articles were less reliable than more recent ones. Second, most environmental concerns

arise because of human impacts on the environment, and these are normally amplified by

technology. The mention of technology, as a keyword or in the title or abstract, does not indicate

any reflective inquiry into technology. Third, in all but a few articles, philosophical aspects of

technology were a peripheral concern, so they were expressed more summarily, if at all, in the

abstracts.

The challenges encountered in analyzing EE were minimal compared to what was

encountered analyzing RPT/Techné. RPT/Techné had the analogous issue that philosophical

inquiry on the environment was usually a secondary concern. Difficulties with abstracts and

28

keywords in EE paled compared to what was encountered with Techné. Whereas with EE

abstracts and keywords were somewhat unreliable, keywords and abstracts were not even

included in RPT/Techné until the publication was moved in a quarterly electronic format in 1995.

Nearly two decades of articles lack this “metadata,” which not only would have greatly

simplified my study, but also, in a sense, conceals the content of the articles. Unlike EE, which

has digitized all of its volumes, volumes of RPT are not available in an electronic format. These

shortcomings impede the use of indices, such as Thompson Reuters Web of Science, an

interdisciplinary index, that otherwise could be used to assess the “impact” of its articles and

which articles they cite. Further compounding these difficulties, early issues of RPT predate the

period over which Web of Science currently indexes articles, a particular problem because it

excludes early articles, the ones that were fundamental to the extent that the journal operates as a

progressive publication, i.e., that articles build of each other. For the preceding reasons,

indexing tools were used as research supplements, but were of little help.

Editorial and format changes have resulted in many disruptions that serve as obstacles to

longitudinal analysis. Over its history, RPT/Techné has shifted from an annual publication based

on SPT conference proceedings to a more traditional quarterly journal, which is a transition that

if studied could reveal interesting discontinuities. For several years–1985 to 1987–no volumes

were published, and from 1989 to 1992 and from 1995 to 2002, articles were published in more

than one outlet. Though these changes complicate any analysis, as I argued earlier, the different

outlets are best considered as one journal since the SPT community that supported them was

largely the same.

I initially tried to identifying relevant articles by reviewing editor introductions for

volumes that lacked abstracts. Unfortunately, while many were descriptive and informative,

29

others were far too concise to be helpful. In many cases, summaries provided in the editors’

introductions added little other than the title of the essay. Had they been more consistently more

informative, the introductions could have served as the counterpart to EE abstracts for

quantitative and bibliometric analysis, which would likely yield interesting insights. Yet even if

this were the case, Techné would differ from EE for the abstracts would have been the editors,

not the authors. The amount of work required to build roughly equivalent provisional abstracts

and keywords for all of the articles exceeded the time allotted to my project, though I anticipate

the results would be valuable.

These impediments, while frustrating, point to one aspect of the value of this project.

RPT is rarely held by university libraries.32 Yet from its origin it has regularly published essays

that are well researched and clearly articulate important aspects of a range of topics, including

those that have to do with the environment. The limited availability of RPT means that, absent

efforts like mine, part of the intellectual endowment accumulated over the last thirty years is

being dissipated. This loss is not occurring deliberately, i.e., with as the result of a conscious

decision that recent scholarly contributions exceed earlier articles in quality, breadth, or depth, as

far as I can tell. Instead, it seems to occur absent any direct cause. At a minimum, the loss leads

to some intellectual inefficiency, as contemporary scholars must rework what their predecessors

had already investigated. It also leads to the loss of the history of ideas, a lineage that can reveal

the forces—intellectual, political, and physical—that led to the current state of affairs. For all

those that do not subscribe to a Hegelian progression of intellectual history, there is no reason to

assume that current publications are sublimations of their predecessors. It is at least possible,

32 A search of www.worldcat.org for one early volume of the journal resulted in one match, at the

Universite Libre de Bruxelles - Bibliotheques. While this is not accurate—Texas A&M has most of the volumes—it is indicative of the rarity of a complete set of RPT.

30

and perhaps likely, that early articles in RPT (as well as JSPT) capture and articulate important

concepts, theories, and conflicts more clearly than later articles do.

While my approach has some important limitations, no approach can claim

comprehensiveness for matters that cross so many aspects of life. Reuniting philosophical

approaches to technology and nature expands the field of study to include all physical beings.

The most expansive interpretation would include non-fictional literature—especially that which

discusses the natural sciences—and fiction that affects how nature or art and beings in general

are conceptualized, an expanse that exceeds the grasp of any one human intellect. More

common approaches to manage the scope of academic inquiry, which are also integral parts of

the intellectual tapestry, also have limitations. Concentrating on a particular issue such as

climate change or hydrofracking necessarily treats other issues peripherally, and more general

claims cannot be substantiated from such a specific inquiry. Limiting an inquiry to a particular

philosophical approach such as hermeneutics provides a sliver of the philosophical insight, but it

necessarily excludes all others. Focusing on a particular intellectual who bridges the two

specializations such as Hans Jonas often results in at best incremental development, and, at

worse, a loss of clarity and force from the author’s original formulations. By pointing out the

shortcomings of other common approaches, I do not mean to disparage their importance. They

provide the fabric for the intellectual tapestry, thread by thread. My project aims to illumine the

artwork as a whole, to describe its development and the people who have developed it.

Subsequent Lines of Inquiry

In general, this work is intended as an foray to bring two separate specializations into

contact. Intellectuals from one specialization or another discipline may find that it serves as a

handy reference to the historical development of different ideas in each specialization, and how

31

they can proceed with it is limited only by their creativity. Scientists or policy-makers whose

work touches both specializations can test the first-order theories from the journal summaries

and the second-order reflection of this work. Instructors may be spurred into further

developments by student comments, and so on.

There are a number of other lines of inquiry that deserve to be adumbrated at this point.

• Most promisingly, more comparative analysis can be done to identify where progress has

been made in one specialization that can enrich or perhaps is in contrast with what has

happened in the other specialization. Points of convergence, divergence, and conflict can

be sketched out in more detail, and new syntheses can be developed.

• Consideration of how environmental ethics and philosophy of technology can inform

other “conventional” philosophical approaches, such as hermeneutics and feminism, can

be done by overlaying the histories sketched out here with journals dedicated with the

conventional approaches.

• More information about the authors, including their backgrounds, current positions, and

other interests, would further flesh out the biographical history. This research could

indicate viewpoints that have been excluded or have been “repressed.”

• Many more quantitative comparisons can be made between the two journals. These

studies would be aided immensely by the digitalization of early volumes of RPT. A

comparison could be done between the case studies chosen to see how they differ

between specializations, perhaps even when the same issue is at stake, and plotting them

geographically could lead to awareness of areas that have been ignored. A comparison

between citations may also prove fruitful, for example, to compare how different articles

develop the phenomenological insights of someone such as Merleau-Ponty.

32

• Digitalization would also enable more quantitative analysis into the general trends of

each journal. Meta-analysis would provide reflective insights into the workings of social

groups that function, to a degree, autopoeitically.

• The study could be expanded to include another journal. Those focused on policy or

environmental science would add still another dimension to the intellectual tapestry.

At this point, let me background further extensions and move to the current project.

33

CHAPTER 3

NATURE (PHYSIS) IN RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY AND TECHNOLOGY/TECHNÉ

The concept of nature has been a topic of interest in Research in Philosophy and

Technology (RPT) since its second volume (1979), which included two articles on the topic.33

While many articles have been published since that time, two volumes deserve special attention

for the purposes of this inquiry. The topic of the 1992 theme section was “Technology and the

Environment,” edited by Frederick Ferré. Ferré was the chair of the Department of Philosophy

at the University of Georgia from 1984 to 1991, was an established voice in environmental ethics

discourse, and had also published Philosophy of Technology (1984). The theme section consists

of five parts, “Technology and Environmental Ethics,” “Ethics versus Activism? An Exchange,”

“Technological Hazards, Economics, and Environmental Management,” “Technology and

Harvesting the Earth,” and “Technology and Nature: Struggle or Synthesis?”

The other primary volume of interest was the 1999 volume titled “Philosophies of the

Environment and Technology.” Published under the general editorship of Carl Mitcham, the

volume was guest edited by Marina Paola Banchetti, Don E. Marietta, Jr., and Lester Embree,

who were Florida Atlantic University professors at the time. Banchetti and Embree still teach at

FAU; Marietta, an Episcopal priest turned philosophy professor, died on 2006. The primary aim

of the volume, according Banchetti, is “examining the possibility, perhaps even the desirability,

of merging environmental philosophy with philosophy of technology.”34 While the two

specializations are not ignorant of the other, “participants in neither subdiscipline are anywhere

near being sufficiently prepared in the discussion and insights of the other.”35 According to

33 See the List of Abbreviations for the shorthand used for the different publications associated with the

Society for Philosophy and Technology. 34 Maria Banchetti, Introduction, RPT 18 (1999): 4. 35 Ibid., 4.

34

Banchetti, environmental ethics discourse is overly fixated on wilderness, which can be

counterbalanced by the attention to the built environment, its processes, and its consequences in

philosophy and technology. Philosophy of technology, on the contrary, often displays a “naïve

anthropocentrism” that underestimates ecological concerns.36 The volume did not build

permanent bridges over the deep faults between the specializations (or subdisciplines as she calls

them), and I submit that Banchetti’s diagnosis still holds: there still are not enough participants

who have robust knowledge in both specifications, and the volume failed to lead to significant

sustained dialogue between the specializations.

On the whole, articles published in RPT: Techné that dealt with nature in a

philosophically interesting way can be grouped into five constellations. Several articles focus on

the term nature from its origins in Greek times through the present. The second constellation

corresponds most closely with this dissertation, which focuses on intersection of nature and

technology. Contributors include notable environmental philosophers J. Baird Callicott, Holmes

Rolston, III, and Eric Katz, post-phenomenologist Don Ihde and Deweyan Larry Hickman, and

ecofeminist Karen Warren. Hickman’s effort to begin a dialogue with environmental

philosophers deserves special commendation, though it was not met with much of a response.

The third constellation consists of articles on some combination of science and technology and

nature. It can be divided into three groupings: one on nature and science, a second on Heidegger

and nature, which includes several articles that develop the thought of Albert Borgmann, and the

third on how novel technologies such as biotechnology and nanotechnology have led to

reconsidering how nature is conceptualized. The fourth constellation consists of two articles on

religion, which both follow the vein of Lynn White, Jr.’s connection between Western

36 Ibid., 5.

35

Christianity and Western technology. The fifth constellation consists of nature and technology in

politics and policy.

Nature Seen Historically

The first constellation of papers that can be discerned investigate the meaning of nature in

different historical periods. Wolfgang Schadewaldt recovered the original sense of the Greek

term, which differs from the Latin term and how nature is now used in contemporary speech, and

David E. Tabachnick looked back to Thucydides and Sophocles to see how the ancient Greeks

understood phusis and tuche (chance), which work together to frustrate technical projects while

in a surprising way enriching human existence. Klaus Michael Meyer-Abich advocated for a

return to the Greek and Roman understandings of nature. Douglas Groothuis applied Blaise

Pascal’s critique of the Enlightenment aims of scientific knowledge and technological progress

to Francis Bacon’s proposal for a new organon, and Jacques Ellul contrasted how primitive

technique freed humans from the demands of nature, but modern technique asserts its own

demands that are constraints. Gregor Schiemann offered a contemporary definition of nature,

“that which is not produced by human beings,” that depends on scientific knowledge to address

the issue of how to consider the products of nanotechnologies, which seem to be neither natural

nor artificial. Based on a literature survey, Jacob Klein explained seven dimensions of the term

nature, which can be mapped to human ritual. Gao Desheng and Zou Tsing provided a brief

summary of the relationship between humanity and nature in Chinese philosophy.

Wolfgang Schadewaldt explained that the universal sense of the term “nature” arises

from the Latin word natura, from the verb nasci, which means to be born.37 The word referred

to “the uterine orifice of a female quadruped,” the place where new beings come to be. Natura,

37 Wolfgang Schadewaldt, “The Concepts of Nature and Technique according to the Greeks, RPT 2 (1979):

159-171.

36

though, is an early translation of the Greek term phýsis. The Greek term never designated a set of

objects that is often meant by the term today.38 The root verb phýo, used chiefly in the botanical

and zoological realms, means “bring-forth,” “put forth,” or “make to grow.” The noun phýsis

works similarly in function to an English gerund, and it means “a coming-to-pass, an event, a

directing activity.”39 The comprehensive sense of the Greek term, which meant “the wholeness

and unity of form and motion, law and life, causality and purpose,”40 has splintered since Greek

concepts were rediscovered in Europe at the end of the medieval period. The ancient Greeks

understood techné as physis plus, a “coming-to-be” that requires imagination, design, and

production as preparatory steps to “perfect” nature by altering it to meet human needs.

David E. Tabachnick’s “Techné, Technology, and Tragedy” honed in on differences

between premodern and modern technology.41 Advocates of the latter tend to deny tragedy as “a

defining characteristic of human existence even in the technological age.” Premodern technics

accepts limitations of and lack of control expected in modern technologies, which can be seen by

investigating Thucydides’ The History of Peloponnesian War, in which chance (tuche) gains a

sort of agency through the workings of nature (phusis), subverting the aims of craft (techné). For

example, thunderstorms douse the arsonery of the Peloponnesians, and the plague that struck

Athens was introduced through attempts to conquer the Egyptians. Sophocles proposed that the

fourth stage of technical achievement, after humans have subordinated the earth and its animals,

the elements, and disease, is a confusion between good judgment and technical judgment, which

puts humans at risk again. Tabachnick followed Heidegger’s take on the tragedy of techné: “the

38 Ibid., 161-163. The closest Aristotle came to this sense of the term, according to Schadewaldt, is phýsis-

natura, which is undifferentiated primal matter, and as hóle phýsis, the entire visible cosmos. 39 Ibid., 160. 40 Ibid., 164. 41 David E. Tabachnick, “Techné, Technology, and Tragedy,” Techné: RPT 7, no. 3 (2004): 90-111.

37

technical imposition of order is the spur for the renewal of disorder,” which is counterintuitively

a good thing, because overcoming death, an apparent success, actually results in dehumanization.

Klaus Michael Meyer-Abich argued that a biocentric perspective is superior to one that

considers nature as that which can be dominated, through experiment or as resource.42 The

principle necessary for this shift can be found in Ernst Bloch, who seeks to reorient “nature”

from things (natura naturata) to the existing of those beings (natura naturans). Meyer-Abich

argued that “natural conditions prevail where something can grow by itself or is nonviolently

assisted to develop its inherent qualities. Natural, therefore, is not only what is not artificial–

indeed the artificial may be more natural than what has wildly grown–but not every technology

fulfills the criterion of being natural.”43

In “Bacon and Pascal on Mastery over Nature,” Douglas Groothuis contrasted Francis

Bacon’s advocacy of a new epistemology by which “nature could be deciphered, demystified,

and ultimately commanded to release humans from the iron grip of necessity” with Blaise

Pascal’s critique on the project of scientific and technological progress.44 Bacon’s stepwise

inductive method promised to free its practitioners from hasty leaps in reasoning and from

uncertainties associated with Aristotelian concepts of final causation and teleology that were

important to the Scholastics. In doing so, he transforms knowledge from contemplation or

recognition to a hut or discovery, to use Paolo Rossi’s phrases cited by Groothuis.

Though Pascal did not respond directly to Bacon, Groothuis redeploys Pascal, who

himself was a scientist and experimenter, in fact, one far more accomplished than Bacon, for that

purpose. Pascal’s first criticism of Bacon is that he does not heed his own exhortations against

42 Klaus Michael Meyer-Abich, “What Sort of Technology Permits the Language of Nature? Conditions for

Controlling Nature-Domination Constitutionally,” Philosophy and Technology. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 80. P&T 1 (1983): 211-232.

43 Ibid., 230.

38

hubris in his project of expanding human knowledge. According to Pascal, “The secrets of

nature are hidden; though she is ever active, we do not always discover her doings. Time reveals

them from age to age and although nature constantly remains uniform, she is not uniformly

known,”45 and if this is right, Bacon’s comprehensive epistemic effort is doomed to fail. Pascal

also retained a sense of wonder at the expanse of the universe and at the miniscule within it.46

He wrote that it is as “impossible to know the parts without knowing the whole as to know the

whole without knowing the individual parts”47 due to the interconnectedness of nature, a holistic

sensitivity that anticipates the balance that many ecologists try to strike.

Jacques Ellul posited that the encroachment of technique leads to “a more extreme

evaluation of nature.”48 Yet this elevation of “nature” as a guiding principle for human behavior

is an anthropological mistake: humans are artificial beings that change their environment

through their work and gain their identities “over and against nature.”49 Because humans are

artificial, Ellul makes the dual claim that “nature is not a model, and nature is not a limitation on

human action,” though humans act “in a natural environment and in relation to it.”50 Humans

gained freedoms, i.e., the loosening of the bonds of the necessities of nature, through their

societies, in which knowledge, religion, art, and technique were developed. Modern technique,

however, reverses this relationship.

That is to say, we now have to consider that what used to be means to freedom has become a condition of slavery and what has always been the mechanism of necessity has become the occasion for a possible freedom. This is the main difficulty for ecology

44 Douglas Groothuis, “Bacon and Pascal on Mastery over Nature,” RPT 14 (1994): 191-203. 45 p. 196, from E. Cailliet and J.C. Blankenagel, Great Shorter Works of Pascal (Philadelphia: Westminster

Press, 1948), p. 46. Quoted in Wells, p. 59. 46 Pascal’s thought is also in contrast with René Descartes’s Discourse on Method, who argues for dividing

a thing into its parts for the sake of knowing it better. 47 Pascal, Pensees, fragment 199/72. 48 Jacques Ellul, “Nature, Technique and Artificiality,” RPT 3 (1980): 264. 49 Ibid., 267 (italics in original). 50 Ibid., 268, 277 (italics in original).

39

which should not be a romantic dream or a medieval pastoral, but which should be correctly thought in terms of a precise analysis of the technical world.51

A reinterpretation of ecology, the science most closely related to environmental ethics, provides

a germ for the fusion of philosophy, technology, and the environment that Banchetti had

requested. Unfortunately, Ellul does not provide more detail about his idea, which seems to

promote inquiry similar to what is found in Science and Technology Studies at the cost of

ignoring the natural context in which people act and how the organisms in that context behave at

different levels of human manipulation.52

Gregor Schiemann proposed that the term “nature” should be understood as “that which

is not produced by human beings” in “Nanotechnology and Nature: On Two Criteria for

Understanding Their Relationship.”53 Whereas Aristotle explains things that come about on their

own accord, in contrast to craft or chance, Schiemann’s definition is atemporal and experimental.

An object should be considered natural “if it is impossible with all scientific methods available at

a given time to detect that it was produced by human action; alternatively, an object is to be

defined as artificial if it can be scientifically demonstrated that it was produced by human

action.” His epistemic approach makes it possible that many objects can be considered neither

natural nor artificial, including some that are of artificial origin. He claims that at least at the

present, the inability of an object to adapt “attests to a human origin.”

From a literature survey of the many uses of the term nature, Jacob Klein identified seven

dimensions of the term that can be mapped to the dimensions of human ritual.54 The first is that

nature is horizontal, by which he means that “by nature” only makes sense in relation to

51 Ibid., 275. 52 I pursue this line of reasoning at some length in Chapter 5. 53 Gregor Schiemann, “Nanotechnology and Nature: On Two Criteria for Understanding Their

Relationship,” Hyle 11, no. 1 (2005): 77-96, http://www.hyle.org/journal/issues/11-1/schiemann.htm. 54 Jacob Klein, “The Concepts of Nature and Technique According to the Greeks,” RPT 2 (1979): 173-188.

40

something else. A person may be evil by nature, but the qualification implies an alternative. The

second sense of the term is rivalry, such as the distinction between supernatural or revolutionary

events and those that regularly occur. Klein described an inward sense of nature, which means

that a being must maintain its stable identity (or be itself) while simultaneously changing (or

coming to be).

Humans also have a vertical relationship with nature, in that its behavior can be

explained by laws that can be explained through mathematical principles. Klein calls this the

“submission of nature to mathematically formulated principles.”55 He emphasizes the difference

between the laws of nature, mentioned previously, and the law of nature, which has a moral

sense that is inherent and can be revealed by reason and reflection. The law of nature was often

understood, at least in the 17th century, “as reflecting the inviolable mathematical principles of

nature.”56 The moral sense is opposed with the passionate sense, which operates at least

somewhat independently of and often contrary to the faculty of reason. The last sense Klein

identifies is the relationship of detached nearness. Experience of the grandeur of nature can be

sublime, which can “shake our detachment and transform it into the feeling of our minuteness

and insignificance.”57

In “Philosophy of Technology in China,” Gao Dasheng and Zou Tsing note that Chen

Changshu and Yuan Deyu both distinguish artificial nature and natural nature.58 The relationship

between humanity and nature is one that should be coordinated (Bian Chunyuan); seen

evolutionary (Hua Daming and Hua Liguang), from coordination, to human domination, to a new

coordinated equilibrium. Technology has been argued to be a dynamic force that dominates

55 Ibid., 181. 56 Ibid., 184. 57 Ibid., 186.

41

nature (Liu Zeyuan), which demands an approach that accounts for material and intellectual

production, as well as social construction.

At the Intersection of Nature and Techné

A second constellation can be divined from papers that are based on a philosophical

approach to the intersection between physis and techné. J. Baird Callicott contributed two

articles that sketch out how technology will likely change based on recent advances in ecology.

Holmes Rolston, III, argued that arguments that claim nature has now become part of culture

confuse epistemological dependency with ontological dependency. Don Ihde proposed a critical

realism as a “third way” between the dystopian future imagined by many environmentalists and

the utopian future imagined by advocates of technology. Larry A. Hickman took a Deweyian

pragramatist approach in arguing that nature can be valued in the immediacy of the moment, i.e.,

unreflectively, and reflectively, which is technological to the extent that it depends on judgment

and techniques, understood broadly. In the same paper, Hickman also interrogated the ideas of

Callicott, Bryan Norton, Michael Zimmerman, and Rolston. In an earlier paper, Hickman

explained Dewey’s understanding of the relationship between nature and machine technology.

Karen Warren situated ecofeminism at the intersection of feminism; science, technology, and

development; and environmental concerns, arguing that they should be necessarily intertwined.

T. Maarten T. Coolen developed a notion of philosophical anthropology in which humanity is

realized, in part, through their technology. Herbert Simon connected the artificial and the natural

in the human brain, according to Sytse Strijbos.

RPT also published a group of papers from the 1994 Central Division American

Philosophical Association author meets critics session on David Rothenberg’s Hand’s End:

58 Gao Dasheng and Zou Tsing, "Philosophy of Technology in China,” Philosophy and Technology:

Practical, Historical, and Other Dimensions. P&T 6 (1989): 133-151.

42

Technology and the Limits of Nature. Dwight Furrow proposed that the ethical claims of nature

are stronger than just discovering the limits of ecosystem manipulation that would lead to

fundamental alteration of their functions. David Abram argued that Rothenberg always had

portrayed nature as passive, which understates its interventions in human existence. David

Lovekin argued that two forgotten characteristics of good design, ingenio and fantasia, can be

rediscovered by looking at the drawings of sixteenth century engineer Agostino Ramelli.

Callicott argued that the reified dichotomy between nature and humans, a baneful and

unhelpful artifact based on Western philosophical, religious, and political history, has

exacerbated the mechanistic tendencies of the modern period.59 Such tendencies have led to or

worsened many of the environmental issues faced today. Fortunately, the postmodern “model of

nature” is organismic, which promotes concern for the “health” of an ecosystem which can be

determined by “objective and intrinsic” ecological indices using hierarchy theory.60 Mechanistic

technology, Callicott argued, will give way to appropriate technology, such as the embrace of

solar power by some of his friends and a 1989 National Academy of Sciences Board on

Agriculture recommendation of organic, smaller-scale farming techniques, that is attuned to the

“holistic, systematic, dynamic concept of nature.”61

Six years later, Callicott addressed the question of “After the Industrial Paradigm,

What?”62 He argued that since our social relations follow our conception of nature, as

materialistic and individualistic modernity recedes into the rearview mirror, the interrelationships

that are the topic of inquiry for environmental studies will become increasingly important.

59 J. Baird Callicott, “The Role of Technology in the Evolving Concept of Nature,” RPT 13 (1993): 201-

222. 60 Ibid., 209. 61 Ibid., 215. Callicott limits his expertise, perhaps too much for us to take him seriously, by saying that

“the furthest thing from any expertise that I may have is alternative technology design. The next furthest thing from my ken is an analysis of the economic, social, and political obstacles to alternative technology development and how to overcome them” (211). Instead, he offered historical insight into the affects of changing scientific paradigms.

43

Mechanical industries, Callicott, reasons, will give way to “electronic state systems,” those that

connect us to each other, which will have less environmental impact.

Rolston’s essay “A Managed Earth and the End of Nature?” argued that wilderness has

clearly ceded ground to managed land, but to understand “the End of Nature” to be its cessation

is an overstatement of its demise.63 To say that nature is part of culture is to confuse

epistemological dependency with ontological dependency. Nature always asserts its

independence. In Rolston’s words, “Nature contains entropic forces that tear down high

negentropic structures, unless these are constantly maintained by an informed energy content.”64

Man’s body and his artifacts both decay.

Rolston roughly equated the urban with the political as a place where “the contributions

of spontaneous nature are no longer evident in the criteria of evaluation,” one that is artifactual

and the technological.65 He identified a “symbiosis zone” that results from the overlap of urban

areas and those that are predominantly natural as an important area that deserves further study,

writing “much of life does take place in the symbiotic zone, and there we need an adequate

theory lest our practices go astray.”66 Yet such an analysis seems to deserve a far more

sophisticated understanding of the artifactual, which seem to be situated on a spectrum—perhaps

using Borgmann’s distinction between real and hyperreal—just as Rolston does with the natural.

In “Phil-Tech Meets Eco-Phil: The Environment,” Ihde claimed that overly optimistic

accounts of technology often made by its proponents are paralleled by dystopian critiques of

technology common to environmentalists are exaggerations that need to be replaced by a

62 Callicott, “After the Industrial Paradigm, What?” RPT 18 (1999), 13-26. 63 Holmes Rolston, III, “A Managed Earth and the End of Nature?” RPT 18 (1999): 143-164. 64 Ibid., 161. 65 Ibid., 158. 66 Ibid., 159.

44

“critical realism.”67 The upshot of such a realism is that environmental concerns are considered

in the design of new technologies, rather than as externalities to other fields.

Hickman’s “Green Pragmatism: Reals without Realism, Ideals without Idealism” made

the most headway toward working between the specializations.68 Hickman, a Dewey scholar

whose expertise is in philosophy and technology, attempts to use Dewey’s epistemological

constructs to illuminate the complexities involved with intrinsic value that garnered significant

attention in environmental ethics over the preceding twenty years. According to Hickman,

Dewey claims “inquiry is thus a technological enterprise because it involves techniques: it

involves the invention, development, and deliberate use of tools and other artifacts (such as rules

of inference) brought to bear on raw materials (such as data) and intermediate stock parts (such

as the results of previous inquiries) to resolve and reconstruct situations which are perceived as

problematic.”69 The highest level of inquiry, a “criticism of criticisms,” allows one to

distinguish nature from culture. According to Hickman’s Deweyan epistemological construct,

nature can be valued qua nature in the moment, i.e., when it is done unreflectively. But after

deliberation, nature can be said to be valuable, a claim influenced by culture that requires

judgment.

Hickman compared his interpretations of Dewey’s thought to the writings of Callicott,

Bryan Norton, Michael Zimmerman, and Rolston. If one combines Callicott’s distinction

between the source of value and its locus and Norton’s distinction between felt and considered

preferences—the former are unreflective while the latter depend on judgment—one approaches

Dewey’s theory of valuation, Hickman argued. According to Norton’s terminology, Dewey is a

67 Don Ihde, “Phil-Tech Meets Eco-Phil: The Environment,” RPT 18 (1999): 27-38. 68 Larry A. Hickman, “Green Pragmatism: Reals without Realism, Ideals without Idealism,” RPT 18

(1999): 39-56. 69 Hickman, “Green Pragmatism,” 43.

45

weak anthropocentrist.70 Dewey “thought that both human life and its wider context, nonhuman

nature, are unintelligible without the recognition that it is only with the advent of reflective

consciousness that nature comes to have deliberate preferences. It is only with the advent of

reflective consciousness that nature comes to have ‘a mind of its own.’”71

Hickman contrasts Dewey’s kindred spirits Callicott and Norton with Zimmerman and

Rolston, whose value theories deserve the same rebuke Dewey gave “idealists” in a 1909 essay

called “Is Nature Good? A Conversation.” Zimmerman’s advocacy of panentheism is meant to

result in a “nondualistic awareness” that can reveal our cognitive constructions,72 which

Hickman charges simply replaces subject/object dualism with covert dualism between cognitive

and non-cognitive elements of human thought. Rolston’s “idealistic strategy” inverts Hickman’s

value scheme by calling as valuable that which cannot be secured, that which is primitive and

originary. For Rolston, a thing must be valuable to be valued. The act of securing, central to

Hickman’s pragmatist understanding, may actually destroy value by shifting it to the human

realm.

In the end analysis, Hickman seemed more interested in claiming that Dewey’s thought is

sufficient for environmental philosophy and more comprehensive than any other philosopher of

technology.73 While Hickman’s contribution deserves commendation for comparing

environmental philosophy to pragmatist philosophy, his allegiance to Dewey prevents it from

70 Norton, “Environmental Ethics and Weak Anthropocentrism,” EE 6, no. 2 (Summer 1984): 134, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics19846233. Norton says a “value theory is strongly anthropocentric if all value countenanced by it is explained by reference to satisfactions of felt preferences of human individuals. A value theory is weakly anthropocentric if all value countenanced by it is explained by reference to satisfaction of some felt preference of a human individual or by reference to its bearing upon the ideals which exist as elements in a world view essential to determinations of considered preferences.” (Italics in original.)

71 Hickman, “Green Pragmatism,” 49 (italics in original). 72 Ibid., 51. 73 Hickman, “Green Pragmatism,” 55. According to Hickman, “Dewey is, to my knowledge, the only

philosopher to have advanced a critique of technology as part of a broad-front philosophical program, including social and political philosophy, educational philosophy, ethics, and logic or the theory of inquiry. No other

46

being more constructive, which would have required Hickman to be more circumspective, e.g.,

to understand Dewey in Rolston’s framework to plumb Dewey’s possible shortcomings, instead

of using Dewey as the standard.

Hickman had relayed Dewey’s understanding of the proper relationship between humans

and non-humans ten years earlier.74 Dewey thought that the conception of the world as machine

that had gained popularity in the modern period led to three possible perspectives, even as he had

thought it should be considered an organism. “A machine can be contemplated as something

finished, and its workings discovered and admired. Further, it can be examined as something

complete but in needs of occasional repair. Or it can interacted with as something ongoing,

unstable and provisional, as a tool which is utilized for enlarging transactions of self and society

with environing conditions.”75 The third perspective yields a “genuine transaction with nature,

awareness of such transaction, and inclusion of that awareness in the metatheories of science.”76

According to Hickman, “Dewey wanted to locate technology in a realm that is neither

supernatural or extranatural, an organic realm in which the only telic elements are those of the

natural ends of objects, individuals, and events, all of which may be utilized as means to further

ends.”77

Warren’s “Women, Nature, and Technology: An Ecofeminist Philosophical Perspective”

situated ecofeminism at the intersection of feminism; science, technology, and development; and

environmental concerns.78 She defined feminist analysis is “the lens through which the

philosopher of technology, so far as I know, has done this. Heidegger’s work notoriously lacked a coherent social philosophy, and it exhibited no philosophy of education.”

74 Larry A. Hickman, "Doing and Making in a Democracy: Dewey's Experience of Technology,” Philosophy and Technology: Practical, Historical, and Other Dimensions. P&T 6 (1989): 97-111.

75 Ibid., 102. 76 Ibid., 102. 77 Ibid., 104. 78 Karen Warren, “Women, Nature, and Technology: An Ecofeminist Philosophical Perspective,” RPT 13

(1993): 13-29.

47

discussion and analysis takes place,” on that “is self-consciously both sex-gendered and opposed

to male gender bias,”79 and feminist issues as those that affect the lives and work of women.

Feminism is inadequate if it fails to consider issues of science, technology, and development and

those of the environment. Likewise, studies of science, technology, and development and of the

environment are inadequate if they do not include feminist analysis that can identify oppressive

hierarchical conceptual frameworks. Warren concluded that for technology to be good it must (i)

be appropriate and local; (ii) be appropriate for women, i.e., that does not lead to their continued

inferiority; (iii) not shift control to men in its implementation; (iv) be collaborative and cross-

cultural, rather than expert-driven; (v) “environmentally sound”; and (vi) not arise from

“patriarchal conceptual frameworks.”80

According to Katz, the most serious flaw of Carl Mitcham’s Thinking through

Technology: The Path between Engineering and Philosophy is that “Mitcham’s analysis of the

structure and meaning of technology does not escape a fundamental technological orientation.”81

Its anthropocentrism precludes giving environmental ethics its due, and environmental ethics

ends up as a subset of philosophy of technology because Mitcham understands it as a kind of

applied ethics. His approach also excludes “modes of thought outside the technological

paradigm—such as poetry, literature, and myth”– and the aims of both ancient technology

(“cultivation” of nature and human dimensions) and modern technology (“construction” of both

dimensions) are always anthropocentric, activities “guided by human ends and interests.”82 In

his response “On Never Being Through Thinking Through Technology,” Mitcham states that he

found Katz’s critique troubling and proposes that a more historical study of technological

79 Ibid., 15 (italics in original). 80 Ibid., 25. 81 Eric Katz, “The Place of Nature in the Understanding of Technology: One Critical Reading of Thinking

through Technology,” RPT 16 (1997): 171-178.

48

artifacts that properly appreciates causa instrumentalis as its foundation may allow space for

nature to retain or regain its otherness.83

In “Philosophical Anthropology and the Problem of Responsibility in Technology,” T.

Maarten T. Coolen developed a notion of ethical responsibility based on a philosophical

anthropology that adequately accounts for the concept of responsibility.84 Coolen argued that

humans are technological beings. He wrote “It belongs to human self-expression, to human

autonomy, to transform nature with the aid of technology. To give up the technical

transformation of nature would be to give up being human. Therefore, the environmental

problem is a necessary counterpart of the sort of being which must transform what is outside

itself in order to be able to realize itself.”85 What is necessary, he claimed, was a relationship

between humans and nature that values nature instrumentally as well as intrinsically.

In an article focused on Herbert Simon’s understanding of the relation between humans

and computers, Strijbos charted Simon’s conception of the relation of the artificial and the

natural.86 The former includes all of human culture, while the latter is partly human and partly

non-human. The two realms are connected through the human brain, and artifacts and natural

objects both obey natural laws, though artifacts “derive their identity from the human purposes

which they embody.”87 The other connection between the natural and artificial is what he called

“synthesis,” design or composing, which transforms nature into artifact.88 In artifacts, unlike

natural things, the function, inner environment, and outer environment are related.

82 Ibid., 174, 177. 83 Carl Mitcham, “On Never Being through Thinking through Technology,” RPT 16 (1997): 179-182. 84 T. Maarten T. Coolen, "Philosophical Anthropology and the Problem of Responsibility in Technology,”

Technology and Responsibility. P&T 3 (1987): 41-65. 85 Ibid., 61-62. 86 Sytse Strijbos, "Computer and World Picture: A Critical Appraisal of Herbert A. Simondon,” Broad and

Narrow Interpretations of Philosophy of Technology. P&T 7 (1990): 67-86. 87 Ibid., 70. 88 Ibid., 71.

49

Techné: RPT also published papers and a transcript from the 1994 Central Division

American Philosophical Association author meets critics session on Rothenberg’s Hand’s End:

Technology and the Limits of Nature. Having translated Arne Naess’s Ecology, Community and

Lifestyle, Rothenberg was a respected voice in the environmental community. In Hand’s End, he

sought to find boundaries in nature for the spiraling effects of technological innovation, which

satisfies some desires and stimulates others, while inducing unintended consequences in their

use. Nature is best considered as a “home” for humans, where legitimate interests of humans and

non-humans coincide. Moral boundaries can be found when humans leave the confines of

“home,” which leads to drastic and sometimes irreversible consequences, such as nuclear war

and global warming. Conceptualizing nature as “other” or wilderness fails because the human

perspective is anthropocentric by definition, and our experience and understanding of nature

depends on technological innovations. The critics in the panel were Furrow, Abram, and

Lovekin.

Furrow critiqued the claim that the limits of nature, which can only be discovered when

they are transcended, are helpful for making moral decisions about technology.89 He pointed out

that “our technically-inspired actions come too soon to anticipate their consequences yet too late

to do anything about their effects.”90 Furrow had no truck with either of Rothenberg’s proposed

solutions, to recover a Kantian sense of the sublime and to develop technologies that highlight

unique qualitative experiences, but he doubted they would change the breakneck pace of

technological innovation. More problematically, Furrow thought it is impossible to understand

the interests of nature from within Rothenberg’s integrated conception, and the sublime should

be understood by Lyotard’s postmodern conception: “the sublime no longer functions as a

89 Dwight Furrow, “The Discomforts of Home: Nature and Technology in Hand’s End,” RPT 15 (1995):

169-175.

50

regulative ideal but simply makes reference to the impossibility of presenting the

unpresentable—an invocation of the impossibility of knowledge, not a glimpse of nature’s

internal limit.”91 Furrow thought that the otherness of nature should be conserved, that the

guiding direction for technology is that nothing should “reduce the sense of enormity, of

incomprehension, and unfamiliarity in our confrontation with nature.”92

Using Marshall McLuhan’s terms, Abram described Hand’s End as a “cool book” that

has gaps that provoke active participation from the reader, but what he finds surprising is that

nature is always presented as passive, as bereft of non-human agencies and intentions.93 Nature

becomes “our context,”94 a term which Abram pointed out arises in the use of technologies for

writing. It is literally the words around the term. But in earlier hunter-gatherer periods, where

tribes took on animals symbolically, “human culture does not so much project itself, or its

engagements onto the natural world, but rather introjects onto itself the perceivable patterns of

the natural terrain, taking nonhuman nature as the metaphor and model for its own activities.”95

Lovekin proposed that the right boundaries for technology can be found by looking at the

premodern drawings of Agostino Ramelli, the sixteenth century engineer to the king of France

and Poland.96 Ramelli drew unique machines that emphasized aesthetics, both in design, where

it may come at the price of efficiency, and in decoration, with many ornate drawings, and

encouraged community development. These designs evoked “ingenio and fantasia,” two human

states that escape the dominant understanding of technology as efficiency.97

90 Ibid., 171. 91 Ibid., 174. 92 Ibid., 175. 93 David Abram, “Nature at Arm’s Length,” RPT 15 (1995): 177-180. 94 Ibid., 179. 95 Ibid., 179. 96 David Lovekin, “Rothenberg, Ramelli, and Heidegger: Considerations of Otherness,” RPT 15 (1995):

181-190. 97 Ibid., 190.

51

Three articles addressed the artefactualizing of nature, its morality, and reverting to a

more “natural” state through restoration or other interventions. Even though he recognized that

ecosystems are in dynamic equilibrium, Mario Bunge argued that human effects should still be

minimized. J. A. Doeleman argued that economics is the proper analysis to determine whether

technological advances should be constrained to conserve nature or technological advances

should be employed to replace its functions. Eric Katz argued that restoration, a step that would

rarely make sense in Doeleman’s framework, is nothing more than a technological fix.

Mario Bunge identified the biological as well as the economic, political, and cultural as

four subsystems in human society.98 Organisms are open systems that are “entropic towards the

environment and inwardly negentropic.”99 His understanding of an ecosystem is that it is in

dynamic equilibrium, one that is constantly evolving. He saw the human role is one that should

have minimal environmental impact, except after droughts and floods, when some organisms

endanger the survival of others and when consumption by some animals leads to starvation of

others. Use of non-renewable natural resources should be prohibited, as should development that

comes at the expense of future generations.

J. A. Doeleman argued that technologies primarily consume nature, and, in response,

other technologies are developed to “save” nature, for example, through pollution abatement and

conservation management.100 But the scale of human intervention has led to the development of

“nature-replacement technology,” which “competes with nature-saving technology,” and the

“preferred” choice should be made using tools of economics.101 Replacement technologies, such

as aquaculture, will likely be preferred because (a) conservation is contrary to growth, which

98 Mario Bunge, "Development and the Environment,” Technological Transformation: Contextual and

Conceptual Implications. P&T 5 (1999): 285-304. 99 Ibid., 289. 100 J. A. Doeleman, “Environment and Technology: Speculating on the Long Run,” RPT 12 (1992): 5-32.

52

shows no signs of abating; (b) nature conservation entails prohibitive economic and opportunity

costs; and (c) embrace of nature-replacement tends to reinforce its preference.

In the last part of the 1992 theme section, Katz argued that ethical arguments for

ecosystem restoration of nature as “restitutive justice,” such as those given by Paul Taylor or

Peter Wenz, are just another instance of an anthropocentric “technological fix,” this time

concealed in environmental concern.102 The section also included Eric Higgs’s essay, largely

based on a report on the activities of the Environment and Technology project, “Musings at the

Confluence of the Rivers of Techné and Oikos.”103 Interestingly and without explanation, Higgs

contrasted technology with environment, understood as cultural and ecological surroundings. He

argues that the joint inquiry of technological power and environmental consequences is

characterized by “patent incompleteness” and urges individual scholarship and formation of

working groups.104

Science, Technoscience, and Nature

The “Science, Technoscience, and Nature” constellation consists of three groups of papers,

“Science and Nature,” “Heidegger,” and “Novel Technologies.”

Science and Nature. Several articles described how nature and its study can or should change

the practice of science. John F. Post argued that reenchantment of nature can and should be

accomplished first by accepting “minimal physicalist theses” as foundational, which can be

augmented with values discerned from nonreductive determination, and then the divine can be

reintroduced, once the subject-predicate literalism in theology is overcome. Steven Vogel’s

criticism of the attempts of Herbert Marcuse and Jürgen Habermas to overcome a subject-object

101 Ibid., 13. 102 Eric Katz, “The Big Lie: Human Restoration of Nature,” RPT 12 (1992): 231-241. 103 Eric Higgs, “Musings at the Confluence of the Rivers Techné and Oikos,” RPT 12 (1992): 243-258. 104 Ibid., 255.

53

divide between humans and nature led him to argue for a science that can contribute to human

liberation. In a sweeping essay, Raphael Sassower argued that, while often thought as opposites,

Francis Bacon and Donna Haraway understand nature in a similar way, one that is coherent with

the demands of ecology. Donald Beggs highlighted the importance of interdisciplinarity in a

critique of Robert V. Bartlett’s understanding of ecological rationality. Albert A. Anderson

argued that Callicott unnecessarily and undesirably diminished reason when he accepted Hume’s

distinction between analytic and synthetic judgments, which, as Plato thought, are integrated.

Post proposed that attempts to reintroduce enchantment into the objectivist worldview of

modern science should start from its minimal physicalist theses.105 Post had previously argued

that these theses are “(i) every entity whatever is a mathematical-physical entity; (ii) there can be

no difference between things without some mathematical-physical difference between them; and

(iii) all truth whatever in the sciences or beyond, is determined by truths at the level of

mathematical physics.”106 The path toward reenchantment proceeds first by recognizing that this

foundation is “entirely congenial to holistic thinking,”107 and that the foundation is correct but

not complete. Values, stricken from the discourse in the seventeenth century, can be regained

through nonreductive determination, which means “purely descriptive or natural facts about the

world (including us) might nonreductively determine which of our value judgments are true.”108

Post interpreted this in a strong sense, in which objective value means that “there is one and only

one correct distribution” of value judgments, and in a weak sense, in which “the natural

properties of people and things, in conjunction with the normative principles one happens to

105 John F. Post, “On Reenchanting the World,” RPT 10 (1990): 243-279. 106 Ibid., 248. 107 Ibid., 249. 108 Ibid., 253.

54

hold, determine one and only one distribution of truth-values over the value judgments.”109 Post

argued that “normative imperatives are grounded in nonnormative fact, in the sense of

determination, even if such grounding by itself enables no one to formulate or derive the

imperatives from any indicatives,” and from this basis intrinsic value can be said to arise from a

reunified understanding of value and nature.110 Two other steps are necessary for reenchantment

of nature. First, it can be recovered by understanding “moods, emotions, desires, and passions”

as descriptions that “roughly are like that for an appropriate human in appropriate conditions,”

thereby retaining the nonreductive physicalism and what are normally considered to be

subjectivist judgments.111 Second, divine immanence can be recovered by breaking “subject-

predicate literalism in theology,” which eliminates the problem of trying to recognize a

supernatural being in a physicalist frame, but at the cost of assigning any causation to beings that

cannot be said to exist.112

In “New Science, New Nature: The Habermas-Marcuse Debate Revisited,” Vogel argued

that neither of the two debaters hold a philosophy that is coherent with respect to science and

nature.113 Herbert Marcuse took up the Frankfurt School criticism of science as a domination of

nature. Along these lines, revolutionary science must free both humans and nature of

domination: both must be subjects, not objects to be manipulated. Jürgen Habermas claimed

that the extension of methods of natural science to the social realm was flawed because it

confuses two human interests, which Vogel articulated as “prediction and control of nature (the

‘technical’ interest) and in the achievement of mutual understanding on the basis of undistorted

109 Ibid., 254 (italics in original). He is offering an alternative to Mackie’s argument from queerness. 110 Ibid., 261. 111 Ibid., 264. 112 Ibid., 272. 113 Steven Vogel, “New Science, New Nature: The Habermas-Marcuse Debate Revisited,” RPT 11 (1991):

157-178.

55

communication (the ‘communicative’ interest),”114 whose possibility depends on an unjustified

split between human nature and nature as the subject of inquiry. He says “at no level do we have

access to some ‘nature in itself’ independent of human activity; nature is rather always

something we constitute through our social practices—through our ‘work’ (which is inseparable

from the social structures that organize it) and through our ‘interaction’ (which is inseparable

from the processes of material production and reproduction that condition it).”115 In Vogel’s

assessment, neither Marcuse nor Habermas is able “to assimilate conclusions about the active

character of our relations with nature to his prior commitment to a ‘materialism’ that sees nature

as independent of the human, and the result in each case is conceptual failure.”116 What is

necessary is to ignore impossible aims of a “pure description of an external reality” and instead

construct a “science [that] would finally know itself to be social, to be historical, to be

‘interested,’ and hence would know its own connection to the world it helps create.”117 In this

way, science can function as an instrument of human liberation.

In "Intellectual Responsibility for an Ecology Agenda," Raphael Sassower argued that the

conditions that will improve ecological well-being are the adoption of a critical approach to

technology informed by the history of ideas, commitment to social ideals, and the desire for a

better future.118 He linked the thoughts of Donna Haraway with those of Francis Bacon,

considering them as two people who both argue that technoscience and nature are "two

interrelated concepts that draw their definitions from each other since neither has logical or

historical primacy." Bacon said that "Man, being the servant and interpreter of Nature, can do

114 Ibid., 162. 115 Ibid., 169. 116 Ibid., 158. 117 Ibid., 174. 118 Raphael Sassower, “Intellectual Responsibility for an Ecology Agenda,” JSPT 1, no. 1/2 (Fall 1995):

74-82, doi: 10.5840/techne199511/214.

56

and understand so much and so much only as he has observed in fact or in thought of the course

of nature...Nature to be commanded must be obeyed," which Sassower called a realist approach

to the relationship between technoscience and nature that parallels Haraway's constructivist

perspective. In a similar way, by proposing cyborgs, Haraway sought to collapse the split

between humans and their environment: "nature cannot pre-exist its construction, its articulation

in heterogeneous social encounters, where all of the actors are not human and all humans are not

'us,' however defined."119

For Beggs, interdisciplinarity is a necessary part of ecological rationality.

Interdisciplinary work involves “more than one discipline to create locally coherent outcomes

that are sustained and substantial.”120 He analyzed Robert V. Bartlett’s articulation of

substantive and functional moments of ecological rationality, where the former “attempts to

maximize goods given a plurality of goals” and the latter “discovers technical means” to achieve

a single goal. Bartlett’s schema fails with regards to substantive ecological rationality because

he accepts models of rationality from policy studies, thus retaining a multidisciplinary

perspective, rather than allowing the substantive moment to arise from ecological studies and

problems. It fails with respect to functional ecological rationality because it erringly assumes

that ecological rationality is more fundamental than economic, political, or social rationality.

Anderson argued in "Prometheus Suffers: Technology and the Ecological Crisis" that

Callicott, who follows David Hume's understanding of the Is-Ought dilemma, wrongly accepted

the analytic/synthetic distinction, which led to an impoverished view of reason.121 In In Defense

119 Haraway, Donna J. “Otherworldly Conversations; Terran Topics; Local Terms,” Science as Culture 3,

no. 1 (1992): 64-98, as quoted in Sassower, “Intellectual Responsibility.” 120 Donald Beggs, “The Interdisciplinary Constraint on Ecological Reason,” JSPT 2, no. 3/4 (Spring-

Summer 1997): 140-144, doi: 10.5840/techne199723/418. 121 Albert A. Anderson, “Why Prometheus Suffers: Technology and the Ecological Crisis,” JSPT 1, no. 1/2

(Fall 1995): 28-36, doi: 10.5840/techne199511/28.

57

of the Land Ethic, Callicott argued that ethics must historically precede rationality, which arises

recently in evolutionary history relative to sociality. According to Anderson, Hume’s distinction

is inferior to Plato’s integration. Plato rightly thought of reason as a dialectic of "these processes

of division and bringing together, as aids to speech and thought.”122 Anderson said "Knowing

cannot be separated either from reason or from experience. Knowing, reasoning, and

experiencing are grounded in being and goodness." The measure of goodness, according to

Plato, arises from a receptivity to the natural forms of things, and the key corrective is to expand

technical expertise to include "politike techne, the art required for human beings who naturally

live in cities."

Heidegger. Development of Martin Heidegger’s philosophy, especially through the work of

Albert Borgmann, provided the departure point for several more philosophical articles on

science, technology, and nature. Wolfgang Schirmacher thought that ecology needs to be

grounded on “eco-sophia,” which accounts for that which remains concealed. Don Ihde

critiqued Heidegger for discounting imaging tools as reductions without recognizing that they

give a better understanding of the world, and without which Heideggerian hermeneutics cannot

assess whether a greenhouse gas effect exists. David Strong contributed three articles. In the

first, he argued that any adequate environmental ethic must recognize that a technology replaces

just one dimension of a multidimensional object, while attempting to control the object or the

event to put it to human use. In the second, he criticized environmental ethicists, especially

Rolston, for depending too much on methodical science for discovery, for understating the value

of technology, and for neglecting the reduction of rich phenomena of existence caused by the

scientific lens. In the third, Strong identified patience and openness as the qualities needed to

122 Plato, Phaedrus, translated by W. R. M. Lamb (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1967), 266b,

as quoted by Anderson.

58

recognize the sometimes blurry boundary of wilderness and technology. Lastly, Andrew Light

criticized Borgmann’s continuum between reality and hyperreality.

In Eco-Sophia, Schirmacher credited Heidegger’s ontological critique for “ecological re-

thinking” that is necessary for a wholesale shift in our way of being in the world.123 Schirmacher

thought that better ecology, as guided by modern science, will lead us to a more destructive

future. An attempt to identify with nature is folly, for humans are artificial. What is needed is

“Eco-Sophia,” which “takes seriously precisely that which is concealed, the nascent human

being, still, and perhaps always, in concealedness.”124 Paradoxically, the improvement of

computers, wherein computers take on the instrumental tasks and goals that are characteristic of

a world driven by technological thinking, results in the possibility of a nonanthropocentric ethics

that does not privilege humans.

In “Whole Earth Measurements,” Ihde argued that neither Husserlian phenomenology nor

Heideggerian hermeneutics as stated have the tools to address the question of whether a

Greenhouse Effect exists.125 Husserlian phenomenology needs to supplemented with the concept

of “technoscience as a thoroughly technologically embodied science” to explain how

measurements of gases imperceptible to an unaided human are mediated, indirect observations

rather than the mathematized, abstract shapes of which Husserl was skeptical. Heideggerian

hermeneutics lacks “Earth-as-Planet as a necessary presupposition for dealing with whole earth

measurements,” of which Heidegger was critical because images are pictures and, thus,

reductions. Ihde argues that imaging technologies as they are used in science permit a “look

through the image.” After hermeneutic interpretation, the images and their amplifications

123 Wolfgang Schirmacher, “Eco-Sophia,” RPT 9 (1989): 125-134. 124 Ibid., 130. 125 Don Ihde, “Whole Earth Measurements,” JSPT 2, no. 2 (Winter 1996): 91-98, doi:

10.5840/techne19972229.

59

formed by technoscience, itself already constructive, yield a better understanding of the world

than one can gain from modern epistemology.

Strong contributed three articles relevant to this inquiry in successive years that develop

the importance of nature as a counterforce to technology. In the first, he argued that the escape

from technological entrapment comes through refocusing on ontological concerns.126 Otherwise,

environmental ethics is always at risk of subversion by technological consciousness. A “bi-

centric” way of being in the world, in which human self-realization is paired with a “‘letting be’”

of things allows us to recognize focal things that “gather and assemble a world.”127 Strong

argued “a philosophy of environmental ethics must also be a philosophy of technology,” and this

is where environmental ethicists fall short.128 Rolston, whom Strong called “currently the most

comprehensible and sensible philosopher in environmental ethics,”129 articulated a conception of

environmental ethics that begins with discovery130 that also attends to human needs. Strong

criticized Rolston for overemphasizing the role of science, especially biology and ecology, in

discovery131; for understating the importance of technology, which is valuable to the extent that

it satisfies basic human needs but not for vanity, status, and other human desires, or, as Strong

put it, what is often considered “the character of the good life in a technological society”;132 and

for not noticing the impossibility of recognizing the Heideggerian fourfold of earth, sky, mortals,

and divinity in commodities or in nature when viewed through a scientific lens. Strong saw deep

126 David Strong, “The Technological Subversion of Environmental Ethics,” RPT 12 (1992): 33-66. 127 Ibid., 35. 128 Ibid., 44. 129 Ibid., 34. 130 Ibid., 46. Strong uses Rolston’s words, “What is ethically puzzling, and exciting, in the marriage and

mutual transformation of ecological description and evaluation is that here an ought is not so much derived from an is as discovered simultaneously with it,” from Rolston, Environmental Ethics (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1988), 2.

131 Strong wrote “To be let be biologically is not yet to be fully let be” (51), and the search for universal ethics grounded on science through aesthetics to necessarily reject what Strong calls “orienting beauty.”

132 Ibid., 50.

60

ecologists, who generally work from inclinations to values, as kindred spirits, yet he says they

rarely voice an adequate explanation of what is wrong with technological domination–which can

be found by Heidegger and Borgmann–and they appeal to a formal approach to realization that

Strong thought was doomed to fail.

Strong’s “The Implications for Nature of Borgmann’s Theory of Technology” follows

Borgmann’s critique that technology promises easier, faster, ubiquitous, and safer living, but that

it does not satisfy human desires for freedom and enrichment.133 Technology subverts by

presenting an object that satisfies one aspect of a multidimensional thing as a replacement—

Coolwhip instead of whipped cream—by serving as the de facto cultural standard, which

replaces excellence with progress, especially material progress, and by transforming natural

events and objects into devices to be controlled and utilized. Recognizing the effects of

technology is a prerequisite to any successful environmental ethic.

In “Challenging Technology,” Strong argued that, freed from the demands and ultimately

unsatisfying pleasures of consumption, natural and cultural things deserve precedence.134 Unlike

devices, cultural and natural things make “demanding claims” that require attention and

respect.135 Following Kant, Strong thinks that with proper cultural training humans can

experience the “overwhelming might in nature” as sublime and not terrible.136 The cultural

training or education needed is a “deeper kind of lived experience, metaphorically, the

experience of the wild,” which is especially powerful when it is shared.137 “Wilderness is a place

mostly untouched by modern technology,”138 which stands in contrast to apparent wilderness.

133 Strong, “The Implications for Nature of Borgmann’s Theory of Technology,” RPT 13 (1993): 223-252. 134 Strong, “Challenging Technology,” RPT 14 (1994): 69-92. 135 Ibid., 72. 136 Ibid., 73. 137 Ibid., 75 (italics in original). 138 Ibid., 83.

61

The latter is enframed and tamed by devices, in which experiences are made more shallow and

superficial as they are governed by technological standards of “ease, instantaneity, ubiquity, and

safety…comfort, convenience, speed, and so forth.”139 Following Henry Bugbee, Strong argued

that recognizing the essential differences between wilderness and technology depends on

patience and openness. Patience is necessary because to welcome and acknowledge things on

their terms requires time and commitment. Strong used openness in the sense used by

existentialist Gabriel Marcel, as “the openness of the person in his or her entirety,” which

includes candor about one’s self and “active receptivity in participation” with persons and

things.140 In order to challenge technology, humans need to change the way we build, that is, the

way nature is artifactually reshaped, so that we can dwell in our surroundings. The sense of

dwelling, though, depends first on the wilderness experience.

Borgmann’s work was the focus of one other contribution to RPT/Techné. Light

challenged the nature-artifact distinction that Borgmann developed in Crossing the Postmodern

Divide in “Three Questions on Hyperreality.”141 Light asked whether Borgmann’s conception of

a continuum between reality and hyperreality, in which the former possesses a “commanding

presence” in temporal, spatial, and communal continuity and the latter is “disposable” and

discontinuous, should be replaced by considering hyperreality, nature, and artifacts as three

subsets of reality.142 Doing so reduces the prominence given to hyperreality. The second

question posed by Light is whether the continuum between natural reality and non-natural reality

is unfairly biased against cities. Light concluded by asking whether Borgmann’s distinction only

139 Ibid., 71. 140 Ibid., 82. 141 Andrew Light, “Three Questions on Hyperreality,” RPT 15 (1995): 211-222. 142 Albert Borgmann, Crossing the Postmodern Divide (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992), 38, as

quoted in Light, “Three Questions,” 213.

62

applies those of economic privilege who can afford commodities (in Borgmann’s sense of the

term) and may distract those from more pressing social concerns.

Novel Technology. Biotechnology, especially genetic engineering and genetic testing, and

nanotechnology have blurred the distinction between art and nature in a new way. According to

Keekok Lee, molecular deoxyribonucleic acid (DNA) technology can create a “paradigmatic

biotic artefact,” though Jim Wishloff was not persuaded by her moral claims, which he thought

should be disregarded because they depend on philosophical materialism. Anne Chapman

argued that this technology is dangerous because it encourages a domineering attitude, is

accompanied by uncertainties, and increases disparities in power and wealth. Sylvia Blad used

genetic and protein testing offers a way to test anthropological concepts, such as Peter

Sloterdijk’s “anthropogenetic mechanism,” to see if they are right. Wolfgang Schirmacher

elevated the creative plasticity that is gained through genetic modification as an act that is truly

human because other organisms do not have that capability. Christopher Preston proposed that

many environmental ethics provide the conceptual resource necessary to assess moral issues

involved with nanotechnologies, namely the deference given to evolutionary and ecological

processes that are not manipulated.

In “Patenting and Transgenic Organisms: A Philosophical Exploration,” Lee argued that

biotechnology “permits a quantum leap, so to speak, in the degree of control of biotic nature”

beyond Mendelian genetics, which generally works within species through processes similar to

natural evolution, even if their appearance would be unlikely without human intervention.143

Molecular DNA technology permits transference of genetic content between species, kingdoms,

and between eukaryotes and prokaryotes, which makes them the “paradigmatic biotic artefact,”

143 Keekok Lee, “Patenting and Transgenic Organisms: A Philosophical Exploration,” Techné: JSPT 6, no.

3 (Spring 2003): 166-175, doi: 10.5840/techne20036323.

63

one that is novel enough to deserve patent protection. In a response to Lee, Wishloff argued that

her implicit adoption of philosophical materialism ignores more fundamental questions,

including those regarding differences between the animate and inanimate, whether animals are

beings with an essence, and whether life is a commodity or mystery.144

Chapman used the distinction between the natural and unnatural to argue against

“Genetic Engineering: The Unnatural Argument.”145 The former is characterized by biological

processes learned through experience whose outcome is at least somewhat uncertain and

uncontrollable, and successful use of “natural methods” or “natural technologies” depends on

altering human actions to correspond to what has been learned. The latter is characterized by

physical and chemical processes that arise from the application of scientific theories in these

areas, which can be better controlled with less uncertainty. Unnatural technologies can be

considered successful to the degree that they make minimal demands on humans to alter their

actions. Chapman cited the attitude of domination, uncertainty that arises with its novelty, and

expected inequalities of wealth and power that will arise from its use as reasons why genetic

engineering should be considered morally wrong.

Blad argued that the true distinction between between chimpanzees and humans is based

on the social, cultural, and technological environment in which the latter live, that is, those

attributes that paradoxically makes humans less suited to surviving outside of it in “The Impact

of ‘Anthropotechnology’ on Human Evolution.”146 Blad followed philosopher Peter Sloterdijk

in identifying an “anthropogenetic mechanism,” consisting of “group-internal criteria for

144 Jim Wishloff, “Patenting and Transorganic Organisms: A Reply to Lee,” Techné: JSPT 6, no. 3 (Spring

2003): 176-180, doi: 10.5840/techne20036324. 145 Anne Chapman, “Genetic Engineering: The Unnatural Argument,” Techné: RPT 9, no. 2 (Winter 2005),

http://scholar.lib.vt.edu/ejournals/SPT/v9n2/chapman.html. 146 Sylvia Blad, “The Impact of ‘Anthropotechnology’ on Human Evolution,” Techné: RPT 14, no. 2

(Spring 2010): 72-87, doi: 10.5840/techne201014211.

64

selection, the unburdening of the body through technology, a tendency toward ‘neoteny’ (a

delayed and prolonged juvenile stage), and ‘transference,’ the (re-generation of self-created

‘spheres’ in space and time), that must be taken to understand recent human evolution.”147

Fitness based on adaptations that arise from our cultural tools (understood broadly) have genetic

consequences, which can be evaluated. Empirical genomic data (including “genome architecture

and dynamics, epigenetic patterns, and ‘epi-phylogenetic memory’”148) can be used to test

philosophical anthropology theories once the connection between genetic constitution and

phenotypic expression are made, and such an evaluation offers some support of Sloterdijk’s

theory.

Schirmacher proposed that humans as homo sapiens, homo faber, and homo creator has

been surpassed by homo generator.149 Prior to gene technology, humans connected or

accelerated evolutionary processes by breeding. Homo generator, by contrary, works “without

any restrictions, with the fundamental building blocks of life.” Humans are able to “repair”

nature, but these are often just “elimination of its malfunction indication system” and “are

usually carried out with the same mindlessness which caused the preceding devastation.”150 The

capability of genetic modification, Schirmacher argued, sets humans apart from animals in terms

of freedom and responsibility. The moral law, which separates the two kinds of beings, is joined

with freedom and responsibility because humans are not bound to evolutionary processes.

Humans alone have a “creative plasticity.”151

147 Ibid., 72. 148 Ibid., 84. 149 Wolfgang Schirmacher, “Homo Generator: The Challenge of Gene Technology,” Technology and

Responsibility. P&T 3 (1987): 203-225. 150 Ibid., 205, 206. 151 Ibid., 209.

65

After noting some surprise that, as of 2004, there were no articles on nanotechnology

written by academic environmental philosophers, Preston argued that environmental ethics

provides an appropriate framework to address questions raised by the development and use of

nanotechnologies.152 His argument depends on the assumption shared by a diverse group of

environmental philosophers, including Aldo Leopold, Rolston, and Robert Elliot, that some

value should be given to untouched (or better, at least for Leopold, perhaps lightly manipulated)

evolutionary and ecological processes. Natural objects deserve moral value based on their origin

in a “creative process,” not for their own features. From this position, Preston affirmed Lee’s

concern that the intentional replacement of autopoietic organisms with artifacts leads to an

ontological loss because nature is no longer “other” than humans, but he finds that it is less

consequential than she believes for moral matters. He finds more convincing the claim that the

absence of nano-sized particles in evolutionary processes suggests that the burden of doubt

should rest on those advocating their use.

Religion and Transcendence

Two papers discuss the relation between religion, technology, and the environment.

Frank R. Harrison critiqued the connection between technology and the environment forged by

Lynn White, Jr.’s “The Historical Roots of the Ecologic Crisis,” arguing that atomistic-

mechanical principles deserve more blame than a failed analysis of a diverse religious tradition.

Paul van Dijk provided a sweeping analysis of religion and technology, starting from Genesis,

through Bacon, Descartes, and Marx, to the present, that offers many theological resources that

may offset the desire for technological domination.

152 Christopher J. Preston, “The Promise and Threat of Nanotechnology: Can Environmental Ethics Guide

Us?” Hyle 11 no. 1 (2005): 19-44, http://www.hyle.org/journal/issues/11-1/preston.htm.

66

Frank R. Harrison focused his analysis of “The Judeo-Christian Tradition and Crises in

Contemporary Technology” on White’s “The Historical Roots of the Ecologic Crisis.”153

Harrison argued that White mistakes philosophical causes for religious ones. The former has

carried more heft in defining the terms “nature, cognition, value, and person” in the West since

the beginning of the technological movement.154 On this point Harrison followed Ellul and the

sociologist Lewis Moncrief. More importantly, though, White made a conceptual mistake by

applying “the Judeo-Christian tradition” to a family of traditions composed of many strands that

have varied over the last two millennia. “The White position takes a limited portion of the

Judeo-Christian tradition, gives it a specific interpretation, and then defines the entire tradition in

terms of that portion while disallowing any counterevidence to the allegedly universal empirical

claims the position sets forth.”155 Harrison argued that atomistic-mechanical principles, at best

weakly associated with religion, determine how concepts such as nature are defined today.

Spurred by Günther Anders’s insight that our intellectual capabilities have outstripped

our emotional capabilities to respond to our new potential, Paul van Dijk argued that moral

fantasy is necessary to develop the appropriate attitude toward the natural world.156 “Church and

theology” are important in a cultural-historical analysis because he thought White was right by

claiming that “the fundamental attitudes that have contributed to the ecological crisis have

biblical roots.”157 Van Dijk’s assessment is more tempered than White’s, though, because he

noted that biblical dominion implies responsibility and care. According to the biblical sense of

proper political authority, God’s covenant, which positions humans as stewards of nature,

153 Frank R. Harrison, “The Judeo-Christian Tradition and Crises in Contemporary Technology,” RPT 10

(1990): 103-118. 154 Ibid., 104 (italics in original). 155 Ibid., 109. 156 Paul van Dijk, “Environmental Ethics and the Recovery of Culture,” RPT 17 (1998): 25-43. 157 Ibid., 30.

67

demands that rulers must be available to and show concern for their subjects.158 Such a position

is contrary to an exercise of absolute power over the non-human world. Interpreted according to

biblical norms, violent technological practices that can arise from a strong anthropocentric view

are an expression of a form of self-idolatry, i.e., seeking to impose the human image on nature.

In a two-page section called “Cultural-Historical Anamnesis,” van Dijk traced the

anthropocentric perspective back to the ascetic-monastic tradition, which understood Genesis

1:26 as “the domination of reason over affects (symbolized in animals) and the body (symbolized

in the earth).”159 Later, the concept of God as absolute freedom bound by no law was inherited

by humans, who sought to act the same way in their dealings with nature. The same trajectory

was followed during and after the Enlightenment. Francis Bacon’s work is an attempt to escape

the consequences of the Fall and regain human domination through scientific knowledge and

technological innovations. René Descartes’s separation of the res cogitans from the res extensa

leads to a one-dimensional understanding of knowing, which results in a one-dimensional way of

being. Karl Marx can be interpreted as seeing human work on nature as a form of alienation that

must be overcome, and neo-Marxist Ernst Bloch viewed nature as a “subject” rather than as just

matter.

Van Dijk offered Jürgen Moltmann’s emphasis of the trinitarian sense of God as an

antidote to the dominating position that arose from the late medieval perspective. A second

antidote to human exploitation in nature can be found in Gerhard Liedke’s extension of

Galtung’s “conflict theory” to ecological issues. Increasing technological power leads to an

asymmetrical power distribution between humans and nature. Based on the importance of the

158 Van Dijk argued that in the “hermeneutic horizon” of contemporary ecological issues, the same-day

creation of animals and humans should be understood as a sign of “solidarity,” and human dominion should be understood as serving and guarding what God had created (31).

159 Ibid., 32.

68

revelation of humans as friends of God, humans should pursue an associative relationship with

nature by strengthening “the underlying partner ‘nature’” or voluntarily forgoing technological

power.160 A sacramental resource for an associative relationship is Holy Communion, in which

bread and wine, which are both natural and cultural, take on an eschatological reality. The

science behind an associative relationship must take on an “unselfish interest” that follows

Augustine’s relationship between truth and knowledge as “Non intratur in veritatem, nisi per

charitatem,” or “One does not arrive in truth except through charity.”161 Augustine’s use of the

passive form of the verb in the above quotation points toward van Dijk’s prescription to

counteract technological domination. It is receptivity, “fear of the Lord…kenosis (Phil. 2:6),

dispossession,”162 an attitude that is contrary to the Promethean aim of domination.

Politics and Policy

Several articles are concerned with politics and policy at the intersection of nature and

technology. Dick G. A. Koelega proposed that a state is justified in protecting ecological goods

insofar as they are conditions for individual autonomy of its citizens. Frederick Rapp argued that

a regionalized ethics by which desires and quality of life can be assessed must be complemented

by humility in order to be effective at a global scale. Jose A. Lopez Cerezo and Marta Gonzalez

Garcia positioned lay participation as a necessary epistemic and political complement to expert

knowledge for technological and environmental policy, which are naturally complex. Stephen

Brockman’s assessment of the post-1968 German Green movement credits the anti-technology

“fundamentalist Greens” as the antithesis needed for the ascent in “full consciousness” of the

“realist Green party.” Karen Wiley traced the history of wetlands, which now provides a buffer

160 Ibid., 35. 161 Augustine, Contra Faustum, §32. 162 Van Dijk, “Enivronmental Ethics,” 39.

69

to technological development, in the U. S. from its regulative dependency on navigation to its

expansive understanding based on public benefit.

According to Koelega, the liberal state is sanctioned in restricting technological

development and use to prevent environmental deterioration if ecological goods such as

environmental preservation and biodiversity are understood as necessary conditions for

individual autonomy.163 Koelega followed Joseph Raz, who argued that in addition to John

Rawls's primary goods such as social rights and liberties, the state also should offer a varied

collection of life options that matter, and Will Kymlicka, who claimed that the state should

support cultural minorities. Since environmental resources are necessary for cultures to sustain

materially and, in many cases, to inspire and form aesthetic judgment, protection of natural

habitat becomes a legitimate political aim.

In "Explosion of Needs, Quality of Life, and the Ecology Problem," Friedrich Rapp

argued that many of the human needs that technology meets as well as those it creates are

assessed in a regionalized ethics.164 "This type of understanding and behavior serves a short-

term fulfillment of human desires, and hence it corresponds to a short-term quality of life. On

the other hand there is the broader, more far-reaching perspective that includes distant areas, the

globe as a whole, as well as generations to come, i.e., global ethics." In order to address

ecological concerns, the ethics of technology should take a "moderate, caring attitude" in the

tradition of "Francis of Assisi, Pascal, Kirkegaard [sic], and Dostoyevsky" "to fetter the Unbound

Prometheus of modern technology."

163 Dick G. A. Koelega, “Technology, Ecology, Autonomy, and the State,” JSPT 1, no. 1/2 (Fall 1995): 62-

70, doi: 10.5840/techne199511/212. 164 Friedrich Rapp, “Explosion of Needs, Quality of Life, and the Ecology Problem,” JSPT 1, no. 1/2 (Fall

1995): 71-73, doi: 10.5840/techne199511/27.

70

Lopez Cerezo and Gonzales Garcia focused on epistemic and political concerns to argue

for more “Lay Knowledge and Public Participation in Technological and Environmental

Policy.”165 The authors accepted a pragmatist formulation of knowledge, “a network of beliefs

enjoying the property of warranted assertability.” They argued that experts should collaborate

with those without a scientific degree but who are directly involved in the issue in order to craft

policy that is efficient, which they take to mean “one that counts on sufficient resources

(cognitive, material, and organizational) in order to fulfill given aims within a set agenda” and to

gain political legitimacy.

Nature is important in their inquiry because “expert knowledge is knowledge negotiated

with respect to a double interacting tribunal: nature and society.” Lopez Cerezo and Gonzales

Garcia propose that social ecology has similar characteristics to ecosystem ecology, that is, that

both involve “complex, multidimensional equilibrium of functional interdependence.” Experts

simplify complexity in order to predict behavior at the price of uncertainty, and their analysis

proceeds over “open networks or open causal chains,” which results in indeterminacy. These

consequence of these limitations is that expert knowledge is not self-sufficient: “it is constrained

but not dictated by nature.” The authors point to the approach to eucalyptus planting in the

Asturias of Spain as the “technicization” of a social problem related to environmental issues

since it was dominated by technical experts.

In his analysis of the post-1968 German Green movement, Brockman argued that the

apparent ascent of “realist Greens,” who accept technology and market economics but work

energetically to oppose instantiations that have harmful environmental consequences, over the

fundamentalist Greens who advocate a wholesale rejection of technology, masks an important

165 Jose A. Lopez Cerezo and Marta Gonzales Garcia, “Lay Knowledge and Public Participation in

Technological and Environmental Policy,” JSPT 2, no. 1: 36-58, doi: 10.5840/techne1996216.

71

political history.166 The fundamentalist Greens, who found common cause with Marxists and

other critics of the economic static quo, had no counterpart in the Eastern part of reunified

Germany. Eastern Greens were most concerned with replacing antiquated, inefficient, polluting

Soviet-era technology with “post-industrial technologies,” aligning with the aims and rhetoric of

the realists.167 Yet Brockman concludes that the presence of the fundamentalist wing was

necessary for the Hegelian progression from thesis to antithesis to synthesis that leads to “full

self-consciousness,” an escalation that makes no sense is a logic that denies the principle of non-

contradiction.168

Karen Wiley investigated “The Evolution of ‘Wetlands’ as a Regulatory Concept,” which

is a limit to technological encroachment.169 The term itself is new, first appearing in Webster’s

Dictionary in 1961, and it developed in two separate social groups. Interest in wetland

protection arose from duck hunters, whose concern over preserving waterfowl habitat can be

traced back to the 1934 Federal Duck Stamp Program. Over the next twenty-five years, the U.S.

Fish and Wildlife Services revised the definition to depend on hydrology, soils, and vegetation.

Wiley focused on the development of the term in statutory, regulative, and case law. Its

regulation depended on an extension from “navigable waters,” which, following English

Common Law, only included waters touched by tides, then to “indelible navigability,” which

means that if a body of water or river has been navigated once, all of it is perpetually considered

navigable, to finally all water, a change made in a 1972 amendment to the Federal Water

Pollution Control Act. The term “wetlands” was first enshrined in regulation by a 1975 U.S.

Army Corps of Engineers to include “marshes, shallows, swamps, and similar areas that are

166 Stephen Brockman, “Green without Red? The Limits of Technological Critique,” RPT 13 (1993): 283-

289. 167 Ibid., 293. 168 Ibid., 296.

72

contiguous or adjacent to the above-described lakes, rivers, and streams, and that are periodically

inundated and normally characterized by the prevalence of vegetation that requires saturated soil

conditions for growth and reproduction.”170 This regulatory step was justified based on the

public benefit derived from these spaces. To put it another way, the artifactual foundation—

water that can be navigated in a boat—is replaced by an instrumental foundation.

Sustainability. A few other papers focused on the political concern of sustainability. Cesar

Cuello Nieto proposed a conception of sustainability that integrates biotic and abiotic elements.

Stanley R. Carpenter contributed two articles. In the first, he recognized the sustainability

concerns that arise from the fact that a U.S. person uses one hundred times the energy of a

hunter-gatherer, and argued that ecological economics is necessary when ecosystems are at risk

of discontinuities due to exhaustion or overuse. In the second, he proposed a blend of regulation

and market functions to manage common-pool resources and, by doing so, avoid the tragedy that

Garrett Hardin predicted. Paul B. Thompson integrated the anthropocentric interpretation of

sustainability as resource sufficiency with its ecocentric interpretation as functional integrity by

extending the timeframe of the former and including humans in the latter to ensure that social

institutions and ecological systems are also preserved. Don E. Marietta, Jr., addressed

sustainability concerns somewhat obliquely by proposing “descriptive reflection” to distinguish

needs and desires and to create a taxonomy of technologies based on the needs each meets.

Cuello Nieto supported a multidimensional model of sustainability that “places the

improvement of the human condition (social and human development) as its primary goal, and

places respect for environmental quality and the limits of nature at the core of any economic,

169 Karen B. Wiley, “The Evolution of ‘Wetlands’ as a Regulatory Concept,” RPT 17 (1998): 141-159. 170 Schlauch, Paul J. and Thomas L. Strickland, “Changing Land to Water - The Alchemy of the Federal

Wetlands Regulatory Scheme,” Rocky Mountain Mineral Law Institute (New York: Matthew Bender), 652-653, as quoted in Wiley, “Evolution of ‘Wetlands,’” 144.

73

political, educational, and cultural strategy” to allow the regeneration of culture and nature.171

To do so requires a change in how humans conceive nature: its resources are not unlimited, and

its existence should be valued intrinsically. An anthropocentric views of nature should be

replaced by “a universalistic conception in which all biotic and abiotic factors of the universe are

integrated in a totality of interconnected and interdependent elements.” Cuello accepted Hans

Jonas’s assessment of modern technology as operating on a expansive spatial scale, with

extended temporal duration, at a radical fundamental level, and with novel uncertainty, and

proposed what he considered a new holistic conception of sustainability.

In response to Cuello, Paul Durbin provides his own guidelines in an attempt to answer

the question “Can There Be a Best Ethic of Sustainability?”172 Durbin’s “American Pragmatist,

Dewey-based” take on the environmental issues in development projects—the application with

which Cuello is concerned—should “define the relationship between humans and non-human

nature in a way that allows due consideration for natural phenomenon in every case” and “heed

scientific evidence about natural capacities for regeneration in the ecological niche involved.”

His more limited claims arrive from his distrust of foundational or holistic approaches to

philosophical questions, which he proposes lacks the interplay of theory and practice necessary

to address these issues.

Carpenter used Boyden and Dovers’s concept of technometabolism to assess human

interaction with the environment.173 The original daily Human Energy Equivalent (HEE) of

2400 kCal or 10 megajoules, which had doubled in the hunter-gatherer phase, and had risen to 56

171 César Cuelllo Nieto, “Toward a Holistic Approach to the Ideal of Sustainability,” JSPT 2, no. 2 (Winter

1996): 79-83. doi: 10.5840/techne19972227. 172 Paul T. Durbin, “Can There Be a Best Ethics of Sustainability?” JSPT 2, no. 2 (Winter 1996): 84-90,

doi: 10.5840/techne19972228. 173 Stanley R. Carpenter, “Toward Refined Indicators of Sustainable Development” JSPT 2, no. 2 (Winter

1997): 65-70, doi: 10.5840/techne19972225.

74

HEEs in the average developing country and 100 HEEs for each person in the U.S. in the late

1990s. This increase concerned Carpenter, who proposed that the fungibility of natural capital

and its technological substitutions assumed in neoclassical economics must be complemented

with a secondary analysis that takes an ecological economics approach, which protects existing

elements, relationships, and processes. The secondary approach is necessary when technological

encroachment has resulted in ecosystems that are “approaching breakdown or shifts in state, or

where certain amenities considered valuable by the citizenry but undervalued by standard

economic measures, are threatened with extinction.”

In “Sustainability and Common-pool Resources: Alternatives to Tragedy,” Carpenter

argued that common-pool resources (CPR) are not subject to the tragedy of the commons if they

are able to be recognized and determined rightly to be scarce.174 CPR are said to have “high

subtractability,” meaning that an individual’s use affects what is available to others, and

“difficult exclusion,” meaning that it is difficult or impossible to deny access to certain groups of

people. Identifying them as such permits approaches that blend market determination and

political controls in their management.

Paul Thompson investigated “Sustainability as a Norm” as resource sufficiency, which is

anthropocentric and concerned with intergenerational justice, and as functional integrity, which

he considers ecocentric in the spirit of Deep Ecology and intrinsic value.175 To analyze resource

sufficiency, Thompson proposes a rolling fifty-year window to assess whether a resource is

abundant, renewable, or critical, based on whether a shortage is foreseen. Following Jeffrey

Burkhardt, he proposes that responsibility to humanity in general, rather than duties to a specific

174 Carpenter, “Sustainability and Common-Pool Resources: Alternatives to Tragedy,” JSPT 3, no. 4

(Summer 1998): 170-183, doi: 10.5840/techne19983420. 175 Paul Thompson, “Sustainability as a Norm,” JSPT 2, no. 2 (Winter 1996): 99-110, doi:

10.5840/techne19972230.

75

person, are the proper grounding for sustainability. Functional integrity demands identifying

“crucial elements” and acting in such a way—including setting up appropriate social

institutions—to keep them within an acceptable range that is normally historically grounded.

This process is normally occurs on relatively independent farms that are meant to be held in a

family for many generations, but not in processes oriented toward short term or individual gain

such as in confined animal feeding operations (CAFO) practiced by the dairymen in Erath

County, Texas. The tension between anthropocentric and ecocentric values can be minimized by

extending the timeframe of the former and expanding the latter to include humans as part of the

ecosystems so that both social institutions and ecological systems are preserved.

Marietta, who contributed “Decisions Regarding Technology: The Human Factor,”

argued that a phenomenological approach to technology can reveal insights about the human

condition if they are articulated intersubjectively through a process he calls descriptive

reflection.176 Distinguishing human needs and desires is a critical aspect of assessing

technologies and of defining sustainability. A second critical aspect is to categorize technologies

based on the needs they meet.177 They can be therapeutic or prosthetic, make life more

convenient, add interest and value to human experience, or allow one to establish an identity or

garner social approval.

The articles summarized above are weakly related to each other, and, with the exception

of the Heideggerian-inspired critiques, do not follow Collins’s linear discourse hypothesis. The

content of the articles varies widely, and the merits of the arguments remain largely unevaluated.

A similar conclusion will be found in the analysis of similar articles in EE in the next chapter.

176 Don E. Marietta, “Decisions Regarding Technology: The Human Factor,” RPT 18 (1999): 57-72. 177 Needs is Marietta’s term, which I consider too strong.

76

CHAPTER 4

TECHNOLOGY (TECHNÉ) IN THE JOURNAL ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS

The intimate relationship between the environment and technology suggests that a

comprehensive inquiry into environmental ethics requires a robust ethical inquiry into

technology. After all, the environment provides some of the “fundamental materials” for

technology, and, in its creation, and often in its use, the environment is refashioned. An analysis

of articles in Environmental Ethics reveals that articles that offer philosophical introspective into

technology can be grouped into five constellations that differ somewhat from the constellations

developed in the third chapter.178 Similarly to the previous chapter, the goal is to provide a

comprehensive overview of the image of technology over the first “academic lifespan” of the

journal. Unlike the coordinated approach found in RPT/Techné, which summoned attention

based on conference themes, inquiry into technology in EE arose naturally and appeared at

roughly the same frequency over the life of the journal.

One constellation of articles are historical inquiries into techné, in one of its derivatives

(e.g., technology) or familial concepts, such as artifacts and the built environment. Whereas

articles in RPT/Techné focused on etymology and literature, those in EE focused on the rhetoric

of decline and the role of technology in evolutionary history.

A second constellation is composed of articles that address ways of making and the

natural world. It is, in a way, a less theoretical counterpart to the constellation from RPT/Techné

that deals with philosophical approaches at the intersection of physis and techné. The paths

explored in EE on design, artworks, earthworks, and restoration address important topics that are

obscured in RPT/Techné because of the attention its contributors gave to modern technology.

178 Hereafter, Environmental Ethics is referred to as EE. See the List of Abbreviations for a full list of all

abbreviations used..

77

A third constellation consists of articles that investigate some aspect of the relationship

between science and technology and nature. Just as its complement in the previous chapter,

many articles are inspired by Heideggerian critique, and a few focus on its later development in

the work of Albert Borgmann. The form of this constellation has the most in common with the

constellation seen in RPT/Techné.

A fourth constellation, which also has a counterpart with a cluster from RPT/Techné,

includes two articles that assess the impact on Lynn White, Jr.’s “The Historical Roots of Our

Ecologic Crisis.” Though the authors are largely critical of White’s historical thoroughness,

each credits him with drawing attention to parts of medieval life that had been ignored by

historians and theologians.

Articles considered part of the fifth constellation reflect on artifacts and nature through

the lens of aesthetics, an approach that was not attempted in RPT/Techné, save David Lovekin’s

invocation of aesthetics in the premodern drawings of Agostino Ramelli, which was discussed in

Chapter 3. The authors introduce themes of receptivity, freedom, and the act of appreciating

objects, whether they are natural or made by humans, in a creative way.

Techné Seen Historically

The historical relation of nature and artifact are investigated in two articles in EE. The

apparent novelty of the critique of Heidegger and his successors can be understood as just

another instance of the rhetoric of decline, according to Andrew R. Murphy. Elizabeth

Skakoon’s focus on evolutionary history, and the role of our technology in it, showed that an

overly simplistic relationship between humans and artifacts leads to an incomplete understanding

of human development, a take that is similar to Sylvia Blad’s consideration of

anthropotechnology discussed in the previous chapter. Unlike Blad, who aimed to test

78

anthropological claims, Skakoon was most concerned about the effect that recognizing the

historical importance of artifacts should have on the scientific practitioner and on any

environmental ethics that depends on such science.

Murphy took issue with the revolutionary characteristics attributed to Heidegger and

those influenced by him.179 Murphy understood these critiques as part of a long rhetorical

tradition of decline that begins with Hesiod, Thucydides, and Ovid. Borgmann’s denigration of

“devices,” which depend on a metaphysics thoroughly informed by modern science that exalts

mechanism, should be considered only the most recent rhetorical critique inasmuch as it is a

critique of technology. Heidegger’s position was preceded by Ernst Haeckel’s opposition to

“anthropism,” which consists of anthropocentrism, anthropomorphism of the Christian God as

engineer, and an “anthropolatric view that ‘ends in the apotheoisis of the human organism’ and a

mind/body distinction.”180 Haeckel’s argument was itself preceded by Victorian critiques of

urban living, especially John Ruskin’s, which condemned the separation between humans and

nature that occurred in urban environments. Recognizing the political nature of environmental

degradation claims draws attention to the rhetorical dimension that can be missed when their

historical lineage is ignored. Such recognition expands environmental discourse to include

emotional and intellectual components that determine relevant “facts of the case” and relay them

in a persuasive manner: the “politics of nature” is “created” rather than “discovered.”181

Skakoon proposed a middle way between modern philosophers trapped in Cartesian

dualism and the “outside-in” approach of environmental philosophers, which presupposes

179 Andrew R. Murphy, “Environmentalism, Antimodernism, and the Rhetoric of Decline,” EE 25, no. 1

(Spring 2003): 79-98, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics200325146. 180 Ibid., 88. 181 Ibid., 98.

79

“ontological independence” of nature.182 While the latter can be interpreted to yield limits on

human behavior, it replaces a dualism between humanity and nature with one that separates

human biological attributes from cultural and artifactual elements. Such a dualism is

problematic because of the plasticity of human brains, which have evolved to depend on

artifacts. Inspired by philosopher Barry Allen’s Knowledge and Civilization, she argued “It is

through interaction with the external artifactual environment that we complete these neural

circuits and acquire a functional relationship with the environment.”183 The middle way is one

that incorporates the intertwined evolutionary history of humans and their tools.

In Skakoon’s analysis, several important differences between humans and other animals

come into relief when an evolutionary viewpoint is taken. First, the complexity of our tools,

which always arise in “economies” or “kits,” require intergenerational instruction. “The

cultivation of technique implies the existence of standards and pedagogy” which are not optional,

since Skakoon argues that the toolkits have become necessary for survival.184 The need for

instruction distinguishes human and animal artifacts. Second, tools and humans form networks

in Bruno Latour’s sense of the term, and “artifactual economies always produce more than our

intentions because in an economy, everything acts and reacts to everything else, thereby

producing new artifacts and new possibilities for action.”185 This recognition reveals shows that

Eric Katz’s understanding of the relationship between humans and their artifacts is “too

simplistic.”186 Third, again, following Allen, she defines artifacts as “the effects (both intended

and unintended) of human performance” on account of the uncertainty that accompanies human

182 Elizabeth Skakoon, “Nature and Human Identity,” EE 30, no. 1 (Spring 2008): 37-49, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics200830116. 183 Ibid., 44. 184 Ibid., 45. 185 Ibid., 45. 186 Ibid., 45.

80

actions, the tools they make and use, and the consequences that arise, which, on the whole, form

an “evolving environment.”187

One other article that discussed the historical sense of nature and culture would have been

enriched by a consideration of artifacts. David W. Kidner’s “Fabricating Nature: A Critique of

the Social Construction of Nature” assessed social construction as a cultural and historical

product, without employing the comparison between techné and physis that is seemingly

telegraphed by the title word “fabricating” as part of the “critical realism” advocated by the

author.

Making and the Natural World

The articles that fit under this heading can be further subdivided into three clusters. Articles

included in the first concentrate on the activity of designing, in which ecological concerns need

to be integrated with principles of design. The second cluster consists of articles about how the

consideration of artwork and artifacts can inform environmental ethics. Articles in the third

cluster focus on a unique hybrid of techné and physis, earthworks, which are also called

environmental art.

On Design. Two papers fit in this cluster. Roger J. H. King argued that an environmental ethics

that ignored the built environment is inadequate by showing the necessity of the concept of

“exhibitive” judgments, phenomenological insight, theory about the political aspect of artifacts,

and the shared social construction of “nature” and “the artifactual.” Yuriko Saito proposed that

the ambiguity of what one must do to design with nature, rather than against it, is frequently

resolved by aesthetics, and she encouraged landscape architects to set off ecologically-important

features using the same pointers as are used to highlight valued objects cultivated or created by

humans.

187 Ibid., 46-47.

81

King synthesized concerns about the natural environment with those about the built

environment.188 The aim of his paper does not seem quite obvious to him, at one point saying his

goal is “to make a case for the relevance of the built environment to environmental ethics”; at

another he says he “outline[s] four different perspectives from which we can draw support for

such a claim”; at yet another he implies that he is “integrating these four positions with

environmental ethical reflection”; and lastly he states his argument as one that “has sought to

show why the character of the built environment is significant for environmental ethics.”189

These are four different though obviously related claims.

His motivation was similar to that behind my current project. He noted that “as

philosophers concerned with how humanly engineered systems have degraded wild

environments and threatened nonhuman species, we have paid less attention to the built,

artifactual, or domesticated environments in which humans actually live.”190 Such a division is

unadvisable, however, because the built environment shapes perceptions of the natural world.

The four positions he considers are Justus Buchler’s pragmatism-informed concept of

exhibitive judgements, Don Ihde’s post-phenomenological insights, Langdon Winner’s attention

to social and psychological concerns, and Steven Vogel’s recognition of social construction of

built and natural environments. Somewhat surprisingly, Buchler does not integrate these four

positions to form a coherent environmental ethic. He also does not investigate how, for example,

Buchler’s pragmatism improves or differs from Bryan Norton’s, or how Ihde’s phenomenology

improves or differs from Lester Embree’s, for example. It seems that the goal of his paper is to

argue that environmental ethicists should situate their studies as part of general philosophical

188 Roger J. H. King, “Environmental Ethics and the Built Environment,” EE 22, no. 2 (Summer 2000):

115-131, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics200022230. 189 Ibid., 115, 116, 117, 129. 190 Ibid., 115.

82

theories, in the case of Buchler, or that they should pay attention to philosophical inquiries about

technology, in the the last three cases, rather than approaching the non-human environment as

their sole interest or perhaps even as its origin. Nevertheless, the article sketches several

interesting possibilities.

Buchler’s ambitious project was to develop a unified theory of human experience. From

this expansive effort, King honed on Buchler’s pragmatism-informed concept of exhibitive

judgments. They are judgments regarding “what we make or contrive,” which Buchler argued

was as necessary for understanding the “direction” of an individual as what he says (the

assertive) or what he does (the active).191 Human inclinations are not static. Technological

creations change both what is and what is possible in the future, and they are open to

interpretation and judgment. They also shape our ethical consciousness. According to Buchler,

“‘the encounter with possibilities is at least as important and extensive as the encounter with

actualities.’”192

The recognition that our technological activities contribute to self-interpretation can be

extended with Ihde’s phenomenological insights. Ihde argued that self-understanding is always

connected to an understanding of a world, one that is now predominantly technological. Human

mental models are formed by this “deanimated and mechanized” world, and subsequently we

interpret ourselves as part of it.193 King concludes that arguments for “non-human concerns”

such as wilderness protection must take into account the ordering of the world in which they are

uttered.

191 Ibid., 118. 192 Justus Buchler, Metaphysics of Natural Complexes (New York: Columbia University Press, 1966), 148,

as cited in King, “Environmental Ethics,” 120. 193 King, “Environmental Ethics,” 123.

83

King attempted to expand Langdon Winner’s attention to the psychological and social

consequences of technology, a “form of life” that he thinks should “enlarge possibilities for

growth in human freedom, sociability, intelligence, creativity, and self-government,” to also

include environmental concerns.

We might add here that we should also pay attention to how technological systems affect our experience of nonhuman nature, our ability to see ourselves as members of communities that extend beyond the boundaries of immediate habitation, and the possibilities for developing a responsible relationship with both the built and wild environments.194

Articulations of environmental ethics should attend to the ethical inertia possessed by

contemporary artifacts and the built environment, which, King concludes, “is the focal point of a

network of commitments and opportunities–a way of life–that leave the present and future

generations indebted.”195

King used Steven Vogel’s emphasis on the social construction of built and natural

environments to argue against nature having “value and meaning in itself that imposes moral

limits on the projects and aspirations of humans.”196 While care must be taken so that this claim

is not interpreted as a justification for subjugating nature, the shared mediation in both

environments encourages an evisceration of the dualistic approach that splits ethics into two, one

concerned with humans and the other with non-humans. Further, recognition of the sociality of

nature rejects the “view from the outside” demanded by deep ecology. The step of inserting the

subject into his or her surroundings makes that the material environment, in which a subject is

situated and by which they are influenced, relevant.

194 Ibid., 124. 195 Ibid., 125. 196 Ibid., 126.

84

An upshot of King’s conception of environmental ethics is that the boundary zones

between the built and natural environments, which are often neglected by environmental

philosophers, become a central point of concern.

Yuriko Saito’s second contribution to EE critiqued the presuppositions of the ecological

design movement, which he called a “kind of Copernican revolution” because it encourages

designers to work with nature, rather than against it.197 An appeal to nature is problematic

because nature is a social construction, which further complicates an unarticulated difficulty of

moving from facts to norms. As Saito notes, “we have Frank Lloyd Wright, a prominent

architect, and Jens Jensen, a landscape architect, both taking nature as “the authority for design,”

while disagreeing on how to interpret this “nature” as the guide.”198 Why, Saito asked, are

ecosystems in a climax state instructive, but disturbances and other ascending or descending

states are not? Nature can be understood as “competition, exclusion, exploitation, and survival,”

rather than “balance, integrity, order, and health,” to use Neil Evernden’s words.199 Saito argued

that the common preference for native over exotic organisms depends on a point in time that is

not obvious, and the catalog of species present at that point of time is, to varying degrees,

unknown.

Given these difficulties, how, then, should environmentally-attuned landscape designers

make decisions? “Whether or not it is wise or desirable, our actions/inactions regarding

protection of nature are greatly influenced, sometimes even determined,” Saito said, “by the

aesthetic dimension of the object.”200 An aesthetic sense, developed through education, can

motivate care and concern, even for organisms that have important roles in ecosystem behavior,

197 Yuriko Saito, “Ecological Design: Promises and Challenges,” EE 24, no. 3 (Fall 2002): 245-261, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics200224314. 198 Ibid., 249 (italics in original). 199 Ibid., 251.

85

such as maggots and mosquitos, but that appear repulsive prima facie.201 Citing landscape

architect Joan Nassauer’s term of “cultural sustainability,” Saito gives landscapers the charge of

developing an ecologically-attuned aesthetics that works in concert with the “cues and clues,”

such as borders and fences, that are already used to set off what deserves respect.202

Artworks and Artifacts. Artworks and artifacts have inspired environmental ethicists in several

ways. One, the precedent of ascribing value to artworks has been cited as ethicists expand their

range of concerns to include natural objects. Comparing the differences between artifacts and

natural objects can bring into relief differences that are important in ethical deliberations.

Artifacts and art can act to accompany and intensify experiences of nature, rather than existing in

opposition. Moreover, even though artifacts and nature are largely treated separately in

disciplinary philosophical work, their experience is usually intertwined, and whether care for

artifacts is encouraged may affect whether humans tend to care for natural things.

Andrew Brennan argued that “The Moral Standing of Natural Objects” can be discerned

by comparing them to moral standing ascribed to artifacts.203 The former lack any function

determined by an external designer. The “lack of intrinsic function,” the ability of an individual

to take on different functions in different circumstances, is prima facie a shortcoming. Yet after

further consideration, it indicates a “value beyond functional utility.” He proposed that it is this

quality by which “all natural things may claim moral considerability.”204

200 Ibid., 257. 201 Aesthetics of Artworks is covered in the last part of this chapter. 202 Ibid., 261. 203 Andrew Brennan, “The Moral Standing of Natural Objects,” EE 6, no. 1 (Spring 1984): 35-56, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics19846118. 204 Ibid., 44.

86

By this measure, Brennan concludes that natural objects, which include non-humans

organisms and other abiotic elements, deserve moral considerability, whereas works of art do

not.

Subtract the expressive power and the fitness for its purposes from a painting and you are left with an artifact of no particular value: the canvas, the wood for the frame, even the frame itself and the pigments in the oils, might all have been put to better use. But subtract the functions assigned by people and animals to a valley and its river, take away the ski lifts, the beaver dams, and the scenic views and you are left with an object containing within it hundreds of self-regulating systems living in a kind of natural anarchy, an object that partly determines its own climate, serving no one’s purpose, but still worthy of respect purely in its own right.205

Moral consideration, which is closely linked to freedom, can only be claimed by natural objects.

Because artifacts are intentionally constrained by their design, they can make no claim. Yet here

it seems that Brennan’s example runs into difficulty: can a “self-regulating system” have

artifactual components? If so, do they assume a share of moral concern? How does autonomy,

the purview of the individual organism, translate to a cooperative system, and would not its

emphasis exclude concern for abiotic elements?

For Thomas Leddy, nature can be appreciated through cultural media, including science,

technology, mythology, and especially the arts.206 Listening to Wagner can add a dramatic

quality to landscape viewing. Binoculars present the natural world through another medium.

Natural art, including earthworks, develop “a dialectic . . . in which nature, artist, and culture are

all elements”207 that escape the narrow confines of science. Arguing against dualistic claims by

environmental aestheticians, Leddy reminds the reader “that humans too are products of nature,

and that our artifacts are also natural, even the ugliest of them.”208 Using a phenomenological

205 Ibid., 46. 206 Thomas Leddy, “A Defense of Arts-Based Appreciation of Nature,” EE 27, no. 3 (Fall 2005): 299-315,

doi: 10.5840/enviroethics200527318. 207 Ibid., 304. 208 Ibid., 311.

87

approach, the subject and object should be considered points on a continuum between aesthetic

projection and reception.

Frederik Kaufmann’s “Machines, Sentience, and the Scope of Morality” argues that

applying the same reasoning that is used to assign moral standing to non-sentient organisms,

abiotic elements, and aggregates such as ecosystems leads to machines receiving similar

standing.209 “A tree or an ecosystem maintains itself in homeostatic equilibrium; each is a

complex system of balanced interdependent subsystems. The same holds for an engine.”210 The

latter can be said to have good or well-being understood in the broad sense of telos that must be

used to say that non-living beings and aggregations have interests that can be harmed. An

externally-imposed telos seems an inadequate standard, since human goals do not solely arise

“from an autonomous, self-legislating, rational will.”211 It can be argued that outside forces

partially, and, in some instances perhaps, completely determine our goals. The assignment of

moral status based on the origins of natural selection, which gives plants standing but not

machines, can be countered by a thought experiment: why should an identical organism that

arose through any other process, say, spontaneous generation, not be granted similar status since

they have the same functions? To put it another way, is etiological knowledge a prerequisite for

moral standing?212

Such reasoning, Kaufmann believed, demands that interests be yoked to mentality, a

concept more demanding than simply having sentience.213 Beliefs, memory, and the capacity to

209 Frederik Kaufmann, “Machines, Sentience, and the Scope of Morality,” EE 16, no. 1 (Spring 1994): 57-

70, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199416142. 210 Ibid., 60. 211 Ibid., 63. 212 Similarities exist between the way this question is posed and Gregor Schiemann’s argument in “Nature

Seen Historically” in Chapter 3. 213 Kaufmann understands sentience as “the capacity to feel pleasure or pain, and hence to an organism’s

ability to suffer or enjoy…. Construed more broadly, sentience can include a range of states of consciousness from ‘raw feels’ and affects of various kinds to emotions, intentions, beliefs, wishes, etc” (67).

88

judge are required for one to have interests, to prefer one state or condition to another, which he

understands “in terms of desires (actual, potential, or idealized).”214 Consequentially, if

crustaceans and small infants are assumed to have interests, then machines should, or moral

standing should be defined in a way that does not depend on interests.

Terri Field pointed out shortcomings of developing a place-based ethics of care that

ignores the built environment when it largely artifactual.215 Philosophers dedicated to this task,

such as Jim Cheney and Karen Warren, have erred by focusing almost entirely on relationships

between humans and other “natural” objects, in particular people and animals. Warren only

requires that one individual in a relationship be a “moral being,” which may not preclude an

artifact from being the “Other,” since agency is not an essential characteristic.

Field thought that overcoming such an arbitrary limitation opens several important

questions of ethics that are excluded by environmental ethicists. Can artifactual relationships be

meaningful? How do experiences in artificial environments alter our skills or capabilities to

develop relationships with objects in nature? Does “care” directed toward artifacts reduce

concern for the natural environments? Does this imply that ethics should prioritize some kinds

of relationships, perhaps those with humans or sentient beings, over others, rather than simply

making space for bioregional narratives? Field argued that Rolston’s concept of a “storied

residence,” which includes knowing about the non-human organisms that are our neighbors,

should be expanded to include knowledge of mass transit, architecture, etc.

In the first footnote of the paper, she provides one of the clearest definitions of what she

means by the term artifacts that I found in EE. “By artifacts I mean human-made objects as

opposed to naturally occurring entities. I realize that the line cannot be drawn so easily between

214 Ibid., 70.

89

natural and nonnatural entities (e.g., a garden is both natural and human-made), and evidence of

‘naturalness’ can be found in all our artifacts to some extent. However, my reasons for focusing

on artifacts and the artifactual environment should become clear throughout the paper.”216 Many

other articles in EE would have been improved by explicit conceptual definitions, even if they

are, like Field’s, somewhat hazy.

Earthworks. Earthworks are distinct hybrids that manipulate natural objects, often pairing them

with human constructions, that are inspired by aesthetic concerns. Prominent examples include

Peter Smithson’s Black Jetty and Otto Piene’s Rainbow over Munich. Unlike other artifacts,

their function does not contribute to human convenience or comfort. They also have more in

common with fine art, a sense of techné usually ignored in philosophical inquiries and critiques

that were found in RPT/Techné. Their creation raises a host of ethical, political, and aesthetic

issues.

Peter Humphrey’s investigation into whether earthworks should be considered ethical

concluded that no assessment can be made based on the genus; instead, creations must be

assessed individually.217 The results of the assessment vary depending on whether one values

nature instrumentally or intrinsically. If one takes an instrumental perspective, some earthworks

should be considered ethical if they meet the following three conditions. They must yield

sufficient aesthetic benefit or inspire considerable concern for the environment; they must

minimize environmental damage; and they must last for a limited time. If one values nature

intrinsically, the ethical requirements are heightened, perhaps to the point of impossibility. An

earthwork would have to reverse the trend of environmental degradation to be ethical, which

215 Terri Field, “Caring Relationships with Natural and Artificial Environments,” EE 17, no. 3 (Fall 1995):

307-320, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199517320. 216 Ibid., 307, n.1.

90

Humphrey claimed has not happened yet, or, at a minimum, it would have to be the best

alternative to achieve such an end, a condition which he doubted is ever the case.

Jason Simus’s defense of environmental artworks in “Environmental Art and Ecological

Citizenship” proceeded by labeling them as anthropogenic disturbances, motivated by moral,

social and ecological concerns.218 Such disturbances must be understood in the dynamism of

nature, which is always in flux, rather than as a wholly or desirably stable state, which he

characterizes as naïve innocence. As long as they do not cause extensive disturbance of spatial

and temporal scales, artworks can be aesthetically acceptable. Their creation includes public

participation by those who contribute to the construction of these assemblages, and their

reception, often by a far wider audience, is a form of what Andrew Light called ecological

citizenship. Light understood environmental restoration as healing the human-nature

relationship as well as reversing environmental damage. Within Simus’s framework,

environmental restoration often coincides with environmental artwork, which would seem to

multiply its value. Yet Simus argued that earthwork that is art alone has “as much democratic

potential as restoration does”219 because the artist’s act as a cultural agent can spur public

discourse on environmental and social issues.

Bryan Bannon’s “Re-Envisioning Nature: The Role of Aesthetics in Environmental

Ethics” argued that aesthetic judgments can do more to inform environmental ethics.220 Usually

aesthetic judgments are only used to correlate ecological well-being with scientific evaluation.

Bannon claims that “certain kinds of land art present a non-dualistic vision of human activity

217 Peter Humphrey, “The Ethics of Earthworks,” EE 7, no. 1 (Spring 1985): 5-21, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics1985717. 218 Jason Simus, “Environmental Art and Ecological Citizenship,” EE 30, no. 1 (Spring 2008): 21-36, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics200830115. 219 Ibid., 32. 220 Bryan Bannon, “Re-envisioning Nature: The Role of Aesthetics in Environmental Ethics,” EE 33, no. 4

(Winter 2011): 415-436, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics201133445.

91

within nature and that this vision is a necessary precondition for linking aesthetic and ecological

values in a successful way.”221 Earth artworks “educate our perceptions not in terms of specific

categories through which we will come to understand the world around us, but in accentuating

salient relationships that alter and expand our means of categorization.”222

Drawing off the aesthetic (and hermeneutic) concept of a world and our participation in

it, through making and remaking, earthworks always reshape our norms by altering perceptual

frameworks. Toward this end, sculptor Andy Goldsworthy’s works deserve special mention.

Bannon praises Goldsworthy’s work for its presentation of “a world in which human forces are

not occluded in the work such that we begin to perceive nature and the human influence within it

differently” by drawing our attention to aspects that regularly go unnoticed and by having an

engaged relationship with the landscape rather than one that is merely passive.223 While most

earth artwork is static, Goldsworthy’s ephemeral projects highlight the fluidity and fragility of

the natural world and its intertwinement with humans, a relationship in which both parties

experience vulnerability.

Restoration. The issue of restoration clearly demonstrates the difficulty of separating physis and

techné. Is a restored ecosystem natural, or does it inherit, or retain vestiges of, artifactuality from

its designers or builders? Questions such as these are philosophically complex. They demand

consideration of how parts relate to their systems, the degree human intentions are transferred to

their objects, issues over concepts such as anthropocentrism, freedom, and artifactuality, and the

relationship between nature and culture.

The articles published on restoration best fit the model of intellectual discourse proposed

by Randall Collins. The discourse originates with philosopher Robert Elliot’s “Faking Nature,”

221 Ibid., 416. 222 Ibid., 425.

92

published in the interdisciplinary journal Inquiry.224 Elliot argued that genesis and history matter

when assessing the environment. No matter how perfect the work of environmental engineers,

their work always is always inferior, a “forgery” of what originated first in nature. Eric Katz

invoked Elliot’s line of reasoning in the course of defending the moral claim made by nature that

is manifest in human’s attraction to otherness, a “yes, and” response using Collins’s terminology.

Katz’s article, in turn, precipitated several “no, but” responses, in which he was taken to task for

making genealogical, conceptual, and ontological mistakes about the relation between artifacts

and nature, and that his argument was impervious to the benefits that restoration offered. The

discourse most closely approximates dialogue, too, for Katz has responded to his critics, both in

a comment and in a second essay, which commemorated the twentieth anniversary of his first

article. A summary of the discourse follows.

Katz argued that the “Call of the Wild,” the human attraction to encounters with “wild

nature,” is a moral claim made by the natural world.225 The attraction to wild things can never be

satisfied by technologies, which, by design, promise what Thomas Birch called “control of

otherness.”226 Both the conservation and restoration movements, Katz claims, are too

anthropocentric to recognize that they are subject to this limitation. While adherents of the

former tend to see non-humans as resources, advocates of the latter introduce a moral difficulty:

“If a restored environment is an adequate replacement for the previously existing natural

environment, then humans can use, degrade, destroy, and replace natural entities and habitats

223 Ibid., 427. 224 Robert Elliot, “Faking Nature,” Inquiry 25, no. 1 (March 1982): 81-93, doi:

10.1080/00201748208601955. 225 Eric Katz, “Call of the Wild,” EE 14, no. 3 (Fall 1992): 265-273, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199214321. 226 Thomas H. Birch, “The Incarceration of Wildness: Wilderness Areas as Prisons,” EE 12, no. 1 (Spring

1990): 18, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19901215.

93

with no moral consequences whatsoever.”227 The restored area lacks continuity with the past and

is itself, in a sense, a human artifact and a forgery of the original.

Consideration of artifacts is central to Katz’s analysis. He argued that values and moral

obligations differ between what is owed to artifacts, for which function and purpose are central,

and what is owed to natural objects, which evolve without those concerns for human well-being.

Human encroachment of the latter is rightly called domination because natural objects are

prevented from exercising their freedom and reaching their self-realization. Human activity

should be restrained to leave space for the natural world to continue “its own process and history

of development independent of human intervention and activity.”228 Such restraint is “resistance

to the total domination of the technological world.”229

Steven Vogel argued that Elliott’s and Katz’s arguments against ecological restoration

are flawed genealogically and conceptually.230 They are flawed genealogically because they

unreasonably exclude artifacts made by one species, whose origin came about from “natural

selection,” from what are considered natural. Their conceptual flaw is that they overstate the

determinacy of the human craftsman with regard to its object. To Vogel, how an object is used is

more important than what the maker intended, and what an object does means more than its

origin, for example, in the case of genetically modified animals, which obviously possess an

internal telos.

The truth, of course, is that every artifact we build produces unanticipated effects, which means that every artifact has more to it than its producers intended: and so, what an artifact is always exceeds its relation to human intention. It does so because every artifact is real, and not simply an idea in someone’s head: it’s not (merely) an intention but rather the realization of an intention, and that makes a difference for as every

227 Ibid., 269. 228 Ibid., 271. 229 Ibid., 273. 230 Steven Vogel, “The Nature of Artifacts,” EE 25, no. 2 (Summer 2003): 149-168, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics200325230.

94

engineer, every gardener, and indeed every human being knows, to make something real is precisely to see it enter a realm beyond intention.231

By Vogel’s assessment, Katz’s fundamental error is adopting a conception of artifacts that is

overly instrumentalist and utilitarian. People are motivated to create artifacts or reshape nature

for different reasons. One is to allow the unpredictable to happen. Many people do not seek

domination, even if their actions can be said to somehow satisfy human desire. Restoration, in

particular, is to “go against human interests narrowly (and anthropocentrically) construed.”232 In

this case, Katz’s view of intention and anthropocentrism seemingly contradict each other:

restoration is an anti-anthropocentric intention.

Differences between human intention and actual consequences arise and develop over

time. Indeed, Vogel claimed, “when humans produce an artifact, I am suggesting, no matter

what it may be, they do so by allowing processes to come into play which then operate,

independently, to bring about a result—which result may bear a greater or lesser resemblance to

what the producers originally had in mind.”233

According to Vogel, wildness, not ontological purity, is what humans value in “natural”

settings. An appeal to history that considers non-human actions and human transformations is

more meaningful than one that privileges the former. It also provides better guidance in

determining what may be appropriate for a particular place. Vogel concluded that the value of

restoration comes “precisely from our experience in it of our involvement in the world, our

responsibilities regarding it, the concreteness and the difficulty of the work we have to do in it,

and our dependence on forces not our own to make anything we do possible.”234 Such

231 Ibid., 156 (italics in original). 232 Ibid., 158 (italics in original). 233 Ibid., 164. 234 Ibid., 165.

95

experience yields self-knowledge about human actions and their consequences as well as

humility because every artifact is dependent on nature.

Yeuk-Sze Lo attacked Katz’s rejection of restoration, in which he argued that the

ontological nature of what has been restored takes on the intention of the restorer, and, by doing

so, possesses less moral value.235 She faulted Katz for confusing origin and orientation–“to

confuse anthropogenic with anthropocentric is just like confusing self-originatedness with

selfishness”236–and for making a false distinction between not acting, which can be

nonanthropocentrism, and acting, which is always anthropocentric. By Katz’s reasoning,

humans who survive based on medical aids become artifacts as well, second-rate substitutes of

others. His error stems from a dichotomous view of artifactuality: in the previous example, the

person’s “ontological dependence on technology is only partial.”237 The person’s continued

existence depends on her internal capabilities, not just the technology.

To support this claim, Lo distinguished autonomy, which is “the capacity to act or

develop in accordance with one’s own personality, telos, or principles,” from “being

autonomous,” which is “actually acting or developing” in those ways.238 Human manipulation

of nature—and other humans as well—can further or retard the capacity, or it can just restrict its

application.

According to Lo, Katz’s analysis included two other failings. First, restored natural

systems should be thought of as reproduced, not redesigned. A copy depends on a template,

which requires no novelty, and novelty is necessary for invention. Restorations are imitations,

not inventions, and the primary “blueprint” was created without human involvement. To the

235 Yeuk-Sze Lo, “Natural and Artifactual: Restored Nature as Subject,” EE 21, no. 3 (Fall 1999): 247-266,

doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199921316. 236 Ibid., 253. 237 Ibid., 254.

96

extent that restored systems vary from their templates is simply an imperfect reproduction, not a

new design. Second, Lo argued Katz’s reasoning is “at least ill-grounded and at worst unjust” by

advocating separation from nature, which she judges to be poor, especially when compared with

gaining a proper attitude of care and respect.

C. Mark Cowell argued that, far from deserving Katz’s criticism, ecological restoration

“has the potential to engender, through science and technology, a positive, symbiotic relationship

between humans and the environment,” which stands in contrast to how most other interactions

are characterized.239 It also transforms ecology from a observational, descriptive science that is

precautionary to one that is predictive, experimental, and demands action. Humans are not

limited to what Eugene Hargrove called “environmental therapeutic nihilism” but can engage in

prudent manipulation. By directly reconnecting humans with their environments, new values

may arise, which Cowell proposes can lead to a “participatory-gardener” relationship that blurs

the boundaries between natural preserves and landscapes harnessed for production.240 As he puts

it, “the poles of human and natural dissolve and are replaced by a full spectrum of

participation.”241 Participation increases understanding, which can contribute to harmonious

behavior.

Cowell’s claims about the relationship of nature and technology are contrary to most

others. Elliot had argued that restored areas are deprived of their origin and history, which make

them forgeries. Hargrove had assigned preservationist duties to the “existence of good in the

world,” and the goods of nature deserve more protection than art because it is irreplaceable on

238 Ibid., 256. 239 C. Mark Cowell, “Ecological Restoration and Environmental Ethics,” EE 15, no. 1 (Spring 1993): 19-

32, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199315136. This understanding contrasts with Barry Commoner’s Third Law of Ecology, “Nature knows best,” which Eugene Hargrove dubbed “environmental therapeutic nihilism.”

240 Ibid., 32. He argues that restoration, as presently done, results in a new set of nature preserves because humans are excluded from species of concern.

241 Ibid., 32.

97

account of its complexity.242 Bruce Foltz explained the traditional position using Heideggerian

terms by arguing that the shift to resource (Bestand) can never be undone.243

Implicit in all of the restorationists’ responses, according to Cowell, is the claim “that

humans and their technology are natural.”244 Following William Jordan, he argued that too

many preservationists adopt a view that is “selectively anti-ecological,” that is, despite the

attention given to relationships and interactions of all others species, humans are encouraged to

sever all interspecies relationships. Inspired by Carolyn Merchant, Cowell claimed that human

participation in nature must recognize the responsibilities that arise from the ability of our

species to transform nature.

Restoration management can aim for a static goal, the recreation of the climax

community, which requires external compensation for unwanted perturbations, whether natural

or not. It can also embrace dynamism and use the climax community as a reference point rather

than a goal. If the goal of restoration management is “the reintroduction (or simply the

uninhibited operation of) presettlement forces,”245 humans are neglected from the analysis. Any

new values formed by direct interaction during the restoration process are at risk of dissipating,

Cowell thought.

Katz made two more contributions to the discourse in the journal that has proceeded

largely from “Call of the Wild.” The first is a brief comment, a “yes, and” amendment to Robert

Elliot, and thus his own, initial argument.246 Elliot’s analogy between nature and a material

artifact is inexact because the latter has a stability that the former lacks. Instead of using a

242 Ibid., 24. 243 Foltz, “On Heidegger and the Interpretation of Environmental Crisis,” EE 6, no. 4 (Winter 1984), 330,

doi: 10.5840/enviroethics1984643. (In the article Foltz ultimately argues against this position.) 244 Cowell, “Ecological Restoration,” 26. 245 Ibid., 30. 246 Katz, “Artefacts and Functions: A Note on the Value of Nature,” EE 18, no. 2 (Summer 1996): 222-224,

doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199618236.

98

painting for comparison, Katz proposed that a dynamic human activity, such as dance or music,

corresponds better with the active processes and flux involved in nature. He also attempts to

explicitly state the superficial attitude that he fears restoration encourages. “What needs to be

restore,” he says, “is not degraded ecological systems but the human capacity for understanding

the limits and meaning of our power over the natural world.”247

Katz’s second substantial contribution to EE came twenty years later in “Further

Adventures in the Case against Restoration.”248 In it, he defended his argument that authenticity

was lost in an area that had been restored because its genesis and history had been radically

changed, and so the area is rightly called an artifact. No hybrid of natural and artifactual is

possible, he claimed, because a dualistic conception of natural objects and artifacts is necessary

to form “a normative principle to check the power of human domination.”249

His support of this exclusivity rests on linguistics. First, he summons Helena Siipi’s

linguistic analysis, which claims “the important distinction we should consider is between

artifacts and non-artifacts, not between artifacts and natural entities.” Second, he cites Paul M.

Keeling’s Wittgensteinian practical analysis of the use of the terms, rather than their essence, to

support his claim that “the dualism of nature and artifact thus does not need to be defended; it is

pre-supposed in any discussion of the value of the natural environment.”250 Though Siipi’s claim

contradicts Keeling’s, Katz interprets both as support of his dualistic presumption.

The difficulty in following his response, which seems intended for maximum rhetorical

effect, exemplifies the philosophical challenges involved with this task. Some of his claims

seem circular, and some of his terminology seems inconsistent. An example of the former is his

247 Ibid., 224. 248 Katz, “Further Adventures in the Case against Restoration,” EE 34, no. 1 (Spring 2012): 67-97, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics20123416. 249 Ibid., 86.

99

claim that restoration is never restoration of nature. This is a truism within his taxonomy

because he defines nature as that which is (and apparently, has been) free from human

intentionality and design. As an example of the difficulties involved in the latter, he said

“restored ecosystems or entities are no longer natural beings but artifacts,” yet “entities can be

more or less artifactual and more or less natural.”251 He claimed “restoration projects may be

more or less artifactual because of the kind and amount of new functions that result from the

restoration activity,”252 though I am unable to imagine a “project” that is not wholly artificial

according to his definition.

Part of this difficulty arises from the number of definitions of artifacts that are included in

the paper. For Katz, it is the imposition of human agency, which changes the character of an

area by altering its causal history. They are “the physical manifestations of human intention and

design…human purpose imposed on the world of nature.”253 For Helena Siipi, artifacts are

entities that are intentionally modified to add a new function. For Keeling, the distinction

between human and non-human agency determines the “internal grammatical relation” of artifact

and nature.

One would expect that a feminist contribution may be able to advance a discussion

impeded by concerns about dualism. Unfortunately, Colette R. Palamar’s “Restorashyn:

Ecofeminist Restoration,” the only feminist foray into environmental restoration, does not

mention artifacts at all.254 Her concerns are limited to organisms, with a focus on attempts to rid

250 Ibid., 92 (italics in original). 251 Ibid., 74, 76. 252 Ibid., 89. 253 Ibid., 72. 254 Colette R. Palamar, “Restorashyn: Ecofeminist Restoration,” EE 28, no. 3 (Fall 2006): 285-301, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics200628318.

100

an environment of its non-invasive, usually non-native species. This desire, she argues is a “tacit

acceptance of oppression and domination in the practice of ecological restoration.”255

Science, Technology, Technoscience, and Nature

The first paper in this constellation is Don Howard’s response to Barry Commoner’s The

Closing Circle, an early submission that stood on its own, drawing neither extension or

correction. The rest of the papers depend on or respond to the philosophy of Martin Heidegger.

Depending on the author, Heidegger’s work inspires a repositioning of metaphysics, it remedies

shortcomings in Marx, or it provides a ground that for an ethics that is neither anthropocentric

nor overly concerned with valuation. Refracted by Albert Borgmann, Heidegger’s thought

backgrounds a critique of ecologism, the use of natural science as a dominant, exclusive way of

describing the natural world, and it is applied in an assessment in backcountry hiking tools. The

dialogue includes one dissenting voice that argued that Heidegger’s importance is overstated, at

least for environmental concerns.

Howard on Commoner. Don Howard’s “Commoner on Reductionism” challenged Barry

Commoner’s claim that the environmental harms of modern technologies spring from

reductionist science, which originated in physics and, in 1979, was influencing molecular

biology.256 Howard argued that Commoner used the term “reductionism” for what philosophers

of science call an “analytic approach.” Yet philosophers of science only used reductionism to

refer to the explanation of one theory in terms of another, not to refer to the process of studying a

complex object in terms of its components. Howard also thought Commoner’s critique failed

because it made the mistaken assumption that relational properties cannot be studied using an

analytic mode.

255 Ibid., 287.

101

According to Commoner, a study of a technological object such as the automobile is

concerned with the “systematic application of scientific or other organized knowledge to

practical tasks.” A study of an ecosystem, on the contrary, “cannot be subdivided into

manageable parts, for its properties reside in the whole, in the connections between the parts.”

Using the approach of the former, i.e., studying it “fragment by fragment,” “is precisely how it

has been used in the series of blunders that have generated the environmental crisis.”257 Howard

argued that the difference between the study of artifacts and ecosystem science is one of degree

rather than of kind, which arises from the fact that our knowledge of ecosystems and their

workings is always incomplete.

Commoner’s assignment of blame to the connections between scientific analysis,

technology built based on its principles, and environmental issues that have arisen from the use

of such technologies is thus erroneous. Both molecular biologists and engineers, Howard noted,

pay too little attention to relations in the systems they study. The molecular biologists and

engineers are dissuaded from such efforts because analysis on complex systems is often

expensive and because knowledge is overly disciplined, meaning that few individuals can do

such analysis on their own and multidisciplinary teams must be constructed. These problems,

Howard argued, have their philosophical origin in the common pedagogy of sciences. The

analytic approach should be spared Commoner’s reproach: his holism risks ushering in a new

era of “obscurantism.”

Heideggerian-Informed Articles. Bruce V. Foltz argued that almost all previous inquiries into

environmental ethics are inadequate because they are primarily informed by the natural sciences,

256 Don Howard, “Commoner on Reductionism,” EE 1, no. 2 (1979): 159-176, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics19791224. 257 Barry Commoner, The Closing Circle (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1971), 184-185, as quoted by

Howard, “Commoner,” 171 (italics in original).

102

especially ecology.258 Ethics inspired by the sciences disproportionately emphasize material

things, the common objects of study for natural scientists, at the expense of relationships between

the things. This deficiency is exacerbated when it occurs in ecosystem analysis, for from it the

only conclusion that can be drawn is that humans disturb the balance of nature present in the

ecosystem. From such a baseline, environmental ethics becomes an articulation of ways to

regulate human actions to reduce or eliminate any present imbalances, a result that can be

evaluated by the same scientific framework that led to the identification of unethical behavior.

Foltz’s Heideggerian proposal is that primacy of inquiry can be given to relation with

nature from the position of relation itself as well as or instead of giving primacy to the natural

objects viewed through the perspective of the natural sciences. The “post-metaphysical

understanding of nature,” which depends on “neither the part-whole relation of ecology nor the

standpoint of metaphysical thinking, which situates itself everywhere and nowhere,” is one that

is also a “post-technological understanding of nature.”259 Such a perspective saves an

environmental ethicist from the circular trap of the natural sciences and the disengaged,

disinterested trap that snares the modern objectivist.

An understanding of the world as standing-reserve [Bestand], which informs a

technological way of thinking, must be considered as only one possible way, and a secondary

one at that, to interpret the world. An appreciation of constant presence, which is a way of being

in which self-withholding and absence are part of the field of study, is more fundamental even

though it had been largely ignored in the history of Western philosophy since the time of the

258 Bruce V. Foltz, “On Heidegger and the Environmental Crisis,” EE 6, no. 4 (1984): 323-338, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics1984643. 259 Ibid., 325.

103

Greeks.260 The interpretation of nature as “what is indifferently present (vorhanden) to detached

observation,” an interpretation commonly held by natural scientists, is a second-order

understanding that obscures the meaningfulness embedded in our primal experience of nature.261

The second-order appreciation opens up a third-order understanding, which is what can be

gleaned from experiment. These derivative understandings of nature forfeit its “integral,

enchanting, and inspiring power” and “the sheltering, preserving, and self-concealing aspect of

physis,” which Foltz proposed is the “earth’s primary carrying capacity.”262

A Heideggerian corrective was also posited by Hwa Yol Jung as a way to address

limitations in Marxist analysis.263 In her reading, Marx’s concerns over alienation of humans

from each other and his desire for slave liberation cannot be extended to address human

alienation from the environment. Such an extension is impossible largely because of Marx’s

conception of technology, which is as a tool of human production meant to harness the power of

nature. Marx did not see how the advance of “History” came at the loss of nature, his conception

of man was overly determined by man as homo faber, and his economic and social thought was

conditioned by the Enlightenment promise of technology. Jung argues that the environmental

concern is more fundamental than social criticism of capitalism and socialism, one that

“demands no less than a radical deconstruction of modern technomorphic culture and its

metaphysical foundations.”264

260 From such a perspective, restoration becomes incoherent. It is merely something “challenged forth”

twice. 261 Foltz, “On Heidegger,” 332. 262 Ibid., 335-336. 263 Hwa Yol Jung, “Marxism, Ecology, and Technology,” EE 5, no. 2 (Summer 1983): 169-171, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics1983522. 264 Ibid., 171.

104

Heidegger’s thought directly informed Christopher Manes’s defense of the ontological

ambiguities present in biocentric environmental ethics.265 Manes appropriated Heidegger’s

definition of technology as “a ‘relationship’ between humanity and things that forces them to

appear only in a utilitarian mode.”266 Such a conception leads to positive values, a diminution of

the Being of a thing in its Heideggerian sense. Neither mysticism, which attempts to ignore

technology, nor phenomenology, which, in articulating the background conditions in which we

interpret the world, elevates the Self over and above other organisms, can properly ground

biocentrism. “Biocentric environmentalism is the last reservoir of revolutionary energy in a

technological culture whose chief accomplishment is assimilating its critics” precisely by

avoiding the desire to make claims about positive value,267 which reinforces a technological way

of viewing the world.

Heidegger through Borgmann. Heidegger’s influence is channeled through noted philosopher of

technology Albert Borgmann in contributions from David Strong and Sarah Pohl. Strong argued

that a scientifically-informed ecology must be complemented with “disclosive discourse,” that is,

a language of engagement expressed through first-person narrative or poetry.268 Such a synthesis

escapes the confines of modern natural science, which arise from its claim to universalism and

objectivity conveyed through a reductionist mode of communication that admits only

experimental knowledge. Disclosive discourse presents “nature and natural things in their most

profound and powerful appeal,” just as it does the same with artwork, music, and human signs.269

It requires full engagement of mind and body and complete cognizance of one’s surroundings,

265 Christopher Manes, “Philosophy and the Environmental Task,” EE 10, no. 1 (Spring 1988): 75-82, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics198810124. 266 Ibid., 76 n. 2. 267 Ibid., 81. 268 David Strong, “Disclosive Discouse, Ecology, and Technology,” EE 16, no. 1 (Spring 1994): 89-102,

doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199416144. 269 Ibid., 90.

105

those that are natural as well as those that are cultural. It is superior to the language of one

science or even a harmony of sciences because it reveals more fundamental insights into human

being. The importance of disclosive discourse is hard to overstate: without it, ecology loses its

subversive character.

Strong provided a corrective to Mark Sagoff’s well-known understanding of ecology as

two sciences. According to Sagoff, one science of ecology promotes domination of nature, and

the other results in respect for nature. Strong understands that this bifurcation as one science that

searches for theories and laws that can be directed toward two different and exclusive goals.

Sagoff’s explanation of science also lacks two peripheral though important understandings of its

practice. Science is a social activity motivated and affected by human passions and weaknesses.

It is also a body of knowledge that is applied in technology, which has its own human-

contributed characteristics such as resourcefulness or imperialism.270 For ecology in particular,

the first peripheral understanding orients the objects studied in scientific practice from the nearly

infinite options that are possible. The powerful direction that arises from this understanding of

the practice of science is evident from John and Mildred Teals’ study of swamp marshes. Their

inquiry “is initiated, prompted, by the various powers of marshes that stirred and awakened” the

scientists rather than the one that was determined by science in its central sense, i.e., as a search

for or application of laws of physics, chemistry, and biology.271

Disclosive discourse depends on contact with wild nature, which is at risk when the

present age is thoroughly technological. A second risk of living in a technological age in which

the value of technological progress is also assumed. The promise of comfort, convenience, and

availability of new technology overshadows the “disburdenment, disengagement, diversion,

270 Strong is using Albert Borgmann’s distinction in Technology and the Character of Contemporary Life:

A Philosophical Inquiry (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 17.

106

distraction, and loneliness” that arises from its adoption.272 Technology is harmful not just

because it is the cause of environmental harm, but, more fundamentally, it also degrades our

sense of engagement, a prerequisite for disclosive discourse. Both natural and cultural things

deserve deep engagement, an engagement that surpasses the quantitative conclusions that

disinterested, experimental science can provide.

Pohl’s “Technology and the Wilderness Experience” synthesized Borgmann and Strong’s

concern for deep engagement within the framework of Alasdair MacIntyre’s virtue ethics, which

she then applied to assess the kinds of gear that are appropriate for backcountry hiking.273 Her

essay is inspired by personal experiences and narrative, not theoretical concerns, bolstered by

MacIntyre’s concept of practice, to determine which goods are “internal” to the practice of

backcountry hiking. The assessment is guided by Albert Borgmann’s distinction between things

and devices, and Pohl shares his advocacy for focal practices.274 Moreover, Pohl sees the habits

formed by backcountry hiking as contributing to the development of characteristics, such as

greater mental clarity and self-sufficiency balanced by the recognition of our relationships with

others and greater mental clarity, that result in flourishing.275 Citing Strong and Borgmann, Pohl

positions the experience of wilderness as a counterforce to consumerist tendencies in

contemporary culture.

Religion and Transcendence

271 Strong, “Disclosive Discourse,” 96. 272 Ibid., 100. 273 Sarah Pohl, “Technology and the Wilderness Experience,” EE 28, no. 2 (Summer 2006): 147-163, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics200628229. 274 Things are artifacts that are connected to their social, temporal, and material origins that require skill to

use. Devices are artifacts in which connections are severed and operate regardless of skill or attention. A focal thing “gathers the relations of its context and radiates into its surroundings and informs them.” from Borgmann, Technology and the Character of Contemporary Life, 197.

275 Pohl, “Technology and the Wilderness Experience,” 157.

107

Two articles address the relation of technology and religion through the lens of medieval

historian Lynn White, Jr.’s influential “The Historical Roots of Our Ecologic Crisis.” As best as

I could tell, none of the articles that discussed other religions and the environment devoted much

attention to how the religion influenced how artifacts and technology are understood.

White’s paper argued for a connection between technology, religion, and ethics, and its

respondents challenge central aspects of his argument. On the one hand, the discourse fits the

model of academic journal discourse, especially on an interdisciplinary topic: the papers form a

focused, sustained dialogue on an ethical importance. On the other hand, White published in

Nature, not a philosophical journal. The responses are also an academic lifespan removed from

White’s publication, which is problematic because of the critical nature of their assessment. In

her Spring 2009 paper, Robin Attfield writes “by now, the influence of ‘Roots’ has become a

cultural given, unlikely to be modified by journal articles, however broad or scholarly.”276

White’s paper gained widespread attention for at least four reasons. First, it provided a

historical justification for positing that an individual’s worldview affects how he interprets a

range of environmental issues. Religion necessarily falls under the purview of environmental

ethics. Part of the reason White’s article became a lightning rod is that advanced economies

based on modern science and technology developed in cultures in which Christianity was a

dominant cultural force, and any assessment of environmental ills is inadequate if it does not

consider religion. Second, though White’s research was over medieval history, his paper was

published in Nature, a scientific journal. Third, White’s paper was timely: it corresponded to a

rise in popular concern about the environment that led to the development of the academic

276 Robin Attfield, “Social History, Religion, and Technology: An Interdisciplinary Investigation into Lynn

White, Jr.’s ‘Roots,’”, EE 31, no. 1 (Spring 2009): 32, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics20093114. I think she understates the persistence of cultural influences and the relevance of her contribution, but it bears wondering why Attfield did not attempt an original work instead of one derived from White.

108

specialization of environmental ethics. Fourth, White’s paper possesses an interpretative

uncertainty that makes it good fodder for discussion, even forty years after its publication.

Should it be considered primarily an indictment of Christianity? Or as an attempt to draw

attention to how environmental concerns depend on an individual’s broader worldview? Who

should pay attention to White’s argument?

Attfield argued that White’s paper should be understood historically because he was a

practicing medieval historian.277 It also should be understood theologically, since much of his

account is based on an interpretation of Christian history from Church Fathers such as Tertullian

and Irenaeus through the Middle Ages, and because of the voluminous response from

ecotheologians that followed the publication of White’s paper. The term ecotheology itself was

popularized and legitimized by White’s paper.

Attfield’s assessment of White’s paper is mixed. Compared to White’s earlier study of

medieval history, Medieval Technology and Social Change, “Roots” ignores historical evidence

that the eight-oxen plough had been used since almost the second century C.E. in Italy, and later

in Syria and Sardinia, and in Mexico prior to colonization. To call it the product of Western

Christianity is at best a rhetorical exaggeration. Further, White’s argument has been criticized

for implicitly depending on technological determinism or cultural determinism. It also ascribes a

single causal influence to religion and individual beliefs when social and economic influences

also matter. In Attfield’s assessment, White’s paper should be considered a rhetorical success

for its success linking values to beliefs and institutions, in spite of its many failings, which

include errors in the history of technology.

Elspeth Whitney contributed two papers, twenty years apart, to EE. In the first, she noted

evidence that casted doubt on White’s connection between medieval Christianity and

109

environmental degradation, methodological issues about his historical analysis, and issues about

the relationship between technology and democracy.278 On the last point, White connected

technology to compassion. As Whitney quoted,

Engineers are arch-enemies of all who, because of their fortunate position, resist the surge of the mass of humankind toward a new order of plenty, of mobility, and of personal freedom. Within the societies which have consolidated about the Marxist and the Western democratic revolutions, engineers’ activities are the chief threat to surviving privilege.279

As Whitney remarked, White’s link between technology, compassion, and environmental

degradation leads to a line of inquiry that has been underdeveloped.

In the second, she claimed that the tremendous attention given to White’s paper for its

contribution to ecotheology and environmental ethics has led to many overlooking his role as an

environmental historian who successfully drew attention to the importance of agriculture during

the medieval period.280 White’s more extensive Medieval Technology and Social Change,

published in 1962, as well as his later writings, focused on a newfound “‘imagination’” toward

harnessing forces in nature toward “‘labour-saving technology’” more so than it did the role of

religion.281 In “Roots,” however, White introduced “a false dichotomy between Christianity as

hermeneutics and Christianity as cultural expression rooted in history” that led to confusion

interpreting the medieval period and contemporary environmental issues.282 Despite

longstanding neglect by environmental historians, White was one of the first to value “the ways

in which cultural perceptions, ideologies, ethics, and myths have become part of an individual’s

277 Attfield, “Social History, Religion, and Technology,” EE 31, no. 1 (Spring 2009): 31-50. 278 Elspeth Whitney, “Lynn White, Ecotheology, and History,” EE 15, no. 2 (Summer 1993): 151-169, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics199315229. 279 White, “Engineering and the Making of a New Humanism,” in Dynamo and Virgin Reconsidered:

Essays in the Dynamism of Western Culture (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1971), 149, as quoted by Whitney, “Lynn White,” 153.

280 Elspeth Whitney, “The Lynn White Thesis: Reception and Legacy,” EE 35, no. 3 (Fall 2013): 313-331, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics201335328.

281 Ibid., 316.

110

or group’s dialogue with nature.”283 Therefore, he deserves credit in spite of what has been

called his “Hegelian position,” his one-dimensional analysis that only considered religion, which

he interpreted monolithically, and his failure to mention that environmental degradation in

western Europe was far from unique.

Aesthetics of Artworks

Three articles focus on an aesthetics of nature vis-a-vis an aesthetics of artworks. While

noting that both an aesthetics of art and an aesthetics of nature have moral significance, Yuriko

Saito emphasized the differences between the moral implications of the two. Janna Thompson

took an opposite task, arguing that the similarities between the activity of appreciating art and

nature lead to a responsibility to protect natural entities that is at least as great as the

responsibility to preserve important artworks. Roger Paden, Laurlyn K. Harmon, and Charles R.

Milling attempt to restore the concepts of the sublime and picturesque, terms that originated in an

aesthetics of natural objects but are commonly thought to refer to artworks, that can be helpful in

engendering a sense of moral responsibility for natural beings and in describing evolution-based

science, respectively.

According to Saito, a developed aesthetics of nature has a moral component.284 A related

argument has been made by cultural geographer Yi-Fu Tuan, who compared the relationship

between aesthetic relevance and moral goodness. Art has a moral aspect because it asks one to

adopt the perspective of the artist, to step outside of one’s self. The primary similarity between

aesthetics of art and aesthetics of nature is that both should be experienced and situated in their

own context. Yet the appreciation of nature differs from that of art because to exclusively

282 Ibid., 318. 283 Ibid., 321. 284 Yuriko Saito, “Appreciating Nature on Its Own Terms,” EE 20, no. 2 (Summer 1998): 135-149, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics199820228.

111

appreciate nature for its visual affects or cultural associations is a-moral. Instead, to understand

nature “for what it is” through natural history sciences, such as geology and biology, and

indigenous traditions and bioregional narratives that emphasize natural rather than human

behavior, has moral value.285 According to Saito, moral value arises through being receptive to

nature rather than exerting one’s will upon it.

Thompson proposed that Hargrove’s argument that an environmental ethic can be based

on aesthetic value can supported by the similarity of the activity of appreciating art works and

appreciating the environment.286 Like art history and art criticism, scientific knowledge,

including natural history, “makes proper appreciation possible and at the same time provides a

basis for judgments about aesthetic worth.”287 She gives several reasons for this claim. Both

kinds of appreciation must be learned and are both difficult. Aesthetics of nature and artworks

satisfy the senses, please the intellect, and inspire imagination. Some “disturb and challenge our

old habits of perception and imagination”288; others connect us to our past. From this, Thompson

concluded that “Everyone (whether they make the effort to appreciate this worth or not) has a

duty to protect and preserve natural beauty that is at least as demanding as the duty to preserve

great works of art.”289

Roger Paden, Laurlyn K. Harmon, and Charles R. Milling offered a correction to Allen

Carlson’s influential history of aesthetics.290 Carlson erred by ignoring aesthetics prior to the

eighteenth century. From the ancient Greeks through the Renaissance, beauty was understood

“to be primarily understood to be a quality of nature, specifically natural objects insofar as they

285 Ibid., 136. 286 Janna Thompson, “Aesthetics and the Value of Nature,” EE 17, no. 3 (Fall 1995): 291-305, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics199517319. 287 Ibid., 296. 288 Ibid., 302. 289 Ibid., 305.

112

are symmetrical, balanced, and well-ordered.”291 Such concepts can be applied to small

organisms and objects in nature, but they say little about nature on a larger scale, such as a

mountain range, a forest, or an ocean.

Two new aesthetic categories, the “picturesque” and the “sublime,” were proposed for

such experiences. These were not adapted to an aesthetics of nature from works of art, as

Carlson believed. Instead,

What actually happened in the eighteenth century was that aestheticians shifted their attention from individual natural objects to landscapes. This shift implies that there are two separate fields of study within the aesthetics of nature—the aesthetics of individual natural objects and environmental aesthetics—and that what later occurred in the early eighteenth century was a shift from the former to the latter.

Unlike dominant narratives of aesthetics, the relationship between the categories of beauty,

sublime, and picturesque did not depend on size. A thing called the sublime brought out a

“subjective effect” of awe.292 The picturesque, usually associated with landscapes, “makes

essential reference to the notions of complexity and intricacy”293 by the absence of symmetry,

balance, and harmony. It is “fascinating and surprising, open to constant reinterpretation and

reassessment,” though not awe-inspiring, and demands “continuous creative engagement.”294

The sublime fell victim to the disinterestedness popular in eighteenth century aesthetic theories.

The origins of the picturesque were obscured and lost through etymology: it is the painting that

depicts a picturesque scene, not a scene that is called picturesque because it would make a good

painting.

The authors argue that the categories of the picturesque and sublime can be rehabilitated

to serve contemporary concerns. “Aesthetic theories inspired by the picturesque might be

290 Roger Paden, Laurlyn K. Harmon, and Charles R. Milling, “Philosophical Histories of Nature,” EE 35,

no. 1 (Spring 2013): 57-77, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics20133516. 291 Ibid., 62. 292 Ibid., 66.

113

particularly appropriate to nature as understood by contemporary evolution-based science,” and

“discussions of the transformative power of the sublime might do more to lead us ‘from beauty

to duty,’ than arguments about natural beauty as disinterested pleasure.”295

Having mapped out five constellations of articles from EE that generally correspond the

constellations found in RPT/Techné, the task is to integrate the two charts. This is the task of the

next chapter.

293 Ibid., 67. 294 Ibid., 68. 295 Ibid., 76-77.

114

CHAPTER 5

TOWARD A STEREOSCOPIC VIEW OF TECHNÉ AND PHYSIS

Wilfrid Sellars argued that the goal of philosophy in the present era is to integrate the

manifest and scientific images encountered, rather than letting the scientific image have

disproportionate influence, so as to see a coherent whole.296 The preceding chapters have

painted pictures of how nature has been understood in RPT/Techne, and, likewise, technology in

EE.297 The task of the next two chapters is to bring environmental philosophy and philosophy of

technology together into a stereoscopic representation.

This chapter explores the intersection between the two specializations in more detail.

First, I complete a longitudinal analysis that charts the frequency of articles that discuss the other

specialization in each interdisciplinary journal and discuss the human and institutional factors

behind their variance.

Next, I investigate the individuals who have published in both journals and the

institutions that have supported them. Paul T. Durbin’s history of philosophy of technology,

which is based on the framework developed by Walter Watson in The Architectonics of

Meaning,298 is given special attention. Durbin, whose history progresses through important

contributors to the Society of Philosophy and Technology, located the intersection of

environmental philosophy and philosophy of technology in the person and work of Andrew

Light. Durbin’s work is important because of his longstanding influence in the specialization,

and his portrayal of Light’s pragmatist orientation illuminates the novelty of my project.

296 Wilfrid Sellars, “Philosophy and the Scientific Image of Man,” in In the Space of Reasons: Selected

Essays of Wilfrid Sellars, edited by Kevin Scharp and Robert B. Brandom (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 2007), 369-408.

297 See the List of Abbreviations to see the shorthand used to refer to frequently mentioned journals. 298 Walter Watson, The Architectonics of Meaning: Foundations of the New Pluralism (Albany, New York:

State University of New York Press, 1985).

115

Given the short lines of discourse investigated in the third and fourth chapters and the

limited overlap between contributors, I conclude the chapter by offering my own integration of

the two specializations that starts from one promising article from Jacques Ellul on “Nature,

Technique and Artificiality” to sketch an image of the interrelated concepts of freedom,

evolution, and ecology informed by the history and depth of philosophy of technology and

environmental philosophy.

Longitudinal Interspecialization Analysis

Both RPT/Techné and EE published articles on a number of topics that do not depend on

and would not be improved by more attention to nature and techné respectively. Such concerns,

if they arise, are secondary or tertiary to the article as it stands. For example, RPT/Techné

published articles on such themes as media, politics, design, and risk, and many contributors to

EE focused on intrinsic value and intrinsic worth, moral consideration of species and individuals,

and the importance of wilderness and its romantic depictions. As interest in these areas waxed

and waned, it is expected that attention to what appears to be a fringe topic such as nature for

Techné and techné for EE would vary.

In additional to such natural variance, institutional factors also affected the frequency of

articles germane to my inquiry. The histories of both specializations seem to have inherited the

attributes of their topics. From its beginning as the official publication of the Society for

Philosophy and Technology (SPT), RPT/Techné has had a relatively consistent community

involved in the composition and publication of articles who have also tended to the development

of the specialization, i.e., they took an active role in impressing a design on the literature and the

society. This directedness holds even though RPT/Techné has had several different editors and a

bit of an uneven publication history over its lifetime. It can be attributed in part to the body of

116

literature that had been consolidated before the society was formed. SPT arose several years

after the publication of Carl Mitcham and Robert Mackey’s anthology Philosophy and

Technology: Readings in the Philosophical Problems of Technology.299 It can be attributed in

part to the institutional inheritance SPT obtained from the stable, long-established

interdisciplinary community of the Society for the History of Technology, which had published

Technology and Culture for 20 years before SPT was formed. In the third volume, Durbin

remarked that the first two volumes of RPT provided the single best introduction to philosophical

issues involved in technology, and that the second volume addressed regional bias found in the

first issue by introducing more European voices.300 At least two more decisions led to some

unity among contributors. One, RPT regularly published extensive annotated bibliographies on

the specialization and on other specializations that they found germane, including Eric Higgs’s

efforts on environmental ethics discussed later in this chapter. Bibliographies tend to contribute

to a shared foundation of knowledge that makes discourse possible. Two, RPT/Techné often

published theme issues that followed biannual conference themes, which directed contributions

toward certain topics.

The preceding comments suggest that the treatment of nature in RPT would be systematic

and regular, notwithstanding the spurts that would arise when themed volumes were dedicated to

environmental issues. This is true to an extent—some of the spike in articles can be traced to the

twelfth volume on Technology and the Environment and the eighteenth volume on Philosophies

of the Environment and Technology, and some remnants from the Peniscola, Spain biannual

conference were published in volume 2, no. 3/4 in the Journal for the Society of Philosophy and

Technology—yet what stands out is the lack of attention given the environment in every decade

299 Carl Mitcham and Robert Mackey, eds., Philosophy and Technology: Readings in the Philosophical

Problems of Technology (New York: Free Press, 1983[1972]).

117

other than the 1990s. The spurts themselves prevent discourse analysis, because contributors

generate a multifaceted analysis of an issue at one moment in time, but without being informed

by the others because the different voices speak, as it were, simultaneously.

When SPT shifted its support from RPT to the Society of Philosophy and Technology

electronic quarterly in 1995, one might have thought that it would imitate the journals from other

disciplines (and like EE). Slightly after the transition, Paul T. Durbin wrote “There is no

coherent theme for this double issue. In that respect, it is much more like the contents of any

field's professional journal. We clearly have not yet arrived. But we are getting somewhere.”301

Durbin was optimistic, but after he ceded editorial responsibilities to Pieter Tijmes and Davis

Baird, over half of the volumes were themed or largely dominated by a theme, and conceptual

issues of nature and the environment were not regularly addressed. The following figure shows

the papers that address conceptual issues of the other specialization over the first generation of

each specialization.

As may be expected from a journal that studies a topic influenced by Darwin, EE evolved

more organically. Its development can be traced back to Eugene Hargrove’s elevator inspiration

in 1977, and the field was still in its infancy.302 Six years earlier, J. Baird Callicott had

volunteered to teach the first environmental ethics course at the University of Wisconsin-Stevens

Point.303 After doing so, Callicott quickly realized there was little literature on the topic: there

was nothing that corresponded to the Mitcham/Mackey anthology for some time. In addition to

the institutional, the pivotal societal event that galvanized environmental concern was Earth Day,

300 Paul T. Durbin, Introduction to the Series, RPT 3 (1980): 1-4. 301 Durbin, Preface to JSPT 2, no. 3/4, 112. 302 Eugene Hargrove, “How, When, Where, and Why,” EE 1, no. 1 (Spring 1979): 1, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics1979111. 303 University of North Texas Faculty Page for J. Baird Callicott,

https://philosophy.unt.edu/people/faculty/j-baird-callicott.

118

Figure 1. Cross-Specialization Articles in EE and RPT: Techné.

which happened first in 1969. The International Society for Environmental Ethics was founded

in 1987. Contrast this to the development and use of the atomic bomb, which occurred in 1945

and the institutional history of SPT listed above. In many ways, RPT/Techné had a head start of

more than two decades.

Despite the lack of institutional guidance, articles that took conceptual issues of

technology seriously in EE were published at a regular pace over the history of the journal. The

bursts in interest given to nature in RPT/Techné do not have a counterpart in articles on

technology in EE. Even in the absence of such bursts, temporal discourse analysis was still

impossible because the intellectual give-and-take that is often thought to be part of the practice

119

of academic discourse did not arise, which is the main reason that clusters of articles on a

particular topic are best considered constellations.

Brief Sketches of Crossover Contributors

At this point, it is possible to make good on my promise in the second chapter to pay

attention to the people behind the articles in both EE and RPT/Techné and the institutions that

support them, rather than just the ideas themselves or their frequencies. There were twenty-four

individuals who published in both journals over that time period. Of them, five published a

single article in each journal, and eight published more than one article in both journals. Of the

remaining contributors, nine of them published more in EE, and the other two published more in

RPT/Techné. By far the most common departmental home is in the philosophy departments of

various universities, but contributors were also part of departments of economics, political

science, environmental studies, environmental sciences, anthropology and sociology, and

agricultural economics. One author, J.A. Doeleman, published his second article while

employed by the International Labor Office in Geneva, Switzerland. Such diversity is proof that

the editors of both journals welcomed interdisciplinary contributions. The brief summaries of

the individual and the theses that he or she advanced that follow below show the diversity in

interests and approaches.

Multiple Articles in Both Journals. Of the eight authors who published more than one article in

each journal, J. Baird Callicott, Eric Katz, Steven Vogel, and Michael Zimmerman are more

closely associated with environmental philosophy, and Frederick Ferré, Kristin Shrader-

Frechette, and Paul Thompson primarily concerned with philosophy and technology. They are

all philosophers, though their research areas are diverse. Callicott is the best-known defender of

a biocentric environmental ethic developed from the writings of game manager Aldo Leopold.

120

Katz’s main concern is with the ethics of restoration. Vogel’s most recent work is on the end of

nature as a guiding concept for environmental ethics, and Zimmerman is a Heidegger-inspired

ecologist. Ferré, now deceased, edited RPT from 1989 to 1994, and published an introductory

textbook Philosophy of Technology in 1995. Shrader-Frechette, the third president of SPT,

focused on technological assessment and epistemic and ethical risk analysis. Thompson, another

past president of SPT, has written widely on agricultural issues, especially those that have to do

with biotechnology.

As part of the Department of Philosophy at the University of Wisconsin, Stevens Point,

Callicott was one of the contributors to the inaugural issue of EE. In this article, he proposed,

using some symbolic logic, an environmental ethic developed from Leopold’s The Land Ethic,304

which he further described as a holistic alternative to the animal liberation movement in the

Winter 1980 issue.305 In 1982, he published two articles, the first defending Leopold’s reasoning

from charges that it had violated Hume’s is/ought distinction,306 and the second contrasting

Western material and mechanical worldviews of nature to those of American Indians, which

attributed a spiritual sense or kinship to non-humans.307 In 1985, he argued that the Cartesian

separation between subject and object is eviscerated by quantum theory, which justifies intrinsic

value through “axiological complementarity.”308 The following year, Callicott explained that

ecology also collapses the subject/object split, which is replaced by a field ontology.309 Next, he

304 J. Baird Callicott, “Elements of an Environmental Ethic,” EE 1, no. 1 (Spring 1979): 71-81, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics19791110. 305 Callicott, “Animal Liberation: A Triangular Affair,” EE 2, no. 4 (Winter 1980): 311-338. 306 Callicott, “Hume’s Is/Ought Dichotomy and the Relation of Ecology to Leopold’s Land Ethic,” EE 4,

no. 2 (Summer 1982): 163-174, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19824214. 307 Callicott, “Traditional American Indian and Western European Attitudes toward Nature: An Overview,”

EE 4, no. 4 (Winter 1982): 293-318, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics1982443. 308 Callicott, “Intrinsic Value, Quantum Theory, and Environmental Ethics,” EE 7, no. 3 (Fall 1985): 257-

275, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19857334. 309 Callicott, “The Metaphysical Implications of Ecology,” EE 8, no. 4 (Winter 1986): 301-316, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics19868432.

121

proposed a “univocal” moral philosophy based on the work of Hume and Adam Smith, Darwin

and Leopold which incorporates human, “mixed,” and “biotic” concerns.310 In a 1992 paper

developed from an author-meets-critiques session on Holmes Rolston III’s Environmental

Ethics, Callicott argued that objective intrinsic value, as Rolston develops it, rests on the

Cartesian divide between subject and object, and is obsolete in a post-modern worldview.311 In

1996, having moved to the University of North Texas in Denton, Texas, he amended Leopold’s

Land Ethic to survive the “deconstruction” of the concepts of ecosystem and biotic community

by using the evolutionary time scale and a reasonable spatial extent as a standard against which

the consequences of current actions should be judged.312 He defended his argument in Earth’s

Insights, a “tour” of world religions and the conceptual resources each has, from its critics.313

His last article in EE, published in 2008, proposed that the top priority to govern human entry

and activity in the wilderness areas at the far south of Chilé should biodiversity preservation.

Callicott’s two contributions to Research in Philosophy and Technology were made in

1993 and 1998. In the first, while he was still at the University of Wisconsin-Stevens Point, he

argued that the replacement of the mechanistic conceptualization of nature by an organismic one

will lead to adoption of appropriate technology.314 In the second, written while he was faculty at

the University of North Texas, Callicott proposed that electronic state systems, which have less

310 Callicott, “The Case against Moral Pluralism,” EE 12, no. 2 (Summer 1990): 99-124, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics199012220. 311 Callicott, “Rolston on Intrinsic Value: A Deconstruction,” EE 14, no. 2 (Summer 1992): 129-143, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics199214229. 312 Callicott, “Do Deconstructive Ecology and Sociobiology Undermine Leopold’s Land Ethic,” EE 18, no.

4 (Winter 1996): 353-372, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19961843. 313 Callicott, “Many Indigenous Worlds or the Indigenous World? A Reply to My ‘Indigenous’ Critics,” EE

22, no. 3 (Fall 2000): 291-310, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics200022319. 314 Callicott, “The Role of Technology in the Evolving Concept of Nature,” RPT 13 (1993): 201-222.

122

environmental consequences, will become more important because their relational capabilities

match those of an ecological understanding of the world.315

Ferré, a longtime member of the Department of Philosophy at the University of Georgia

in Athens, provided an early sketch of a “personalistic” organicism that retains the benefits of

holism without forfeiting an individual’s value, creativity, and agency in EE in Fall 1989.316 Six

years later, the same journal published “Value, Time, and Nature,” in which he argued that

evolution, like painting, can be considered a kalogenic process, that is, a process in which time

depends on the creation and defense of beauty.317 His contributions to RPT/Techné start just

after his first paper in EE. “Technology, Nature, and Miracle” is a response by Ferré to two

papers, one by Jane Mary Trau and the other by John F. Post, on the epistemic and ethical

assumptions that undergird the use of artificial techniques in human reproduction.318 The same

year, he responded to two essays on his book Philosophy of Technology, one from Joseph Pitt

and the other from Peter Limpter, in P&T.319 In the 1999 RPT volume, which studied the theme

of Philosophies of the Environment and Technology, he proposed a nondualistic understanding

of neomatter as energetic and self-organizing that is far richer than what many consider “mere”

matter.320 His 1997 inquiry into how personalistic organicism, which follows a line of reasoning

similar to Hans Jonas in The Phenomemon of Life, though Ferré does not cite Jonas, can

315 Callicott, “After the Industrial Paradigm, What?” RPT 18 (1999): 13-26. 316 Frederick Ferré, “Obstacles on the Path to Organismic Ethics: Some Second Thoughts,” EE 16, no. 3

(Fall 1989): 231-241, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics198911314. 317 Ferré, “Value, Time, and Nature,” EE 17, no. 4 (Winter 1995): 417-431, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics19951748. 318 Ferré, “Technology, Nature, and Miracle,” RPT 10 (1990): 281-286. 319 Ferré, “Defining Horizons: A Reply to Joseph C. Pitt,” Broad and Narrow Interpretations of Philosophy

of Technology. P&T 7 (1990): 17-23, and “Clarifying and Applying Intelligence: A Reply to Peter Limper,” Broad and Narrow, 37-41.

320 Ferré, “On Matter and Machines,” RPT 18 (1999): 131-142.

123

illuminate the ethical issues raised by cloning, also shows the inadequacy of materialism.321 He

also published two retrospectives, a personal history in 1995,322 and a reflection on the state of

the specialization—internally fractured, but in a good way—and of the external circumstances

that increase general interest in the topic.323

Jung, who worked in the Department of Political Science at Moravian College in

Bethlehem, Pennsylvania, is a rare contributor whose contributions to the two journals were

stepwise. In 1981, EE published his “The Oprhic Voice and Ecology,” in which Orpheus is “the

voice of ecology incarnate” by his music, which makes “rocks, mountains, streams, trees, forests

and animals dance as well as men.”324 Music has a “roundness” that, in matching the shape of

the globe, expresses a global harmony that counteracts speciesism and individualism. The

following year in RPT, he sketched out a theory of politics that depends the oral nature of

communication and is aware of the influence of electronic media.325 The next year in EE, Jung

argued that the elements in Karl Marx’s early writings that appear to give nature its due are lost

in his later works and do not provide a basis for environmental philosophy.326 In 1999, he

argued in RPT that the “calculative models” of cognition inherent in a technological view, which

springs from Descartes, are incompatible with sociality, “an active mode of being in the world,

that is, the active mediator of the ‘I’ and ‘circumstance.’”327

321 Ferré, “On Replicating Persons: Ethics and the Technology of Cloning.” JSPT 3 (1997).

http://scholar.lib.vt.edu/ejournals/SPT/v3n2/FERRE.html. 322 Ferré, “Philosophy and Technology after Twenty Years,” SPT 1, no. 1/2 (1995): 4-7, doi:

10.5840/techne199511/23. 323 Ferré, “Philosophy and Technology: Another Look 15 Years Later,” Techné: RPT 14, no. 1 (2010): 23-

25, doi: 10.5840/techne20101414. 324 Hwa Yol Jung, “The Orphic Voice and Ecology,” EE 3, no. 4 (Winter 1981): 329-340, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics1981344. 325 Jung, “Language, Politics, and Technology,” RPT 5 (1982): 43-63. 326 Jung, “Marxism, Ecology, and Technology,” EE 5, no. 2 (Summer 1983): 169-171, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics1983522. 327 Jung, “The Genealogy of Technological Rationality in the Human Sciences,” RPT 9 (1989): 59-75

(italics removed).

124

Katz’s first article was published in EE while he was a Ph.D. candidate at Boston

University in 1979. In it, he pointed out that any argument for the preservation that depends

utilitarian ethics can only be said to be true for some alignment of human desires, which makes it

ultimately always open to revision.328 As faculty in the Departments of Philosophy and

Environmental Science at Barnard College and the Department of Philosophy at St. Joseph’s

College in Patchogue, New York, he noted that understanding the environment as an organism

diminishes the importance of each individual natural entity in a way that the community model

does not.329 He critiqued Anthony Weston’s proposal for a pragmatic shift in environmental

ethics away from intrinsic value for mistaking the ground of moral obligations and for its

anthropocentrism.330 After moving to the Science, Technology, and Society Program at the New

Jersey Institute of Technology in Newark, Katz published “The Call of the Wild,” a defense of

preservation in contrast to conservation and, especially, restoration.331 The next year he

published “Moving beyond Anthropocentrism: Environmental Ethics, Development, and the

Amazon” with Lauren Oechsli, in which they support a nonanthropocentric instrumentalism that

seeks to maximize the good of nonhuman nature.332 In 1989, he published a defense of a

pragmatic anthropocentrism that may be appropriate in some situations as he adopted what

Andrew Light called “metaphilosophical pragmatism.”333 Finally, in 2012 he wrote “Further

Adventures in the Case against Restoration,” in which he invoked Helena Sipii’s linguistic

328 Eric Katz, “Utilitarianism and Preservation,” EE 1, no. 4 (Winter 1979): 357-364, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics19791430. 329 Katz, “Organism, Community, and the ‘Substitution Problem,’” EE 7, no. 3 (Fall 1985): 241-256, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics19857337. 330 Katz, “Searching for Intrinsic Value: Pragmatism and Despair in Environmental Ethics,” EE 9, no. 3

(Fall 1987): 231-241, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics1987935. 331 Katz, “The Call of the Wild: The Struggle against Domination and the Technological Fix of Nature,” EE

14, no. 3 (Fall 1992): 265-273, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199214321. 332 Katz and Lauren Oechsli, “Moving beyond Anthropocentrism: Environmental Ethics, Development, and

the Amazon,” EE 15, no. 1 (Spring 1993): 49-59, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199315139.

125

analysis and Paul M. Keeling’s Wittgensteinian analysis as support of his argument against the

widespread acceptance of restoration.334

Katz had a much smaller role in RPT. He argued that restoration as restitutive justice is

another anthropocentric technological fix in the 1992 volume as faculty in the Department of

Humanities at NJIT.335 His 1996 review of Carl Mitcham’s Thinking through Technology argued

that the book is framed by a technological view of the world that leads Mitcham to consider

environmental ethics just another kind of applied ethics.336 Katz also contributed a 35-page

select annotated bibliography on environmental ethics literature from 1983 through 1987 in

1989,337 and one that was 38 pages covering literature from the next three years in 1992.338

At the Department of Philosophy at the University of Louisville, Shrader-Frechette first

appeared in the pages of RPT in the 1980 volume with two articles on the nuclear energy

industry, the first on the reasons for more democratic involvement in nuclear energy decisions,

which had been centralized by the federal government in the Price-Anderson Act,339 and the

second a critique of two papers from Herbert Inhaber and Frank Adams that support nuclear

power, which focus on the technical details and include no explicit ethical consideration.340 Two

years later, now at the University of California-Santa Barbara, she turned her attention to

disparities in economic and environmental benefits and harms that went unrecognized in

333 Katz, “A Pragmatic Reconsideration of Anthropocentrism,” EE 21, no. 4 (Winter 1999): 377-390, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics19992144. 334 Katz, “Further Adventures in the Case against Restoration,” EE 34, no. 1 (Spring 2012): 67-97, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics20123416. 335 Katz, “The Big Lie: Human Restoration of Nature,” RPT 12 (1992): 231-241. 336 Katz, “The Place of Nature in the Understanding of Technology: One Critical Reading of Thinking

through Technology,” RPT 16 (1997): 171-178. Katz’s review was the one that gave Mitcham pause. 337 Katz, “Environmental Ethics: A Select Annotated Bibliography, 1983-1987,” RPT 9 (1989): 251-285. 338 Katz, “Environmental Ethics: A Select Annotated Bibliography II, 1987-1990,” RPT 12 (1992): 287-

324. 339 Kristin Shrader-Frechette, “Technology, Public Policy, and the Price-Anderson Act,” RPT 3 (1980):

313-342. 340 Shrader-Frechette, “Adams, Inhaber, and Risk-Benefit Analysis: Ethical and Methodological Problems

with Two Recent Assessments of Nuclear Power,” RPT 3 (1980): 343-365.

126

technology assessments, especially when undertaken at the federal level.341 A year later in what

is considered the first volume of P&T, she argued that nonmarket consequences, such as pain

and suffering, should be included in a quantified assessment of risk, even though the conversion

is disputed.342 She also had two papers published in 1985, then at the University of Florida, one

which proposed that intelligent laypeople, not scientists, should staff the “science court”

advocated by Alex Michalos, and its mandate should include technology policy, not just

scientific fact,343 and a second that argues that commercial and military involvement in the

“plutonium economy” are inextricably linked.344 Two years later, Shrader-Frechette summarized

the range of metaphysical, methodological, and ethical criticisms of Risk-Cost-Benefit Analysis

(RCBA), concluding that its interpretation is problematic in a capitalistic utilitarian political

environment and that its subjectivity and uncertainty are often understated.345 The following

year, she emphasized informed consent and equality in economic and social positions as

conditions for which increased compensation can fairly persuade individuals to take on risks that

would not be placed on the general public.346 In 1992, she argued that risk experts need to have

their estimates calibrated to correct for biases, which can be done by reviewing past predictions

and results.347 She turned her attention to funding for academic research and positions in 1991,

warning that corporate and government clout may diminish academic freedom and direct it away

341 Shrader-Frechette, “Environmental Impact Analysis, Technology Assessment, and the Problem of

Geographical Equity,” RPT 5 (1982): 115-130. 342 Shrader-Frechette, "Technology Assessment and the Problem of Quantification,” Philosophy and

Technology. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 80, P&T 1 (1983): 151-164. 343 Shrader-Frechette, “Technology Assessment, Expert Disagreement, and Democratic Procedures,” RPT 8

(1985): 103-129. 344 Shrader-Frechette, “The Plutonium Economy: Technological Links and Epistemological Problems,”

RPT 8 (1985): 189-220. 345 Shrader-Frechette, “The Real Risks of Risk-Cost-Benefit Analysis,” Technology and Responsibility.

P&T 3 (1987): 343-357. 346 Shrader-Frechette, "Public and Occupational Risk: The Double Standard,” Technology and

Contemporary Life. P&T 4 (1988): 257-277. 347 Shrader-Frechette, “Calibrating Assessors of Technological and Environmental Risk,” RPT 12 (1992):

147-155.

127

from public interest if it is not subject to some limits.348 The same year she pointed out the anti-

democractic principles in the Bayesian decision-making process used to assess risk because

egalitarian concerns and a participative process are subjugated to an optimization of utility,

which is especially problematic when assessing grave risks with low probability.349 In 1999, she

turned her attention to global issues, arguing that all individuals who live in First World

countries have a responsibility to prevent the transfer of technology that has unacceptable risks

and hazards to Third World countries.350 Her most recent contribution, made as a faculty

member at the University of Notre Dame, was a critique of Joe Pitt’s epistemic approach to

philosophy of technology in Thinking through Technology, in which she faulted him for making

the same ideological and rhetorical mistakes he blamed on his colleagues in the specialization.351

Her contributions to EE are more limited, though she has been important in the

development of the concept of environmental justice. She argued for recognizing that

technological assessment nearly always leads to a technological fix that ignores ethical and

political options, even though such a position can be refuted philosophically and historically.352

Nine years later, now at the Department of Philosophy at the University of South Florida in

Tampa, she argued that informed consent by and compensation for those who might be affected

by radwaste are the best ways to deal with the ethical dilemmas it engenders.353

348 Shrader-Frechette, "Adam Smith and Alma Mater: Technology and the Threat to Academic Freedom,”

Europe, America, and Technology: Philosophical Perspectives. P&T 8 (1991): 175-189. 349 Shrader-Frechette, "Technology, Bayesian Policymaking, and Democratic Process,” Democracy in a

Technological Society, P&T 9 (1992): 123-137. 350 Shrader-Frechette, “Risk and Technology Transfer: Equal Protection across National Borders,”

Technological Transformation: Contextual and Conceptual Implications. P&T 5 (1999): 259-275. 351 Shrader-Frechette, “Reductionist Philosophy of Technology: Stones Thrown from Inside a Glass

House,” Techné: JSPT 5, no. 1 (Fall 2000): 21-28, doi: 10.5840/techne20015115. 352 Shrader-Frechette, “Environmental Impact Assessment and the Fallacy of Unfinished Business,” EE 4,

no. 1 (Spring 1982): 37-47, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19824138. 353 Shrader-Frechette, “Ethical Dilemmas and Radioactive Waste: A Survey of the Issues,” EE 13, no. 4

(Winter 1991): 327-343, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199113438.

128

Thompson, who held a dual appointment with the Departments of Agricultural

Economics and Philosophy at Texas A&M University in College Station, Texas, in 1984,

proposed that advocates and opponents of nuclear energy can be organized on a need and safety

matrix. Any consensus will require advocates, who usually use deductive arguments, and

opponents of nuclear energy, who commonly employ informal arguments, to develop more

sophisticated arguments that are informed by philosophy of science, ordinary language

philosophy, and hermeneutics.354 Two years later, he drew attention to the epistemological and

methodological criticisms that are levied against uncertainty arguments and proposed two

approaches, one that addressed the relationship between scientific research and policy, and the

other that dealt with the lack of societal knowledge and the inability of scientists to convey

information to the general public.355

Almost a decade later, Thompson sought to raise issues about how the disciplinary

structure of applied science influences the choice of research topics, which, in agricultural

science, are production efficiency and human health, which he thought had a “technological

character,” and to consider other aims, such as sustainability, justice, or broad scale rural

development would require significant overhaul of people, equipment, and funding

institutions.356 A year later in RPT, Thompson investigated the different moral assumptions,

common paths of inquiry, and movements in environmental ethics kindred to sustainability, as

resource sufficiency, on one hand, or as functional integrity, on the other, which he then applied

354 Paul B. Thompson, “Need and Safety: The Nuclear Power Debate,” EE 6, no. 1 (Spring 1984): 57-69,

doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19846121. 355 Thompson, “Uncertainty Arguments in Environmental Issues,” EE 8, no. 1 (Spring 1986): 59-75, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics19868118. 356 Thompson, "Technological Values in the Applied Science Laboratory,” New Directions in the

Philosophy of Technology, P&T 11 (1995): 139-151.

129

to dairy farming in Erath County, Texas.357 In 2000, at Purdue University, he contributed an

extended commentary on Joe Pitt’s Thinking About Technology, which praised Pitt’s

epistemological approach to issues of technology while panning his response to social critics.358

Three years later, he contributed another extended commentary, this time on Larry Hickman’s

Philosophical Tools for a Technological Culture, in which he faulted Hickman for “hammering

away” that “Dewey is the answer to every question.”359 Finally, as part of the Department of

Philosophy at Michigan State University in 2007, Thompson argued that exclusion, alienability,

and rivalry, concepts from institutional theory, are pertinent to understanding technical

change.360

Steven Vogel, from the Department of Philosophy at Denison University in Granville,

Ohio, published published both of his articles in RPT before his articles in EE. In 1991, he

argued argued that the relationship between nature and science is flawed in the accounts of

Herbert Marcuse or Jürgen Habermas, and that scientific practice must be aware of its history

and social setting as well as its function in shaping the contours of human life.361 In his 1999

response “On Michael Zimmerman’s Contesting Earth’s Future,” he critiqued Zimmerman’s

Hegelianism, which ignored “real people and real practices,” and noted that Habermas lurked in

the background of the book.362 In a 2002 EE article, he argued for a “postnaturalism” in

environmental philosophy that no longer depends on a concept of nature that is problematic and

357 Thompson, “Sustainability as a Norm,” Techné: JSPT 2, no. 2 (1997): 99-110, doi:

10.5840/techne19972228. 358 Thompson, “Thinking About Thinking About Technology,” Techné: JSPT 5, no. 1 (2000): 29-34, doi:

10.5840/techne20015116. 359 Thompson, “Putting Pragmatism to Work?” Techné: JSPT 7, no. 1 (Fall 2003): 41-44, doi:

10.5840/techne20037116. 360 Thompson, “Theorizing Technological and Institutional Change: Alienability, Rivalry and Exclusion

Cost,” Techné: RPT 11, no. 1 (2007): 19-31, doi: 10.5840/techne20071113. 361 Steven Vogel, “New Science, New Nature: The Habermas-Marcuse Debate Revisited,” RPT 11 (1991):

157-178. 362 Vogel, “On Michael Zimmerman’s Contesting Earth’s Future,” RPT 18 (1999): 195.

130

that, in a sense, refers to nothing because everything has been affected by human activities.363 In

“The Nature of Artifacts,” Vogel argued that Katz’s critique of restoration depended on

genealogical and conceptual flaws that blurred important distinctions between human intention

and actual consequences.364

Zimmerman, who was housed in the Department of Philosophy at Tulane University in

New Orleans during the span in which his articles were published in RPT and EE, wrote a

number of articles for each journal. He contributed two articles to RPT that were published in

the second volume and a third article that was published in 1983. In the first, he argued that

philosophy has supported the advance of technological culture, which has reduced most

philosophy departments to a technical discipline closed off to critical and reflective inquiry.365

In the second, he argued that technology cannot be called neutral because it impresses its

character on economics and social and political institutions, an insight that can be drawn from

Heidegger’s work and its extension of his student Herbert Marcuse.366 In the third, following

Heidegger, he critiqued the rise of humanism, which elevates human concerns above all others,

as a force that contributes to the nuclear arms race. In addition to the three articles, his book

Contesting Earth’s Future was the fodder for several papers contributed to a symposium, to

which he composed a short response, that were published in the 1999 volume.367

Zimmerman’s activity in EE spanned the 1980s and 1990s. In 1983, he proposed that a

Heideggerian ethos of “letting beings be” can resolve issues that had been inherited in Western

363 Vogel, “Environmental Philosophy after the End of Nature,” EE 24, no. 1 (Spring 2002): 23-39, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics200224139. 364 Vogel, “The Nature of Artifacts,” EE 25, no. 2 (2003): 149-168, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics200325230. 365 Michael E. Zimmerman, “Technological Culture and the End of Philosophy,” RPT 2 (1979): 137-145. 366 Zimmerman, “Heidegger and Marcuse: Technology as Ideology,” RPT 2 (1979): 245-261. 367 Zimmerman, “Recognizing the Limits of Contesting Earth’s Future,” RPT 18 (1999): 199-216.

131

philosophy, especially through the analytic strand.368 Three years later in RPT, he offered the

same Heideggerian prescription to offset the risk of nuclear war, which he thought cannot be

solved by a humanism based on a modern ontology.369 In 1987, he imagined a conversation

between deep ecologists and radical feminists, through the voice of Ariel Salleh, that discloses

common ground and differences between the two groups.370 He continued to promote

nondualism as a precedent for escaping a domineering perspective of nature in “Quantum

Theory, Intrinsic Value, and Panentheism.”371 In 1993, he revisited his connection between

Heidegger and deep ecology after the former’s support of National Socialism came to light, an

article in which he emphasized the difference between the progressive actualization of potential

of deep ecologists with the degeneration present in Heidegger.372

Multiple Contributions, Environmental Ethics Centric. Of the ten contributors to both journals

who had a single contribution to RPT/Techné, all but John Lemons were in departments of

philosophy. Lemons was in Life Sciences and related departments. Of the authors, only Robert

Frodeman, Don E. Marietta, and Holmes Rolston, III three contributed to the 1999 RPT volume

that specifically sought to discuss the two specializations. David Abram and Karen Warren were

the two authors whose contributions addressed the same issue, perception and alterity for Abram

and ecofeminism for Warren, from perspectives of each specialization. The contributions for the

others addressed a variety of topics from which I could discern no coherent project: they were

often responses to the comments of others. The only institutional overlap was that of David

368 Zimmerman, “Toward a Heideggerian Ethos for Radical Environmentalism,” EE 5, no. 2 (Summer

1983): 99-131, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics1983524. 369 Zimmerman, “Humanism, Ontology, and the Nuclear Arms Race,” RPT 6 (1983): 157-172. 370 Zimmerman, “Feminism, Deep Ecology, and Environmental Ethics,” EE 9, no. 1 (Spring 1987): 21-44,

doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19879112. 371 Zimmerman, “Quantum Theory, Intrinsic Value, and Panentheism,” EE 10, no. 1 (Spring 1988): 3-30,

doi: 10.5840/enviroethics198810126. 372 Zimmerman, “Rethinking the Heidegger-Deep Ecology Relationship,” EE 15, no. 3 (Fall 1993): 195-

224, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199315316.

132

Abram and Anthony Weston, who were both at SUNY-Stony Brook for a time. The others were

at different universities in the United States, and Keekok Lee worked at the University of

Manchester in the United Kingdom.

Abram, who taught in the Department of Philosophy at SUNY-Stony Brook, had two

publications in EE that sandwiched one in RPT. In 1988, Abram argued that Merleau-Ponty’s

phenomenological framework, which stresses situatedness and bodily perception, is a superior

alternative to environmental studies grounded on a mechanistic ecology.373 Seven years later, in

“Nature at Arm’s Length,” a critique of David Rothenberg’s Hand’s End, he focused on the lack

of alterity and subjectivity given to nature, which is conceptualized instead as our “context.”374

In 2005 in “Between the Body and the Breathing Earth: A Reply to Ted Toadvine,” Abram

defended his The Spell of the Sensuous: Perception and Language in a More-than-Human World

from Toadvine’s interpretation, which claimed that Abram shorted verbal and symbolic

reflection and that his ecophenomenological framework precluded alterity.375

Now at the University of North Texas (UNT), Frodeman first contributed to EE and

RPT/Techné from Fort Lewis College in Durango, Colorado, and then from the Departments of

Philosophy and Environmental Science at the University of Tennessee at Chattanooga. In 1992,

he argued that, in many formulations, the holism of deep ecology and the “individualism and

subjective bias” in postmodern thought are incompatible.376 Seven years later, he argued that the

science of geology can provide moral limits regarding our use and attitude toward natural

373 David Abram, “Merleau-Ponty and the Voice of the Earth,” EE 2, no. 1 (Summer 1988): 101-120, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics19881027. 374 Abram, “Nature at Arm’s Length,” RPT 15 (1995): 177-180. 375 Abram, “Between the Body and the Breathing Earth: A Reply to Ted Toadvine,” EE 27, no. 2 (Summer

2005): 171-190, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics200527229. 376 Robert Frodeman, “Radical Environmentalism and the Political Roots of Postmodernism: Differences

that Make a Difference,” EE 14, no. 4 (Winter 1992): 307-319, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19921443.

133

materials.377 In 2006, he published “The Policy Turn in Environmental Philosophy,” in which he

argued that environmental philosophy should be interdisciplinary and policy-driven, not the

production of literature for consumption by environmental philosophers.378 In 2008, he

published “Philosophy Unbound: Environmental Ethics at the End of the Earth,” in which he

argued that interdisciplinarity is necessary for philosophy to contribute to epistemic and ethical

concerns in the Cape Horn region of Chile.379

In 1980, Alastair Gunn, from the Department of Philosophy at the University of Waikato

in Hamilton, New Zealand, proposed that any suitable account of species preservation must be

founded on a principle of intrinsic value.380 Three years later, he argued that traditional ethics,

which are based on an individualistic, utilitarian view of society, cannot support the concept of

environmental stewardship.381 In 1991, he argued that concern over species extermination does

not provide a sufficient justification for opposing acts that significantly degrade the

environment.382 In 1992, Alastair Gunn advocated institutional advocacy, a “surrogate

guardian,” on behalf of future generations to promote their interests in issues of environmental

quality, especially with regards to long-lasting pollutants in RPT.383 Two years later, in the

pages of EE, he drew attention to internal policies of countries in the global North that need

reformation, which were not addressed as the same countries were paternalistically dictating

environmental policies of the global South in “Environmental Ethics and Tropical Rain Forests:

377 Frodeman, “The Rebirth of Gaia and the Closure of Homo Technologicus,” RPT 18 (1999): 95-113. 378 Frodeman, “The Policy Turn in Environmental Ethics,” EE 28, no. 1, (Spring 2006): 3-20, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics200628136. 379 Frodeman, "Philosophy Unbound: Environmental Ethics at the End of the World,” EE 30 (2008): 313-

324. 380 Alastair S. Gunn, “Why Should We Care about Rare Species?” EE 2, no. 1 (Spring 1980): 17-37, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics1980217. 381 Gunn, “Traditional Ethics and the Moral Status of Animals,” EE 5, no. 2 (Summer 1983): 133-153, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics1983528. 382 Gunn, “The Restoration of Species and Natural Environments,” EE 13, no. 4 (Winter 1991): 291-310,

doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199113437.

134

Should Greens Have Standing?”384 His most recent contribution extends the work of landscape

architect Ian McHarg to address environmental issues in urban zones.385

Keekok Lee, as a member of the Department of Philosophy at the University of

Manchester in Manchester, United Kingdom, contributed her analysis of Richard Sylvan’s Last

Person Argument (LPA) to EE in 1993.386 Her contribution took place in two steps, first the

assessment of the argument to strong and two kinds of weak instrumentalism, which can be

psychological and aesthetic use or public service use, and second the use of the LPA when

applied to preservation instead of destruction of nature. Three years later, she wrote “The Source

and Locus of Intrinsic Value: A Reexamination,” in which she argues that Rolston’s grounding

of intrinsic value is more robust than Callicott’s, which accepts a Humean basis, though neither

is fully correct.387 Her single contribution to RPT came in 2003. In “Patenting and Transgenic

Organisms: A Philosophical Exploration,”388 she argued that the products of molecular DNA

technology deserve protection because its novelty, earned by crossing species, kingdoms, or the

gap between eukaryotes and prokaryotes, is more than an incremental advance from Mendelian

genetics.

Over the span of his three contributions in EE and one in RPT, John Lemons had three

different institutional homes. In 1981, from the Environmental Studies program at New England

College in Henniker, New Hampshire, he contributed “Cooperation and Stability as a Basis for

383 Gunn, “Engineering Ethics and Hazardous Waste Management,” RPT 12 (1992): 135-146. 384 Gunn, “Environmental Ethics and Tropical Rain Forests: Should Greens Have Standing?” EE 16, no. 1

(Spring 1994): 21-40, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199416139. 385 Gunn, “Rethinking Communities: Environmental Ethics in an Urbanized World,” EE 20, no. 4 (Winter

1998): 341-360, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19982043. 386 Keekok Lee, “Instrumentalism and the Last Person Argument,” EE 15, no. 4 (Winter 1993): 333-344,

doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19931545. 387 Lee, “The Source and Locus of Intrinsic Value: A Reexamination,” EE 18, no. 3 (Fall 1996): 297-309,

doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199618320. 388 Lee, “Patenting and Transgenic Organisms: A Philosophical Exploration,” Techné: JSPT 6, no. 3

(2003): 166-175, doi: 10.5840/techne20036323.

135

Environmental Ethics,” in which he positions intra- and interspecies cooperation as a viable

alternative to competition in grounding ecosystem stability, while also outlining some of the

conceptual issues involved with using stability as a foundational concept in environmental

ethic.389 Two years later, Lemons had moved to the Department of Biology and Ecology at Deep

Springs College in California when he wrote “Atmospheric Carbon Dioxide: Environmental

Ethics and Environmental Facts,” which argued that environmental ethics is complicated by a

paucity of environmental facts in many cases, and environmental issues are not just the result of

inadequate theory or a weak will.390 In 1990, at the Department of Life Sciences at the

University of New England in Biddeford, Maine, Lemons, writing with Donald A. Brown and

Gary E. Varner, accused Congress of violating the National Environmental Policy Act of 1969

by approving the Yucca Mountain, Nevada nuclear waste disposal site, regardless of whether the

principle of existing in “productive and enjoyable harmony” is understood as setting boundaries

for which technologies are appropriate or as a way of ensuring that environmental concerns are

balanced against economic interests.391 The following year, writing with Charles Malone, he

assessed the ethical and policy implications of nuclear waste disposal by reviewing the track

record of the Department of Energy and the Nuclear Waste Policy Act and its amendments,

which he argued had become a more comprehensive as a policy guide than the NEPA.392

Don E. Marietta, housed in the Department of Philosophy at Florida Atlantic University

in Boca Raton, Florida, first contributed a defense of grounding environmental ethics on

389 John Lemons, “Cooperation and Stability as a Basis for Environmental Ethics,” EE 3, no. 3 (Fall 1981):

219-230, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19813320. 390 Lemons, “Atmospheric Carbon Dioxide: Environmental Ethics and Environmental Facts,” EE 5, no. 1

(Spring 1993): 21-32, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19835132. 391 Lemons, John, Donald A. Brown, and Gary E. Varner, “Congress, Consistency, and Environmental

Law,” EE 12, no. 4 (Winter 1990): 311-327, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199012429. 392 Lemons, and Charles Malone, “The Nuclear Waste Policy Act and Its Amendments,” RPT 11 (1991): 5-

32.

136

ecological sciences to the third issue of EE,393 which he defended against Tom Regan’s

criticisms the following year.394 Two years later, Marietta argued for the superiority of a

phenomenological approach over the common post-Enlightenment distinction between facts and

values and the limitations of only accepting ethical conclusions derived deductively.395 In 1988,

he defended a moderate holism, or holism as a principle, in “Ethical Holism and Individuals,”

while dismissing more extreme expressions such as Callicott’s or Katz’s reductionist

perspective.396 His only contribution to RPT, which was included in volume for which he was a

guest editor, was “Decisions Regarding Technology: The Human Factor,” in which he argued

that for boundaries of appropriate technology to have political support, discussions on the topic

must delineate different uses of technology and address the kinds of fears caused by

technology.397 The first contribution of Christopher J. Preston, in 1988 a graduate student in the

Department of Philosophy at the University of Oregon in Eugene, was a defense of Rolston’s

explanation of non-subjective intrinsic value from the epistemological criticisms levied by

Norton and Callicott.398 Two years later, then at the Department of Philosophy at the University

of South Carolina in Columbia, he followed up with “Conversing with Nature in a Postmodern

Epistemological Framework,” in which he argued that agency in nature is more

epistemologically durable when freed from the metaphor of inquiry as conversation that had

393 Don E. Marietta, Jr., “The Interrelationship of Ecological Science and Environmental Ethics,” EE 1, no.

3 (Fall 1979): 195-207, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19791327. 394 Marietta, “World Views and Moral Decisions: A Reply to Tom Regan,” EE 2, no. 4 (Winter 1980): 369-

371, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19802429. 395 Marietta, “Knowledge and Obligation in Environmental Ethics: A Phenomenological Approach,” EE 4,

no. 2 (Summer 1982): 153-162, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19824221. 396 Marietta, “Ethical Holism and Individuals,” EE 10, no. 3 (Fall 1988):251-258, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics198810314. 397 Marietta, “Decisions Regarding Technology: The Human Factor,” RPT 18 (1999): 57-72. Uses include

therapeutic and prosthetic, ease or convenience, making life more interesting, and contributing to interest, worth, identity, and social connectivity. Fears arise from the overwhelming scale of modern technology, a lack of understanding or control, and the knowledge that harms can come from technologies.

398 Christopher J. Preston, “Epistemology and Intrinsic Values: Norton and Callicott’s Critiques of Rolston,” EE 20, no. 4 (Winter 1998): 409-428, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19982047.

137

been championed by Jim Cheney. In 2005, while in the Department of Philosophy at the

University of Montana in Missoula, his “The Promise and Threat of Nanotechnology: Can

Environmental Ethics Guide Us?” was published in Hyle, a joint publication with Techné: RPT

in which he argues that it can. In the same year, he published “Public Health and

Environmentalism: Adding Garbage to the History of Environmental Ethics,” written with

Steven H. Corey, which is an argument that follows lines of thought of the environmental justice

movement by focusing on New York City in the nineteenth century.399

Holmes Rolston III, from the Department of Philosophy at Colorado State University in

Fort Collins, led off the introductory issue of EE with “Can and Ought We to Follow Nature?” in

which he argued that humans should indeed follow nature in the sense of engaging it to orient

interest and value and in constructing a proper attunement to the cycles of that natural world and

appropriate human interaction with it.400 Already in this article he drew attention to the

symbiotic zones where the cultural and natural interact, a space he returned to in his sole RPT

contribution on “A Managed Earth and the End of Nature?”401 Two years after his first article in

EE, Rolston contributed an inquiry into ten types of values associated with nature, noting value

has both a subjective and relational sense as well as an objective sense that can be described by

science, and that the two senses often inform each other.402 The next year, he proposed that

natural value, especially understood in an evolutionary ecological sense, consists of humanly

subjective, naturally subjective, and objective values.403 In 1985, Rolston associated seven

“meaning levels” of value with twelve types of value to develop principles for management of

399 Preston and Steven H. Corey, “Public Health and Environmentalism: Adding Garbage to the History of

Environmental Ethics,” EE 27, no. 1 (Spring 2005): 3-21, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics200527138. 400 Holmes Rolston, III, “Can and Ought We to Follow Nature?” EE 1, no. 1 (Spring 1979): 7-30, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics1979114. 401 Rolston, “A Managed Earth and the End of Nature?” RPT 18 (1999): 143-164. 402 Rolston, “Values in Nature,” EE 3, no. 2 (Summer 1981): 113-128, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19813245.

138

wild spaces.404 Seventeen years passed between this article and Rolston’s next contribution,

“Environmental Ethics in Antarctica,” in which he argued that the continent offers an

opportunity to develop an ethic that is not burdened by national and political disputes over

sovereignty and ownership.405 This was followed by his most recent contribution that looked at

the symbiosis between the cultured urban and wild events that take place without regard to

humans in the Rocky Mountain region in which he spent the last third of his life.406

Karen Warren, in the Department of Philosophy at Macalester College in St. Paul,

Minnesota, published four articles in EE and one in RPT. Her 1987 article “Feminism and

Ecology: Making Connections” argued that ecofeminism illuminates shortcomings in other

versions of feminism.407 This article was followed by a 1990 article on “The Power and the

Promise of Ecological Feminism” that connected the domination experienced by women to what

has been experienced by non-human nature, making the strong claim that any adequate

environmental ethic must connect the two.408 Three years later, in a contribution with Jim

Cheney, she critiqued Callicott’s metaphysical claims as being incompatible with hierarchy

theory. Hierarchy theory allows integration of the multiple spatial and temporal scales needed to

interpret ecological phenomena, which should be grouped into separate organizational levels.409

The same year, her “Women, Nature, and Technology,” which argued that ecofeminism

integrates feminism, environmental concerns, and science and technology studies, and provides

403 Rolston, “Are Values in Nature Subjective or Objective?” EE 4, no. 2 (Summer 1982): 125-151, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics19824218. 404 Rolston, “Valuing Wildlands,” EE 7, no. 1 (Spring 1985): 23-48, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19857111. 405 Rolston, “Environmental Ethics in Antarctica,” EE 24, no. 2 (Summer 2002): 115-134, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics200224226. 406 Rolston, “Mountain Majesties above Fruited Plains: Culture, Nature, and Rocky Mountain Aesthetics,”

EE 30, no. 1 (Spring 2008): 3-20, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics200830114. 407 Karen J. Warren, “Feminism and Ecology: Making Connections,” EE 9, no. 1 (Spring 1987): 3-20, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics19879113. 408 Warren, “The Power and the Promise of Ecological Feminism,” EE 12, no. 2 (Summer 1990): 125-146,

doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199012221.

139

an appropriate lens that reveals an essential aspect of the relationship between women, nature,

and technology was published in the Feminism-themed volume of RPT.410 Her last contribution

to EE argued for a nondistributive justice, which focuses on the “processes, functions, structures,

and relations” that produce unjust distributions as a supplement to, or in some cases, a better

alternative than, the distributive model of justice.411

From 1985 to 2004, Anthony Weston published six articles in EE and one in RPT. His

first contributions occurred while he was housed in the Department of Philosophy at SUNY-

Stony Brook. The first promoted pragmatism, which recognizes the connection between beliefs

and values, as an option for environmental ethics that does not depend on agreement on the

existence of the intrinsic value of non-human nature.412 Two years later, he explained how deep

ecologists and ethicists interpret James Lovelock’s Gaia hypothesis differently, in ways other

than Lovelock himself did.413 In 1989, his sole contribution to RPT, which used resources from

Ivan Illich’s Tools for Conviviality to sketch out a definition of appropriate technology, was

published.414 In 1992, he proposed a stepwise evolution between ethics and culture, on the one

hand, and environmental ethics, on the other, rather than an attempt to find a new eco-oriented

ground for ethics.415 Four years later, at Elon College, North Carolina, he drew attention to the

reinforcing relationship between disvaluing nature, a cognitive act, and devaluing nature, which

409 Warren and Jim Cheney, “Ecosystem Ecology and Metaphysical Ecology: A Case Study,” EE 15, no. 2

(Summer 1993): 99-116, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199315226. 410 Warren, “Women, Nature, and Technology,” RPT 13 (1993): 13-29. 411 Warren, “Environmental Justice: Some Ecofeminist Worries about a Distributive Model,” EE 21, no. 2

(Summer 1999): 151-161, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199921228. 412 Anthony Weston, “Beyond Intrinsic Value: Pragmatism in Environmental Ethics,” EE 7, no. 4 (Winter

1985): 321-339, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19857431. 413 Weston, “Forms of Gaian Ethics,” EE 9, no. 3 (Fall 1987): 217-230, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics1987933. 414 Weston, “Ivan Illich and the Radical Critique of Tools,” RPT 9 (1989): 171-182. 415 Weston, “Before Environmental Ethics,” EE 14, no. 4 (Winter 1992): 321-338, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics19921444.

140

is shown by the consequences of acting as though value cannot be subscribed to nature.416 In

1998, he proposed that Tom Birch’s advocacy of universal consideration should be considered as

one contribution to rather than the foundation of environmental ethics, which is still at an early

stage in which pluralism is expected and should be welcomed.417 Finally, he pushed that a

multicentric understanding of the non-human world is a better paradigm for environmental

philosophers than the concentric circles that are used to express the expansion of ethics to more

and more beings.418

Multiple Contributions, Techné-Centric. The number of EE-centric contributors dwarfs the

number of RPT/Techné-centric contributors, which only includes Andrew Light, David Strong,

and Leonard J. Waks. This disparity arose in spite of the fact that the relation of technology to

nature and the environment were the themes of two volumes. Light has worked in a variety of

institutions, including the University of California-Santa Barbara, the Environmental Health

Program and the Environmental Risk Program at the University of Alberta, the Department of

Philosophy at the University of Montana, and is now active in national politics. Strong, who has

been employed by the Department of Philosophy at Rocky Mountain College in Billings,

Montana, took a more stable path.

In 1992 while at the University of California-Santa Barbara, Light mapped out some

possible changes in attitudes toward nature that may arise if the environmental ontology of

Martin Buber or Arne Naess and the deep ecologists, which he thought symbiotic, were more

widely adopted.419 His next contributions came while he worked at the University of Alberta.

416 Weston, “Self-Validating Reduction: Toward a Theory of Environmental Devaluation,” EE 18, no. 2

(Summer 1996): 115-132, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199618227. 417 Weston, “Universal Consideration as an Originary Practice,” EE 20, no. 3 (Fall 1998): 279-289, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics199820319. 418 Weston, “Multicentrism: A Manifesto,” EE 26, no. 1 (Spring 2004): 25-40, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics200426139. 419 Andrew Light, “The Role of Technology in Environmental Questions,” RPT 12 (1992): 83-104.

141

Two of his contributions were included in the 1995 volume of RPT as a postdoctoral fellow in

the Environmental Risk Program in the Department of Philosophy. The first was a response that

introduced and framed responses to David Rothenberg’s Hand’s End: Technology and the Limits

of Nature. In the second, he interrogated Albert Borgmann over the concept of hyperreality, a

simulated and stimulating environment that exceeds intensity found in real things, about whether

it granted too much standing to hyperreality and whether it was biased against city dwellers and

the poor.420 His sole EE article was written with Eric Higgs, a member of the Department of

Anthropology and Sociology at the University of Alberta. In it, they drew attention to the

political context over the question of what restoration is, especially as it is shaped by cultural

contexts, and of the political problems inherent in the commodification or nationalization of

restoration.421 Light’s next two contributions to RPT took place while he worked in Philosophy

Department of the University of Montana. In a paper from a symposium on the recent work of

Andrew Feenberg, Light revealed the relevance of some of Marx’s theory in Andrew Feenberg’s

Alternative Modernity and Critical Theory of Technology.422 Two years later, in 1998, he

critiqued the sufficiency of Douglas Kellner’s notion of media democracy to be a potent force

against global capitalism and the identity politics that media democracy tends to favor.423

Finally, in 2002 while housed in the Environmental Philosophy program at New York

University, Light argued that, to move forward, the field of philosophy of technology should be

based on a Wittgenstein-inspired descriptivism, rather than on social-normative claims.424

420 Light, “Three Questions on Hyperreality,” RPT 15 (1995): 211-222. 421 Andrew Light and Eric Higgs, “The Politics of Ecological Restoration,” EE 18, no. 3 (Fall 1996): 227-

247, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199618315. 422 Light, “Critical Theorist of Technology: Feenberg on Marx and Democracy,” RPT 16 (1996): 131-137. 423 Light, “Media, Identity, and Politics: As Critique of Kellner,” RPT 17 (1998): 187-200. 424 Light and David Roberts, “Toward New Foundations in Philosophy of Technology: Mitcham and

Wittgenstein on Descriptions,” RPT 19 (2000): 125-147.

142

Strong’s four contributions to the two journals were published in fast succession. In a

1992 article in RPT, he proposed a synthesis of environmental philosophy and philosophy of

technology in which human realization is paired with a “letting be” of natural things that offer

orientation.425 The next year in the same journal, he advised environmental ethicists to consider

how Albert Borgmann’s device paradigm has become the cultural standard.426 In 1994, he

identified the patience and openness found in wilderness as a potent challenge to the advance of

the device paradigm in the pages of RPT,427 and he argued that poetry, literature, and artwork

provides a disclosive discourse to environmental and technological worldviews that seem to

claim sufficiency in EE.428

Seven of Leonard Waks’s articles were published in RPT/Techné. The first, in 1989, as a

professor of Science, Technology, and Society at Pennsylvania State University, focused on

Ellul’s concern with technique applied to human subjects in the human sciences, education, and

work.429 He made several contributions to Europe, America, and Technology: Philosophical

Perspectives. He introduced four papers birthed at a 1990 symposium on Ivan Illich held by his

department,430 one of which was his reassessment of Illich’s Deschooling Society, which he

thought retained relevance even though the social conditions had changed from when it was

written.431 He also wrote an introduction for three papers from a Symposium on Education in

425 David Strong, “The Technological Subversion of Environmental Ethics,” RPT 12 (1992): 33-66. 426 Strong, “The Implications for Nature of Borgmann’s Theory of Technology,” RPT 13 (1993): 223-252. 427 Strong, “Challenging Technology,” RPT 14 (1994): 69-92. 428 Strong, “Disclosive Discourse, Ecology, and Technology,” EE 16, no. 1 (Spring 1994): 89-102, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics199416144. 429 Leonard J. Waks, “The Oil in the Machine: Jacques Ellul on Human Techniques in the Technological

Society,” RPT 9 (1989): 155-170. 430 Waks, "Ivan Illich's Philosophy of Technology: Introduction,” Europe, America, and Technology:

Philosophical Perspectives. P&T 8 (1991): 15-16. 431 Waks, "Ivan Illich and Deschooling Society: A Reappraisal,” Europe, America, and Technology:

Philosophical Perspectives. P&T 8 (1991): 57-73.

143

Science, Technology, and Values that was published in the same volume.432 Again, he

contributed a paper that argued that for STS to recognize environmental issues but not exacerbate

them, the learning environment should be altered so that more of the content and process are

determined by the learner, more group work should be done, and learners have more authority in

the classroom.433 In 1995, having moved to the Educational Leadership and Policy Studies

program at Temple University, he published a book length volume in RPT, Technology’s School,

in which he developed a more comprehensive vision of what education should be to support

democratic ideals and participation, especially against the pressures of technology.434 In 1997,

he argued for extra-academic support for interdisciplinary studies, which do not fit in the

traditional organizational structure of the university but contribute to the public good.435 Waks’s

only contribution to EE was sandwiched between his last two RPT/Techné contributions, and in

it he argued that the importance of environmental philosophers and activists will recede as

environmental rights become subjugated by a technocratic approach to environmental issues.436

One Contribution in Each Journal. The six contributors who published a single article in each

journal are impressively diverse geographically and in their approaches. They were housed in

institutions in Australia, Canada, Germany, and the United States and in departments that range

from Theology, Ethics, and Philosophy to Economics. One is a software engineer. Somewhat

interestingly, and perhaps a cause of some concern, no contributors have published just one

article in both of the journals since Michel Dion, before the turn of the century. The contributors

432 Waks, “"Symposium on Education in Science, Technology, and Values: Introduction,” Europe,

America, and Technology: Philosophical Perspectives. P&T 8 (1991): 193-195. 433 Waks, “STS Education and the Paradox of Green Studies,” Europe, America, and Technology:

Philosophical Perspectives. P&T 8 (1991): 247-257. 434 Waks, Technology's School: The Challenge to Philosophy. RPT Supplement 3 (1995): 1-267. 435 Waks, “Public Intellectuals and Interdisciplinary Studies,” RPT 16 (1997): 61-70. 436 Waks, “Environmental Claims and Citizen Rights,” EE 18, no. 2 (Summer 1996): 133-148, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics199618228.

144

interests range from practical policy concerns to theoretical aims of regrounding environmental

ethics.

Michel Dion was part of the faculté de théologie, d’éthique et de philosophie, Université

de Sherbrooke in Sherbrooke, Quebec. To RPT, he contributed “Institutionalizing

Environmental Ethics in the Corporation,” in which he argued that corporate ethics and culture

must be aligned with environmental goals, and ultimately to the common good, not mere profit

maximization, for environmental ethics to have purchase, in 1993.437 In an article published in

summer 1998 in EE, he offered a typology of environmental policies based on whether they

emphasize technical or ecological rationality and centrism.438

In 1980, J. A. Doeleman published “On the Social Rate of Discount: The Case for

Macroenvironmental Policy” as a member of the Department of Economics, University of

Newcastle, New South Wales, Australia. In this EE article, he argued that environmental

policies should be constructed from the basis of absolute minimal environmental standards, and

the policies should let discounting resolve itself naturally, rather than utilizing a temporal rate of

discount in assessing environmental standards.439 His RPT contribution, in 1992, which was

discussed in more detail in Chapter 3, posited that people will be more likely to accept artificial

ecosystem services than the sacrifices necessary to preserve natural ecosystem services.440 At

the time this article was published, Doeleman was working at the International Labor Office in

Geneva, Switzerland.

437 Michel Dion, “Institutionalizing Environmental Ethics in the Corporation,” RPT 13 (1993): 301-318. 438 Dion, “A Typology of Corporate Environmental Policies,” EE 20, no. 2 (Summer 1998): 151-162, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics199820229. 439 J. A. Doeleman, “On the Social Rate of Discount: The Case for Macroenvironmental Policy,” EE 2, no.

1 (Spring 1980): 45-58, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19802112. 440 Doeleman, “Environment and Technology: Speculating on the Long Run,” RPT 12 (1992): 5-32.

145

As a part of the Department of Philosophy and former director of the environmental

studies program at the University of Victoria (B.C.), Alan R. Drengson published “Shifting

Paradigms: From the Technocratic to the Person-Planetary.”441 In this EE paper, he utilized

Thomas Kuhn’s concept of paradigms to argue that the shortcomings of the mechanistic,

technological epoch signal that its dominance will yield to one in which technology will be

judged by the organic and holistic principles of deep ecology. Three years later, his article “Art

and Imagination in Technological Society,” in which he argued that four-dimension simulation

will result in technique again subjugated to art, rather than the inverse, was published in RPT.442

Joseph Grange, of the Philosophy Department of the University of Southern Maine in

Portland, became interested in environmental philosopher in the course of a post-doctoral NEH

fellow at the University of Chicago charged with studying technology and culture. In his 1985

EE article on “Being, Feeling, and Environment,” he focused solely on the fundamental

importance of emotions in Spinoza and Heidegger in forming a unitive grounding for

environmental studies.443 Nine years later in RPT, he argued that Alfred North Whitehead’s

process philosophy offers a better ontology of technological beings than Heidegger’s critique and

Borgmann’s extension of it in Technology and the Character of Contemporary Life because

Whitehead creates an “open space” in which the “possible danger and goodness of technology”

can be adjudicated.444

As a software engineer and philosophy graduate student at the University of Montana,

Bill Hook published “The Fate of Skills in the Information Age,” in which he develops the

441 Alan R. Drengson, “Shifting Paradigms: From the Technocratic to the Person-Planetary,” EE 2, no. 3

(Fall 1980): 221-240, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics1980233. 442 Drengson, “Art and Imagination in Technological Society,” RPT 6 (1983): 77-91. 443 Joseph Grange, “Being, Feeling, and Environment,” EE 7 no. 4 (Winter 1985): 351-364, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics19857432. 444 Grange, “Whitehead and Heidegger on Technological Goodness,” RPT 14 (1994): 161-173.

146

concept of focal skills from Borgmann’s concept of focal practices in 2000.445 Focal skills are

always at risk of being lost, either from refinement of a device that makes the skill unnecessary,

or as the claim that it makes is weakened. Three years later, he attempted to fuse Daniel

Dennett’s thoughts on DNA and phenotypes with Albert Borgmann’s theory of information to

defend intrinsic value for non-human biotic things.446

In 1979, Klaus Michael Meyer-Abich, from the Philosophy Department at the University

of Essen, Germany, argued that, starting from a normative concept of nature, problem-oriented

interdisciplinary work and education that instills a relationship with nature can be pursued.447 He

followed a similar line of argument four years later in RPT, where he argued that nature must be

considered as beings that are existing (natura naturans) rather than as things that can be

utilized.448

On the whole, the number of academics—just twenty-seven—who had published in both

journals over the first thirty-five years was lower than I expected. There was also some overlap

between the contributors to both journals and those who discussed nature in RPT/Techné and

techné in EE, but not as much as I anticipated. Most of the Anglophone world, including

Australia, New Zealand, the United Kingdom, and many states in the United States are included,

but the only non-Anglophone in the group was Michel Dion from Quebec. To the degree that

environmental ethics began as response to concerns in the United States, the international

diversity is impressive. Yet the lack of contributions from Latin America, Africa, Asia, and

445 Bill Hook, “The Fate of Skills in the Information Age,” RPT 19 (2000): 101-123. 446 Hook, “Intrinsic Value: Under the Scrutiny of Information and Evolutionary Theory,” EE 25 (2003):

359-373, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics20032543. 447 Klaus Michael Meyer-Abich, “Toward a Practical Philosophy of Nature,” EE 1, no. 4 (Winter 1979):

293-308, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19791423.

147

continental Europe suggest any global environmental philosophy, and, to the degree they are

related, philosophy of technology, is missing voices that can deepen and extend the ideas that

have been discussed over the past thirty-five years. Moreover, the amount of interplay between

the specializations seems to be less than in the past, perhaps as each specialization gained more

sound footing in different universities.

Andrew Light: Durbin’s Synthesis between the Specializations

Paul T. Durbin’s Philosophy of Technology: In Search of Discourse Synthesis,449

published in its entirety as the whole of RPT volume 10, number 2 (Winter 2006), is a narrative

of philosophy of technology that identifies to connection points between the specialization and

environmental philosophy. Durbin was inspired by Walter Watson’s The Architectonics of

Meaning: Foundations of the New Pluralism to categorize important individuals in SPT.450

Watson’s scheme organizes individuals by the controversies in which they respond, and he

groups authors into one of four categories. One group consists of those writers whose style is

includes discussion of values that is dialectical and idealistic, in the sense of Plato’s sense of the

term, and Watson understands this group as following in Plato’s tradition. A second group is

best considered Aristotelian because they use an encyclopedic approach within a discipline or a

specialization. A third group is narrative-based and anti-methodical in style, which Watson

connects to Protagoras, for whom humans are “the measure of all things.” A fourth group uses

an objectivist, methodical approach that is linked not to any ancient Greek philosopher, but to the

448 Meyer-Abich, “What Sort of Technology Permits the Language of Nature? Conditions for Controlling

Nature-Domination Constitutionally,” Philosophy and Technology. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 80. P&T 1 (1983): 211-232.

449 Paul T. Durbin, Philosophy of Technology: In Search of Discourse Synthesis, published as a special volume of Techné: RPT 10, no. 2 (Winter 2006).

450 Walter Watson, The Architectonics of Meaning: Foundations of the New Pluralism (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 1985).

148

style and approach of modern science. The groups are not inclusive: Watson recognizes that

hybrids are possible and have become increasingly more common in the last five hundred years.

In Durbin’s history, Kristin Shrader-Frechette and Stanley Carpenter had highlighted

environmental concerns as members of SPT and in the pages of RPT. Shrader-Frechette and

Carpenter both primarily attended to practical or policy concerns, rather than more philosophical

issues. According to Durbin, Shrader-Frechette encouraged the discussion of actual technologies

rather than Heidegger’s technology and Ellul’s technique, in a sense taking an empirical turn two

decades before Hans Achterhuis’s book.451 Durbin positioned Shrader-Frechette in the science

quadrant, with the provision that her concern for Rawlsian justice is at odds with a purely

descriptive approach. Carpenter is not situated in Durbin’s Watsonian scheme, though his

approach to sustainability policy would likely lead Durbin to place him in the same quadrant.

Light takes a more philosophical look at both technology and the environment. An

environmental pragmatist, he measured the relative success of the environmental ethics

enterprise primarily on its effectiveness in addressing contemporary environmental issues,

especially questions having to do with restoration. Durbin situated Light’s work as part of a

discourse that includes one group of voices that claim restoration is unnecessary, another who

approach environmental issues as environmental economists, a third group that is concerned with

“traditional” environmental ethics concerns such as interests and rights of non-humans (i.e., the

majority of the EE articles), a fourth composed of ecofeminists concerned with domination of

other humans and other animals, and a fifth that grants wild areas value on their own accord.

Watson’s framework in the hands of Durbin falters in his analysis of the “controversies”

that surround Light. Instead of providing a list of how the four quadrants should be filled, as he

451 Shrader-Frechette earned her bachelor’s degree in mathematics, a Ph.D. in philosophy, and had post-

docs in community ecology, economics, and hydrogeology.

149

did for most individuals in his twenty-five chapter history of philosophy and/or technology,

Durbin wrote

Controversies in environmental ethics and philosophy of technology? Light is clear that he is a pragmatist (restoration ecologist). His website says he is opposed to the whole now-standard environmental ethics spectrum (whether we view this as a range extending from environmental economics to “deep ecology,” or as a left/right political spectrum), because it has “not achieved what it set out to accomplish.” But critics doubt that Light’s favored restoration ecology will work—or that it is even necessary. Ecofeminists want to deal with the strongly “symbolic” issues of false dichotomies. And, in the most fundamental challenge (in these terms) to environmental pragmatism, Callicott says it abandons the field, giving up on the effort to devise a defensible holistic or biocentric rather than human-centered philosophy—thus, by default, ending up with a human-centered view which will not lead to “pragmatic” solutions that match the environmental challenge.452

Three of the opponents seem to map well to Watson’s framework. The language of

environmental economics uses the “scientific” voice. Deep ecology is most consonant with

those following Platonic transcendence, wherein the day-to-day environmental phenomena that

humans experience reveals glimmerings of a holistic integrity missed by those who remain in the

Cave. The Protagorean perspective, though excluded from the summary quoted above, can

describe those who reject preservation and restoration.

When trying to situate Callicott and ecofeminists vis-à-vis Light, however, the

shortcomings of the framework become clear. In Durbin’s understanding, Callicott’s

biocentrism can be placed as an adversary of the Protagorean perspective, which would add

another dimension to Watson’s framework, or perhaps as pre-Protagorean, i.e., as one who

fundamentally challenges the Protagorean anthropocentric assumptions that frame Watson’s

entire architectonics. In the brief summary quoted above, the ecofeminists attention to

“symbolic” issues seems to place them in a Platonic quadrant, a strange place for an ecofeminist

philosopher such as Val Plumwood, whose “Mountains of Dualism” can be understood as a 20th

452 Durbin, Philosophy of Technology, 163.

150

century sketch that supplants Plato’s Allegory of the Cave.453 The ecofeminist approach contains

a Protagorean measure, for ecofeminists adopt anti-methodical approaches and emphasize

individual lived experiences, the social construction of views of women and nature, and the

epistemic shortcomings of reductive modern science, whose practitioners tend to downplay or

ignore their own social situatedness. Alas, Durbin did not describe the hybrid of perspectives

that form the congruence of ecofeminists’ voices, especially to set it apart from Light and Durbin

himself. He appreciated the activism of ecofeminists and situated them as kindred spirits to him,

even if he thought their preoccupation with identifying and annihilating dualisms can prevent

them from achieving their environmental goals.

Where does Light fit in Durbin’s Watson-inspired scheme? The remaining category is

for those who work in an Aristotelian tradition, i.e., those “who stress method and discipline (in

the school subject matter or professional discipline sense), and who emphasize the pigeonholing

of objects within large encyclopedic schemes.”454 In the concluding essay of the book, Durbin

notes that only Carl Mitcham wrote in the Aristotelian tradition.455 Durbin proceeds to repurpose

the quadrant as a home for “Social Democrats” or “Progressives” and assigns Light to this

quadrant, though with some reservations.456

In this framework, my project is best understood as a Watsonian Aristotelian effort, and

as the chiral counterpart of Light’s project. Whereas Light triangulates philosophy and

technology, environmental philosophy, and praxis, the triad for this project is philosophy and

technology, environmental philosophy, and theoria. Such a claim is an oversimplification

453 Val Plumwood, Feminism and the Mastery of Nature (New York: Routledge, 1993), 3. 454 Durbin, Philosophy of Technology, 8. 455 Durbin differentiates his approach as more “creative” than Aristotle’s approach, which he thinks seems

to “pigeonhole” authors rather than to let them “have their own say” (8). 456 Durbin simply writes “And Andrew Light, at least in his environmental pragmatism, belongs here”

(219), without any clarifying account.

151

according to Light’s pragmatist background—which sees praxis and theoria as deeply

intertwined—as well as to my own philosophical approach. Philosophers concerned with

technology and the environment are knee-capped if they refuse to respond to any external stimuli

because the artifactual and the non-human worlds permit a near infinite number of possibilities.

In order to say much, especially about ethical concerns, facts matter. Yet for an inquiry to be

properly philosophical in the sense that Plato uses to describe dogs in Republic, some theorizing

must be done. The most difficult decisions I made to winnow the project came from excluding

many articles on sustainability, appropriate technology, and energy from my analysis. These

topics are of political interest today and have the potential to contribute to more theoretical

understandings of how humans inhabit the world, yet they are usually approached in a way that

depends on and adds little to an appropriately complex notion of technology and nature. To put

it simply, these concerns mean more to Light, though they inform this project, and my project

may inform work on those areas.

Weaving between the Specializations

None of the contributions to RPT or EE show the kind of conversancy with the other

specialization that is necessary to give an adequate account of a philosophy of technology and

the environment that is conceptually rich enough to inform practice. One reason for this

shortcoming is the limited length of journal articles, which makes such an effort difficult. Yet

the absence can also be attributed to the gulf between the two academic communities, the

voluminous literature that has arisen over the last thirty-five years in each field; the empirical

turn in philosophy and technology and at least some shift toward policy turn in environmental

ethics or practical objectives457; and a general trend away from theoretical efforts toward those

457 Bryan Norton, Andrew Light, and Eric Katz are prominent supporters of the turn toward pragmatic

policy, which appears in EE most clearly in Robert Frodeman’s “The Policy Turn in Environmental Philosophy.”

152

that are localized in space, time, and community,458 or, like Andrew Light’s work, directed

toward pragmatic goals. Larry Hickman’s admirable attempt to engage environmental

philosophers suffered from hyperspecialization—Dewey is taken as the standard against which

all measured—and a shallowness that necessarily arose because he took on four environmental

philosophers in a single article. One consequence of a lack of interaction between the

communities in the journals is that authors do not receive feedback from colleagues in other

specializations as part of the peer review process.

The aim for this section is to craft a brief reflection that integrates the two specializations

on the topics of freedom, ecology, and evolution. Articles in RPT/Techné and EE provide the

starting and inflection points for the reflection, but I also borrow from other sources from each

specialization to add depth and breadth. This approach forgoes the Aristotelian approach that

sets up comprehensive categories using some methodology that was used earlier in the chapter—

here I have no pretensions of the universality claimed by Watson, who thought he had developed

“the first truly useful taxonomy of all ideas,” or of the same import, namely “the most significant

philosophical discovery of the present century.”459 Instead, it begins from one specific

contribution, without the claim that this is the best or only starting point. It is motivated by

wonder or curiosity, rather than pragmatic aims—its telos is not the solution of a particular

problem—and the goal is deeper understanding, not generation of rhetorical support for a

political goal.460 It is successful to the extent that it adds depth or clarifies real or apparent

458 Cf. the many situated environmental issues, and more generally “The Empirical Turn in the Philosophy

of Technology,” edited by Peter Kroes and Anthonie Meijers, in the Research in Philosophy and Technology series and Hans Achterhuis’s American Philosophy of Technology: The Empirical Turn (Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana University Press, 2001).

459 Walter Watson, The Architectonics of Meaning: Foundations of the New Pluralism (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1985), back cover blurb and ix.

460 Aristotle, Metaphysics A, 982b12.

153

aporias through a dialectical consideration of issues that intersect philosophy of technology and

environmental philosophy.

The title of Jacques Ellul’s “Nature, Technique and Artificiality” suggests that it is a

fitting starting point for thinking through issues that arise at the intersection of the two

specializations.461 In Ellul’s broader project, he had argued that in the past humans had gained

their freedom by subduing the demands of nature and by protecting themselves from its risks, but

this is not the case in the present, mechanized world. Ellul’s sociological analysis identifies an

inflection point between premodern and modern technology when technique surpassed the

machine, when all other values are diminished with respect to efficiency, which alone is granted

universal acclaim. A chasm exists between the machine and the primitive technologies that

preceded it. More primitive technologies were dependent on the guidance of a skilled operator

who could adjust the tool when raw materials varied or when a different product was desired.

Machines are designed to function the same way all of the time: given an expected input, they

create a consistent, precise product. They are “cookie cutters.” Compare a lathe to a specialized

tool found in a contemporary production line.

The human view of the non-human world is transformed by a worldview centered around

the machine. Among other things, “nature” provides the raw materials needed for the machine.

For machine performance to be optimized, raw materials must be continuously available, and

their characteristics must be within specifications. Oddities and localized variances in the so-

called “products” of nature that may have provoked wonder or led to the creation of a unique

product by a skilled craftsman begin to be seen as imperfections that can “gum up the works.”

The demand for consistent resources begins to determine agricultural patterns and the

461 Jacques Ellul, “Nature, Technique and Artificiality,” RPT 3 (1980): 159-171. The article is summarized

in Chapter 3.

154

transportation system by which they can be moved. In an economy governed by this mindset,

conservation can be defended, but preservation has few defenders. The demands of the machine

explain an important force behind forestry management principles employed in the United States

that were criticized by Aldo Leopold for only optimizing yield without concern for non-

commercial species.462 Langdon Winner pointed out that the tomato population was transformed

by the development of the mechanical tomato harvester, which consequently resulted in the

breeding of tomatoes that are “hardier, sturdier, and less tasty” than what had previous been

available, all so they could work with the machine.463

Ellul’s critique goes further, though. La technique has surpassed the machine: it is no

longer just an “ensemble of means” to a particular productive end. Instead, it becomes “the

totality of methods rationally arrived at and having absolute efficiency (for a given stage of

development) in every field of human activity.”464 Machines are subjugated by technique, which

inherits only the demand for efficiency. In a similar way, humans are also subjugated by

technique: increasingly complex sociotechnical systems common in advanced economies

require a stable supply of dependable operators. Operators are ideally unskilled so that they are

readily available and interchangeable. Particular things and people are no longer worthy of

consideration, and humans are treated like machines when they no longer contribute—or, more

precisely, when they are no longer the optimum contributors—to a particular process. Then they

are discarded, perhaps retrained—or, one could say, retooled—or retired.

Ellul is most concerned with the imposition of technique into human activities such as

politics, science, and education. Technique turns what was “tentative, unconscious, and

462 Aldo Leopold, “The Land Ethic,” in A Sand County Almanac (New York: Ballantine, 1966), 237-264. 463 Langdon Winner, “Do Artifacts Have Politics?” Daedalus 109 (1) (Winter 1980): 126,

http://www.jstor.org/stable/20024652.

155

spontaneous” “into the realm of clear, voluntary, and reasoned concepts” (20). The former

interfere with what is implied by technique, i.e., predictable, rational efficiency. While

individual humans do not lose their agency, the priority of technique entails a desire for

domination of what is natural, which includes those things that have their own ends, and for

optimal results such organization must occur the political level. Ellul’s pessimistic sociological

assessment has a corollary in environmental issues. The employment of humans without concern

for their individual attributes or long-term well-being common in the multinational economic

systems common today has a counterpart in commonly held attitudes toward use of

environmental “resources.” Ellul adopted the view that the world is best understood as though

this is truly the Anthropocene epoch, and thus ecology “should be correctly thought in terms of a

precise analysis of the technical world.”465

On the one hand, there is an element of truth in Ellul’s claim. It points toward the

scarcity of attention of the industrial and everyday environment in environmental ethics,

especially prior to rise of environmental justice as an area of philosophical interest. On the other

hand, Ellul’s claim indicates a lack of familiarity with the principles and history of the science of

ecology as it had developed in the twentieth century. Concerns over the romanticism of ecology

is a critique pertinent to ecology qua natural history, and, to a lesser degree, the ambiguous

holism of Clementian ecology. To some degree, population ecology, starting in the 1920s, and

ecosystem ecology, from the 1960s, which approaches the non-human, non-artifactual entities

through the tools of modern technoscience, already had answered Ellul’s charge. According to

biologist James H. Brown, “[Raymond] Pearl (1925), [A. J.] Lotka (1925), [Vito] Volterra

464 Ellul, The Technological Society, translated by John Wilkinson, New York: Vintage, 1964), xxv (italics

in original). 465 Ellul, “Nature, Technique and Artificiality,” 275.

156

(1926), and others had laid the foundation of a mathematical theory for ecology,”466 an important

step toward a “technical analysis.” Ecosystem ecologists applied thermodynamic principles to

glean a better understanding of mass and energy movements in ecosystems. In his 1969 paper

“The Strategy of Ecosystem Development,” Eugene P. Odum described how to analyze a

biological community as “all of the organisms in a given area (that is, ‘community’) interacting

with the physical environment so that a flow of energy leads to characteristic trophic and

material cycles within the system,”467 which lent additional precision and method to ecology and

distancing it from its origins in natural history. To the extent that all objects can be subsumed

under these ecological principles to yield a “precise analysis of the technical world,” population

and ecosystem ecologists can be said to already have succeeded.

Ellul also made a category error by treating ecology as analogous to the physical

sciences, for which a “precise analysis” is possible. Whereas modern science typically proceeds

by isolating its object of inquiry, ecology recognizes the interdependence, reciprocity, and

mutuality of organisms. The completion of a “precise analysis” depends on stability of the

objects studied, but the changing populations, genetic constitutions, and the landscapes in which

organisms live creates a dynamism, the flux of nature, of which, to some degree, humans are a

part. As Callicott noted, a “field ontology” is more representative. While environmental

philosophers may err ascribing an anthropomorphic form of agency to animals and plants, there

is no doubt that they respond, learn, and assert themselves in unpredictable ways into our lives in

a way that inanimate objects cannot.

466 James H. Brown, “New Approaches and Methods in Ecology,” in Foundations of Ecology: Classic

Papers with Commentaries, edited by Leslie A. Real and James H. Brown (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1991), 447.

467 Eugene P. Odum, “The Strategy of Ecosystem Development,” Science 164 (18 April 1969): 262-270.

157

Let me turn back to the concept of freedom, which in Ellul’s history first takes the form

of husbanding natural objects to satisfy needs and being safe from natural risks, and then in the

technological society takes the form of activity outside of la technique. Freedom can also be

understood as the opportunity to act voluntarily, that is, in a way not governed by instinct or

necessary. In her article on anthropotechnology and human evolution, Sylvia Blad argued that

what makes humans distinct are precisely those attributes that are not driven by the needs of

necessity encapsulated in Ellul’s first definition. She is not concerned with technique, but rather

freedom from the impositions of Darwinistic survival. Machines and other implements are part

of the “tool kits” that are integrated into human being: what they can do is no longer necessary

for humans to do, so freedom is manifested by the loss of capabilities “won” through evolution.

Compare this understanding of evolution with Callicott’s proposition that evolutionary

time provides the measure of the morality of an act in an ecological sense.468 Freedom is acting

against inclination when foresight indicates that the energy and material flows in nature will be

interrupted. Or think about Holmes Rolston, III’s lead article in the first issue of EE: nature is

given a stability that allows us to “follow it” as an orienting force that guides humans in finding

their place in the cosmos.469 For Rolston and Callicott, the proper exercise of freedom seems to

be limited by its consequences so as to not negatively affect other organisms any more than is

appropriate for a human.

In fine, we can construct a multidimensional understanding of freedom. From Ellul

freedom is understood as not being assimilated into technique. From Blad, freedom is acting

contrary to evolution, whereas with Callicott, moral freedom demands acting within its

boundaries. For Rolston, contrary to Ellul and Blad, the harms and threats of nature, along with

468 Callicott, “Deconstructive Ecology,” 353-372. 469 Rolston, “Can and Ought,” 7-30.

158

its splendor and profundity, are not something that must be avoided, but they instead serve to

instruct and orient students.

The preceding chapter sketched out three different ways to integrate the two

specializations, a longitudinal analysis, a focus on contributors to both journals, and a reflection

on freedom, ecology, and evolution that integrates many important thinkers from both camps.

This certainly does not exhaust the options available. In the next chapter, I propose an ethical

construct based off of W. D. Ross’s ethical theory that is comprehensive enough to serve as a

basic framework for concerns of environmental philosophers and philosophers of technology.

159

CHAPTER 6

ROSS’S DUTIES AS A COMPREHENSIVE ETHICAL THEORY

The goal of this chapter is to test the adequacy of a modified version of W. D. Ross’s

prima facie duties as a comprehensive ethical theory that can address issues of the environment

and technology. I am evaluating the theory against the standard expressed by Paul van Dijk, who

wrote in RPT that “the task of ethics and of an ethicist is to sharpen and accentuate the

conscience, to stretch moral fantasy, making people sensitive to the ethical aspects of the

problem situation [sic] at issue.”470 In my opinion, Ross’s theory has received less traction than

is due to it, perhaps in part because it starts from common perspectives and seeks to clarify them,

in part because it has no clever architectonic structure, and in part because it neither promises nor

delivers definitive answers to ethical questions.

The fluidity of our technological environment and the flux of nature, though, mitigate

against the possibility of deductive-nomological certainty and definitive answers, one in which a

combination of lawlike premises are combined with particular observations to explain a general

result or a specific event.471 As Albert Borgmann pointed out, as scientific inquiry has become

increasingly precise, it has lost its power to explain the relevance or significance of an event.

The technological-mathematical character of modern science can refine “pre-scientific”

generalizations about nature into predictive laws, but this narrow focus comes at a cost.

Epistemic claims are severed from metaphysics and ethics, and only a subset of such claims are

considered valid. Borgmann noted that that deductive-nomological claims neglect the “world-

470 Paul van Dijk, “Environmental Ethics and the Recovery of Culture,” RPT 17 (1998): 25-43. See the List

of Abbreviations for the shorthand used to refer to frequently referenced journals. 471 This explanation is inspired by Albert Borgmann’s explanation of the reasoning common in modern

science in Technology and The Character of Contemporary Life: A Philosophical Inquiry (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 15-26.

160

articulating and world-signifying” power of deictic explanations, which “outline and highlight

the crucial features of something that is also a kind of explanation.”472

Not just science is affected by this attenuation. The term technoscience, first used in a

context that explicitly takes ethical concerns into account by Gilbert Hottois in the 1970s,

describes the deep integration and reciprocal dependency of modern science and contemporary

technology.473 The term corrects a simplistic yet commonly held understanding of technology as

the application of science. Technological practices and devices are often thought to arise from

“pure” theory developed independently. This apparent one-way relationship was clearly

reversed in James Watts’s development of the steam engine, which preceded the science of

thermodynamics. Hans Jonas described the evolution of “modern science-infused technology”

as one in which “cognitive purpose” is eclipsed by the practical aim of doing work.474

Technoscience, which describes the imbroglio of what Aristotle would have separated into

techné and episteme, also attends to the social context in which the aims of different projects are

determined and carried out. Both technology and science, however they are split, share a

grounding of technoscience, one reason that the apodeictic explanations that yield greater

technological capabilities and ecological knowledge have advanced beyond the deictic

explanations necessary to understand their relevance and ethical value.

The lawlike structure associated with technoscience, along with its increasing precision,

obscures the character of techné component in technoscience. In Aristotle’s taxonomy of the

intellectual virtues, techné, along with phronesis, deals with “things that are capable of being

472 Borgmann, Technology and the Character of Contemporary Life, 25. 473 Gilbert Hottois, “Technoscience” in the Encyclopedia of Science, Technology, and Ethics 4, edited by

Carl Mitcham (Detroit: Thomson Gale, 2005), 1914-1916. Hottois developed the idea of technoscience in P&T in “Technoscience: Nihilistic Power Versus a New Ethical Consciousness” 3 (1987):69-84.

474 Hans Jonas, “Seventeenth Century and After: The Meaning of the Scientific and Technological Revolution,” in Philoosophical Essays: From Ancient Creed to Technological Man (New York: Atropos Press, 1980), 46-82.

161

otherwise.”475 Since most technological projects affect natural objects, taken as a whole nature

also should be considered that which could be otherwise, even as individual organisms are still

properly considered physis, or beings that seek their own internally prescribed ends. Moreover,

human inclinations and our technological and natural environment should be understood as

having a trajectory, an inertia that must be taken into account that is missed if they are thought to

be static like a snapshot.476 The immeasurable number of possible technological milieus and

natural terroirs, our environment most broadly understood, suggest that a law-driven approach to

ethics of technology and the environment is bound to fail, that a moral act will depend on the

situation, and a moral theory must be responsive and comprehensive.

Ross’s duties provide a possible starting point for developing an overarching framework

that can situate ethics of technology and nature. There is some precedent for this synthesis.

Ross’s theory was explored in several articles in EE, and, though I found just a single passing

mention of him in RPT/Techné, his theory is briefly mentioned in the leading textbook on

Engineering Ethics,477 an area of professional ethics which is influenced by philosophy of

technology.

Ross’s duty ethics is malleable and more open to expansion to include issues of

technology and nature because Ross himself claimed no “completeness or finality” for his

divisions of prima facie duties.478 His refusal to ground his ethics in a single principle or to

construct a symmetrical architectonic makes his ethics responsive to human needs, desires, and

the state of the environment. To recognize duties that correspond to the built environment or to

475 Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 1140a1. 476 This insight is an expansion from the claim made by Justus Buchler’s attention to exhibitive judgments

relayed by Roger J. H. King and discussed in Chapter 4. 477 Charles E. Harris, Michael S. Pritchard, Michael J. Rabins, Ray James, and Elaine Englehart,

Engineering Ethics: Concepts and Cases, fifth edition (Boston: Wadsworth, 2014), 32. 478 W. D. Ross, The Right and the Good, edited by Philip Stratton-Lake (Oxford: Oxford University Press,

2002), 20.

162

non-humans, then, does not undercut his foundation, and it requires no major overhaul.

Moreover, while attentive to moral judgments of the common man and, especially, the moral

aristocrat, he also recognized the limitations of descriptive ethics. He noted that “many of the

most strongly felt repulsions towards certain types of conduct are relics of a bygone system of

totems and fetishes, their connexion with which is little suspected by those who feel them.”479

Historical and contemporary moral beliefs are instructive, not authoritative, and the recent

origins of EE and RPT/Techné suggest that their concerns were understated and less important at

the time when Ross wrote The Right and the Good, which was published in 1930, and when he

gave the Gifford Lectures at the University of Aberdeen from 1935-1936 that would be

published as Foundations of Ethics in 1939.480

To work through a possible synthesis of Ross’s duties and an ethics of technology and the

environment, I start by explaining Ross’s theory in some detail. Next I turn to his references to

animals and artifacts before looking at how he has been employed in EE and the philosophy and

technology literature, especially Tom L. Beauchamp and James F. Childress’s important

textbook on biomedical ethics. Then I consider how Ross’s theory can be extended to also

encompass future generations, non-human beings, and artifacts. Finally, inspired by the work of

Albert Borgmann and Shannon Vallor, I propose some new “communicative” or “ecological”

virtues.

Explanation of Ross’s Duty Ethics

Ross argued that what makes an act right is how well it satisfies the many prima facie

duties that an agent faces in any particular situation. Such duties emerge from morally

479 Ibid., 13. 480 Ross, The Foundations of Ethics (London: Clarendon Press, 1939).

163

significant acts.481 These include duties that are based on one’s own previous acts, which he

called duties of fidelity, which includes telling the truth and communicating honestly, and duties

of reparation, i.e., restitution for damages that one has caused. Ross noted that fidelity is an

imperfect description of what he intends because it describes a state of mind, whereas the duty is

toward the act, regardless of the state of mind, and the duty arises simply because we have made

a promise or caused some injury.

A second division of duties arises based on acts done on behalf of an individual, which

Ross called duties of gratitude.482 Like fidelity, the term gratitude suffers the defect of referring

to a motivation, whereas Ross wanted to draw attention to the act, “the returning of services,

irrespective of motive.”483

Ross’s third division of duties is composed of are those that have to do with justice,

which demand that an agent act in such a way that happiness or pleasure coincide with merit.

Though “justice” is sometimes used to describe a motivation for action, it is also used to describe

acts irrespective of motive, unlike fidelity and gratitude, so this term needs less explanation.

Ross argued that virtue and pleasure, two intrinsic goods, must reasonably coincide by way of a

thought experiment in which one must prefer a world in which pleasure primarily resides on

those who are virtuous and pain on those who are vicious, rather than vice versa.

Two other divisions includes the positive duties of beneficence, i.e., to improve the lot of

another by virtue, intelligence, or pleasure, and the negative duties related to avoid causing harm

to others, non-maleficence. Virtue, intelligence, and pleasure are the three simple intrinsic goods

481 Ross, Right and the Good, 21. 482 Ross calls reparation and gratitude “twin duties.” 483 Ibid., 23.

164

identified by Ross.484 Even though Ross listed non-maleficence last, he also explained that it

should generally have priority over beneficence, that is, as he put it, it is “prima facie more

binding. We should not in general consider it justifiable to kill one person in order to keep

another alive, or to steal from one in order to give alms to another.”485

Sandwiched between non-maleficence and beneficence are the duties to one’s own self-

improvement. It is positioned after the duties of beneficence because it is the promotion of

intrinsic goods of virtue and knowledge turned inward. It is important to note that no duty for

self-pleasure exists, even though pleasure is considered one of the intrinsic goods. Ross gave

two reasons to explain this seeming incongruity. First, the desire for pleasure is a natural

inclination, one that is pursued even if no reflection is made about duty. Second, the satisfaction

of the other duties, which usually benefit other actors, almost always comes at a cost of one’s

own pleasure. The natural inclination for pleasure is properly checked when “we think of our

own pleasure not as simply our own pleasure, but as an objective good, something that an

impartial spectator would approve,” it is at that point “that we can think of the getting it as a

duty; and we do not habitually think of it in this way.”486 To put it another way, pleasure is a

good when obtained through the joy of accomplishing some duty, and not all simple pleasures or

preference satisfactions fit in this category, though some may.

Prima facie duties differ from the more popular concept of duty that Immanuel Kant

derived from the relation of the reason and the will. Duties that arise from this concept, which

can be revealed by submitting a maxim to the test of the categorical imperative, always must be

followed for an action to be moral. They are absolute. For Kant, an act clearly has moral worth

484 In Foundations, Ross identified “the activity of the mind which leads to knowledge” as a good, as well

as artistic creation or excellence, which necessarily remains more loosely defined than scientific excellence (270). 485 Ross, Right and Good, 22. 486 Ibid., 26.

165

if it arises from reason directing the will toward duty and away from self-interest and inclination.

The categorical imperative is simple, i.e., it is one law, so duties cannot conflict. If they were to

conflict, Kant’s project of finding universal imperatives would have failed.

All of Kant’s duties are universal, but he makes one important distinction between strict

or narrow (commonly called perfect) duties and broad (commonly called imperfect) ones.487

Perfect duties are absolute, i.e., they must always be followed, and they include telling the truth

and refusing to commit suicide even when life is bitterly unpleasant. Not fulfilling strict duties

does conceptual violence to the underlying actions: communication loses its internal purpose if

falsehoods may be peddled at any given time, and committing suicide acts against the more

fundamental, internal purpose of being. Imperfect duties should be pursued when possible, but

there are situations in which not fulfilling them is morally acceptable. The two imperfect duties

discussed by Kant in Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals are to improve one’s self and to

aim to increase the happiness of others. Kant explains their categorical scope by saying that it is

impossible to will that not doing these things should “be implanted in us as such a law by a

natural instinct.”488

Ross followed Kant in setting duty in opposition to pleasure for one’s self or pursuing

one’s self-interest. Ross wrote “The performance of most of our duties involves the giving up of

some pleasure that we desire, the doing of duty and the getting of pleasure for ourselves come by

a natural association of ideas to be thought of as incompatible things.”489 He thought that, just as

Kant did, duties are revealed a priori, i.e., independent of experience. Yet other details of these

theories differ rather dramatically. Ross, who described absolute or universal duties, such as

487 Immanuel Kant, Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals, translated by James W. Ellington, third

edition, (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1993), 423. 488 Ibid., 423. 489 Ross, Right and the Good, 25.

166

those in Kant’s work as “duty proper,” used the term prima facie to describe the conditional

nature of his duties, though he is uneasy with the term.

The phrase ‘prima facie duty’ must be apologized for, since (1) it suggests that what we are speaking of is a certain kind of duty, whereas it is in fact not a duty, but something related in a special way to duty. Strictly speaking, we want not a phrase in which duty is qualified by an adjective, but a separate noun. (2) “Prima” facie suggests that one is speaking only of an appearance which a moral situation presents at first sight, and which may turn out to be illusory; whereas what I am speaking of is an objective fact involved in the nature of the situation, or more strictly in an element of its nature, though not, as duty proper does, arising from its whole nature.490

While my primary focus is on the normative elements of Ross’s theory and its extension to

technology and the environment, a brief description of his epistemology is helpful to understand

the preceding quotation. Ross was both an epistemological and a methodical intuitionist. He

held that we can have direct knowledge of moral truths. Ross’s duties have a real referent, that

is, they refer to objective moral knowledge, which he compares to the “spatial or numerical

structure expressed in the axioms of geometry or arithmetic.”491 They are real in a second sense:

“each rests on a definite circumstance which cannot seriously be held to be without moral

significance.”492 Ross’s duties are also pluralistic, lacking an ultimate principle or hierarchy that

can be used for an algorithmic application of the theory, a claim that situates him as a methodical

intuitionist. On this point, Ross was unapologetic: “Loyalty to the facts is worth more than a

symmetrical architectonic or a hastily reached simplicity.”493

The moral certainty described above only applies to the most fundamental moral

propositions can be known with any certainty. Particular judgments are rarely self-evident:

often prima facie rightness and wrongness coincide, and humans never know all the facts or all

the consequences. This recognition led Ross to another important distinction. He contrasted

490 Ibid., 20 (italics in original). 491 Ibid., 30. 492 Ibid., 20.

167

what is right, i.e., what an individual decides to do with imperfect knowledge, and what is

morally good, i.e., what should be chosen if one were omniscient. Nonetheless, imperfect

knowledge does not discharge duty. Each duty is conditionally binding: it is “an act which

would be a duty proper if it were not at the same time of another kind which is morally

significant.”494 Though there is no single method by which one can organize prima facie duties,

he notes that “a great deal of stringency belongs to the duties of perfect obligation”: the duties of

keeping our promises, repairing wrongs we have done, and of returning the equivalent of

services we have received.495 I will return to the idea of stringency at the end of this chapter.

Ross’s duties can be situated between Kant’s sole concern with motive and act, with no

regard for consequences, and the singular focus on consequences of the hedonistic utilitarians,

with no concern for motive or act. Ross’s duties arise from recognition of the relevant features

of a certain state of affairs. Their satisfaction is not affected by motivation but rather by the

successful completion of the appropriate act, which then should obtain a fitting state of affairs.

Thus, consequences matter, but not exclusively, or as Ross put it, “no one means by ‘right’ just

‘productive of the best possible consequences’, or ‘optimific.’”496 Ross gives two situations in

which satisfying duties are not optimific. A promise should be fulfilled even if it does not lead

to optimum consequences, and justice overrides the desire of optimizing pleasure if it were to be

concentrated in vicious individuals.

While Ross did not take motivation into account when considering rightness, he does

when considering goodness. He wrote “for if we hold that actions are morally good when and

because they proceed from certain motives, we can hardly fail to ascribe moral goodness to those

493 Ibid., 23. 494 Ibid., 19. By duty proper Ross means Kant’s absolute duty. 495 Ibid., 41. 496 Ibid., 34.

168

same desires when they do not lead to action.”497 So the same with desires and emotions as with

dispositions, or Ross called them, “permanent modifications of character.”498

Ross’s elevation of virtue, unfortunately, received little clarification in his work, which

was directed toward the epochal issue of determining moral rules and their justifications.

Unsurprisingly, as one of the most influential scholars on Aristotle in the first half of the

twentieth century, he uses Aristotelian concepts to describe virtue only in general terms, that

intellectual and moral virtues should be praised, and pace Kant, and can be cultivated in others,

and that one should follow the ideal person and strive develop a similarly lofty character. Ross’s

understanding of virtue differs from Aristotle’s because of the emphasis the latter gives to a

stable or ingrained disposition that is present when an act is done and then motivates it.499 Only

a courageous person can act in a courageous way; the same act done by a coward is not properly

called courageous. Aristotle’s virtue is thus called dispositional, whereas Ross’s understanding

is called occurrent-state because it prioritizes the act and gives secondary importance to

disposition. In my research, I found no list of virtues in Ross like those that appear in Aristotle’s

Nicomachean Ethics and Thomas Aquinas’s Summa Theologiae. This omission means that there

is no framework by which to test the “ecological” or “communicative” virtues that I propose at

the end of the chapter.

At this point, let me put Ross’s theory of prima facie duties in the background and bring

to the fore what he said and what has been said about his theory regarding issues of artifacts and

the environment.

Ross and Ethics of Artifacts and the Environment

497 Ross, Foundations, 290. 498 Ibid., 292. 499 Thomas Hurka, “Virtuous Act, Virtuous Dispositions,” Analysis 66, no. 1 (Jan. 2006): 69-76, doi:

10.1111/j.1467-8284.2006.00591.x.

169

Though Ross does not specifically address environmental ethics or ethical or political

issues related to artifacts in The Right and the Good or in Foundations of Ethics, a thumbnail

sketch can be made by reading the former text closely and working with the meager resources

available. I then proceed to review how Ross’s theory, as it happens always taken from The

Right and the Good, was employed in the pages of EE. I was unable to find any serious

treatment of his work in RPT/Techné, or even in more theory-centric literature on technology in

general, though he receives mention in professional ethics. As mentioned earlier, Ross’s prima

facie duties are mentioned briefly in Harris et al.’s Engineering Ethics, and he plays a bit role in

Beauchamp and Childress’s prominent work on biomedical ethics, which is the best-developed

work in the most mature field of professional ethics.

In the first appendix called “Rights,” which follows the second chapter of the book titled

“What Makes Right Acts Right?” in The Right and the Good, Ross briefly mentioned infants,

who are complicated because they are “potential moral agents,”500 and animals. The former

hints at the issue of future generations, which is discussed at some length by Peter Wenz in EE,

and is necessary to account for the temporal duration and uncertainty of modern technology, and

the latter, as part of animal ethics, are clearly part of environmental ethics. The aim of the

appendix is to determine the relationship between duties and rights, and animals and infants

allow Ross to do that.

Ross noted that some have justified duties toward animals in an instrumental way, on

account of crafting a particular disposition in a human that might manifest itself in interpersonal

relationships. Ross’s reasoning was less oblique: “if we think we ought to behave in a certain

way to animals, it is out of consideration primarily for their feelings that we think we ought to

behave so; we do not think of them merely as a practising-ground for virtue. It is because we

170

think of their pain as a bad thing that we think we should not gratuitously cause it.”501 Ross

adopted the position, hypothetically at this point, that while animals can have interests, and

humans can have duties toward them, they cannot have rights, which can only be claimed by

moral agents. Much later, in the chapter on the things that are intrinsically good, he definitively

stated that “the pleasure of animals is always good, and the pain of animals always bad, in itself

and apart from its consequences.”502 This is categorically true for animals, whereas it is not true

for humans, for which an assessment must include the complicating factors of just deserts, moral

good, or evil.

An incomplete sketch of Ross’s ethics of artifacts can be made from a few short

comments in The Right and the Good. In the same appendix cited previously, he wrote “I

suppose that the duty of the owner of a historic house is essentially a duty to his contemporaries

and to posterity; and he may also think it is a duty to his ancestors.”503 Artifacts and other

material things are, ceteris paribus, intrinsically good because they often yield pleasure.

Material things are valuable in a second instrumental way: the development of virtues, the best

of the intrinsic goods, often depends on material things. As Ross noted, “Virtue owes many of

its opportunities to the existence of material conditions of good and material hinderances to

good.”504

The seed of a politics of artifacts can be found in his concerns about justice, which

involved structural concerns as well as interpersonal obligations. “The sense of a general

obligation to bring about (so far as we can) a just apportionment of happiness to merit is often

greatly reinforced by the fact that many of the existing injustices are due to a social and

500 Ross, Right and the Good, 49. 501 Ibid., 49. 502 Ibid., 137. 503 Ibid., 49.

171

economic system which we have, not indeed created, but taken part in and assented to; the duty

of justice is then reinforced by the duty of reparation.”505 It is possible to use the phrase “social

and economic system” in a broad sense that includes the built environment and the devices used

in it, though I see no reason to think that Ross did.

Ross has garnered attention in several articles in EE, two from contributors who had also

had articles published in RPT/Techné. In most cases, Ross was just mentioned in passing. Don

E. Marietta, in article that argued that “extreme holistic environmental ethics” is inadequate,506

agreed with Ross’s take that making a correct moral statement requires some luck, and Ross was

summoned simply as an authority to buttress Marietta’s claim, despite the fact that the article did

not mention Ross elsewhere. In “Individualism, Holism, and Environmental Ethics,”507

Shrader-Frechette developed a holistic anthropocentric and biocentric ethics in which “strong”

human rights, such as the right to life and bodily integrity, have priority over environmental

concerns, but weak human rights, such as property, are trumped by environmental concerns.

Ross, who stated that the just distribution of happiness based on merit is an intrinsic good, is

briefly cited as part of a critique of the ethical individualism of William Frankena.508 In Tom

Regan’s argument for the necessity of an environmental ethic, he criticized the risk of counting

on the moral judgments of “thoughtful and well-educated people,” which Ross thought must

form the starting point for any ethical theorist, though he said nothing more about Ross.509

William C. French employs Ross’s clarification of the difference between conditional and actual

504 Ibid., 141. 505 Ibid., 28. 506 Don E. Marietta, “Environmental Holism and Individuals,” EE 10, no. 3 (Fall 1988): 251-258, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics198810314. 507 Kristin Shrader-Frechette, “Individualism, Holism, and Environmental Ethics,” Ethics and the

Environment 1, No. 1 (Spring 1996): 55-69, http://www.jstor.org/stable/40338929. 508 Shrader-Frechette gives no citation for Ross. Ross connects a just distribution of pleasure based on

virtue (p. 140) as well as a just distribution of happiness based on merit.

172

duties in his diagnosis of Paul Taylor’s defense of species equality, though again with no further

discussion of his duties.510

Two articles stand out for seriously engaging Ross’s theory. Robert Elliot, whose

“Faking Nature” article in Inquiry spurred a line of discussion of ecosystem restoration,511

including contributions by Eric Higgs in both EE and RPT/Techné, used Ross’s openness to the

coincidence of instrumental and intrinsic value as part of his metaethical defense of Rolston’s

explanation of systemic value. Rolston had claimed that since systemic value depends on yet

exceeds instrumental value, instrumental value can be said to be a source of intrinsic value. 512

The second paper, written by Peter Wenz, addressed the normative content of Ross’s theory,

which is the focus of this chapter. Wenz defended formalism in general and Ross’s duties in

particular as superior to contractarian and utilitarian ethical theories for addressing energy policy

issues for future generations.513 Wenz argued that the prima facie duties of nonmaleficence,

justice, and reparation can be extended to future generations and to possible people.

Nonmaleficence and beneficence check the (at least politically) undesirable conclusion that a

sudden shift in energy sources is necessary and moral, which would impose significant suffering

on humans alive now and in the near future. In a later paper, Wenz mentioned W. D. Ross’s

509 Tom Regan, “The Nature and the Possibility of an Environmental Ethic,” EE 3, no. 1 (Spring 1981): 19-

34, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19813131; Ross, The Right and the Good, 41. 510 William C. French, “Against Biospherical Egalitarianism,” EE 17, no. 1 (Spring 1995): 39-57, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics199517135. Here he cites Lawrence Johnson’s species-ranking, which is based on “complexity, diversity, balance, organic unity or integrity,” in Johnson, A Morally Deep World: An Essay on Moral Significance and Environmental Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 227, as cited in French.

511 Robert Elliot, “Faking Nature,” Inquiry 25 (March 1982): 81-93, doi: 10.1080/00201748208601955. 512 Robert Elliot, “Instrumental Value in Nature as a Basis for the Intrinsic Value of Nature as a Whole,”

EE 27, no. 1 (Spring 2005): 43-56, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics200527140. 513 Peter S. Wenz, “Ethics, Energy Policy, and Future Generations,” EE 5, no. 3 (Fall 1983): 195-209, doi:

10.5840/enviroethics19835321.

173

theory as expressing a moderate and not extreme pluralism taken metaphysically, but here Wenz

does not address Ross’s normative content.514

I found only one mention of W. D. Ross in RPT/Techné, a passing reference in Carl

Mitcham and René von Schomberg’s “The Ethics of Engineers: From Occupational Role

Responsibility to Public Co-Responsibility,”515 though the lack of indexing of early volumes and

online availability led me to use several peripheral inquiries to come to this conclusion. A search

on Google Scholar for W. D. Ross and technology led to no relevant results. Ross’s work is

given a few paragraphs in the “Deontology” entry in the Encyclopedia of Science, Technology,

and Ethics and in its successor, Engineering, Science, Technology, and Ethics: A Global

Resource, the most comprehensive reference books for the specialization, but Ross was not given

a standalone entry. The only relevant resource listed in the bibliographies, which are generally

extensive and excellent, is Beauchamp and Childress’s Principles of Biomedical Ethics, which is

usually considered primarily a work on professional ethics, not ethics of technology.

Ross’s prima facie duties seem to lurk behind Beauchamp and Childress’s identification

of respect for autonomy, nonmaleficence, beneficence, and justice as basic principles that can be

in conflict in Principles of Biomedical Ethics.516 Yet Beauchamp and Childress expend no effort

to explain the similarities and differences between their principles and Ross’s at either a

metaethical or a normative perspective. They do not explain why respect for autonomy should

be added to Ross’s list, and why duties of fidelity, reparations, gratitude, and self-improvement

are not relevant, or at least not relevant enough to be mentioned, in biomedical ethics. In their

514 Peter Wenz, “Minimal, Moderate, and Extreme Moral Pluralism,” EE 15, no. 1 (Spring 1993): 61-74,

doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199315140. 515 Carl Mitcham and René von Schomberg, “The Ethics of Engineers: From Occupational Role

Responsibility to Public Co-Responsibility,” RPT 20 (2000): 170. 516 Tom L. Beauchamp and James F. Childress, Principles of Biomedical Ethics, sixth edition (New York:

Oxford University Press, 2009), 13-15.

174

chapter “Moral Theories,” Ross’s prima facie duties are mentioned only as converging with

Richard Brandt’s rule utilitarianism, which they explain by the generally accepted norms of

common morality, and Kantianism is the only deontological theory treated at length.517 In their

chapter on “Method and Moral Justification,” Ross is cited as an authority in agreement with

their claim that “no one has attained a fully specified system of norms for health care ethics,” in

part to justify their acceptance of “disunity, conflict, and moral ambiguity as pervasive features

of the moral life.”518 The recklessness with which Beauchamp and Childress make their

universal claim about norms for health care ethics, and their lack of concern for evidence, is

representative of their superficial approach to Ross’s duties.

Extending Prima Facie Duties

Hans Jonas cited the “scale and causal range” of technological practice as what makes

modern technology “too big for the size of the stage on which it is enacted.”519 Such power, he

argued, exceeds traditional spatiotemporal scales that had bounded traditional actions and their

respective ethical scope. The success of technological advances has put incredible pressure on

the biosphere, Jonas said, before connecting an ethics of technology to environmental ethics,

which he defined as “the expression of this unprecedented widening of our responsibility, which

in turn answers to the unprecedented widening of the reach of our deeds.”520 One measure of an

ethical theory is whether it has the resources to scale to consider citizens from around the globe

and future generations, non-human organisms, the abiotic environment, and the built

environment. In the following section, I put Ross’s prima facie duties to the test for each of

extension.

517 Ibid., 343-349. In my opinion, the authors overstate Ross’s rejection of utilitarianism (362). 518 Ibid., 373-374. 519 Hans Jonas, “Technology as a Subject for Ethics,” Social Research 49:4 (Winter 1982): 893,

http://www.jstor.org/stable/40971222.

175

Extending to a Global Citizenship and Future Generations. To address the global scope and

lasting effects of modern technologies, Ross’s duties must be able to include all living people

today as well as future generations. Such an expansion is necessary to respond to sustainability

concerns, the global spread of pollutants, and long-term waste issues, such as nuclear waste. I

start by tracing the reasoning behind Wenz’s limited application of Ross’s duties to energy

policy to see how well it accommodates future generations. Then, I take a more comprehensive

approach to determine which of the duties are applicable to a global citizenry and future

generations.

In his argument against the use of nonrenewable resources and the generation of

hazardous wastes, Wenz argued that “formalists maintain we intuitively accord human beings the

right to remain unharmed,”521 from which the duty to non-maleficence arises. The prohibition

against causing harm is not qualified by a certain limited temporal span, i.e., harm is prohibited

not just now but also in the future, a line of reasoning by which Wenz extended the prima facie

duty to include an obligation to future people.522 The obligation can also be extended to possible

people, those who may or may not be born based on circumstances, “at least to some extent.”523

On this point, his reasoning is convoluted. After claiming that through moral intuition most

people would say that non-existence is preferable to living below a minimal quality of life, he

claimed that “causing such people to exist is, therefore, changing them from a more to a less

enviable state.”524 I remain unconvinced that any state can be assigned to non-existence.

Fortunately, the problem of identity, which undergirds the possible people argument, is less

520 Ibid., 895. 521 Wenz, “Ethics, Energy Policy, and Future Generations,” 204. 522 Concern about possible people is Wenz’s, not Ross’s. While Ross mentioned “potential moral agents,”

his comments only refer to a class of existing agents who will likely gain moral status at some point, not to potential agents.

523 Wenz, “Ethics, Energy Policy, and Future Generations,” 204. 524 Ibid., 205.

176

relevant because the duties of non-maleficence to future generations hold regardless of the

individual.

In addition to non-maleficence, Wenz also extends duties related to justice and reparation

to future generations and possible people. By assuming that the interests of all humans deserve

equal consideration, he argued that duties of justice are owed to future persons on account of

their humanity. Possible people should be considered as well, because if this were not done

“some possible people could be actualized whose benefits and burdens differ greatly from others

in their society.”525 According to Wenz, duties of reparation also extend to future and possible

people. He argued that “since the duty of reparations requires that compensatory benefits be

accorded those who have been harmed, we thus owe future and possible people new technologies

and energy sources that will enable their lives to be as good as they would have been had we not

consumed the nonrenewable resources or buried the hazardous waste in the first place.”526

Wenz’s assignment of the duties of non-maleficence to future generations seems true at

first—a time lag does not discharge responsibility for an act, for even a bullet takes some time to

reach its target—but upon more reflection it becomes more problematic. Some of the difficulty

arises due to Wenz’s problematic argument that non-existence can be compared and may be

preferable to different states of existence. His illustration of the moral intuition that possible

cases of spina bifida should be avoided, whether it be right or not, collapses important

differences between degrees of harm. The need to claim primacy for protecting the existences of

people in future generations becomes important when determining the relative stringencies of

different duties.

525 Ibid., 206. 526 Ibid., 206.

177

Moreover, assigning a non-absolute primacy to not terminating existence permits other,

less severe degrees of maleficence to be balanced by satisfied duties of beneficence. Wenz’s

conception of beneficence is an oversimplification of the more complex notion in Ross. Wenz

correctly defined the duties of benevolence as the duties to “maximize intrinsic good,”527 yet the

duty to foster the trinity of virtue, knowledge, and pleasure, along with their complexes, is

reduced shortly thereafter to the duty to “maximize total well-being”528 in an argument that

follows utilitarian reasoning. Maximizing pleasure or preference-satisfaction does not satisfy

this goal.

Though Ross said that bad things should not be brought upon others, it is still just a

conditional duty. If it is accepted that some acts lead to both benefit and harm, then some

appraisal of the benefits and harms, again, excluding termination, is necessary to determine if

justice, defined by Ross as the just distribution of intrinsic goods according to merit, has been

met. Though no quantitative analysis is possible, it seems impossible not to say that an increase

in virtue or knowledge is not worth slight discomfort for an individual, whereas no such increase

can be judged to be worth the end of his life or serious impairment by an outsider. One must

take into account the overall store of intrinsic goods, of virtue, knowledge, and pleasure, and of

their opposites, viciousness, ignorance, and pain. In addition, it will be shown that the

assessment of merit, which is rarely easy, becomes nearly impossible.

Two other challenges arise when applying duties of non-maleficence and beneficence,

and thus justice, globally and to future generations. First, most goods and harms result from

collaborative effort of a group of people, and rarely do all deserve the same amount of credit or

blame. Others may have the opportunity to halt a project, even though they are not active

527 Ibid., 206. 528 Ibid., 207.

178

participants in it. Still others may have been influential in creating the conditions in which the

project took place. The difficulty of assigning responsibility in such situations is called the

problem of many hands.

Second, the problem of assigning agency has its counterpart in the inability to know who

the patients will be. This affliction affects contemporaries to a degree. For future generations,

the time lag between act and effect makes it is impossible to know which individuals and groups

will be harmed in the future, or even if anyone will be harmed, because they do not exist yet.

The problems arising from the temporal distance between the act and the possible harm is clear

when reparations are considered. Accepting a properly complex understanding of non-

maleficence and beneficence, it seems impossible to judge whether the general “states of mind”

are worse, and reparations are required, much less to determine who is deserving and how to

transfer different benefits. The same difficulties are found in the assignment of merit.

Ross’s attention to the “social and economic system” in which injustices may arise,

though, suggests that a structuralist assessment may be possible, and if the inertia and the

inherited impact of these systems are considered, one may construct duties to people far removed

in space and time. Ross’s secondary concern about the optimific, a measure of overall well-

being that is not to be disregarded even if it does not have the same importance or always

coincide with the right, suggests that taking structuralist concerns into account is appropriate.

Accepting the structuralist perspective is necessary to shift from duties of the individual to duties

of society, to shift from ethics to politics, a shift in which the individual may not have the moral

potency to transform goodness into right, even given the proper judgment. Yet even this step is

not sufficient. One of Ross’s criticisms of the “ideal utilitarian” is that it does not discriminate

against individuals when a duty is owed to some but not others, and this same problem afflicts

179

Ross when applied to future generations. A more sophisticated sense of justice is necessary to

deal with future generations and possible people.

Duties of fidelity and gratitude only affect future generations indirectly because it is not

possible for them to earn increased consideration when duties conflict. For far-flung

contemporaries, the duties of fidelity that deserves top priority are interpersonal agreements with

an international scope, because they are entered into voluntarily by the individual, followed by

treaties and other agreements made by nation-states. Duties of gratitude, similarly, may exist on

an interpersonal level today, and have corporate manifestations in the relations between nation-

states. Economic, intellectual, environmental or military support that one state has provided for

another may affect the right act to do in a particular situations. Duties of self-improvement,

which apply only to the individual, obviously do not affect future generations or the global

citizenry.

Duties of non-maleficence, and above all, the obligation for maintaining existence,

should be given priority when considering global citizens and future persons. Yet given the

problem of many hands and the uncertainty inherent in technological projects and our lack of

predictive powers of the environmental responses and their affects on humans, any kind of

justice seems to be more a function of luck than reason, a limitation that Ross admitted even

without taking such complications into account. In such cases, moral goodness, which depends

on desires, emotions, and dispositions, becomes more important than moral rightness.

Extension to Organisms. While neither EE nor RPT/Techné provides much guidance on how

non-human living beings should be considered in the prima facie duties, Ross himself provided

minimal guidance on sentient animals. As mentioned earlier, he noted that while animals cannot

have rights, they can possess or be dispossessed of the intrinsic good of pleasure, which implies

180

at least a duty of limited non-maleficence and beneficence to them. While two divisions of

duties, the duties of fidelity, whose linguistic foundation only obligates humans, and the self-

referential duties of self-improvement, which can only be possessed by a moral agent, have

nothing to do with animals, the other divisions deserve a closer look. The section concludes with

a brief reflection on the more limited obligations owed to non-sentient organisms.

The fundamental duties owed to sentient non-humans are duties of non-maleficence. A

prima facie duty to neither end the existence of or inflict pain upon other sentient beings is

consistent with Ross’s theory. The obligation is more binding for sentient beings whose

cognitive capabilities approach those of humans, for it is commonly held that higher levels of

consciousness experience suffering in more profound and enduring ways, and less binding for

simpler organisms. Since harm can be done, the duties of reparation also hold, at least in cases

in which the sentient being that was harmed still exists. A duty satisfied by therapeutic surgery

or pain management for an animal that was injured as the result of human actions, especially if

they are intentional, may also arise. For animals that are intentionally killed, the duty requires

the agents to seek to minimize the pain of the animal.

Whether duties of reparations are transferred to other members of the community, to

other members in an animal’s genetic line, or to the species as a whole, is much murkier. The

simplest case seems to be animals that form relational bonds with other animals that were broken

without good reason. It seems reasonable that humans have the obligation to provide other

opportunities for the animals who lost a companion to have opportunities to form new relational

bonds. Unlike the case with humans, it does not seem that any duty of reparation can survive a

death and be satisfied by an act that increases the pleasure or decreases the pain of another

sentient being in the sufferer’s genetic line, except when the genetic health of a species is

181

considerably improved by such an effort, a condition which is rarely known. Even in this case,

though, reparation is blurred with beneficence. Since Ross focused on the act that was

accomplished, not the motivation, the latter seems to be a better descriptor. The same problem

with calling an act a reparation to another individual in a genetic line applies to the species as a

whole. Such shortcomings seem to sever the common association between reparation and

restoration in cases of habitat degradation and destruction. Habitat restoration is further

complicated because it includes sentient, non-sentient, and abiotic elements. I address these

topics in more detail in the section on stringency.

The duties of beneficence are less binding to sentient beings than the duties of non-

maleficence are. Most clearly, as I noted earlier, there is no good reason not seek to ensure that

animals experience pleasure, all other things being equal, which seems to be true for domestic

and wild animals. While animals are not moral agents, which makes virtue inapplicable, a non-

moral excellence can be developed, at least for domesticated animals. Pet owners seem to have

some responsibility to make sure that the animals are given instruction to keep them from hurting

other animals, including humans, with some qualifications, and to fulfill appropriate needs for

humans. On this last point, I am thinking of seeing eye dogs. By understanding merit as an

excellence, rather than by limiting it to moral virtue, the duties of justice also hold some claim on

an individual moral agent. He or she can distribute pleasure or further training in a manner that,

absent an invocation of justice, would be considered unjust. To understand knowledge as an

intrinsic good for animals requires a redefinition of knowledge or at least a more sophisticated

approach to intrinsic and instrumental value in animals than I can provide.

Duties of gratitude are also pertinent for sentient beings, claim that is true even if one

holds a strong anthropocentrist position. Animals increase the pleasure many experience.

182

Pleasure can arise from aesthetic appreciation, such as what birders pursue, in the relational

affection given by domesticated animals, or in the wonder evoked by encounters with

charismatic megafauna. Their observation can contribute to a better understanding of what our

surroundings consist of and how they function, an increase in knowledge that can be passed

down to future generations. Our interactions with them can also provoke a self-knowledge that

has intrinsic value. They also indirectly provide pleasure through their participation in the web

of ecosystem services that keep humans (as well as other animals and other organisms) alive.

The only relevant duties that I recognize toward non-sentient organisms are those of non-

maleficence. For these beings, the prohibition against inflicting pain does not make sense, but

the organism can be harmed if it no longer exists. Each existence has some value, but the claim

for non-sentient organisms is a far weaker claim than the one that arises from the existence of

sentient beings. A stronger duty can be assigned to non-sentience beings, say, for one who

adopts the reasoned claim made by Hans Jonas that “the organic even in its lowest forms

prefigures mind, and that mind even on its highest reaches remains part of the organic.”529 If this

position is adopted, a duty of gratitude may arise to non-sentient beings that are still somehow

connected with all other beings.

The nuance provided by Ross’s prima facie duties aligns with commonly held moral

intuitions for interaction between humans and non-humans. One can argue that one can and

should value all living beings without being forced into the conclusions that Paul Taylor reached

when extending Kantian to duties toward animals.530 An appeal to relevant duties permits giving

priority to humans over animals without giving humans carte blanche. Among different species

529 Hans Jonas, The Phenomenon of Life: Toward a Philosophical Biology (Evanston, Illinois:

Northwestern University Press, 2001), 1. 530 Paul W. Taylor, Respect for Nature: A Theory of Environmental Ethics (Princeton: Princeton University

Press, 1986).

183

of animals, we can prioritize those that have higher cognitive abilities. Ross’s duties give us

reason to protect monkeys while eradicating mosquitos, though how to extend such concerns

beyond individuals to genetic lines or species is not immediately obvious.

Extension to Artifacts. According to Ross, the value of material objects is instrumental. The

objects themselves have no states of mind, so they cannot experience any of the three simple

intrinsic goods or their complexes. Ross noted that most clearly, material objects result in

pleasure, one of the three simple intrinsic goods. Pleasure arises in many ways such as through

the convenience, comfort, aesthetic enjoyment, and experiences they make possible or intensify.

They directly and indirectly satisfy basic material needs of food and shelter, which is a way of

supporting the existence of others, the most fundamental sense of beneficence or non-

maleficence. Material things are the objects of a great deal of knowledge, whether rigorously

obtained through the scientific method or through less formal observation, especially in the

present epoch of technoscience. The often unintended consequences, such as pollution and

habitat degradation, are understood as maleficence, and their possibility led Jonas to promote a

new categorical imperative: “Act so that the effects of your action are compatible with the

permanence of genuine human life.”531

Duties of gratitude and fidelity often arise from the creation or use of material things,

which are also commonly used to satisfy those duties. Especially when harm is physical,

reparations are often satisfied by transferring material things. Distributive justice deals

primarily with material things. In all of these cases, material objects are merely the means by

which duties are satisfied, and the obligation is always owed to a being.

531 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for a Technological Age (Chicago:

University of Chicago Press, 1984), 11.

184

Most interestingly for this project, Ross also noted that some virtues depend on material

things. The context of Ross’s claim that “virtue owes many of its opportunities to the existence

of material conditions of good and material hindrances to good” makes evident that he is simply

claiming that it is necessary for material goods to exist for virtues to be practiced.532 He only

hypothetically granted some duty toward the historic house mentioned earlier. Duties that appear

to be owed to the house are actually owed to contemporaries and future generations, whose

pleasure or knowledge can be said to be increased above what they would have been had the

owner allowed the house to fall into disrepair. It is not at all clear how one can have a duty to

ancestors in Ross’s framework, even though he suggests the possibility, unless ancestors retain

states of mind after they die.

When Ross’s theories are applied to contemporary life, two shortcomings are noticed.

This is unsurprising, for The Right and the Good and Foundations of Ethics were both written in

the 1930s, when technological tools and a technological way of understanding the world were

not as prevalent. Both books also predate philosopher Martin Heidegger’s “Question

Concerning Technology,” sociologist Jacques Ellul’s la technique, and historian-turned-critic of

technology Lewis Mumford’s work by two decades. The first shortcoming is that Ross treated

the material environment as one that simply existed, not one that is actively and reactively

shaped by humans, a position expressed clearly by scholars who attend to the social construction

of technology.

The position that technology is socially constructed, rather than determined, gained

prominence in the 1980s, first through Wiebe E. Bijker and Trevor J. Pinch’s study on the

evolution of bicycles. Rather than arising from progression toward an objective standard, they

showed how relevant social groups determined the specifications that became commonly

532 Ross, Right and the Good, 141.

185

accepted.533 Bruno Latour proposed actor-network theory to conceptualize interactions between

humans, non-human natural beings, and artifacts.534 Latour proposed that a network better

captures the interrelatedness between “actants” than linear causal chains do, and it collapses a

strict separation between subject and object and agent and patient that are common contemporary

thought. Building off the work of earlier social constructivists and Michel Foucault, Peter-Paul

Verbeek has developed the moral dimension of this line of thought, arguing that moral analysis

should take into account human-technology associations rather than considering humans as

individual moral actors, separate from their artifacts.535

The second shortcoming of Ross’s theory arises from the first. Ross’s view is that

artifacts, along with other material objects, create the necessary conditions for some virtues, is

correct but not complete: a more sophisticated inquiry reveals that not all artifacts contribute to

goodness in the same way, that some artifacts tend to inspire virtue and others increase vice

among their users. Ross usually makes no finer delineation between the “intellectual and moral

virtues” in either of his books on his ethical theory. If nothing else, consideration of how the

traditional virtues apply in the contemporary setting is necessary. I argue that conventional

virtues need to be buttressed with communicative or ecological virtues that accord with the

contemporary setting.

Some Contemporary Techno-Environmental Virtues

While Ross’s ethical theory would have been improved if he offered additional details

about the intellectual and moral virtues he advocated, it is unlikely that he would have identified

533 Trevor J. Pinch and Wiebe E. Bijker, “The Social Construction of Facts and Artifacts: Or How the

Sociology of Science and the Sociology of Technology Might Benefit Each Other,” in The Social Construction of Technological Systems, edited by Wiebe E. Bijker, Thomas P. Hughes, and Trevor J. Pinch (Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press, 1987).

534 Bruno Latour, Science in Action (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1987). 535 Peter-Paul Verbeek, Moralizing Technology: Understanding and Designing the Morality of Things

(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2011).

186

the virtues proposed in this section, largely because he paid much less attention to how things,

natural and artifactual, shape the ground on which we assess and act. Yet given the importance

he placed on virtue, the greatest of intrinsic goods, I think it likely that he would consider how

virtue relates to artifacts were he alive today. From Albert Borgmann, a frequent contributor to

RPT/Techné, I borrow the guidance that can be found by focal practices and things. From

Shannon Vallor, I take three communicative virtues that seem to be in shorter supply now. I also

propose three new virtues attuned to the technological society in which we live.

Borgmann offered some guidance for designers, producers, and users of technology in his

critique of the device paradigm and his advocacy of focal events and practices. He is especially

relevant to my inquiry since his work and the responses to it have been cited in the introduction

to Technology and the Good Life? by Eric Higgs, Andrew Light, and David Strong as the locus

around which the specialization of philosophy of technology developed. The editors note that

Borgmann “addresses questions of nature and environment, rather than restricting reform of

technology to built space and artifacts, thus exceeding the traditional purview of the field.”536

His work, like this project, blends philosophy of technology with environmental philosophy,

though the latter is rudimentary.

Borgmann offered a Heideggerian-inspired critique of the “device paradigm.” Heidegger

was concerned with the hidden yet prevalent en-framing that technology enabled and

encouraged, which excluded dimensions of human existence that were not quantifiable and

controllable. A technological perspective led first to seeing all things of the world as standing

reserve, and finally to seeing other humans, and then one’s self, as the same. According to

536 Eric Higgs, Andrew Light, and David Strong, eds. Technology and the Good Life? (Chicago: University

of Chicago Press, 2000), 12.

187

Borgmann, the fundamental difference between modern technology and premodern technology is

seen as the difference in devices and things.537

Compare the features of an iPod, a device, to a saxophone, a thing. The production of

devices is severed from their sale and use. They are commodified, a term Borgmann used to

describe the disruption of social, temporal, and spatial continuities that accompany devices. The

manufacture of the iPod itself is a discontinuous enterprise, occurring in China, Taiwan, and the

Phillipines.538 The people that sell iPods are separated from the people who make them, and few

of the people who make them purchase them or are in contact with their users. Devices are

interchangeable, designed to function regardless of their surroundings. Their performance

demands no skill on the part of their users. They share many of the same attributes of machines

as described by Ellul, which was discussed in the previous chapter.

Things, on the contrary, respect the continuities in which humans, non-humans, and their

artifacts co-exist. They demand skill and engagement of their users. A saxophone in the hands

of someone without training is useless, and it is useless when the user is not employing his or her

skill. The value of the saxophone, moreover, can be amplified in its setting and by collaboration

with other musicians, e.g., when employed as part of a jazz quartet.

Things tend to lead us to what Borgmann calls focal events and practices, which differ

from the “off-the-shelf,” “plug-and-play” experiences that devices make possible, and Borgmann

claims that the richer experience of things is more rewarding and has greater value than what can

be derived from utilizing devices. Borgmann illustrated focal events and practices by contrasting

a run through a natural area, which connects the runner to his or her environment, perhaps

537 “Thing” is a somewhat unfortunate word choice in English. Though it reflects a certain simplicity, its

generic nature tends to ignore the important attributes that make things different. 538 Hal R. Varian, “Who Really Makes the iPod?” New York Times, June 28, 2007. nytimes.com, accessed

February 14, 2015.

188

offering observations of animals to an observant eye, with a run on the treadmill, and by

contrasting a Roman-length dinner with a thoughtfully crafted guest list and ingredients carefully

selected and prepared, sourced locally when possible, to a meal available at MacDonald’s.

Borgmann aimed to draw attention to the tradeoffs that accompany the use of devices, which are

often unnoticed, because artifacts shape the contours of the decisions people make.

Borgmann identified nature as a “challenge” to technology, a line of inquiry pursued by

Borgmann’s student David Strong in RPT and EE. Borgmann argued that “nature in its wildness

attains new and positive significance within the technological setting”539 because it has resisted

the “approach to reality that was based on science, developed in engineers, and primarily

practiced in factories.”540 Borgmann recognized a “universal eloquence” in nature that speaks in

defense of deictic discourse, which is excluded from a technoscientific framework for

conversation. This eloquence is summoned in the wildness poetry of Henry Bugbee, who hired

Borgmann at the University of Montana, and Borgmann concluded that “discourse of nature can

hope finally to be successful only if it abandons the conceptual outposts and bulwarks and allows

nature to speak directly and fully in one’s words.”541 It is through its experience that time and

space no longer are annihilated but rather regain their expansiveness.

Borgmann’s urge to vet technologies based on whether they contribute to virtue shares

common ground with Ross’s emphasis of virtue over pleasure. In addition, the conditional

nature of Ross’s prima facie duties works well with Borgmann’s analysis. Borgmann never

claims that devices are always to be avoided, but rather, all things being equal, it is better to use a

thing such as a saxophone rather than a device such as an iPod. Neither Borgmann nor Ross give

hard-and-fast rules about when an artifact or moral situation are good or bad, but instead both

539 Borgmann, Technology and the Character, 182. 540 Ibid., 184.

189

urge the practitioner to employ practical judgment to determine the relevant features of a

particular situation.

Vallor argued that new social media tend to encourage habits that are vicious, i.e., they

interfere with Aristotelian excellence of character.542 She wrote that Aristotle’s traditional

virtues need to be supplemented with the “communicative virtues” of patience, honesty, and

empathy. The immediacy of new social media, which is one of the promises of technology in

general, and the ease of exit from challenging or unpleasant conversations discourage the

development of patience. Vallor proposed that the virtue of honesty, “the willingness to put

one’s authentic self in play,” is put at risk by the separation of the physical self and the messages

expressed by its many avatars. A similar separation occurs through many technologies, when

consequences are often far removed, temporally, spatially, and culturally, from ends. The virtue

of empathy, which has no clear antecedent in Aristotle’s writing, is also put at risk by mediated

communication for it is not purely cognitive. It has an emotional dimension that technologically

mediated dialogue often attenuates. The lack of interpersonal interaction is an analogue to a non-

existent or always mediated experience of nature. Vallor’s communicative virtues and her

assessment of new social media, which makes no categorical claims, are also congruent with

Ross’s conditional prima facie duties.

In addition to the communicative virtue developed by Vallor and the guidance of focal

activities offered by Borgmann, I propose three other virtues that must be cultivated to live well,

i.e., to be right and good. These virtues have to do with what we notice, how we act, and which

skills we develop.

541 Ibid., 187. 542 Shannon Vallor, “New Social Media and the Virtues,” in The Good Life in a Technological Age, edited

by Philip Brey, Adam Briggle, and Ed Spence (New York: Routledge, 2012), 193-202.

190

The first is an expanded version of prudence or practical judgment (phronesis), the queen

of the virtues that is the art of correctly judging what is relevant in a particular situation. In the

contemporary environment, the traditional virtues must be include a technoscientific dimension.

Technology can distort as it intermediates. As Don Ihde argued, humans must be able to

integrate and discriminate between various technologies and scientific information in order to get

a right read of the technological and ecological world. For a true read, a complete adequatio rei

et intellectus, an individual must integrate sense perception with scientific information, itself

normally technologically mediated, to make proper decisions about which technologies to

design, build, and utilize. This virtue incorporates what Jonas called a “heuristic of fear” to

properly weigh the possible but often understated or unanticipated negative consequences of

technology against its anticipated benefits.543

The second virtue necessary today is the skilled use of technology, the moral virtue most

closely related with the virtue of thought just described. The virtue is more important in cultures

in which technology is ubiquitous and less so in more primitive societies, though it is valuable in

almost all in which humans are homo faber. The virtue applies to technologies that require a

skilled operator, and development of the virtue requires that humans seek such tools rather than

relying simply on machines.

The third virtue that must be developed is attentive response. By attentive response, I

mean an attentiveness to the actual outcomes of technological projects, which can vary from

expectations, coupled with the appropriate response when deviations are encountered.

Deviations are often missed or characterized as anomalies because the planning and

implementation phases of a technological project fix an expected result in the mind. By this, I

also mean having an attentive disposition to ecological issues, matched by the capabilities, as

543 Jonas, Imperative of Responsibility, 26.

191

best as one can possess, to respond in a proper way when ecosystems are disturbed. This virtue

attempts to reintegrate the natural actants in Latour’s actor-network theory that are absent from

Verbeek’s human-technology hybrids, and it extends Ross’s analysis beyond systems to include

the same actants in an interrelated web. The virtue encapsulates the dual senses of care, toward

natural and artificial objects, that are fused by Terri Field,544 and includes an action, not just a

disposition.

I have grouped Ross’s duties into three levels based on his preferences.545 The first is the

general duty to non-maleficence, which should generally be considered a litmus test for whether

an act is right or not. The second level consists of fidelity, reparations, and gratitude. Such

duties depend on specific acts, so they trump the more general obligations of the third level. The

duty of fulfilling a promise generally trumps a duty of beneficence, even if the person to whom a

promise is owed would benefit more if some other act were completed. The third level includes

duties to self-improvement, beneficence, and justice. It seems to me that beneficence, at least the

pursuit of knowledge and virtue, and self-improvement deserve a slight preference over the

obligation to justice due to the additional complexity of justice, which depends on an accurate

assessment of merit, often over a number of individuals. Pleasure should occupy the lowest

position on this level. These levels apply first and foremost to a tier that includes present and

future humans.

The second tier includes concern for sentient beings, with concern offered on a spectrum

from most to least cognitive ability. The relation of the human tier to the sentient being tier

depends on one’s environmental perspective. A strong anthropocentrist using Ross’s scheme

would place it below pleasure. A weak anthropocentrist would likely place it somewhere along

544 Terri Field, “Caring Relationships with Natural and Artificial Environments,” EE 17, no. 3 (Fall 1995):

307-320, doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199517320.

192

the second or third levels, i.e., they would generally keep their promises to other humans even if

the life of some animal were at stake, but they would not usually value human pleasure over an

animal’s existence. A biocentrist would position it even with the human tier. Generally, priority

should be given to the welfare of individuals, who can enjoy pleasure or pain, rather than

species, though species welfare, including population and genetic well-being, can be considered

as a second-order concern and overall ecosystem health a third order concern.

The third tier includes abiotic things, which includes natural and artifactual beings, which

are unworthy of concern per se. The former deserve respect insofar as they contribute to the

well-being of humans or other living beings, and the latter deserve concern insofar as they

contribute instrumentally to the welfare of humans, especially when they lead to virtue or

knowledge, and other living beings.

The preceding illustrates the upsides and downsides of using Ross’s framework, which

allows the relative weight of different obligations to vary based on the situation that is faced. On

one hand, this flexibility allows one to explain why ecosystem or planetary health may trump

other concerns. On the other hand, the principles do not allow for a deductive defense of specific

policies or decisions, especially for those that consider non-human welfare. Having said that,

however, I believe that many people would make better decisions or judgments were they to take

the different duties and tiers of duties into account, even if they are not forced to. The composite

system also takes into account the broader ecologies—a term derived from Greek oikos,

household or family—which includes organisms, abiotic elements, and artifacts in which humans

operate in a way that most other ethical theories do not.

Fused with Ross’s prima facie duties, the traditional and newly proposed virtues offer a

relatively comprehensive ethical theory that can address the issues associated with the

545 Ross, Right and the Good, 26-28.

193

technoscientific culture common in most industrialized countries today, though it cannot address

all of them. Most problematic seems to be the difficulty of incorporating concern for species and

ecosystem health into Ross’s agent-oriented framework. At best a weak justification can be

made for preserving natural areas. Yet without the possibility of such experiences, what David

Strong called “disclosive discourse” with nature cannot take place, and its “universal eloquence,”

to use Albert Borgmann’s term, goes unperceived. It is through such experiences that the prima

facie duties and their binding force are grasped. Finally, the emphasis that Ross puts on “states

of mind” lends itself to a perplexing assessment of restoration.

194

CHAPTER 7

EPILOGUE

I put the concepts and tools of social epistemology to use to construct a mapping of the

individuals and ideas that have overlapped in the pages of RPT/Techné and Environmental

Ethics, two long running, prestigious journals. Such an effort was necessary because the

specializations of philosophy of technology and environmental philosophy, even though they

were birthed at the same time, have developed without much cross-pollination despite the fact

that the concepts and principles behind them are interrelated. Philosophical efforts can provide

clarity to the cacophony of voices used in public discourse, yet it has been largely lacking to

date. This work is one contribution to the intellectual tapestry, and one that shows the rough

outline of points of intersection and areas in which a counterpart may be missing.

The constellations charted in the third and fourth chapters can be mapped according to

the following figure.

Ch. 3: Nature (Physis) in RPT/Techné Ch. 4: Technology (Techné) in EE Nature Seen Historically Techné Seen Historically

At the Intersection of Nature and Techné Making and the Natural World Science, Technology, and Nature Science, Technology,

Technoscience, and Nature Religion and Transcendence Religion and Transcendence

Politics and Policy Aesthetics of Artworks

Figure 2. Correlation of Constellations in RPT/Techné and EE.

The constellations were allowed to arise naturally based on a survey of the articles, rather than

trying to fit them into a metaphysics/ontology/epistemology/ethics/politics schema or something

similar. The term constellation was used to indicate the weak connection between articles that

demands the viewer to project some form on the data, one that may be disputed. Clear discourse

195

lines that would be expected to arise in academic discourse, especially around a specific topic,

were rarely found within a specialization, much less between them. Efforts to use tools such as

Web of Science™ and Google Scholar™ were frustrated because the fundamental articles in

both journals predate the earliest articles indexed by the former. Moreover, RPT has not been

digitized and is not indexed. The discontinuities of the publications of the Society for

Philosophy and Technology also hindered longitudinal and cross-specialization comparison.

In spite of the lack of interaction in ideas and individuals between the specializations,

constellations found in each specialization overlap a good deal. A closer inquiry at each reveals

many interesting lines for future research, especially once the initial limitation of topics and

journals that guided this investigation is relaxed.

The historical articles in RPT/Techné included articles on the use of the term nature that

spanned Western intellectual history from the ancient Greeks and Romans to a present definition

that is experimental and severed from concerns about origins. The corresponding articles in EE

took a different tack: they had to do with the rhetoric of decline—Heidegger’s critique should

simply be considered the latest in a series of laments that stretches back to the Greeks—and how

anthropological history should be understood. In this case, even though the articles are grouped

under the same title, there is no granular overlap, and worthwhile contributions can be made in

all areas.

Articles on religion and transcendence all focused on Lynn White, Jr.’s “The Medieval

Roots of our Ecologic Crisis” article from Nature. None of the articles from either journal

complemented the quality of White’s historical interpretation: what they noted was that it had

become fixed in the cultural memory in spite of its inaccuracies, and it deserved some credit for

drawing attention to a time period that was often overlooked. Opportunities for future research

196

include a more careful look at how other world religions consider technology. Resources in

Asian religions, into which modern science and technology was adopted or transformed, may

prove fruitful. A reconstruction of the influence of Christianity, technology, and the

environment in Jewish and Christian thought that takes into account subsequent scholarship and

is not tied to a critique of White may be beneficial.

The closest connection and overlap between constellations on both sides were articles

that dealt with modern science, technoscience, or nature. This is also the area that has the best

developed discourse lines. The majority of the articles on both sides deal with Heidegger’s

critique of technology and science, or the offshoot promulgated by Albert Borgmann. The

overlap between these constellations is best suited to a specific inquiry using Randall Collins’s

approach. Such an effort can put the addendum or correction, the “yes, and” or “no, but” form of

discourse analysis to the test. A comprehensive and multifaceted view of the dialogue can likely

be constructed from the process of doing so.

There was less overlap than I expected between two of the constellations, the “At the

Intersection of Physis and Techné” in RPT/Techné and “Making and the Natural World” in EE.

Articles in RPT/Techné specifically addressed philosophical issues of technology and the

environment, motivated in part by the two theme issues mentioned above, though I view these

efforts as largely unsuccessful and rather superficial. Had they been successful, then they would

have been the departure point for my inquiry. The EE articles differed in a significant way: they

largely focused on “low church” technology, what would be called in the RPT/Techné literature

something like technics. Articles in EE raised interesting issues involving environmental art,

design and ecology, and how artifacts can influence environmental ethics by returning to the

premodern sense of craft. These veins of thought, which lack any complement on the

197

RPT/Techné side, perhaps because the distinction between premodern and modern technology is

used to explain why the latter is worthy of a different kind of philosophical reflection, seem

particularly promising for further investigation. Likewise, an explicit attempt at a philosophical

inquiry that combines physis and techné may be fecund for environmental philosophers, and I

hope that my ecumenical effort will contribute to this end.

Interestingly, RPT/Techné articles on policy and politics, including sustainability, paid

more attention to the conceptual and theoretical issues involved with nature than those on the EE

side did with technology, where technology was implicitly “black-boxed,” that is, understood

without concern about details. A monolithic understanding of technology runs counter to the

shift in the philosophy of technology literature, which has increasingly focused on the details of

particular technologies in order to generate an appropriately sophisticated analysis of the

technologies. The focus on specifics, away from technology with a capital “T,” has been called

the empirical turn.

While EE lacked a sophisticated sense of technology in its discussion of politics and

policy, it possessed an interesting vein of articles that connect aesthetics of artifacts and nature

arose that had no cross-specialization corollary in RPT/Techné. My sense is that this is one area

in which the discontinuity between artifacts and nature is such that attempting to generate an

RPT/Techné extension will result in little or no fruit, especially since the understanding of the

world as a machine has generally been eclipsed by that of an organism.

Whereas the third and fourth chapters focused on mapping the constellations, the fourth

and fifth emphasized the points of overlap or lack thereof. Far more can be done with the basic

material on individuals who contributed to both specializations. One could look at the character

of the different articles to see how similar concerns were presented to different. A separate

198

inquiry focused on the individuals who published more than one article in each specialization

that considers their entire corpora would yield another perspective on the overlap between

environmental philosophy and philosophy of technology. The list of individuals whose articles

to RPT/Techné found in Appendix B can contribute to an analysis that is broader than what was

attempted by me here. I nod to the institutions that supported the dual contributors, especially

since both specializations struggled to gain legitimacy, but this information deserves a more

systematic analysis.

I responded to the lack of overlap found between the journals with the riff that begins

with Ellul’s RPT article as an example to show how dialectical thinking between the

specializations can take place when the specializations, and by evaluating W. D. Ross’s ethical

theory as a comprehensive ethic that can fuse environmental, technological, and traditional

ethical concerns. These original efforts are first steps in what is hopefully a long journey for

myself and others who wish to delve into such topics.

The topical overviews that I crafted in the third and fourth chapters should enhance the

self-understanding of both specializations, and the inquiry as a whole may point out some

opportunities for further research. To the degree that my approach was adequate, it depended on

the role of journals in the late 1970s until the present. As the number of journals has

proliferated, the amount of information tends to lead to more specialized inquiries, a trend that

runs opposite to the synthesis at which I aimed. It will be interesting to see how these changes

shape academic inquiries over the next academic generation of these specializations and whether

they regain a broader perspective and a public voice.

199

APPENDIX A

VOLUMES AND EDITORS OF RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY/TECHNÉ

200

Research in Philosophy and Technology

1978-1985, Series Editor Paul T. Durbin

Vol. 1 (1978). Greenwich, Connecticut: JAI Press.

Vol. 2 (1979). Greenwich, Connecticut: JAI Press.

Vol. 3 (1980). Greenwich, Connecticut: JAI Press.

Vol. 4 (1981). Current Bibliography in the Philosophy of Technology: 1975-1976. Compiled by

Carl Mitcham. Greenwich, Connecticut: JAI Press.

Vol. 5 (1982). Greenwich, Connecticut: JAI Press.

Vol. 6 (1983). Greenwich, Connecticut: JAI Press.

Vol. 7 (1984). Greenwich, Connecticut: JAI Press.

Supplement 1 (1984). Jacques Ellul: A Comprehensive Bibliography. Compiled by Joyce Main

Hanks. Greenwich, Connecticut: JAI Press.

Vol. 8 (1985). Greenwich, Connecticut: JAI Press.

1988-1994, Series Editor Frederick Ferré

Supplement 2 (1988). Paul Levinson’s Mind at Large: Knowing in the Technological Age.

Greenwich, Connecticut: JAI Press.

Vol. 9 (1989). Ethics and Technology. Guest editor Carl Mitcham. Greenwich, Connecticut: JAI

Press.

Vol. 10 (1990). Theme: Technology and Religion. Greenwich, Connecticut: JAI Press.

Vol. 11 (1991). Theme: Technology and Politics. Greenwich, Connecticut: JAI Press.

Vol. 12 (1992). Theme: Technology and the Environment. Greenwich, Connecticut: JAI Press.

201

Vol. 13 (1993). Theme: Technology and Feminism. Guest editor Joan Rothschild. Greenwich,

Connecticut: JAI Press.

Vol. 14 (1994). Theme: Technology and Everyday Life. Guest editor George Allan. Greenwich,

Connecticut: JAI Press.

1995-2002, Series Editor Carl Mitcham

Vol. 15 (1995). Social and Philosophical Constructions of Technology. Greenwich, Connecticut:

JAI Press.

Supplement 3 (1995). Leonard J. Waks’s Technology’s School: The Challenge to Philosophy.

Greenwich, Connecticut: JAI Press.

Vol. 16 (1997). Technology and Social Action. Greenwich, Connecticut: JAI Press.

Vol. 17 (1998). Technology, Ethics, and Culture. Greenwich, Connecticut: JAI Press.

Vol. 18 (1999). Philosophies of the Environment and Technology. Guest editors Marina Paola

Banchetti-Robino, Don E. Marietta, Jr., and Lester Embree. Greenwich, Connecticut: JAI

Press.

Supplement 4 (1999). Noel Gray’s Stains on the Screen: The Geometric Imaginary and Its

Contaminative Process, with a Design Bibliography by Gerhard Banse. Greenwich,

Connecticut: JAI Press.

Vol. 19 (2000). Metaphysics, Epistemology, and Technology. New York: JAI, an Imprint of

Elsevier Science.

Vol. 20 (2001). The Empirical Turn in the Philosophy of Technology. Guest editors Peter Kroes

and Anthony Meijers. New York: JAI, an Imprint of Elsevier Science.

202

Vol. 21 (2002). Sport Technology: History, Philosophy and Policy. Guest editors Andy Miah and

Simon B. Eassom. New York: JAI, an Imprint of Elsevier Science.

Philosophy and Technology

1983-1994, Series Editor Paul T. Durbin

Vol. 1 (1983). Philosophy and Technology. Edited by Paul T. Durbin and Friedrich Rapp.

Originally published as Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 80. Dordrecht:

Kluwer.

Vol. 2 (1986). Philosophy and Technology II: Information Technology and Computers in Theory

and Practice. Edited by Carl Mitcham and Alois Hunning. Originally published as

Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 90. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

Vol. 3 (1987). Technology and Responsibility. Papers from the 1985 SPT Conference at the

University of Twente. Edited by Paul T. Durbin. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1987.

Vol. 4 (1988). Technology and Contemporary Life. Papers from the 1985 SPT Conference in

Twente.. Edited by Paul T. Durbin. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1988.

Vol. 5 (1989). Technological Transformation: Contextual and Conceptual Implications. Papers

from the 1987 Technology Transfer and the Third World conference at Virginia Tech..

Edited by Edmund F. Byrne and Joseph C. Pitt. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1989.

Vol. 6 (1990). Philosophy and Technology: Practical, Historical, and Other Dimensions. Edited

by Paul T. Durbin. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1989.

Vol. 7 (1990). Broad and Narrow Interpretations of Philosophy of Technology. Edited by Paul

T. Durbin. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1990.

203

Vol. 8 (1991). Europe, America, and Technology: Philosophical Perspectives. Includes papers

from a 1990 symposium on Ivan Illich at the Pennsylvania State University and some

supported by an NSF grant on "Basic Research on Ethics and Values Education in

Science and Technology.” Edited by Paul T. Durbin. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1991.

Vol. 9 (1992). Democracy in a Technological Society. Includes papers from a 1989 Society for

Philosophy and Technology conference in Bordeaux, France. Edited by Langdon Winner.

Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1992.

Vol. 10 (1993). Philosophy of Technology in Spanish Speaking Countries. A collection of

translations and some new papers. Edited by Carl Mitcham. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1993.

Vol. 11 (1994). New Directions in the Philosophy of Technology. Papers from the 1991 SPT

Conference in Mayaguez, Puerto Rico. Edited by Joseph C. Pitt. Dordrecht: Kluwer,

1995.

Journal of the Society for Philosophy and Technology

1995-1997, Series Editor Paul T. Durbin

Vol. 1, no. 1/2 (Fall 1995). Symposium: Philosophy and Technology after Twenty Years/Papers

from 1993 Peniscola (Spain) Meeting. Electronic quarterly.

Vol. 1, no. 3/4 (Spring 1996). Papers from Valencia, Spain, and Hoftstra University biennial

conferences. Electronic quarterly.

Vol. 2, no. 1 (Fall 1996). Electronic quarterly.

Vol. 2, no. 2 (Winter 1996). Papers from Ninth International Conference of SPT (Puebla,

Mexico). Electronic quarterly.

Vol. 2, no. 3/4 (Spring-Summer 1997). Electronic quarterly.

204

1997-1999, Series Editor Pieter Tijmes

Vol. 3, no. 1 (Fall 1997). Dutch Chandeliers of Philosophy of Technology. Electronic quarterly.

Vol. 3, no. 2 (Winter 1997). Papers from Dusseldorf Meeting. Electronic quarterly.

Vol. 3, no. 3 (Spring 1998). Electronic quarterly.

Vol. 3, no. 4 (Summer 1998). Electronic quarterly.

Vol. 4, no. 1 (Fall 1998). Papers from International Academy of the Philosophy of Science,

Karlsruhe, Germany 1997 Meeting. Guest editors Evandro Agazzi and Hans Lenk.

Electronic quarterly.

Vol. 4, no. 2 (Winter 1998). Papers from International Academy of the Philosophy of Science,

Karlsruhe, Germany 1997 Meeting. Guest editors Evandro Agazzi and Hans Lenk.

Electronic quarterly.

Vol. 4, no. 3 (Spring 1999). Papers from International Academy of the Philosophy of Science,

Karlsruhe, Germany 1997 Meeting. Guest editors Evandro Agazzi and Hans Lenk.

Electronic quarterly.

Vol. 4, no. 4 (Summer 1999). Papers from International Academy of the Philosophy of Science,

Karlsruhe, Germany 1997 Meeting. Guest editors Evandro Agazzi and Hans Lenk.

Electronic quarterly.

Techné: Journal of the Society for Philosophy and Technology

2000-2003, Series Editor Davis Baird

Vol. 5, no. 1 (Fall 2000). Joseph C. Pitt's Thinking about Technology: Foundations of the

Philosophy of Technology. Guest editor Paul T. Durbin. Electronic journal.

Vol. 5, no. 2 (Winter 2000). Electronic journal.

205

Vol. 5, no. 3 (Spring 2001). Electronic journal.

Vol. 6, no. 1 (Fall 2002). Albert Borgmann's Holding On to Reality. Guest editor Phil Mullins.

Electronic journal.

Vol. 6, no. 2 (Winter 2002). Understanding Technological Function: Introduction to the special

issue on the Dual Nature programme. Guest editor Sven Ove Hansson. Electronic

journal.

Vol. 6, no. 3 (Spring 2003). Electronic journal.

Vol. 7, no. 1 (Fall 2003). Larry Hickman's Philosophical Tools for Technological Culture. Guest

editor Paul T. Durbin. Electronic journal.

Techné: Research in Philosophy and Technology

2003-2007, Series Editor Davis Baird

Vol. 7, no. 2 (Winter 2003). Electronic journal.

Vol. 7, no. 3 (Spring 2004). Special Collection: Pragmatist Ethics in the Technological Age.

Guest editor Jozef Keulartz. Electronic journal.

Vol. 8, no. 1 (Fall 2004). Research in Ethics and Engineering. Guest editor Michiel Brumsen &

Sabine Roeser. Electronic journal.

Vol. 8, no. 2 (Winter 2004). Electronic journal.

Vol. 8, no. 3 (Spring 2005). Nanotech Challenges, Part 1. Guest editors Davis Baird and

Joachim Schummer. Electronic journal.

Vol. 9, no. 1 (Fall 2005). Education and Citizenship in the Digital Age. Guest editors Darin

Barney and Aaron Gordon. Electronic journal.

Vol. 9, no. 2 (Winter 2005). Electronic journal.

206

Vol. 9, no. 3 (Spring 2006). Citizenship Engagement and Biotechnology. Guest editors David

Castle. Electronic journal.

Vol. 10, no. 1 (Fall 2006). Electronic journal.

Vol. 10, no. 2 (Winter 2006). Paul T. Durbin's In Search of Discourse Synthesis. Guest editor

Paul T. Durbin. Electronic journal.

Vol. 10, no. 3 (Spring 2007). The Conundrum of Virtual Places. Guest editor Erik Champion.

Electronic journal.

2007-2012, Series Editor Joseph C. Pitt

Vol. 11, no. 1 (Fall 2007). Electronic journal.

Vol. 12, no. 1 (Winter 2008). Electronic journal.

Vol. 12, no. 2 (Spring 2008). Postphenomenology: Historical and Contemporary Horizons.

Guest editor Evan Selinger. Electronic journal.

Vol. 12, no. 3 (Fall 2008). Electronic journal.

Vol. 13, no. 1 (Winter 2009). Electronic journal.

Vol. 13, no. 2 (Spring 2009). Artefacts in Analytic Metaphysics. Guest editors Wybo Houkes

and Pieter Vermaas. Electronic journal.

Vol. 13, no. 3 (Fall 2009). Electronic journal.

Vol. 14, no. 1 (Winter 2010). Electronic journal.

Vol. 14, no. 2 (Spring 2010). Electronic journal.

Vol. 14, no. 3 (Fall 2010). Electronic journal.

Vol. 15, no. 1 (Winter 2011). Electronic journal.

Vol. 15, no. 2 (Spring 2011). Electronic journal.

207

Vol. 15, no. 3 (Fall 2011). Phenomenology and Classroom Computer Simulation. Electronic

journal.

Vol. 16, no. 1 (Winter 2012). Feminism, Autonomy & Reproductive Technology. Electronic

journal.

Vol. 16, no. 2 (Spring 2012). Electronic journal.

Vol. 16, no. 3 (Fall 2012). Electronic journal.

208

APPENDIX B

ARTICLES IN RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY AND TECHNOLOGY/TECHNÉ, 1979-2014,

BY CONTRIBUTOR

209

Abram, David. "Nature at Arm's Length." RPT 15 (1995): 177-180.

Achterhuis, Hans J. "Borgmann, Technology and the Good Life? and the Empirical Turn for

Philosophy of Technology." Techné: JSPT 6 (2002): 64-75.

––––––. "The Courage to Be a Cyborg." RPT 17 (1998): 9-24.

Ackerman, Frank. "Environmental Impacts of Packaging in the USA and Mexico." JSPT 2

(1996): 57-64.

Agassi, Joseph. "Political Philosophy and Its Implications for Technology." RPT 7 (1984): 193-

210.

––––––. "Shifting from Physical to Social Technology." RPT 1 (1978): 199-212.

––––––. "Technology as Both Art and Science." RPT 6 (1983): 55-63.

––––––. "Technology Transfer to Poor Nations." Technological Transformation: Contextual and

Conceptual Implications. P&T 5 (1999): 277-283.

––––––. "Technology, Mass Movements, and Rapid Social Change: A Program for the Future of

Philosophy of Technology." RPT 1 (1978): 53-64.

Agazzi, Evandro. "From Technique to Technology: The Role of Modern Science." JSPT 4

(1998): 80-85.

Agazzi, Evandro and Hans Lenk. "Advances in the Philosophy of Technology: Proceedings of a

Meeting of the International Academy of the Philosophy of Science, Karlsruhe, Germany,

May 1997." JSPT 4 (1998): 1-3.

Agich, George F. "Biomedical Research, Policy, and Philosophy." RPT 3 (1980): 39-51.

Aibar, Eduardo. "The Evaluative Relevance of Social Studies of Technology." JSPT 1 (1996):

85-90.

210

––––––. "Technological Frames in a Town Planning Controversy: Why We Do Not Have to

Drop Constructivism to Avoid Political Abstinence." RPT 15 (1995): 3-20.

al-Hibri, Azizah. "Reproductive Technology and the Future of Women: A Feminist Perspective."

RPT 7 (1984): 255-270.

Alexander, Thomas. "The Technology of Desire: John Dewey, Social Criticism, and the

Aesthetics of Human Existence." Europe, America, and Technology: Philosophical

Perspectives. P&T 8 (1991): 109-126.

Ali, Syed Mustafa. "Too Far, Yet Not Far Enough: A Heideggerian Response To Héctor José

Huyke's Technologies And The Devaluation Of What Is Near." Techné: JSPT 6 (2003):

148-155.

Allan, George. "Environmental Philosophizing and Environmental Activism." RPT 12 (1992):

119-127.

––––––. "Introduction." RPT 14 (1994): 3-8.

––––––. "Making the Everyday." RPT 14 (1994): 175-188.

Allchin, Douglas. "Thinking about Technology and the Technology of 'Thinking about.'"

Techné: JSPT 5 (2000): 5-11.

Alonso, Andoni, Inaki Arzoz, and Nicanor Ursua. "Critical Remarks on Rural Architecture and

Town Planning in the Basque Country: The Case of Navarre, 1964-1994." JSPT 2 (1996):

11-17.

––––––. "Reflections on Architecture: Vernacular and Academic Modes in Architecture and

Town Planning." JSPT 2 (1996): 3-10.

Alvarez, Adelaida Ambrogi. "Sociological Studies and Philosophical Studies: Twenty Years of

Controversy.” JSPT 1 (1996): 91-106.

211

Álvarez, Asunción. "Three Memetic Theories of Technology." Techné: RPT 9 (2005).

Anderson, Albert A. "Why Prometheus Suffers: Technology and the Ecological Crisis." JSPT 1

(1995): 28-36.

Anderson, Lyle V. "Cybernetics, Culpability, and Risk: Automatic Launch and Accidental War."

Philosophy and Technology: Practical, Historical, and Other Dimensions. P&T 6 (1989):

3-25.

Andrew, Edward. "Education and the Funding of Research." Techné: RPT 9 (2005): 44-55.

Angel Quintanilla, Miguel. "The Design and Evaluation of Technologies: Some Conceptual

Issues." Philosophy of Technology in Spanish Speaking Countries. P&T 10 (1993): 173-

195.

Araya, Agustin A. "Changed Encounters with Things and Ontological Transformations: The

Case of Ubiquitous Computing." RPT 19 (2000): 3-31.

––––––. "Experiencing the World Through Interactive Learning Environments." JSPT 3 (1997):

61-74.

––––––. "The Hidden Side of Visualization." Techné: RPT 7 (2003): 74-119.

Arbulu, Jose Felix Tobar. "Plumbers, Technologists and Scientists." RPT 7 (1984): 5-17.

Arisaka, Yoko. "Modernity, Technology, and Difference." RPT 16 (1997): 145-151.

Asveld, Lotte. "Informed Consent in the Fields of Medical Technological Practice." Techné:

RPT 10 (2006): 16-29.

Baigrie, Brian S. and Patricia J. Kazan. "Biotechnology and the Creation of Health Care Needs."

JSPT 2 (1997): 113-126.

Bailey, Lee W. "Skull's Darkroom: The Camera Obscura and Subjectivity." Philosophy and

Technology: Practical, Historical, and Other Dimensions. P&T 6 (1989): 63-79.

212

Baird, Davis. "Encapsulating Knowledge: The Direct Reading Spectrometer." JSPT 3 (1998):

113-118.

––––––. "Note from Editor - on Giuseppe Del Re, Technology and the Spirit of Alchemy." JSPT

4 (1999): 220-220.

––––––. "Notes From The Editor: On Joachim Schummer, Challenging Standard Distinctions

between Science and Technology: The Case of Preparative Chemistry." JSPT 4 (1998):

141-141.

––––––. "Organic Necessity: Thinking about Thinking about Technology." Techné: JSPT 5

(2000): 12-20.

––––––. "Scientific Instrument Making, Epistemology, and the Conflict between Gift and

Commodity Economics." JSPT 2 (1997): 127-139.

––––––. "Thing Knowledge - Function and Truth." Techné: JSPT 6 (2002): 96-105.

––––––. "The Thing-Y-Ness of Things: Materiality and Spectrochemical Instrumentation, 1937-

1955." RPT 20 (2001): 99-117.

Baird, Davis and Joachim Schummer. "Editorial: Nanotech Challenges, Part I." Techné: RPT 8

(2004): 1-3.

––––––. "Editorial: Nanotech Challenges, Part II." Techné: RPT 8 (2005): 1-2.

Baker, Lynne Rudder. "The Metaphysics of Malfunction." Techné: RPT 13 (2009): 82-92.

Baldine, Joanne. "Is Human Identity an Artifact? How Some Conceptions of the Asian and

Western Self Fare During Technological and Legal Development.” JSPT 3 (1997): 75-81.

––––––. "Larry Hickman and Tuning up the Technological Culture." Techné: JSPT 7 (2003): 8-

17.

Balsamo, Anne. "The Virtual Body in Cyberspace." RPT 13 (1993): 119-139.

213

Banchetti-Robino, Marina Paola. "Hermeneutic Technics: The Case of Nuclear Reactors." RPT

18 (1999): 85-94.

––––––. "Introduction [to Philosophies of the Environment and Technology]." RPT 18 (1999): 3-

12.

Bańka, Józef. "'Euthyphronics' and the Problem of Adapting Technical Progress to Man." RPT 2

(1979): 5-14.

Barney, Darin. "Gut Feelings: A Response to Norm Friesen's 'Dissection and Stimulation.’”

Techné: RPT 15 (2011): 209-214.

––––––. "The Morning After: Citizen Engagement in Technological Society." Techné: RPT 9

(2006): 23-31.

Barney, Darin and Aaron Gordon. "Education and Citizenship in the Digital Age." Techné: RPT

9 (2005): 1-7.

Bartle, Richard. "Presence and Flow: Ill-Fitting Clothes for Virtual Worlds." Techné: RPT 10

(2007): 39-54.

Barzel, Alexander. "The Co-Relational Community and Technological Culture." Technology and

Contemporary Life. P&T 4 (1988): 45-62.

Bayertz, Kurt. "Increasing Responsibility as Technological Destiny? Human Reproductive

Technology and the Problem of Meta-Responsibility." Technology and Responsibility.

P&T 3 (1987): 135-150.

Beach, Waldo. "The Impact of the Electronic Media on American Religion." RPT 10 (1990): 71-

79.

214

Beck, Heinrich. "Bio-Social Cybernetic Determination." Philosophy and Technology II:

Information Technology and Computers in Theory and Practice. Boston Studies in the

Philosophy of Science 90. P&T 2 (1986): 85-95.

Beggs, Donald. "The Interdisciplinary Constraint on Ecological Reason." JSPT 2 (1997): 140-

144.

Beiner, Ronald. "Our Relationship to Architecture as a Mode of Shared Citizenship: Some

Arendtian Thoughts." Techné: RPT 9 (2005): 56-67.

Bella, David. "Catastrophic Possibilities of Space-Based Defense." Philosophy and Technology:

Practical, Historical, and Other Dimensions. P&T 6 (1989): 27-40.

Belu, Dana S. "Nature and Technology in Modern Childbirth: A Phenomenological

Interpretation." Techné: RPT 16 (2012): 3-15.

Bensaude-Vincent, Bernadette. "Two Cultures of Nanotechnology?” Hyle 10 (2004): 65-82.

Bensaude-Vincent, Bernadette and Xavier Guchet. "Nanomachine: One Word for Three

Different Paradigms." Techné: RPT 11 (2007): 71-89.

Benson, Ronald E. "Technological Innovation and Health Planning Policy." RPT 3 (1980): 51-

65.

Berg, Bibi Van Den. "I-Object: Intimate Technologies as 'Reference Groups' in the Construction

of Identities." Techné: RPT 14 (2010): 207-225.

Besmer, Kirk. "Embodying a Translation Technology: The Cochlear Implant and Cyborg

Intentionality." Techné: RPT 16 (2012): 296-316.

Best, Kirsty. "Redefining the Technology of Media: Actor, World, Relation." Techné: RPT 14

(2010): 140-157.

215

Biddick, Kathleen. "Stranded Histories: Feminist Allegories of Artificial Life." RPT 13 (1993):

165-182.

Binzberger, Viktor. "Hermeneutic Practices in Software Development: The Case of Ada and

Python.” Techné: RPT 13 (2009): 27-49.

Birkeland, Tore and Roger Strand. "How to Understand Nano Images." Techné: RPT 13 (2009):

182-189.

Black, Michael and Richard Worthington. "Democracy and Reindustrialization: The Politics of

Technology in New York State." RPT 8 (1985): 37-66.

Blad, Sylvia. "The Impact of ‘Anthropotechnology’ on Human Evolution." Techné: RPT 14

(2010): 72-87.

Bloodsworth, Mary. "The Implications of Consistency: Plato's Protagoras and Heidegger's 'The

Question Concerning Technology.’” RPT 19 (2000): 33-43.

Boli-Bennett, John. "The Absolute Dialectics of Jacques Ellul." RPT 3 (1980): 171-201.

Boltuc, Piotr. "The Engineering Thesis in Machine Consciousness." Techné: RPT 16 (2012):

187-207.

Bonia, Kimberly, Fern Brunger, Laura Fullerton, Chad Griffths, and Chris Kaposy. "DAKO on

Trial: A Case Study in the Politics of a Medical Controversy." Techné: RPT 16 (2012):

275-295.

Bontems, Vincent. "Gilbert Simondon’s Genetic ‘Mecanology’ and the Understanding of Laws

of Technical Evolution.” Techné: RPT 13 (2009): 1-12.

Boon, Mieke. "In Defense of Engineering Sciences: On the Epistemological Relations Between

Science and Engineering." Techné: RPT 15 (2011): 49-71.

216

Borden, Iain. "Material Matters: Skateboard Technology and the Politics of Differential Space."

RPT 21 (2002): 79-90.

Borgmann, Albert. "Artificial Intelligence and Human Personality." RPT 14 (1994): 271-283.

––––––. "Communities of Celebration: Technology and Public Life." RPT 10 (1990): 315-345.

––––––. "The Explanation of Technology." RPT 1 (1978): 99-118.

––––––. "Freedom and Determinism in a Technological Setting." RPT 2 (1979): 79-90.

––––––. "The Good Life and Appropriate Technology." RPT 6 (1983): 11-19.

––––––. "Introduction: The Development of Technology in Eastern and Western Europe."

Europe, America, and Technology: Philosophical Perspectives. P&T 8 (1991): 1-11.

––––––. "Kinds of Pragmatism." Techné: JSPT 7 (2003): 18-24.

––––––. "The Moral Assessment of Technology." Democracy in a Technological Society. P&T 9

(1992): 207-213.

––––––. "Philosophical Reflections on the Micro-electronic Revolution." Philosophy and

Technology II: Information Technology and Computers in Theory and Practice. Boston

Studies in the Philosophy of Science 90. P&T 2 (1986): 189-203.

––––––. "Postmodern Ontology." RPT 15 (1995): 223-226.

––––––. "Reply [to Stanley]." Technology and Contemporary Life. P&T 4 (1988): 29-43.

––––––. "Response to My Readers." Techné: JSPT 6 (2002): 76-85.

––––––. "Response to Norm Friesen." Techné: RPT 15 (2011): 201-202.

––––––. "Should Montana Share Its Coal? Technology and Public Policy." RPT 3 (1980): 287-

311.

––––––. "Technology and Democracy." RPT 7 (1984): 211-228.

217

––––––. "Technology and the Crisis of Liberalism: Reflections on Michael J. Sandel's Work."

Technological Transformation: Contextual and Conceptual Implications. P&T 5 (1999):

105-122.

Bos, Bram. "To What Extent Should a Critical Philosophy of Technology Be Constructivist."

RPT 20 (2001): 45-64.

Bradshaw, Leah. "Technology and Political Education." Techné: RPT 9 (2005): 8-26.

Brakel, J. van. "Appropriate Technology: Facts and Values." RPT 3 (1980): 385-402.

––––––. "Telematic Life Forms." JSPT 4 (1999): 208-219.

Braun, Ingo. "The Technology-Culture Spiral: Three Examples of Technological Developments

in Everyday Life." RPT 14 (1994): 93-118.

Brey, Philip. "New Media and the Quality of Life." JSPT 3 (1997): 4-18.

––––––. "Philosophy of Technology after the Empirical Turn." Techné: RPT 14 (2010): 36-48.

––––––. "Social Constructivism for Philosophers of Technology: A Shopper's Guide." JSPT 2

(1997).

––––––. "Technology and Embodiment in Ihde and Merleau-Ponty." RPT 19 (2000): 45-58.

––––––. "Theories of Technology as Extension of Human Faculties." RPT 19 (2000): 59-78.

––––––. "Theorizing the Cultural Quality of New Media." Techné: RPT 11 (2007): 2-18.

Broadhead, Lee-Anne and Sean Howard. "‘Two Cultures,’ One Frontier: The Drexler-Smalley

Debate on the Limits and Potential of Nanotechnology." Techné: RPT 15 (2011): 23-35.

Brockmann, Stephen. "Green without Red? The Limits of Technological Critique." RPT 13

(1993): 283-299.

Broome, Taft H., Jr. "Can Engineers Hold Public Interests Paramount?” RPT 9 (1989): 3-11.

218

––––––. "Imagination for Engineering Ethicists." Broad and Narrow Interpretations of

Philosophy of Technology. P&T 7 (1990): 45-51.

Brownstein, Michael. "The Background, the Body and the Internet: Locating Practical

Understanding in Digital Culture." Techné: RPT 15 (2011): 36-48.

Bruce, Donald M. "Polly, Dolly, Megan, and Morag: A View From Edinburgh on Cloning and

Genetic Engineering." JSPT 3 (1997): 82-91.

Brumsen, Michiel and Sabine Roeser. "Introduction [to Research in Ethics and Engineering]."

Techné: RPT 8 (2004): 1-9.

Bruzina, Ronald. "Art and Architecture, Ancient and Modern." RPT 5 (1982): 163-187.

––––––. "Commentary on Hans Jonas, Technology, and Ethics."" RPT 5 (1982): 152-159.

Bucciarelli, Louis L. "Object and Social Artifact in Engineering Design." RPT 20 (2001): 67-80.

Buell, John. "The Politics of the Common Good." RPT 11 (1991): 105-117.

Bueno, Otàvio. "The Drexler-Smalley Debate on Nanotechnology: Incommensurability at

Work?” Hyle 10 (2004): 83-98.

Bunge, Mario. "Can Science and Technology Be Held Responsible for Our Current Social Ills?”

RPT 7 (1984): 19-22.

––––––. "Development and the Environment." Technological Transformation: Contextual and

Conceptual Implications. P&T 5 (1999): 285-304.

––––––. "Ethics and Praxiology as Technologies.” JSPT 4 (1999): 221-224.

Burke, John P. "Comments on Bernard Gendron's ‘Technology, Democracy, and the Work

Place.’" RPT 5 (1982): 37-41.

Burrow, Sylvia. "Reproductive Autonomy and Reproductive Technology." Techné: RPT 16

(2012): 31-44.

219

Burt, Katrina. "The Internet - Proposing an Infrastructure for the Philosophy of Virtualness.”

Techné: RPT 13 (2009): 50-68.

Butryn, Ted. "Cyborg Horizons: Sport and the Ethics of Self-Technologizations." RPT 21

(2002): 111-133.

Byrne, Edmund. "Humanization of Technology: Slogan or Ethical Imperative?” RPT 1 (1978):

149-177.

––––––. "Law as Technology Assessment." RPT 5 (1982): 101-115.

––––––. "The Normative Side of Technology: Philosophy and the Public Interest." RPT 2

(1979): 91-109.

––––––. "The Two-Tiered Ethics of Electronic Data Processing." JSPT 2 (1996): 18-27.

Byrne, Edmund F. "Can Government Regulate Technology?” Philosophy and Technology.

Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 80. P&T 1 (1983): 17-33.

––––––. "Globalization and Community: In Search of Transnational Justice." Technological

Transformation: Contextual and Conceptual Implications. P&T 5 (1999): 141-161.

––––––. "The Labor-Saving Device: Evidence of Responsibility?” Technology and

Contemporary Life. P&T 4 (1988): 63-85.

––––––. "Microelectronics and Workers' Rights." Philosophy and Technology II: Information

Technology and Computers in Theory and Practice. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of

Science 90. P&T 2 (1986): 205-216.

––––––. "Nuclear Holocaust in American Films." RPT 9 (1989): 13-21.

––––––. "Utopia without Work? Myth, Machines, and Public Policy." RPT 8 (1985): 133-148.

––––––. "Work and Technology: A Bibliographical Essay." Technology and Contemporary Life.

P&T 4 (1988): 295-313.

220

––––––. "Workplace Democracy for Teachers: John Dewey's Contribution." Philosophy and

Technology: Practical, Historical, and Other Dimensions. P&T 6 (1989): 81-95.

Bzdak, David. "On Amnesia and Knowing-How." Techné: RPT 12 (2008): 36-47.

Callicott, J. Baird. "After the Industrial Paradigm, What?” RPT 18 (1999): 13-26.

––––––. "The Role of Technology in the Evolving Concept of Nature." RPT 13 (1993): 201-222.

Camacho Naranjo, Luis A. "Contributions to the Philosophy of Technology in Costa Rica."

Philosophy of Technology in Spanish Speaking Countries. P&T 10 (1993): 71-80.

––––––. "Science, Technology, and Development: Some Models of Their Relationship."

Philosophy of Technology in Spanish Speaking Countries. P&T 10 (1993): 81-87.

Campos, Francisco. "Social Networks and the Urban Environment." JSPT 2 (1996): 28-35.

Caporael, Linda R., E. Gabriella Panichkul, and Dennis R. Harris. "Tinkering with Gender." RPT

13 (1993): 73-99.

Capurro, Rafael. "Hermeneutics and the Phenomenon of Information." RPT 19 (2000): 79-85.

Carella, Michael J. "The Myths of Thomas Szasz." RPT 10 (1990): 299-313.

Carpenter, Stanley R. "Alternative Technology and the Norm of Efficiency." RPT 6 (1983): 65-

76.

––––––. "The Cognitive Dimension of Technological Change." RPT 1 (1978): 213-228.

––––––. "A Conversation Concerning Technology: The 'Appropriate' Technology Movement."

Technology and Contemporary Life. P&T 4 (1988): 87-105.

––––––. "A Discussion [on Albert Borgmann's Technology and the Character of Contemporary

Life]." Technology and Contemporary Life. P&T 4 (1988): 1-12.

––––––. "Instrumentalists and Expressivists: Ambiguous Links Between Technology and

Democracy." Democracy in a Technological Society. P&T 9 (1992): 161-173.

221

––––––. "A Positive Case for Appropriate Technology." RPT 6 (1983): 21-31.

––––––. "Scale in Technology: A Critique of Design Assumptions." RPT 8 (1985): 67-76.

––––––. "Sustainability and Common-Pool Resources: Alternatives to Tragedy." JSPT 3 (1998):

170-183.

––––––. "Technoaxiology: Appropriate Norms for Technology Assessment." Philosophy and

Technology. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 80. P&T 1 (1983): 115-136.

––––––. "Toward Refined Indicators of Susainable Development.” JSPT 2 (1996): 65-70.

––––––. "What Technologies Transfer: The Contingent Nature of Cultural Responses."

Technological Transformation: Contextual and Conceptual Implications. P&T 5 (1999):

163-177.

––––––. "When Are Technologies Sustainable?” JSPT 1 (1995): 37-43.

Carrara, Massimiliano. "Relative Identity and the Number of Artifacts." Techné: RPT 13 (2009):

108-122.

Casey, Tim. "Technology and the Metaphysics of Technique." RPT 16 (1997): 73-86.

Casey, Timothy. "Architecture as Environmental Philosophy." RPT 18 (1999): 73-84.

Castle, David. "The Balance Between Expertise and Authority in Citizen Engagement About

New Biotechnology." Techné: RPT 9 (2006): 1-13.

Cerezo, José Antonio López and Carl Mitcham. "The Social Assessment of the Technology

Paradox." RPT 15 (1995): 53-71.

Cerezo, José Antonio López and Marta Gonzales Garcia. "Lay Knowledge and Public

Participation in Technological and Environmental Policy." JSPT 2 (1996): 36-48.

Cérézuelle, Daniel. "Concerning the Religious Origins of Technological Civilization." RPT 6

(1983): 175-188.

222

––––––. "Fear and Insight in French Philosophy of Technology." RPT 2 (1979): 53-75.

––––––. "From the Technical Phenomenon to the Technical System." RPT 3 (1980): 161-170.

––––––. "Information Technology and the Technological System." Philosophy and Technology

II: Information Technology and Computers in Theory and Practice. Boston Studies in the

Philosophy of Science 90. P&T 2 (1986): 217-225.

––––––. "Reflections on the Autonomy of Technology: Biotechnology, Bioethics, and Beyond."

Technology and Contemporary Life. P&T 4 (1988): 129-144.

Champion, Erik. "When Windmills Turn Into Giants: The Conundrum of Virtual Places."

Techné: RPT 10 (2007): 1-16.

Chapman, Anne. "Genetic Engineering: The Unnatural Argument." Techné: RPT 9 (2005).

Christians, Clifford. "A Theory of Normative Technology." Technological Transformation:

Contextual and Conceptual Implications. P&T 5 (1999): 123-139.

Clarke, Melissa. "Philosophy and Technology Session on Bodies in Technology." Techné: RPT 7

(2003): 120-124.

Clarke, Thomas L., Dennis K. McBride, and Douglas Reece. "All But War Is Simulation." RPT

21 (2002): 215-224.

Clausen, Jonas and John Cantwell. "Reasoning with Safety Factor Rules." Techné: RPT 11

(2007): 55-70.

Coe, Cynthia D. and Matthew C. Altman. "Mandatory Ultrasound Laws and the Coercive Use of

Informed Consent." Techné: RPT 16 (2012): 16-30.

Coeckelbergh, Mark. "The Public Thing: On the Idea of a Politics of Artefacts." Techné: RPT 13

(2009): 175-181.

223

––––––. "Technology as Skill and Activity: Revisiting the Problem of Alienation." Techné: RPT

16 (2012): 208-230.

Cohen, Robert S. "Social Implications of Recent Technological Innovations." Philosophy and

Technology. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 80. P&T 1 (1983): 35-47.

Colapietro, Vincent. "The Pragmatic Turn." Techné: RPT 7 (2004): 19-31.

Condella, Craig. "Democracy, Narcissism, and the World Wide Web." Techné: RPT 16 (2012):

252-274.

Conry, Thomas. "Public Interest: Rights for What? Responsibilities to Whom?” RPT 3 (1980): 5-

10.

Cook, S. D. Noam. "Turing, Searle, and the Wizard of Oz: Life and Custom Among the

Automata or How Ought We to Assess the Attribution of Capacities of Living Systems to

Technological Artifacts?” Techné: RPT 14 (2010): 88-102.

Cook, Scott D. N. "The Structure of Technological Revolutions and the Gutenberg Myth." New

Directions in the Philosophy of Technology. P&T 11 (1995): 63-83.

Cook, Tanya N. "Hooked Up: How Electronic Fetal Monitoring Affects Maternal Agency and

Maternal Autonomy." Techné: RPT 16 (2012): 45-61.

Coolen, T. Maarten T. "Philosophical Anthropology and the Problem of Responsibility in

Technology." Technology and Responsibility. P&T 3 (1987): 41-65.

Cordero, Alberto. "On the Growing Complementarity of Science and Technology." JSPT 4

(1998): 86-92.

Cormac, Earl R. Mac. "Environmental Management: Values, Knowledge, and Categories." RPT

12 (1992): 177-188.

––––––. "Symmetry and Asymmetry in Science and Technology." JSPT 4 (1998): 111-119.

224

––––––. "Values and Technology: How to Introduce Ethical and Human Values into Public

Policy Decisions." RPT 6 (1983): 143-155.

Coyne, Richard. "Thinking Through Virtual Reality: Place, Non-Place and Situated Cognition in

Technological Society.” Techné: RPT 10 (2007): 26-38.

Cózar-Escalante, José Manuel de. "Living in a Nanotech Home: Invisibility, Representation and

Democratic Oversight of Nanotechnological Developments.” Techné: RPT 14 (2010):

124-139.

Cózar, José M. de. "Technology, the Natural Environment, and the Quality of Life." RPT 12

(1992): 67-81.

Cózar, José Manuel de. "Toward a Philosophical Analysis of Efficiency." RPT 19 (2000): 87-

100.

Crabtree, Andy, John A. Hughes, Jon O'Brien, and Tom Rodden. "On the Social Organization of

Space and the Design of Electronic Landscapes." Techné: JSPT 5 (2000): 56-72.

Cramer, Jacqueline. "Societal Role of Dutch Freshwater Ecologists in Environmental Policies."

Technology and Responsibility. P&T 3 (1987): 261-277.

Crane, J. A. "The Problem of Valuation in Risk-Cost-Benefit Assessment of Public Policies."

Technological Transformation: Contextual and Conceptual Implications. P&T 5 (1999):

67-79.

Crane, John. "Risk Assessment as Social Research." Technology and Responsibility. P&T 3

(1987): 279-308.

Crombie, James. "Mumford on How Mining and War Corrupted Our Values: On the Social

Origins of Some Unsustainable Technologies and Accounting Practices." JSPT 2 (1996):

71-78.

225

Croy, Marvin J. "Collingridge and the Control of Educational Computer Technology." JSPT 1

(1996): 107-115.

Cuevas-Badallo, Ana. "A Model-based Approach to Technological Theories." Techné: RPT 9

(2005).

Culver, Keith. "Adoption and Governance of Biotechnology in Democracies." Techné: RPT 9

(2006): 32-46.

Dahlstrom, Daniel. "Comments on Andrew Feenberg's Heidegger and Marcuse." Techné: RPT 9

(2006): 52-61.

Dahlstrom, Daniel O. "Lebenstechnik und Essen: Toward a Technological Ethics after

Heidegger." Technology and Contemporary Life. P&T 4 (1988): 145-159.

Damarin, Suzanne K. "Technologies of the Individual: Women and Subjectivity in the Age of

Information." RPT 13 (1993): 183-198.

Dasheng, Gao and Zou Tsing. "Philosophy of Technology in China." Philosophy and

Technology: Practical, Historical, and Other Dimensions. P&T 6 (1989): 133-151.

Dauenhauer, Bernard P. "Rouse's Knowledge and Power: A Note." RPT 11 (1991): 179-182.

Davion, Victoria. "Zimmerman on Feminism, Truth, and Objectivity." RPT 18 (1999): 167-174.

De Mul, Jos. "Moral Machines: ICTs as Mediators of Human Agencies." Techné: RPT 14

(2010): 226-236.

DeHart, Scott. "Ritual in Technoscientific Medicine." RPT 16 (1997): 87-117.

Demmers, Jim and Dara O'Neal. "Leaver and Takers: Alternative Perspecives on Universal

Access to Telecommunications Technology." Techné: JSPT 5 (2001): 131-143.

226

DeNicola, Daniel. "Paradigms and Paraphernalia: On the Relation Between Theory and

Technology in Science." New Directions in the Philosophy of Technology. P&T 11

(1995): 85-93.

Denouden, Bernard. "Transferred and Transformed Technology: The C.R.S.

Thresher/Winnower." Technological Transformation: Contextual and Conceptual

Implications. P&T 5 (1999): 179-184.

Devon, Richard. "Towards a Social Ethic of Technology." Techné: RPT 8 (2004): 99-115.

Diemer, Alwin. "The Cultural Character of Technology." Philosophy and Technology. Boston

Studies in the Philosophy of Science 80. P&T 1 (1983): 313-318.

Dietrich, Eric. "Cognitive Science and the Mechanistic Forces of Darkness, or Why the

Computational Science of Mind Suffers the Slings and Arrows of Outrageous Fortune."

Techné: JSPT 5 (2000): 73-82.

Dijk, Paul van. "Environmental Ethics and the Recovery of Culture." RPT 17 (1998): 25-43.

Dion, Michel. "Institutionalizing Environmental Ethics into the Corporation." RPT 13 (1993):

301-318.

Doeleman, J. A. "Environment and Technology: Speculating on the Long Run." RPT 12 (1992):

5-32.

Donchin, Anne. "Commercializing Reproductive Technologies: Ethical Issues." Technology and

Responsibility. P&T 3 (1987): 151-172.

Drengson, Alan R. "Art and Imagination in Technological Society." RPT 6 (1983): 77-91.

Dretske, Fred. "Minds, Machines and Meaning." Philosophy and Technology II: Information

Technology and Computers in Theory and Practice. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of

Science 90. P&T 2 (1986): 97-109.

227

Dreyfus, Hubert L. "From Socrates to Expert Systems: The Limits of Calculative Rationality."

Philosophy and Technology II: Information Technology and Computers in Theory and

Practice. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 90. P&T 2 (1986): 111-130.

Durbin, Paul T. "Activist Philosophy of Technology and the Preservation of Biodiversity."

Techné: JSPT 6 (2003): 141-147.

––––––. "Advances in Philosophy of Technology? Comparative Perspectives." JSPT 4 (1998): 4-

15.

––––––. "Can There Be a Best Ethic of Sustainability?” JSPT 2 (1996): 84-90.

––––––. "Environmental Ethics and Environmental Activism." RPT 12 (1992): 107-117.

––––––. "Guest Editor's Introduction." Techné: JSPT 5 (2000): 1-4.

––––––. "Guest Introduction." Techné: JSPT 5 (2000): 48-55.

––––––. "In Defense of a Social-Work Philosophy of Technology." RPT 16 (1997): 3-14.

––––––. "Introduction." Techné: JSPT 7 (2003): 1-7.

––––––. "Introduction: Some Questions for Philosophy of Technology." Philosophy and

Technology. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 80. P&T 1 (1983): 1-14.

––––––. "Marxism and the Democratic Control of Technology." Democracy in a Technological

Society. P&T 9 (1992): 81-89.

––––––. "Philosophical Tools for Technological Culture: Comments from an Activist

Perspective." Techné: JSPT 7 (2003): 25-28.

––––––. "Philosophy of Technology: In Search of Discourse Synthesis." Techné: RPT 10 (2006):

4-320.

––––––. "Reply to George Allan." RPT 12 (1992): 129-132.

228

––––––. "Research and Development from the Viewpoint of Social Philosophy." Technological

Transformation: Contextual and Conceptual Implications. P&T 5 (1999): 33-45.

––––––. "SPT and Social Progress." Techné: RPT 14 (2010): 16-22.

––––––. "Toward a Philosophy of Engineering and Science in R & D Settings." Technology and

Responsibility. P&T 3 (1987): 309-327.

––––––. "Toward a Social Philosophy of Technology." RPT 1 (1978): 67-97.

Dusek, Val. "Ihde’s Instrumental Realism and the Marxist Account of Technology in

Experimental Science.” Techné: RPT 12 (2008): 105-109.

Dussel, Enrique. "Technology and Basic Needs: Proposal for a Debate on Fundamental Criteria."

Philosophy of Technology in Spanish Speaking Countries. P&T 10 (1993): 101-109.

Dust, Patrick H. "Freedom, Power, and Culture in Ortega y Gasset's Philosophy of Technology."

RPT 11 (1991): 119-153.

Dym, Clive L. and Philip Brey. "Languages for Engineering Design: Empirical Constructs for

Representing Objects and Articulating Processes." RPT 20 (2001): 119-148.

Eck, Dingmar van. "Incommensurability and Rationality in Engineering Design: The Case of

Functional Decomposition." Techné: RPT 15 (2011): 118-136.

Eede, Yoni Van Den. "Collecting Our Lives Online: The Use of Digital Media Seen through the

Lens of Collecting Practices." Techné: RPT 14 (2010): 103-123.

Ellul, Jacques. "The Latest Developments in Technology and the Philosophy of the Absurd."

RPT 7 (1984): 77-97.

––––––. "Nature, Technique and Artificiality." RPT 3 (1980): 263-283.

––––––. "The Search for Ethics in a Technicist Society." RPT 9 (1989): 23-36.

229

––––––. "Technology and Democracy." Democracy in a Technological Society. P&T 9 (1992):

35-50.

Embree, Lester. "Personal Environmental Phenomenology, or the Examination of Electric

Vehicle Technology." RPT 18 (1999): 115-130.

Espinas, Alfred. "Introduction to the Origins of Technology." RPT 2 (1979): 201-208.

Ess, Charles. "Borgmann and the Borg: Consumerism vs. Holding on to Reality." Techné: JSPT

6 (2002): 21-32.

Evans, Fred. "Technology as Art and the ‘Spheres of Freedom and Necessity.’" RPT 14 (1994):

219-234.

Fairweather, N. Ben. "Disembodied Sport: Ethical Issues of Virtual Sport, Electronic Games, and

Virtual Leisure." RPT 21 (2002): 235-249.

Fandozzi, Phillip. "Art in a Technological Society." RPT 2 (1979): 111-118.

Fandozzi, Phillip R. "Appropriate? Inappropriate? What's the Difference?” RPT 6 (1983): 33-

41.

––––––. "Art in a Technological Setting." RPT 5 (1982): 3-13.

Farnum, John. "Untangling Technology: A Summary of Andrew Feenberg's Heidegger and

Marcuse." Techné: RPT 9 (2006): 47-51.

Fasching, Darrell J. "The Dialectic of Apocalypse and Utopia in the Theological Ethics of

Jacques Ellul." RPT 10 (1990): 149-165.

––––––. "Mass Media, Ethical Paradox, and Democratic Freedom: Jacques Ellul's Ethic of the

Word." RPT 11 (1991): 77-103.

Feenberg, Andrew. "Active and Passive Bodies: Comments on Don Ihde's Bodies in

Technology." Techné: RPT 7 (2003): 125-130.

230

––––––. "Democratic Socialism and Technological Change." Broad and Narrow Interpretations

of Philosophy of Technology. P&T 7 (1990): 101-123.

––––––. "The Idea of Progress and the Politics of Technology." RPT 5 (1982): 15-21.

––––––. "Pragmatism and Critical Theory of Technology." Techné: JSPT 7 (2003): 29-33.

––––––. "Reply to Dahlstrom and Scharff." Techné: RPT 9 (2006): 81-93.

––––––. "Ten Paradoxes of Technology." Techné: RPT 14 (2010): 3-15.

Fernandez, Eliseo. "Information and Ersatz Reality: Comments on Albert Borgmann's Holding

On to Reality." Techné: JSPT 6 (2002): 8-11.

Ferré, Frederick. "Clarifying and Applying Intelligence: A Reply to Peter Limper." Broad and

Narrow Interpretations of Philosophy of Technology. P&T 7 (1990): 37-41.

––––––. "Defining Horizons: A Reply to Joseph C. Pitt." Broad and Narrow Interpretations of

Philosophy of Technology. P&T 7 (1990): 17-23.

––––––. "On Matter and Machines: An Environmental Speculation." RPT 18 (1999): 131-142.

––––––. "On Replicating Persons: Ethics and the Technology of Cloning." JSPT 3 (1997): 102-

105.

––––––. "Philosophy and Technology after Twenty Years." JSPT 1 (1995): 4-7.

––––––. "Philosophy and Technology: Another Look 15 Years Later." Techné: RPT 14 (2010):

23-25.

––––––. "Technology, Nature, and Miracle." RPT 10 (1990): 281-286.

Fielder, John. "Autonomous Technology, Democracy, and the Nimbys." Democracy in a

Technological Society. P&T 9 (1992): 105-121.

Fitzpatrick, Anne. "Teller's Technical Nemeses: The American Hydrogen Bomb and Its

Development within a Technological Infrastructure." JSPT 3 (1998): 119-123.

231

Fornet-Betancourt, Raúl. "Two Philosophical Approaches to the Problem of Technics and Their

Meaning for Latin America." Philosophy of Technology in Spanish Speaking Countries.

P&T 10 (1993): 271-281.

Friesen, Norm. "Dissection and Simulation: Brilliance and Transparency, or Encumbrance and

Disruption?” Techné: RPT 15 (2011): 185-200.

––––––. "Less is More: A Response to Ihde, Rosenberger, Borgmann, Barney and Sørenson."

Techné: RPT 15 (2011): 229-234.

Frodeman, Robert. "The Rebirth of Gaia and the Closure of Homo Technologicus." RPT 18

(1999): 95-113.

Frossard, David. "‘Peasant Science’: A New Paradigm for Sustainable Development?” RPT 17

(1998): 111-126.

Frost, Robert L. "Mechanical Dreams: Democracy and Technological Discourse in Twentieth

Century France." Democracy in a Technological Society. P&T 9 (1992): 51-77.

Fullinwider, Robert K. "Science and Technology Education as Civic Education." Europe,

America, and Technology: Philosophical Perspectives. P&T 8 (1991): 197-215.

Furrow, Dwight. "The Discomforts of Home: Nature and Technology in Hand's End." RPT 15

(1995): 169-175.

Gaos, José. "On Technique." Philosophy of Technology in Spanish Speaking Countries. P&T 10

(1993): 111-120.

Garbacz, Pawel. "What Is an Artefact Design?" Techné: RPT 13 (2009): 137-149.

Garcia Bacca, Juan David. "Science, Technology, History, and Philosophy in the Cultural

Atmosphere of Our Time." Philosophy of Technology in Spanish Speaking Countries.

P&T 10 (1993): 229-247.

232

Garcia de la Huerta, Marcos. "Globalization: Homogenization with an Increasing Technological

Gap." Philosophy of Technology in Spanish Speaking Countries. P&T 10 (1993): 15-38.

––––––. "Technology and Politics: Toward Artificial History?” Philosophy of Technology in

Spanish Speaking Countries. P&T 10 (1993): 3-14.

García-Merita, María Luisa. "Technology and Human Nature." Philosophy of Technology in

Spanish Speaking Countries. P&T 10 (1993): 145-151.

García, Jóse Antonio López Cerezo and Marta González. "Lay Knowledge and Public

Participation in Technological and Environmental Policy." RPT 16 (1997): 33-48.

Garnar, Andrew. "Portable Civilizations and Urban Assault Vehicles." Techné: JSPT 5 (2000):

97-104.

Garnar, Andrew Wells. "Hickman, Technology, and the Postmodern Condition." Techné: RPT

16 (2012): 231-251.

Gascoigne, Neil. "Philosophy contra Sociology." RPT 16 (1997): 139-144.

Gasparski, Wojciech. "Design Methodology: A Personal Statement." Philosophy and

Technology: Practical, Historical, and Other Dimensions. P&T 6 (1989): 153-167.

––––––. "Tadeusz Kotarbinski's Methodology of the Practical Sciences and its Influence." RPT 6

(1983): 93-106.

Geerts, Robert-Jan. "Self-Practices and the Experiential Gap: An Analysis of Moral Behavior

around Electricity Consumption." Techné: RPT 16 (2012): 94-104.

Gehlen, Arnold. "A Philosophical-Anthropological Perspective on Technology." RPT 6 (1983):

205-216.

Gelberg, J. Nadine. "Developing Sport Technology Policy: A Statement." RPT 21 (2002): 1-3.

Gendron, Bernard. "Technology, Democracy, and the Work Place." RPT 5 (1982): 23-25.

233

––––––. "The Viability of Environmental Ethics." Philosophy and Technology. Boston Studies in

the Philosophy of Science 80. P&T 1 (1983): 187-194.

Gendron, Bernard and Nancy Holmstrom. "Marx, Machinery, and Alienation." RPT 2 (1979):

119-135.

Gerrie, James. "Canada's Three Mute Technological Critics." Techné: RPT 9 (2005).

––––––. "Three Species of Technological Dependency." Techné: RPT 12 (2008): 184-194.

––––––. "Using and Refusing: A Philosophy of Technology Critique of James Rachels's Attack

on the Distinction between Killing and Letting Die." Techné: RPT 16 (2012): 317-329.

––––––. "Was Foucault a Philosopher of Technology?” Techné: RPT 7 (2003): 66-73.

Giese, Mark. "Altered States: Images of Technology in Two Prime Time Syndicated Television

Series." RPT 14 (1994): 9-26.

Gillette, Michael A. "The Ethical Implications of Implanting Life on Lifeless Planets." RPT 13

(1993): 319-325.

Goldman, Michael. "Against Feyerabend: The Meaning of Progress in Science." RPT 3 (1980):

28-38.

Goldman, Steven L. "Philosophy, Engineering, and Western Culture." Broad and Narrow

Interpretations of Philosophy of Technology. P&T 7 (1990): 125-152.

––––––. "The Technè of Philosophy and the Philosophy of Technology." RPT 7 (1984): 115-144.

Good, Robert C. "Religion and Technology: A Look at Television Evangelists and Viewers."

RPT 10 (1990): 81-91.

Gorokhov, Vitaly. "A New Interpretation of Technological Progress." JSPT 4 (1998): 16-27.

––––––. "Politics, Progress, and Engineering: Technical Professionals in Russia." Democracy in

a Technological Society. P&T 9 (1992): 175-185.

234

––––––. "Technological Enlightenment in Russia." JSPT 3 (1997): 106-112.

Grange, Joseph. "Whitehead and Heidegger on Technological Goodness." RPT 14 (1994): 161-

173.

Gray, Chris Hables. "The Culture of War Cyborgs: Technoscience, Gender, and Postmodern

War." RPT 13 (1993): 141-163.

Gray, Elizabeth Dodson. "Parenting Technology." RPT 14 (1994): 59-68.

Gray, Noël. "Geometric Constructions and the Constructions of Geometry." RPT 15 (1995): 21-

36.

Grinbaum, Alexei and Jean-Pierre Dupuy. "Living with Uncertainty: Toward the Ongoing

Normative Assessment of Nanotechnology." Techné: RPT 8 (2004): 4-25.

Groothuis, Douglas. "Bacon and Pascal on Mastery over Nature." RPT 14 (1994): 191-203.

Grote, Jim. "The Plots of Thinking through Technology." RPT 16 (1997): 155-161.

––––––. "René Girard's Theory of Violence: An Introduction." RPT 12 (1992): 261-270.

Guilmet, George. "Incontinence and Biomedicine: Examples from Puyallup Indian Medical

Ethnohistory." Technology and Responsibility. P&T 3 (1987): 173-201.

Guilmet, George M. "The Effects of Traditional Eskimo Patterns of Cognition on the Acceptance

or Rejection of Technological Innovation." RPT 8 (1985): 149-159.

Gunn, Alastair S. "Engineering Ethics and Hazardous Waste Management: Why Should We

Care about Future Generations?” RPT 12 (1992): 135-146.

Hahn, Robert. "Technology and Anaximander's Cosmical Imagination: A Case-Study for the

Influence of Monumental Architecture on the Origins of Western Philosophy/Science."

New Directions in the Philosophy of Technology. P&T 11 (1995): 95-138.

235

Hamilton, Edward and Andrew Feenberg. "The Technical Codes of Online Education." Techné:

RPT 9 (2005): 97-123.

Hanks, Joyce M. "A Way Out in A No-Exit Situation? Jacques Ellul on Technique and the Third

World." RPT 7 (1984): 271-286.

Hansen, Ejvind. "Communicative In-Betweens of Email Communication." Techné: RPT 13

(2009): 13-26.

Hansson, Sven Ove. "De-Marginalizing the Philosophy of Technology." Techné: RPT 16 (2012):

89-93.

––––––. "The Epistemology of Technological Risk." Techné: RPT 9 (2005).

––––––. "Great Uncertainty About Small Things." Techné: RPT 8 (2004): 26-35.

––––––. "Philosophical Perspectives on Risk." Techné: RPT 8 (2004): 10-35.

––––––. "Safe Design." Techné: RPT 10 (2006): 45-52.

––––––. "Understanding Technological Function: Introduction to the Special Issue on the Dual

Nature programme." Techné: JSPT 6 (2002): 87-92.

Hardman, Alun. "Evaluating Changing Sport Technology: An Ethnocentric Approach." RPT 21

(2002): 135-155.

Harney, Maurita. "Computation and Gender." RPT 13 (1993): 57-71.

Harrison, Frank R., III. "The Judeo-Christian Tradition and Crises in Contemporary

Technology." RPT 10 (1990): 103-118.

Hartley, Peter. "Kelly and the Wheelies." RPT 17 (1998): 127-139.

Hastedt, Heiner. "Enlightenment and Technology: Outline for a General Ethics of Technology."

RPT 14 (1994): 205-217.

236

Havas, Katalin G. "Contradictions in Principles of Ethics and Contemporary Technology.” JSPT

4 (1999): 225-228.

Heelan, Patrick A. "Machine Perception." Philosophy and Technology II: Information

Technology and Computers in Theory and Practice. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of

Science 90. P&T 2 (1986): 131-156.

Hehir, J. Bryan. "The Relationship of Moral and Strategic Arguments in the Defense Debate."

RPT 3 (1980): 367-383.

Hennig, Jochen. "Changes in the Design of Scanning Tunneling Microscopic Images from 1980

to 1990." Techné: RPT 8 (2004): 36-55.

Hessenbruch, Arne. "Beyond Truth: Pleasure of Nanofutures." Techné: RPT 8 (2005): 34-61.

Heyboer, M. "The Normative Implications of the Configuration of the Applied Sciences: A

Comment on Thompson." New Directions in the Philosophy of Technology. P&T 11

(1995): 153-157.

Hickman, Larry A. "The ‘Summa Technologica’ of Carl Mitcham." RPT 16 (1997): 163-170.

––––––. "Doing and Making in a Democracy: Dewey's Experience of Technology." Philosophy

and Technology: Practical, Historical, and Other Dimensions. P&T 6 (1989): 97-111.

––––––. "Four Effects of Technology." JSPT 3 (1998): 184-189.

––––––. "Green Pragmatism: Reals without Realism, Ideals without Idealism." RPT 18 (1999):

39-56.

––––––. "The Phenomenology of the Quotidian Artifact." Technology and Contemporary Life.

P&T 4 (1988): 161-176.

––––––. "Populism and the Cult of the Expert." Democracy in a Technological Society. P&T 9

(1992): 91-103.

237

––––––. "Postphenomenology and Pragmatism: Closer Than You Might Think?” Techné: RPT

12 (2008): 99-104.

––––––. "Revisiting Philosophical Tools for Technological Culture." Techné: JSPT 7 (2003): 45-

56.

––––––. "Techne and Politeia Revisited: Pragmatic Paths to Technological Revolution." JSPT 1

(1996): 116-127.

––––––. "Techniques of Discovery: Broad and Narrow Characterizations of Technology." New

Directions in the Philosophy of Technology. P&T 11 (1995): 207-218.

Higgs, Eric. "Introduction to the Symposium [on Douglas Kellner's Media Culture]." RPT 17

(1998): 163-167.

––––––. "Musings at the Confluence of the Rivers Techné and Oikos." RPT 12 (1992): 243-258.

Hildebrandt, Mirellie. "Legal and Technological Normativity: More (and Less) Than Twin

Sisters." Techné: RPT 12 (2008): 169-183.

Hollander, Rachelle D. "Toward a Model of Professional Responsibility." RPT 9 (1989): 37-44.

Holz, Hans Heinz. "The Import of Social, Political, and Anthropological Considerations in an

Adequate Philosophy of Technology." Philosophy and Technology. Boston Studies in the

Philosophy of Science 80. P&T 1 (1983): 319-322.

Hong, Sungook. "Man and Machine in the 1960s." Techné: RPT 7 (2004): 50-78.

Hood, Webster F. "Dewey and Technology." RPT 5 (1982): 189-207.

Hook, Bill. "The Fate of Skills in the Information Age." RPT 19 (2000): 101-123.

Hottois, Gilbert. "Aspects of a Philosophy of Technique." RPT 9 (1989): 45-57.

––––––. "Technoscience: Nihilistic Power versus a New Ethical Consciousness." Technology

and Responsibility. P&T 3 (1987): 69-84.

238

Houkes, Wybo and Pieter E. Vermaas. "Artefacts in Analytic Metaphysics: Introduction."

Techné: RPT 13 (2009): 74-81.

––––––. "Produced to Use: Combining Two Key Intuitions on the Nature of Artefacts." Techné:

RPT 13 (2009): 123-126.

Howard, H. Wendell. "Technology: Artistic Medium and Muse." RPT 14 (1994): 139-159.

Hübner, Kurt. "Philosophy of Modern Art and Philosophy of Technology.” JSPT 4 (1998).

Huning, Alois. "Homo Mensura: Human Beings Are Their Technology–Technology is Human."

RPT 8 (1985): 9-16.

––––––. "Preferences and Value Assessments in Cases of Decision under Risk." JSPT 4 (1999):

229-232.

––––––. "Technology and Human Rights." Philosophy and Technology. Boston Studies in the

Philosophy of Science 80. P&T 1 (1983): 49-57.

Huyke, Héctor José. "Technologies and the Devaluation of What is Near." Techné: JSPT 6

(2003): 156-165.

Ihde, Don. "The Corpus is Not Yet Closed…." Techné: RPT 12 (2008): 126-132.

––––––. "Dissection and Simulation: A Postphenomenological Critique." Techné: RPT 15

(2011): 203-205.

––––––. "The Historical-Ontological Priority of Technology over Science." Philosophy and

Technology. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 80. P&T 1 (1983): 235-252.

––––––. "Phil-Tech Meets Eco-Phil: The Environment." RPT 18 (1999): 27-38.

––––––. "Philosophy of Technology (and/or Technoscience?): 1996-2010." Techné: RPT 14

(2010): 26-35.

––––––. "Philosophy of Technology, 1975-1995." JSPT 1 (1995): 8-12.

239

––––––. "A Response to My Critics." Techné: RPT 7 (2003): 131-136.

––––––. "Technology and Cultural Variations." RPT 8 (1985): 17-33.

––––––. "Technology, Utopia and Dystopia." RPT 6 (1983): 107-125.

––––––. "Whole Earth Measurements." JSPT 2 (1996): 91-98.

Innis, Robert E. "The Meanings of Technology." Techné: JSPT 7 (2003): 34-40.

Jacobsen, Jeffrey and Lynn Holden. "Virtual Heritage: Living in the Past." Techné: RPT 10

(2007): 55-61.

Jalbert, John E. "Money, Technology, and the Tragedy of Culture in the Thought of Georg

Simmel." RPT 15 (1995): 37-51.

––––––. "Phenomenology and the Autonomy of Technology." Technology and Responsibility.

P&T 3 (1987): 85-98.

James, David N. "Risking Extinction: An Axiological Analysis." RPT 11 (1991): 49-63.

Johnston, Stephen. "Sustainability, Engineering, and Australian Academe." JSPT 2 (1997): 145-

158.

Johnston, Stephen, Alison Lee, and Helen McGregor. "Engineering as Captive Discourse." JSPT

1 (1996): 128-136.

Jones, William B. and A. Warren Matthews. "Toward a Taxonomy of Technology and Religion."

RPT 10 (1990): 3-23.

Julliard, Yannick. "Ethics Quality Management." Techné: RPT 8 (2004): 117-135.

Jung, Hwa Yol. "The Genealogy of Technological Rationality in the Human Sciences." RPT 9

(1989): 59-82.

––––––. "Language, Politics, and Technology." RPT 5 (1982): 43-63.

Kanitscheider, Bernulf. "Humans and Future Communication Systems." JSPT 4 (1999): 152-158.

240

Katz, Eric. "The Big Lie: Human Restoration of Nature." RPT 12 (1992): 231-241.

––––––. "The Place of Nature in the Understanding of Technology: One Critical Reading of

Thinking Through Technology." RPT 16 (1997): 171-178.

Kellner, Douglas. "Intellectuals, the Public Sphere, and New Technologies." RPT 16 (1997): 15-

31.

––––––. "Media Culture, Social Theory, and Cultural Studies." RPT 17 (1998): 201-215.

Keulartz, Josef. "Introduction [to Pragmatist Ethics in the Technological Age]." Techné: RPT 7

(2004): 1-9.

Keulartz, Josef, Michiel Korthals, Maartje Schermer, and Tsjalling Swiestra. "Pragmatism in

Progress: A Reply." Techné: RPT 7 (2004): 39-49.

Kirchhoff, Michael David. "Material Agency: A Theoretical Framework for Ascribing Agency to

Material Culture." Techné: RPT 13 (2009): 206-220.

Klagge, James. "The Good Old Days: Age-Specific Perceptions of Progress." Technological

Transformation: Contextual and Conceptual Implications. P&T 5 (1999): 93-104.

Klein, Jacob. "On the Nature of Nature." RPT 2 (1979): 173-188.

Kleindorfer, George B. and James E. Martin. "The Iron Cage, Single Vision, and Newton's

Sheep." RPT 6 (1983): 127-142.

Kockelkoren, Petran. "Toward a Technological Intimacy with Things." RPT 17 (1998): 45-57.

Koelega, Dick G. A. "Technology, Ecology, Autonomy, and the State." JSPT 1 (1995): 62-70.

Koenne, Werner. "On the Antagonism between Philosophy and Technology in Germany and

Austria." RPT 2 (1979): 235-244.

Kornwachs, Klaus. "A Formal Theory of Technology?” JSPT 4 (1998): 28-39.

Kovacs, George. "The Nature and Meaning of Work." RPT 11 (1991): 183-194.

241

Kramer-Friedrich, Sybille. "Information Measurement and Information Technology: A Myth of

the Twentieth Century." Philosophy and Technology II: Information Technology and

Computers in Theory and Practice. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 90. P&T

2 (1986): 17-28.

Krebs, Peter. "Virtual Models and Simulations: A Different Kind of Science?” Techné: RPT 11

(2007): 42-54.

Kreiling, Frederick C. "Leibniz and Technology." RPT 6 (1983): 217-222.

Krieger, Martin H. "Temptations of Design: A Meditation on Practice." RPT 10 (1990): 217-230.

Kroes, Peter. "Engineering Design and the Empirical Turn in the Philosophy of Technology."

RPT 20 (2001): 19-43.

––––––. "Screwdriver Philosophy: Searle's Analysis of Technical Functions." Techné: JSPT 6

(2003): 131-140.

––––––. "Technical Functions as Dispositions: A Critical Assessment." Techné: JSPT 5 (2001):

105-115.

––––––. "Technological Explanations: The Relation between Structure and Function of

Technological Objects." JSPT 3 (1998): 124-134.

––––––. "Technology and Science-Based Heuristics." New Directions in the Philosophy of

Technology. P&T 11 (1995): 17-39.

Kroes, Peter and Anthonie Meijers. "The Dual Nature of Technical Artifacts: Presentation of a

New Research Programme." Techné: JSPT 6 (2002).

––––––. "Introduction: A Discipline in Search of Its Identity." RPT 20 (2001): xvii-xxxv.

––––––. "Reply to Critics." Techné: JSPT 6 (2002): 110-116.

242

Krohs, Ulrich. "Structure and Coherence of Two-Model-Descriptions of Technical Artefacts."

Techné: RPT 13 (2009): 150-161.

Krois, John Michael. "Ernst Cassirer's Theory of Technology." RPT 5 (1982): 209-222.

Ladriëre, Jean. "The Technical Universe in an Ontological Perspective." JSPT 4 (1998): 40-55.

Lafitte, Jacques. "On the Science of Machines." RPT 2 (1979): 208-223.

Lai, Tyrone. "Cryptanalysis: Uncovering Objective Knowledge of Hidden Realities."

Technological Transformation: Contextual and Conceptual Implications. P&T 5 (1999):

17-32.

Laor, Nathaniel. "The Computer as a Diagnostic Tool in Medicine." Philosophy and Technology

II: Information Technology and Computers in Theory and Practice. Boston Studies in the

Philosophy of Science 90. P&T 2 (1986): 227-238.

Laurent, Louis and Jean-Claude Petit. "Nanosciences and its Convergence with other

Technologies: New Golden Age or Apocalypse?” Hyle 11 (2005): 45-76.

Lawson, Clive. "An Ontology of Technology: Artefacts, Relations and Functions." Techné: RPT

12 (2008): 48-64.

Laymon, Ronald. "Idealizations, Externalities, and the Economic Analysis of Law." New

Directions in the Philosophy of Technology. P&T 11 (1995): 185-206.

Lee, Keekok. "Patenting and Transgenic Organisms: A Philosophical Exploration." Techné:

JSPT 6 (2003): 166-175.

Lee, Steven. "Is the Just War Tradition Relevant in the Nuclear Age?” RPT 9 (1989): 83-90.

Lefebvre, Anne. "The Individuation of Nature in Gilbert Simondon's Philosophy and the

Problematic Nature of the Technological Object." Techné: RPT 15 (2011): 1-15.

243

Leiber, Theordor. "On the Impact of Deterministic Chaos on Modern Science and Philosophy of

Science: Implications for the Philosophy of Technology?” JSPT 4 (1998): 93-110.

Leidlmair, Karl. "From the Philosophy of Technology to a Theory of Media." JSPT 4 (1999):

159-164.

Lemons, John and Charles Malone. "Scientific, Public Policy, and Ethical Implications of the

Nuclear Waste Policy Act and Its Amendments." RPT 11 (1991): 5-32.

Lenk, Hans. "Advances in the Philosophy of Technology: New Structural Characteristics of

Technologies." JSPT 4 (1998): 56-62.

––––––. "Conclusion: Technological responsibility and the Humanities; the University of

Karlsruhe." JSPT 4 (1999): 236-238.

––––––. "Distributability Problems and Challenges to the Future Resolution of Responsibility

Conflicts.” JSPT 3 (1998): 190-205.

––––––. "Ideology, Technocracy, and Knowledge Utilization." Europe, America, and

Technology: Philosophical Perspectives. P&T 8 (1991): 127-140.

––––––. "Notes on Extended Responsibility and Increased Technological Power." Philosophy

and Technology. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 80. P&T 1 (1983): 195-210.

––––––. "Progress, Values, and Responsibility." JSPT 2 (1997): 159-171.

––––––. "Socio-Philosophical Notes on the Implications of the Computer Revolution."

Philosophy and Technology II: Information Technology and Computers in Theory and

Practice. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 90. P&T 2 (1986): 239-245.

––––––. "Toward a Pragmatic Social Philosophy of Technology and the Technological

Intelligentsia." RPT 7 (1984): 23-58.

244

Lenk, Hans and Günter Ropohl. "Toward an Interdisciplinary and Pragmatic Philosophy of

Technology: Technology as a Focus for Interdisciplinary Reflection and Systems

Research." RPT 2 (1979): 15-52.

Lenk, Hans and Matthias Maring. "Ecology and Ethics: Notes about Technology and Economic

Consequences." RPT 12 (1992): 157-176.

Lettow, Susanne. "Somatechnologies: Rethinking the Body in the Philosophy of Technology."

Techné: RPT 15 (2011): 110-117.

Levinson, Paul. "Cosmos Helps Those Who Help Themselves: Historical Patterns of

Technological Fulfillment, and Their Applicability to the Human Development of

Space." RPT 9 (1989): 91-100.

––––––. "Impact of Personal Information Technologies on American Education, Interpersonal

Relations, and Business, 1985-2010." Technology and Contemporary Life. P&T 4 (1988):

177-191.

––––––. "Information Technology as Vehicles of Evolution." Philosophy and Technology II:

Information Technology and Computers in Theory and Practice. Boston Studies in the

Philosophy of Science 90. P&T 2 (1986): 29-47.

––––––. "Technology as the Cutting Edge of Cosmic Evolution." RPT 8 (1985): 161-176.

Levy, Edwin. "Judgment and Policy: The Two-Step in Mandated Science and Technology."

Philosophy and Technology: Practical, Historical, and Other Dimensions. P&T 6 (1989):

41-59.

Lewenstein, Bruce V. "What Counts as a ‘Social and Ethical Issue’ in Nanotechnology?” Hyle

11 (2005): 5-18.

245

Lewin, David. "Technology and the Good Life: Suggestions for a Theological Turn in the

Philosophy of Technology." Techné: RPT 15 (2011): 82-95.

Light, Andrew. "Critical Theorist of Technology: Feenberg on Marx and Democracy." RPT 16

(1997): 131-137.

––––––. "Media, Identity, and Politics: A Critique of Kellner." RPT 17 (1998): 187-200.

––––––. "On Hand's End: Contextualizing the Problem of Nature and Technology." RPT 15

(1995): 165-168.

––––––. "The Role of Technology in Environmental Questions: Martin Buber and Deep Ecology

as Answers to Technological Consciousness." RPT 12 (1992): 83-104.

––––––. "Three Questions on Hyperreality." RPT 15 (1995): 211-222.

Light, Andrew and David Roberts. "Toward New Foundations in Philosophy of Technology:

Mitcham and Wittgenstein on Descriptions." RPT 19 (2000): 125-147.

Limper, Peter. "Albert Borgmann and John Dewey on Everyday Technology." RPT 14 (1994):

27-43.

––––––. "Process Themes in Frederick Ferré's Philosophy of Technology." Broad and Narrow

Interpretations of Philosophy of Technology. P&T 7 (1990): 25-35.

Lockhart, Ted. "Engineers as Social Activists: A Defense." Technology and Responsibility. P&T

3 (1987): 329-341.

––––––. "Technological Fixes for Moral Dilemmas.” JSPT 1 (1996): 137-145.

Loland, Sigmund. "Sport Technologies: A Moral View." RPT 21 (2002): 157-171.

Lompe, Klaus. "On the Social Acceptability of Modern Technology: New Challenges for

Politicians and Scientists in a World of Risks." RPT 11 (1991): 33-48.

246

Longford, Graham. "Pedagogies of Digital Citizenship and the Politics of Code." Techné: RPT 9

(2005): 68-96.

Longino, Helen. "Hazardous Technologies: How Are the Hazards Measured?” RPT 8 (1985):

177-188.

Longy, Francoise. "Function and Probability: The Making of Artefacts." Techné: RPT 10 (2006):

66-78.

López, José. "Bridging the Gaps: Science Fiction in Nanotechnology." Hyle 10 (2004): 129-152.

Lovekin, David. "Artifacts, Politics, and Imagination." RPT 5 (1982): 65-75.

––––––. "Rothenberg, Ramelli, and Heidegger: Considerations of Otherness." RPT 15 (1995):

181-190.

––––––. "Technology as the Sacred Order." RPT 3 (1980): 203-222.

Luegenbiehl, Heinz C. "Ethical Autonomy and Engineering in a Cross-Cultural Context."

Techné: RPT 8 (2004): 57-78.

Lujan, Josh Luis and Luis Moreno. "Biological Diversity and Political Equality: The Social

Impact of Genetic Tests." JSPT 2 (1997): 172-184.

Luÿf, Reginald and Pieter Tijmes. "Modern Immaterialism." RPT 12 (1992): 271-284.

Mabee, Charles. "The Fragility of Time: Orwell and Ellul in the Matrix of Theological Origins."

RPT 10 (1990): 129-148.

MacCormac, Earl R. "Men and Machines: The Computational Metaphor." Philosophy and

Technology II: Information Technology and Computers in Theory and Practice. Boston

Studies in the Philosophy of Science 90. P&T 2 (1986): 157-170.

Magdalinski, Tara and Karen Brooks. "Bride of Frankenstein: Technology and the Consumption

of the Female Athlete." RPT 21 (2002): 195-212.

247

Mainzer, Klaus. "Computer Technology and Evolution: From Artificial Intelligence to Artificial

Life." JSPT 4 (1998): 63-71.

Männikkö, Nancy Farm. "If A Tree Falls in the Forest: A Refutation of Technological

Determinism." RPT 12 (1992): 213-227.

Margolis, Joseph. "Culture and Technology." RPT 1 (1978): 25-37.

––––––. "History, Nature, and Technology." Technology and Contemporary Life. P&T 4 (1988):

217-236.

––––––. "Information, Artificial Intelligence, and the Praxical." Philosophy and Technology II:

Information Technology and Computers in Theory and Practice. Boston Studies in the

Philosophy of Science 90. P&T 2 (1986): 171-186.

––––––. "Political Morality under Radical Conditions." Democracy in a Technological Society.

P&T 9 (1992): 215-233.

––––––. "Pragmatism, Praxis, and the Technological." Philosophy and Technology: Practical,

Historical, and Other Dimensions. P&T 6 (1989): 113-130.

––––––. "Pragmatism, Transcendental Arguments, and the Technological." Philosophy and

Technology. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 80. P&T 1 (1983): 291-309.

––––––. "The Technological Self." Technological Transformation: Contextual and Conceptual

Implications. P&T 5 (1999): 1-15.

––––––. "Three Conceptions of Technology: Satanic, Titanic, and Human." RPT 7 (1984): 145-

158.

Marietta, Don E., Jr. "Decisions Regarding Technology: The Human Factor." RPT 18 (1999):

57-72.

248

Maskit, Jonathan. ""All in Post": On Michael Zimmerman's Contesting Earth's Future." RPT 18

(1999): 175-187.

Maurer, Reinhart. "The Origins of Modern Technology in Millenarianism." Philosophy and

Technology. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 80. P&T 1 (1983): 253-265.

Mayz Vallenilla, Ernesto. "The Present and Future of Humanity." Philosophy of Technology in

Spanish Speaking Countries. P&T 10 (1993): 249-258.

McClure, Mary Ann. "A Passion to Connect: The Science of Jane Goodall, Dian Fossey, and

Birute Galdikas." RPT 16 (1997): 49-60.

McGinn, Robert E. "The Problem of Scale in Human Life: A Framework for Analysis." RPT 1

(1978): 39-52.

––––––. "What Is Technology?” RPT 1 (1978): 179-197.

McGinn, Robert G. "Comment on Zimmerman's ‘Technological Culture And The End Of

Philosophy.’" RPT 2 (1979): 147-153.

McGrail, Robert. "Working with Substance: Actor-Network Theory and the Modal Weight of the

Material." Techné: RPT 12 (2008): 65-84.

Medina, Manuel. "Philosophy, Technology, and Society." Philosophy of Technology in Spanish

Speaking Countries. P&T 10 (1993): 153-166.

––––––. "Technology and Scientific Concepts: Mechanics and the Concept of Mass in

Archimedes." Europe, America, and Technology: Philosophical Perspectives. P&T 8

(1991): 141-156.

Meijers, Anthonie. "The Relational Ontology of Technical Artifacts." RPT 20 (2001): 81-96.

Melo-Martin, Immaculada de. "New Assisted-Conception Technologies: Social Dimensions and

Democratic Participation." RPT 17 (1998): 219-238.

249

Mesthene, Emmanuel G. "Technology as Evil: Fear or Lamentation?” RPT 7 (1984): 59-74.

Meyer-Abich, Klaus Michael. "What Sort of Technology Permits the Language of Nature?

Conditions for Controlling Nature-Domination Constitutionally." Philosophy and

Technology. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 80. P&T 1 (1983): 211-232.

Meyer, Martin and Osmo Kuusi. "Nanotechnology: Generalizations in an Interdisciplinary Field

of Science and Technology." Hyle 10 (2004): 99-128.

Miah, Andy. "Genes, Sports, and Ethics: A Response to Munthe." RPT 21 (2002): 269-289.

––––––. "Immersion and Abstraction in Virtual Sport." RPT 21 (2002): 225-233.

Michalos, Alex C. "A Reconsideration of the Idea of a Science Court." RPT 3 (1980): 10-28.

––––––. "Technology Assessment, Facts and Values." Philosophy and Technology. Boston

Studies in the Philosophy of Science 80. P&T 1 (1983): 59-81.

Michelfelder, Diane P. "The Philosophy of Technology When ‘Things Ain't What They Used to

Be.’" Techné: RPT 14 (2010): 60-68.

Miké, Valerie. "Toward and Ethics of Evidence–and Beyond: Observations on Technology and

Illness." RPT 9 (1989): 101-113.

Miller, Seumas. "Artefacts and Collective Intentionality." Techné: RPT 9 (2005).

Mitcham, Carl. "Do Artifacts Have Dual Natures? Two Points of Commentary on the Delft

Project.” Techné: JSPT 6 (2002): 93-95.

––––––. "Documentation: Analysis of Machines in the French Intellectual Tradition (Espinas,

Lafitte, Weil)." RPT 2 (1979): 189-201.

––––––. "In Qualified Praise of the Leon Kass Council on Bioethics." Techné: RPT 10 (2006): 7-

15.

250

––––––. "Information Technology and the Problem of Incontinence." Philosophy and

Technology II: Information Technology and Computers in Theory and Practice. Boston

Studies in the Philosophy of Science 90. P&T 2 (1986): 247-255.

––––––. "Introduction: El Desafío de la Tecnología: Authors and Issues in Philosophy of

Technology in the Spanish-Speaking World." Philosophy of Technology in Spanish

Speaking Countries. P&T 10 (1993): xix-xxxvi.

––––––. "Introduction: Information Technology and Computers as Themes in the Philosophy of

Technology." Philosophy and Technology II: Information Technology and Computers in

Theory and Practice. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 90. P&T 2 (1986): 1-

14.

––––––. "Notes toward a Philosophy of Meta-Technology." JSPT 1 (1995): 13-17.

––––––. "On Never Being through Thinking through Technology." RPT 16 (1997): 179-182.

––––––. "The Religious and Political Origins of Modern Technology." Philosophy and

Technology. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 80. P&T 1 (1983): 267-273.

––––––. "Responsibility and Technology: The Expanding Relationship." Technology and

Responsibility. P&T 3 (1987): 3-39.

––––––. "Tools for Conviviality: Argument, Insight, Influence." Europe, America, and

Technology: Philosophical Perspectives. P&T 8 (1991): 17-56.

––––––. "Types of Technology." RPT 1 (1978): 229-294.

Mitcham, Carl and René von Schomberg. "The Ethics of Engineers: From Occupational Role

Responsibility to Public Co-Responsibility." RPT 20 (2001): 167-189.

Mody, Cyrus C.M. "Small, but Determined: Technological Determinism in Nanoscience." Hyle

10 (2004): 153-168.

251

Mohr, Hans. "Technology Assessment in Theory and Practice." JSPT 4 (1999): 233-235.

Molina P., Leopoldo. "Education for Freedom versus Socio-Technical Control by Pedagogical

Means." Philosophy of Technology in Spanish Speaking Countries. P&T 10 (1993): 259-

268.

Monserrate, M. Carmen Sanchez. "Prenatal Genetic Tests: Misconceptions and Their

Implications." JSPT 1 (1996): 159-170.

Moriarty, Gene. "The Place of Engineering and the Engineering of Place." Techné: JSPT 5

(2000): 83-96.

Morrow, Raymond A. "Kellner's Reconstruction of Critical Theory: Media Culture and Culture

Studies." RPT 17 (1998): 169-186.

Mosterin, Jesús. "Technology-Mediated Observation.” JSPT 4 (1998): 120-127.

Mullins, Phil. "Introduction: Getting a Grip on Holding On to Reality." Techné: JSPT 6 (2002):

2-7.

––––––. "The Problem and Meaning of Borgmann's Realist Response." Techné: JSPT 6 (2002):

33-47.

Munthe, Christian. "Reply to Miah: Prospects and Tensions in the Meeting of Bioethics and the

Philosophy of Sport." RPT 21 (2002): 291-299.

Murata, Junichi. "From Challenger to Columbia: What Lessons Can We Learn from the Report

of the Columbia Accident Investigation Board for Engineering Ethics?” Techné: RPT 10

(2006): 30-44.

Murray, Craig. "Toward a Phenomenology of the Body in Virtual Reality." RPT 19 (2000): 149-

173.

Murray, Patrick. "The Frankfurt School Critique of Technology." RPT 5 (1982): 223-248.

252

Muthuchidambaram, S. "Diffusion of Technology vis-à-vis Transformation: Increasing

Contradictions Between Technocratic Market Values and Social Democratic Values."

Technological Transformation: Contextual and Conceptual Implications. P&T 5 (1999):

227-248.

––––––. "Information Technology, Citizens' Rights, and Personnel Administration." Technology

and Contemporary Life. P&T 4 (1988): 193-215.

Nauta, Doede and Louk Eduard Fleischhacker. "Labor as Communication and Communication

as Labor." RPT 17 (1998): 59-79.

Neville, Robert C. "Technology and the Richness of the World." RPT 10 (1990): 185-204.

Niadas, Yannis A. "On the Cognitive Demarcation between Technology and Science: An

Attempt at Epistemological Clarification." RPT 19 (2000): 175-213.

Nielsen, Kai. "Marx, the Primacy Thesis, and Technological Determinism." RPT 5 (1982): 249-

259.

––––––. "Technology as Ideology." RPT 1 (1978): 131-147.

Nieto, César Cuello. "Toward a Holistic Approach to the Ideal of Sustainability.” JSPT 2 (1996):

79-83.

Nieto, César Cuello and Paul T. Durbin. "Sustainable Development and Philosophies of

Technology." JSPT 1 (1995): 44-57.

Nordmann, Alfred. "Fusion and Fission, Governors and Elevators." Technological

Transformation: Contextual and Conceptual Implications. P&T 5 (1999): 81-92.

––––––. "Noumenal Technology: Reflections on the Incredible Tininess of Nano." Techné: RPT

8 (2005): 3-23.

253

Noström, Per. "Technological Know-How from Rules of Thumb." Techné: RPT 15 (2011): 96-

109.

Novak, David. "Technology and Its Ultimate Threat: A Jewish Meditation." RPT 10 (1990): 43-

70.

Nunn, Olga. "Skipping Hard-Wired Technology." Techné: RPT 9 (2005).

O'Connell, Brian M. and Joseph R. Herkert. "Engineering Ethics and Computer Ethics: Twins

Separated at Birth?” Techné: RPT 8 (2004): 36-56.

Ouden, Bernard den. "Poverty, Human Rights, and the Consequences of Deforestation." JSPT 1

(1995): 58-61.

––––––. "Sustainable Development, Human Rights, and Postmodernism." JSPT 3 (1997): 92-

101.

Padilla, Hugo. "Technological Objects and Their Epistemological Base." Philosophy of

Technology in Spanish Speaking Countries. P&T 10 (1993): 121-131.

Pena Borrero, Margarita M. "Science, Technology, and Society Education in the Latin American

Context." Philosophy of Technology in Spanish Speaking Countries. P&T 10 (1993):

283-288.

Peña, Carolyn Thomas de la. "Dudley Allen Sargent and Gustav Zander: Health Machines and

the Energized Male Body." RPT 21 (2002): 9-47.

Pfister, Gertrud. "From Snow Shoes to Racing Skis: Skiing as an Example of the Connections

between Sport, Technology, and Society." RPT 21 (2002): 49-77.

Pieters, Wolter. "Reve{a,i}ling the Risks: A Phenomenology of Information Security." Techné:

RPT 14 (2010): 194-206.

254

Pitt, Joseph C. "Against The Perennial: Small Steps Toward a Heraclitian Philosophy of

Science." Techné: RPT 7 (2003): 57-65.

––––––. "The Author Replies." Techné: JSPT 5 (2000): 35-47.

––––––. "The Autonomy of Technology." Technology and Responsibility. P&T 3 (1987): 99-

114.

––––––. "Design Mistakes: The Case of the Hubble Space Telescope." RPT 20 (2001): 149-163.

––––––. "Discovery, Telescopes, and Progress." New Directions in the Philosophy of

Technology. P&T 11 (1995): 1-16.

––––––. "Ethical Colonialism." Techné: RPT 7 (2004): 32-38.

––––––. "Explaining Change in Science." JSPT 3 (1998): 135-140.

––––––. "In Search of a New Prometheus." Broad and Narrow Interpretations of Philosophy of

Technology. P&T 7 (1990): 3-15.

––––––. "On the Philosophy of Technology, Past and Future." JSPT 1 (1995): 18-22.

––––––. "Philosophical Methodology, Technologies, and the Transformation of Knowledge."

JSPT 1 (1996): 146-158.

––––––. "The Technological Twist." Techné: RPT 14 (2010): 69-71.

––––––. "What Engineers Know." Techné: JSPT 5 (2001): 116-123.

––––––. "When is an Image Not an Image?” Techné: RPT 8 (2005): 24-33.

Poel, Ibo van de and Peter Kroes. "Technology and Normativity." Techné: RPT 10 (2006).

Poser, Hans. "On Structural Differences between Science and Engineering." JSPT 4 (1998): 128-

135.

Post, John F. "On Reenchanting the World." RPT 10 (1990): 243-279.

––––––. "A Reply to Ferré, and a Comment on Trau." RPT 10 (1990): 287-290.

255

Preston, Christopher J. "The Promise and Threat of Nanotechnology: Can Environmental Ethics

Guide Us?” Hyle 11 (2005): 19-44.

Pritchard, Michael S. "STS, Critical Thinking, and Philosophy for Children." Europe, America,

and Technology: Philosophical Perspectives. P&T 8 (1991): 217-246.

Procee, Henk. "Technology, Normativity, and the Future: The Aristotelian Turn." JSPT 3 (1997):

19-26.

Proctor, Robert N. "Ivan Illich's Medical Nemesis: Fifteen Years Later." Europe, America, and

Technology: Philosophical Perspectives. P&T 8 (1991): 75-94.

Queraltó Moreno, Ramón. "Does Technology 'Construct' Scientific Reality?” Philosophy of

Technology in Spanish Speaking Countries. P&T 10 (1993): 167-172.

––––––. "Technology as a New Condition of the Possibility of Scientific Knowledge." JSPT 4

(1998): 136-140.

Quintanilla, Miguel A. "Technical Systems and Technical Progress: A Conceptual Framework."

JSPT 4 (1998): 72-79.

Radder, Hans. "Pragmatism, Ethics, and Technology." Techné: RPT 7 (2004): 10-18.

Ramírez Briceño, Edgar Roy. "Ethics, Pernicious Technology, and the 'Technological

Argument.’” Philosophy of Technology in Spanish Speaking Countries. P&T 10 (1993):

89-98.

Rammert, Werner. "Relations That Constitute Technology and Media That Make a Difference:

Toward a Social Pragmatic Theory of Technicization." JSPT 4 (1999): 165-177.

Rapp, Friedrich. "The Chances of Alternative Science and Technology." RPT 7 (1984): 159-176.

––––––. "Cultural Alienation through Technology Transfer." Technological Transformation:

Contextual and Conceptual Implications. P&T 5 (1999): 249-257.

256

––––––. "Explosion of Needs, Quality of Life, and the Ecology Problem." JSPT 1 (1995): 71-73.

––––––. "Introduction: General Perspectives on the Complexity of Philosophy of Technology."

Philosophy and Technology: Practical, Historical, and Other Dimensions. P&T 6 (1989):

ix-xxiv.

––––––. "The Limited Promise of Technology Assessment." Europe, America, and Technology:

Philosophical Perspectives. P&T 8 (1991): 157-173.

––––––. "The Material and Cultural Aspects of Technology." JSPT 4 (1999): 178-185.

––––––. "Philosophy of Technology after Twenty Years: A German Perspective." JSPT 1

(1995): 23-26.

––––––. "The Prospects for Technology Assessment." Philosophy and Technology. Boston

Studies in the Philosophy of Science 80. P&T 1 (1983): 141-150.

––––––. "The Theory-ladenness of Information." Philosophy and Technology II: Information

Technology and Computers in Theory and Practice. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of

Science 90. P&T 2 (1986): 49-62.

Rasmussen, Larry. "Mindset and Moral Vision." RPT 10 (1990): 119-128.

Rathman, Kim Alaine. "Sharing the Harvest of the Skies: Outer Space Commercialization and

Third World Development.” JSPT 3 (1998): 150-159.

Reagle, Joseph, Jr. "Bug Tracking Systems as Public Spheres." Techné: RPT 11 (2007): 32-41.

Relph, Edward. "Spirit of Place and Sense of Place in Virtual Reality." Techné: RPT 10 (2007):

17-25.

Ridder, Jeroen de. "The (Alleged) Inherent Normativity of Technological Explanations." Techné:

RPT 10 (2006): 79-94.

257

Riggs, Damien W. and Clemence Due. "Representations of Surrogacy in Submissions to a

Parliamentary Inquiry in New South Wales." Techné: RPT 16 (2012): 71-84.

Rip, Arie. "There's No Turn Like the Empirical Turn." RPT 20 (2001): 3-17.

Rivers, Theodore John. "The Conception of Time and its Relationship to Technology." RPT 19

(2000): 215-231.

Robinett, Jane. "The Moral Vision of Technology in Contemporary Latin American Fiction."

Philosophy of Technology in Spanish Speaking Countries. P&T 10 (1993): 289-295.

Rockmore, Tom. "Heidegger on Technology and Democracy." Democracy in a Technological

Society. P&T 9 (1992): 187-205.

––––––. "Heidegger on Technology, Nazism, and the Thought of Being." RPT 13 (1993): 265-

282.

Rogers, C. Thomas. "The Ethical End-Use Problem in Engineering." RPT 8 (1985): 77-102.

Rogers, C. Thomas and Robert T. Taylor. "Introduction to "Symposium on Appropriate

Technology"." RPT 6 (1983): 3-10.

Rolston, Holmes, III. "A Managed Earth and the End of Nature?” RPT 18 (1999): 143-164.

Ropohl, Günter. "A Critique of Technological Determinism." Philosophy and Technology.

Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 80. P&T 1 (1983): 83-96.

––––––. "Information Does Not Make Sense – Or: The Relevance Gap in Information

Technology and Its Social Dangers." Philosophy and Technology II: Information

Technology and Computers in Theory and Practice. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of

Science 90. P&T 2 (1986): 63-74.

––––––. "Philosophy of Socio-Technical Systems." JSPT 4 (1999): 186-194.

258

––––––. "Technological Enlightenment as a Continuation of Modern Thinking." RPT 17 (1998):

239-248.

Rosenberger, Robert. "A Phenomenological Defense of Computer-Stimulated Frog Dissection."

Techné: RPT 15 (2011): 215-228.

––––––. "A Phenomenology of Image Use in Science: Multistability and the Debate over

Martian Gully Deposits." Techné: RPT 15 (2011): 156-169.

Ross, Don. "Instrumental Realism and the Idea of Embodied Knowledge." RPT 14 (1994): 251-

269.

Rothbart, Daniel. "The Dual Nature of Chemical Substance." Techné: JSPT 6 (2002): 106-109.

Rothenberg, David. "Feet on the Ground: Responses to Hand's End." RPT 15 (1995): 191-198.

Rothschild, Joan. "Guest Editor's Introduction." RPT 13 (1993): 3-11.

Sabl, Andrew. "False Frankensteins: The Costs and Illusions of Computer Mastery.” Techné:

JSPT 5 (2001): 144-157.

Sabrovsky J., Eduardo. "Is Technology Autonomous?” RPT 15 (1995): 73-91.

––––––. "Thinking Machines and the Crisis of Modern Reason." Philosophy of Technology in

Spanish Speaking Countries. P&T 10 (1993): 39-60.

Sachsse, Hans. "What is Alternative Technology?” Philosophy and Technology. Boston Studies

in the Philosophy of Science 80. P&T 1 (1983): 137-139.

Sacks, Arthur B. "Preface to the Colorado School of Mines Symposium." RPT 17 (1998): 109-

110.

Sanchez, Ana. "A Dialogical Model of Persistent Patriarchalism." JSPT 2 (1996): 49-54.

Sandell, Michelle. "Astronomy and Experimentation." Techné: RPT 14 (2010): 252-269.

259

Saner, Marc A. "Citizenship Engagement, Biotechnology and ICTs: Are There Any Inherent

Problems?” Techné: RPT 9 (2006): 14-22.

Sanmartín, José. "Alternatives for Evaluating the Effects of Genetic Engineering on Human

Development." Broad and Narrow Interpretations of Philosophy of Technology. P&T 7

(1990): 153-166.

––––––. "From World3 to the Social Assessment of Technology: Remarks on Science,

Technology, and Society." Philosophy of Technology in Spanish Speaking Countries.

P&T 10 (1993): 197-209.

––––––. "Genethics: The Social Assessment of the Risks and Impacts of Genetic Engineering."

Philosophy of Technology in Spanish Speaking Countries. P&T 10 (1993): 211-225.

Sardamov, Ivelin. "From 'Bio-Power' to 'Neuropolitics': Stepping Beyond Foucault." Techné:

RPT 16 (2012): 123-137.

Sarlemijn, Andries. "Technological Analogies and Their Logical Nature." Technology and

Contemporary Life. P&T 4 (1988): 237-255.

Sass, Hans-Martin. "Technical and Cultural Aspects of Risk Perception." RPT 9 (1989): 115-

124.

Sassower, Raphael. "The Alarmist View of Technology." Broad and Narrow Interpretations of

Philosophy of Technology. P&T 7 (1990): 167-180.

––––––. "Intellectual Responsibility for an Ecology Agenda." JSPT 1 (1995): 74-82.

Sayes, Edwin. "From the Sacred to the Sacred Object: Girard, Serres, and Latour on the Ordering

of the Human Collective." Techné: RPT 16 (2012): 105-122.

Schadewaldt, Wolfgang. "The Concepts of Nature and Technique According to the Greeks."

RPT 2 (1979): 159-171.

260

Scharff, Robert C. "Feenberg on Marcuse: ‘Redeeming Technological Culture.’" Techné: RPT 9

(2006): 62-80.

Scheele, Marcel. "Social Norms in Artefact Use: Proper Functions Action Theory." Techné: RPT

10 (2006): 53-65.

Schiemann, Gregor. "Nanotechnology and Nature: On Two Criteria for Understanding Their

Relationship." Hyle 11 (2005): 77-96.

Schirmacher, Wolfgang. "Eco-Sophia." RPT 9 (1989): 125-134.

––––––. "From the Phenomenon to the Event of Technology: A Dialectical Aproach to

Heidegger's Phenomenology." Philosophy and Technology. Boston Studies in the

Philosophy of Science 80. P&T 1 (1983): 275-289.

––––––. "Homo Generator: The Challenge of Gene Technology." Translated by Viriginia

Cutrufelli. Technology and Responsibility. P&T 3 (1987): 203-225.

––––––. "Privacy as an Ethical Problem in the Computer Society." Philosophy and Technology

II: Information Technology and Computers in Theory and Practice. Boston Studies in the

Philosophy of Science 90. P&T 2 (1986): 257-268.

Schmid, Anne-Françoise. "Epistemology and Ethics in Engineering." RPT 15 (1995): 227-233.

Schoolman, Morton. "Liberalism's Ambiguous Legacy: Individuality and Technological

Constraints." RPT 7 (1984): 229-252.

Schrader, David E. "Technology: Our Contemporary Snake." RPT 10 (1990): 205-215.

Schummer, Joachim. "Societal and Ethical Implications of Nanotechnology." Techné: RPT 8

(2004): 56-87.

Schuurman, Egbert. "Concern about Responsibility in Applying Science." RPT 5 (1982): 77-86.

261

––––––. "Crisis in Agriculture: Philosophical Perspective on the Relation between Agriculture

and Nature." RPT 12 (1992): 191-211.

––––––. "The Modern Babylon Culture." Technology and Responsibility. P&T 3 (1987): 229-

242.

––––––. "Philosophical and Ethical Problems of Technicism and Genetic Engineering." JSPT 3

(1997): 27-44.

Sclove, Richard E. "The Nuts and Bolts of Democracy: Democratic Theory and Technological

Design." Democracy in a Technological Society. P&T 9 (1992): 139-157.

Selinger, Evan. "Introduction to Postphenomenology Discussion." Techné: RPT 12 (2008): 98-

98.

––––––. "Normative Judgment and Technoscience: Nudging Ihde, Again." Techné: RPT 12

(2008): 120-125.

Seltzer, Michael. "The Technological Infrastructure of Science: Comments on Baird, Fitzpatrick,

Kroes, and Pitt.” JSPT 3 (1998): 141-149.

Shapere, Dudley. "Building on What We Have Learned: The Relations between Science and

Technology." JSPT 4 (1998): 142-151.

Shepard, Philip T. "Impartiality and Interpretive Intervention in Technical Controversy."

Technological Transformation: Contextual and Conceptual Implications. P&T 5 (1999):

47-65.

––––––. "Technological Neutrality and the Changing Normative Context of Applied Science

Research." New Directions in the Philosophy of Technology. P&T 11 (1995): 163-184.

Shogan, Debra. "Disciplinary Technologies of Sport Performance." RPT 21 (2002): 93-109.

262

Shrader-Frechette, Kristin. "Adam Smith and Alma Mater: Technology and the Threat to

Academic Freedom." Europe, America, and Technology: Philosophical Perspectives.

P&T 8 (1991): 175-189.

––––––. "Adams, Inhaber, and Risk-Benefit Analysis: Ethical and Methodological Problems

with Two Recent Assessments of Nuclear Safety." RPT 3 (1980): 343-365.

––––––. "Calibrating Assessors of Technological and Environmental Risk." RPT 12 (1992): 147-

155.

––––––. "Environmental Impact Analysis, Technology Assessment, and the Problem of

Geographical Equity." RPT 5 (1982): 115-130.

––––––. "The Plutonium Economy: Technological Links and Epistemological Problems." RPT 8

(1985): 189-220.

––––––. "Public and Occupational Risk: The Double Standard." Technology and Contemporary

Life. P&T 4 (1988): 257-277.

––––––. "The Real Risks of Risk-Cost-Benefit Analysis." Technology and Responsibility. P&T 3

(1987): 343-357.

––––––. "Reductionist Philosophy of Technology: Stones Thrown from Inside a Glass House."

Techné: JSPT 5 (2000): 21-28.

––––––. "Risk and Technology Transfer: Equal Protection across National Borders."

Technological Transformation: Contextual and Conceptual Implications. P&T 5 (1999):

259-275.

––––––. "Technology Assessment and the Problem of Quantification." Philosophy and

Technology. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 80. P&T 1 (1983): 151-164.

263

––––––. "Technology Assessment, Expert Disagreement, and Democratic Procedures." RPT 8

(1985): 103-129.

––––––. "Technology, Bayesian Policymaking, and Democratic Process." Democracy in a

Technological Society. P&T 9 (1992): 123-137.

––––––. "Technology, Public Policy, and the Price-Anderson Act." RPT 3 (1980): 313-342.

Simmons, Jack. "Educational Technology and Academic Freedom." Techné: JSPT 5 (2001):

158-166.

Simon, Thomas. "Appropriate Technology and Inappropriate Politics." Technology and

Contemporary Life. P&T 4 (1988): 107-128.

Sinclair, George and W. V. Tilson. "The Relationship of Technology to Engineering." RPT 5

(1982): 87-97.

Singer, Bayla. "Automobiles and Femininity." RPT 13 (1993): 31-41.

Skolimowski, Henryk. "The Metaphysics of Paolo Soleri." RPT 3 (1980): 133-152.

––––––. "A New Social Philosophy as Technology Assessment." RPT 5 (1982): 130-141.

Smith, Janet Farrell. "Responsibility and Future Generations: A Constructivist Model."

Philosophy and Technology: Practical, Historical, and Other Dimensions. P&T 6 (1989):

169-186.

Soavi, Marzia. "Antirealism and Artefact Kinds." Techné: RPT 13 (2009): 93-107.

Soliday, Elizabeth. "Autonomy in Maternal Accounts of Birth after Caesarean." Techné: RPT 16

(2012): 62-70.

Sørensen, Estrid. "Comment on Norm Friesen's 'Dissection and Simulation: Brilliance and

Transparency, or Encumbrance and Disruption?'" Techné: RPT 15 (2011): 206-208.

264

Soudek, Ingrid H. and Kathryn A. Neeley. "The Match and Other Agents of Liberation: The Role

of Technology in the Social Thought of Louise Otto." RPT 14 (1994): 119-137.

Spence, Larry D. "Ivan Illich's H2O and the Waters of Forgetfulness." Europe, America, and

Technology: Philosophical Perspectives. P&T 8 (1991): 95-105.

Staley, Thomas W. "The Coding of Technical Images of Nanospace: Analogy, Disanalogy, and

the Asymmetry of Worlds.” Techné: RPT 12 (2008): 1-22.

Stanley, Manfred. "A Critical Appreciation [of Borgmann's Technology and the Character of

Contemporary Life]." Technology and Contemporary Life. P&T 4 (1988): 13-28.

Staudenmaier, John M., S.J. "Problematic Stimulation: Historians and Sociologists Constructing

Technology Studies." RPT 15 (1995): 93-102.

Stokes, Karina. "Bakhtin's Concept of Individualistic Ideolects as a Propitious Model of

Communication among Humans and between Humans and Computers." RPT 19 (2000):

233-252.

Stoner, Ian. "In Defense of Hyperlinks." Techné: RPT 7 (2004): 79-89.

Strijbos, Sytse. "Computer and World Picture: A Critical Appraisal of Herbert A. Simondon."

Broad and Narrow Interpretations of Philosophy of Technology. P&T 7 (1990): 67-86.

––––––. "Ethics and the Systemic Character of Modern Technology." JSPT 3 (1998): 160-169.

Ströker, Elisabeth. "Philosophy of Technology: Problems of a Philosophical Discipline."

Philosophy and Technology. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 80. P&T 1

(1983): 323-336.

Strombach, Werner. "Information' in Epistemological and Ontological Perspective." Philosophy

and Technology II: Information Technology and Computers in Theory and Practice.

Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 90. P&T 2 (1986): 75-81.

265

Strong, David. "Challenging Technology." RPT 14 (1994): 69-92.

––––––. "The Implications for Nature of Borgmann's Theory of Technology." RPT 13 (1993):

223-252.

––––––. "The Technological Subversion of Environmental Ethics." RPT 12 (1992): 33-66.

Sullins, John P., III. "Gödel's Incompleteness Theorems and Artificial Life." JSPT 2 (1997): 185-

195.

Sutz, Judith. "The Social Implications of Information Technologies: A Latin American

Perspective." Philosophy of Technology in Spanish Speaking Countries. P&T 10 (1993):

297-308.

Sviedrys, Romualdas. "A Conceptual Framework for Understanding Technology Transfer to the

Third World." Technological Transformation: Contextual and Conceptual Implications.

P&T 5 (1999): 185-200.

Sweet, William. "Religious Belief and the Influence of Technology." RPT 17 (1998): 249-267.

Swetlitz, Mark. "A Jewish Commentary on the Religious Origins of Technological Civilization."

RPT 6 (1983): 197-205.

Swiestra, Tsjalling. "From Critique to Responsibility: The Ethical Turn in the Technology

Debate.” JSPT 3 (1997): 45-48.

Tabachnick, David E. "The Politics and Philosophy of Anti-Science." Techné: RPT 9 (2005): 27-

43.

––––––. "Techne, Technology, and Tragedy." Techné: RPT 7 (2004): 90-111.

Tamburrini, Claudio. "After Doping, What? The Morality of the Genetic Engineering of

Athletes." RPT 21 (2002): 253-268.

266

Tatum, Jesse. "The Political Construction of Technology: A Call for Constructive Technology

Assessment." RPT 15 (1995): 103-115.

Temple, Katharine. "Doubts Concerning the Religious Origins of Technological Civilization."

RPT 6 (1983): 189-197.

––––––. "The Soclology of Jacques Ellul." RPT 3 (1980): 223-261.

Teschner, George and Alessandro Tomasi. "Technological Paradigm in Ancient Taoism."

Techné: RPT 13 (2009): 190-205.

Thomas, J. Mark. "Are Science and Technology Quasi-Religions?” RPT 10 (1990): 93-102.

Thomasma, David C. "Cultural Issues in Medical Research." RPT 3 (1980): 66-75.

Thompson, Paul B. "Putting Pragmatism to Work." Techné: JSPT 7 (2003): 41-44.

––––––. "Reply to Heyboer." New Directions in the Philosophy of Technology. P&T 11 (1995):

159-162.

––––––. "Sustainability as a Norm." JSPT 2 (1996): 99-110.

––––––. "Technological Values in the Applied Science Laboratory." New Directions in the

Philosophy of Technology. P&T 11 (1995): 139-151.

––––––. "Theorizing Technological and Institutional Change: Alienability, Rivalry and

Exclusion Cost." Techné: RPT 11 (2007): 19-31.

––––––. "Thinking about Thinking about Technology." Techné: JSPT 5 (2000): 29-34.

Tijmes, Pieter. "Euthanasia Considered as Device Paradigm." JSPT 3 (1997): 49-53.

––––––. "Preface: Dutch Chandeliers of Philosophy of Technology." JSPT 3 (1997): 1-3.

––––––. "Scarcity, Labor, and Modern Technology." RPT 17 (1998): 81-106.

Tijmes, Pieter and Peter-Paul Verbeek. "The Place on the Map." RPT 17 (1998): 3-8.

267

Tillberg-Webb, Heather and Johannes Strobel. "Analysis of Technological Ideologies in

Education: A Translation of Lessons from Technological Dystopian Literature into

Educational Theory." Techné: RPT 15 (2011): 170-181.

Tobar-Arbulu, José Felix. "Technopraxiology and Development." RPT 9 (1989): 135-154.

Tondl, Ladislav. "Changes in Cognitive and Value Orientations in System Design." Broad and

Narrow Interpretations of Philosophy of Technology. P&T 7 (1990): 87-98.

––––––. "Information and Systems Dimensions of Technological Artifacts." JSPT 4 (1999): 195-

207.

Toumey, Christopher P. "Narratives for Nanotech: Anticipating Public Reactions to

Nanotechnology." Techné: RPT 8 (2004): 88-116.

––––––. "Reading Feynman Into Nanotechnology: A Text for a New Science.” Techné: RPT 12

(2008): 133-168.

Trau, Jane Mary. "God-Talk, Physicalism, and Technology: A Mutual Endeavor." RPT 10

(1990): 291-295.

––––––. "Humanae Vitae and the Current Instruction on the Origins of Human Life." RPT 10

(1990): 233-242.

Truitt, Willis H. "Dialectics and the Primacy of Human Labor Power." RPT 5 (1982): 261-268.

––––––. "Skolimowski on Soleri." RPT 3 (1980): 153-158.

––––––. "Values in Science." RPT 1 (1978): 119-130.

Tuchel, Klaus. "Friedrich Dessauer as Philosopher of Technology: Notes on His Dialogue with

Jaspers and Heidegger." RPT 5 (1982): 269-280.

Tuman, Myron. "Holding On, and Letting Go: A Review of Holding On to Reality: The Nature

of Information at the Turn of the Millennium." Techné: JSPT 6 (2002): 12-20.

268

Vaccari, Andres. "Dissolving Nature: How Descartes Made Us Posthuman." Techné: RPT 16

(2012): 138-186.

Vaesen, Krist. "How Norms in Technology Ought to Be Interpreted." Techné: RPT 10 (2006):

95-108.

Vahanian, Gabriel. "Artificial Intelligence and Western Culture: A Christian Approach." RPT 10

(1990): 167-183.

Valk, A. C. van der. "Cloning as a Test Case of Autonomous Technology." JSPT 3 (1997): 54-

59.

Valk, Ton van der. "The Negative Teleological Metaphysics of Hans Jonas." RPT 19 (2000):

253-279.

Vallor, Shannon. "Knowing What to Wish For: Human Enhancement Technology, Dignity and

Virtue." Techné: RPT 15 (2011): 137-155.

Vanderburg, Willem H. "Technique and Responsibility: Think Globally, Act Locally, according

to Jacques Ellul." Technology and Responsibility. P&T 3 (1987): 115-132.

Varney, Wendy. "Tumbling into Gendered Territory: Gymnastics and Its Technologies." RPT 21

(2002): 177-194.

Verbeek, Peter-Paul. "Accompanying Technology: Philosophy of Technology after the Ethical

Turn." Techné: RPT 14 (2010): 49-54.

––––––. "Devices of Engagement: On Borgmann's Philosophy of Information and Technology."

Techné: JSPT 6 (2002): 48-63.

––––––. "The Thing about Technology: Toward a Phenomenology of Technological Artifacts."

RPT 19 (2000): 281-299.

269

Verdugo S., Carlos. "Ethics, Science, and Technology." Philosophy of Technology in Spanish

Speaking Countries. P&T 10 (1993): 61-67.

Verene, Donald Phillip. "Technological Desire." RPT 7 (1984): 99-112.

––––––. "Technology and the Ship of Fools." RPT 5 (1982): 281-298.

Vermaas, Pieter E. "Philosophy of Engineering and Technology: A New Book Series." Techné:

RPT 14 (2010): 55-59.

Vincenti, Walter. "The Experimental Assessment of Engineering Theory as a Tool for Design."

Techné: JSPT 5 (2001): 124-130.

Vincenzo, Joseph. "Aristotle and Ellul: Political Phronesis and the Politics of Technique." RPT

15 (1995): 119-142.

Vlot, Ad. "Toward a Juridical Turn for the Ethics of Technology? An Aerospace Case." RPT 20

(2001): 207-218.

––––––. "Toward a Juridical Turn for the Ethics of Technology? Final Remarks." RPT 20

(2001): 245-250.

Vogel, Steven. "New Science, New Nature: The Habermas-Marcuse Debate Revisited." RPT 11

(1991): 157-178.

––––––. "On Michael Zimmerman's Contesting Earth's Future." RPT 18 (1999): 189-198.

Vries, Marc J. De. "Analyzing the Complexity of Nanotechnology." Techné: RPT 8 (2005): 62-

75.

––––––. "Gilbert Simondon and the Dual Nature of Artifacts." Techné: RPT 12 (2008): 23-35.

––––––. "The Nature of Technological Knowledge: Extending Empirically Informed Studies into

What Engineers Know." Techné: JSPT 6 (2003): 117-130.

270

Wachtel, Edward. "To an Eye in a Fixed Position: Glass, Art, and Vision." New Directions in the

Philosophy of Technology. P&T 11 (1995): 41-61.

Waelbers, Katinka and Adam Briggle. "Three Schools of Thought on Freedom in Liberal,

Technological Societies." Techné: RPT 14 (2010): 176-193.

Waks, Leonard J. "Ivan Illich and Deschooling Society: A Reappraisal." Europe, America, and

Technology: Philosophical Perspectives. P&T 8 (1991): 57-73.

––––––. "Ivan Illich's Philosophy of Technology: Introduction." Europe, America, and

Technology: Philosophical Perspectives. P&T 8 (1991): 15-16.

––––––. "The Oil in the Machine: Jacques Ellul on Human Techniques in the Technological

Society." RPT 9 (1989): 155-170.

––––––. "Public Intellectuals and Interdisciplinary Studies." RPT 16 (1997): 61-70.

––––––. "STS Education and the Paradox of Green Studies." Europe, America, and Technology:

Philosophical Perspectives. P&T 8 (1991): 247-257.

––––––. "Symposium on Education in Science, Technology, and Values: Introduction." Europe,

America, and Technology: Philosophical Perspectives. P&T 8 (1991): 193-195.

––––––. "Technology's School: The Challenge to Philosophy." RPT Supplement 3 (1995): 1-267.

Waks, Leonard J. and Carl Mitcham. "Rethinking Technology." RPT 15 (1995): 235-239.

Walterscheid, Kathryn A. "Don Delillo and Daniel Boorstin: White Noise as an Illustration of

"Technology and Democracy"." RPT 14 (1994): 45-57.

Wang, Nan and Wenjuan Yin. "What is the Character of the Techno-Human Condition?”

Techné: RPT 16 (2012): 330-336.

Ward, Andrew. "Virtual Communities: Ontology and Politics." Techné: RPT 14 (2010): 237-

251.

271

Warren, Karen J. "Women, Nature, and Technology: An Ecofeminist Philosophical Perspective."

RPT 13 (1993): 13-29.

Wartofsky, Marx W. "Comments on Hans Jonas: Philosophical Aspects of Technology." RPT 5

(1982): 144-152.

––––––. "Good Science-Bad Science or Dr. Frankenstein's Dilemma." RPT 7 (1984): 177-190.

––––––. "Technology, Power, and Truth: Political and Epistemological Reflections on the Fourth

Revolution." Democracy in a Technological Society. P&T 9 (1992): 15-34.

Weil, Simone. "Two Uncollected Letters on Machines." RPT 2 (1979): 223-234.

Weiss, Dennis M. "Human—Technology—World." Techné: RPT 12 (2008): 110-119.

Wennemann, Daryl J. "The Contemporaneity of the Noncontemporaneous, or the Problem of

Uneven Technological Development." RPT 13 (1993): 253-263.

––––––. "Freedom and Dialectic in Ellul's Thought." RPT 11 (1991): 67-75.

––––––. "An Interpretation of Jacques Ellul's Dialectical Method." Broad and Narrow

Interpretations of Philosophy of Technology. P&T 7 (1990): 181-192.

––––––. "Manheim and Ellul on the Problem of Freedom in a Technological Society: Planned

Society or Technological Civilization?” RPT 15 (1995): 143-162.

––––––. "Middle Level Theory in Ellul's Thought: Where Theory and Practice Meet." RPT 14

(1994): 235-250.

Wesson, Anthony. "Religion, Technology, and Human Autonomy." Technology and

Responsibility. P&T 3 (1987): 243-257.

Weston, Anthony. "Ivan Illich and the Radical Critique of Tools." RPT 9 (1989): 171-182.

Wettstein, A. Arnold. "Ultimate Weapons in a Penultimate Age: A Theological Assessment of

SDI Technology." RPT 10 (1990): 25-41.

272

Whitbeck, Caroline. "Investigating Professional Responsibility." Techné: RPT 8 (2004): 79-98.

Wiley, Karen B. "The Evolution of "Wetlands" as a Regulatory Concept." RPT 17 (1998): 141-

159.

Winner, Langdon. "Decentralization: Its Meaning in Politics and Material Culture." RPT 6

(1983): 43-52.

––––––. "Engineering Ethics and Political Imagination." Broad and Narrow Interpretations of

Philosophy of Technology. P&T 7 (1990): 53-64.

––––––. "Introduction." Democracy in a Technological Society. P&T 9 (1992): 1-11.

––––––. "Myth Information: Romantic Politics in the Computer Revolution." Philosophy and

Technology II: Information Technology and Computers in Theory and Practice. Boston

Studies in the Philosophy of Science 90. P&T 2 (1986): 269-289.

––––––. "Mythinformation: Romantic Politics in the Computer Revolution." RPT 7 (1984): 287-

304.

––––––. "Techné and Politeia: The Technical Constitution of Society." Philosophy and

Technology. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 80. P&T 1 (1983): 97-111.

––––––. "Technological Euphoria and Contemporary Citizenship." Techné: RPT 9 (2005): 124-

133.

Wishloff, Jim. "Patenting and Transgenic Organisms: A Reply to Lee." Techné: JSPT 6 (2003):

176-180.

Woodruff, Russell. "Artifacts, Neutrality, and the Ambiguity of "Use"." RPT 16 (1997): 119-

127.

Wosk, Julie. "The ‘Electric Eve’: Galvanizing Women in Nineteenth- and Twentieth-Century Art

and Technology." RPT 13 (1993): 43-56.

273

Xia, Baohua. "Reconstructing the Disciplinary Consensus of the Philosophy of Technology:

Henry Dircks and the Philosophy of Invention." Techné: RPT 15 (2011): 16-22.

Xue, Lan. "Appropriate Technology in Technology Transfer: A View from the People's Republic

of China." Technological Transformation: Contextual and Conceptual Implications. P&T

5 (1999): 201-225.

Yanov, Dvora. "Ecologies of Technological Metaphors and the Theme of Control.” JSPT 1

(1996): 171-184.

Zandvoort, Henk. "Codes of Conduct, the Law, and Technological Design and Development."

RPT 20 (2001): 193-205.

––––––. "Self Determination, Strict Liability, and Ethical Problems in Engineering." RPT 20

(2001): 219-243.

Zea, Leopoldo. "Satellites and Our Morality." Philosophy of Technology in Spanish Speaking

Countries. P&T 10 (1993): 133-141.

Zenzen, Michael. "Technology, Pornography, and the Object of Desire." RPT 13 (1993): 101-

117.

Zimmerli, Walther Ch. "Forecast, Value, and the Recent Phenomenon of Non-Acceptance: The

Limits of Technology Assessment." Philosophy and Technology. Boston Studies in the

Philosophy of Science 80. P&T 1 (1983): 165-184.

––––––. "Human Minds, Robots, and the Technician of the Future." RPT 9 (1989): 183-196.

––––––. "Variety in Technology, Unity in Responsibility?” Technology and Contemporary Life.

P&T 4 (1988): 279-293.

––––––. "Who Is to Blame for Data Pollution? On Individual Moral Responsibility with

Information Technology." Philosophy and Technology II: Information Technology and

274

Computers in Theory and Practice. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 90. P&T

2 (1986): 291-305.

Zimmerman, Michael E. "Heidegger and Marcuse: Technology as Ideology." RPT 2 (1979):

245-261.

––––––. "Humanism, Ontology, and the Nuclear Arms Race." RPT 6 (1983): 157-172.

––––––. "Recognizing the Limits of Contesting Earth's Future." RPT 18 (1999): 199-216.

––––––. "Reply to McGinn." RPT 2 (1979): 155-156.

––––––. "Technological Culture and the End of Philosophy." RPT 2 (1979): 137-145.

275

REFERENCES

Abram, David. “Between the Body and the Breathing Earth: A Reply to Ted Toadvine.” EE 27

(2005): 171-190. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics200527229.

––––––. “Merleau-Ponty and the Voice of the Earth.” EE 2 (1988): 101-120. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics19881027.

––––––. "Nature at Arm's Length." RPT 15 (1995): 177-180.

Anderson, Albert A. "Why Prometheus Suffers: Technology and the Ecological Crisis." SPT 1

(1995): 28-36. doi: 10.5840/techne199511/28.

Aristotle. Metaphysics. Translated by Joe Sachs. Newburyport, MA: Focus Publishing, 2002.

Aristotle. Nicomachean Ethics. Translated by Joe Sachs. Santa Fe, New Mexico: Green Lion

Press, 1999.

Aristotle. Physics. Translated by Joe Sachs. New Brunswick, New Jersey: Rutgers University

Press, 1995.

Attfield, Robin. "Social History, Religion, and Technology: An Interdisciplinary Investigation

into Lynn White, Jr.'s ‘Roots.’” EE 31 (2009): 31-50. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics20093114.

Banchetti, Maria. Introduction. RPT 18 (1999): 3-11.

Bannon, Bryan. "Re-envisioning Nature: The Role of Aesthetics in Environmental Ethics." EE

33 (2011): 415-436. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics201133445.

Beauchamp, Tom L. and James F. Childress. Principles of Biomedical Ethics. Sixth edition. New

York: Oxford University Press, 2009.

Beggs, Donald. "The Interdisciplinary Constraint on Ecological Reason." SPT 2 (1997): 140-

144. doi: 10.5840/techne199723/418.

276

Birch, Thomas H. “The Incarceration of Wildness: Wilderness Areas as Prisons.” EE 12 (1990):

3-26. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19901215.

Blad, Sylvia. "The Impact of "Anthropotechnology" on Human Evolution." Techné: RPT 14

(2010): 72-87. doi: 10.5840/techne201014211.

Borgmann, Albert. Technology and The Character of Contemporary Life: A Philosophical

Inquiry (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984.

Brennan, Andrew. "The Moral Standing of Natural Objects." EE 6 (1984): 35-56. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics19846118.

Brockmann, Stephen. "Green without Red?: The Limits of Technological Critique." RPT 13

(1993): 283-299.

Bunge, Mario. "Development and the Environment." Technological Transformation: Contextual

and Conceptual Implications. P&T 5 (1999): 285-304.

Callicott, J. Baird. "After the Industrial Paradigm, What?" RPT 18 (1999): 13-26.

––––––. “Animal Liberation: A Triangular Affair.” EE 2 (1980): 311-338.

––––––. “The Case against Moral Pluralism.” EE 12 (1990): 99-124. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics199012220.

––––––. “Do Deconstructive Ecology and Sociobiology Undermine Leopold’s Land Ethic?” EE

18 (1996): 353-372. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19961843.

––––––. “Elements of an Environmental Ethic.” EE 1 (1979): 71-81. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics19791110.

––––––. “Hume’s Is/Ought Dichotomy and the Relation of Ecology to Leopold’s Land Ethic.”

EE 4 (1982): 163-174. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19824214.

277

––––––. “Intrinsic Value, Quantum Theory, and Environmental Ethics.” EE 7 (1985): 257-275.

doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19857334.

––––––. “Many Indigenous Worlds or the Indigenous World? A Reply to My ‘Indigenous’

Critics.” EE 22 (2000): 291-310. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics200022319.

––––––. “The Metaphysical Implications of Ecology.” EE 8 (1986): 301-316. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics19868432.

––––––. "The Role of Technology in the Evolving Concept of Nature." RPT 13 (1993): 201-222.

––––––. “Rolston on Intrinsic Value: A Deconstruction.” EE 14 (1992): 129-143. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics199214229.

––––––. “Traditional American Indian and Western European Attitudes toward Nature: An

Overview.” EE 4 (1982): 293-318. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics1982443.

Carpenter, Stanley R. "Sustainability and Common-Pool Resources: Alternatives to Tragedy."

SPT 3 (1998): 170-183. doi: 10.5840/techne19983420.

––––––. “Toward Refined Indicators of Sustainability.” SPT 2 (1997): 37-43. doi:

10.5840/techne19972225.

Cerezo, José Antonio López, and Marta Gonzales Garcia. "Lay Knowledge and Public

Participation in Technological and Environmental Policy." SPT 2 (1996): 36-48. doi:

10.5840/techne1996216.

Chapman, Anne. "Genetic Engineering: The Unnatural Argument." Techné: RPT 9 (2005).

http://scholar.lib.vt.edu/ejournals/SPT/v9n2/chapman.html.

Collins, Randall. The Sociology of Philosophies: A Global Theory of Intellectual Change.

Cambridge, Massachusetts: Belknap Press, 1998.

278

Coolen, T. Maarten T. "Philosophical Anthropology and the Problem of Responsibility in

Technology." Technology and Responsibility. P&T 3 (1987): 41-65.

Cowell, C. Mark. "Ecological Restoration and Environmental Ethics." EE 15 (1993): 19-32. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics199315136.

Dasheng, Gao and Zou Tsing. "Philosophy of Technology in China." Philosophy and

Technology: Practical, Historical, and Other Dimensions. P&T 6 (1989): 133-151.

Dijk, Paul van. "Environmental Ethics and the Recovery of Culture." RPT 17 (1998): 25-43.

Dion, Michel. “Institutionalizing Environmental Ethics in the Corporation.” RPT 13 (1993): 301-

318.

––––––. “A Typology of Corporate Environmental Policies.” EE 20 (1998): 151-162. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics199820229.

Doeleman, J. A. "Environment and Technology: Speculating on the Long Run." RPT 12 (1992):

5-32.

––––––. “On the Social Rate of Discount: The Case for Macroenvironmental Policy.” EE 2

(1980): 45-58. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19802112.

Drengson, Alan R. “Art and Imagination in Technological Society.” RPT 6 (1983): 77-91.

––––––. “Shifting Paradigms: From the Technocratic to the Person-Planetary.” EE 2 (1980):

221-240. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics1980233.

Durbin, Paul T. "Can There Be a Best Ethic of Sustainability?" JSPT 2 (1996): 84-90. doi:

10.5840/techne19972228.

––––––. “Introduction to the New Journal,” JSPT 1 (1995): 2. doi: 10.5840/techne199511/21.

––––––. “Introduction to the Series.” RPT 3 (1980): 1-4.

279

––––––. Philosophy of Technology: In Search of Discourse Synthesis, published as a special

issue of Techné: RPT 10, no. 2 (2006).

––––––. Preface. SPT 2 (1997): 112.

Elliot, Robert. “Faking Nature.” Inquiry 25 (March 1982), 81-93. doi:

10.1080/00201748208601955.

––––––. “Instrumental Value in Nature as a Basis for the Intrinsic Value of Nature as a Whole.”

EE 27 (2005): 43-56. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics200527140.

Ellul, Jacques. "Nature, Technique and Artificiality." RPT 3 (1980): 263-283.

––––––. The Technological Society. Translated by John Wilkinson. New York: Vintage, 1964.

Ferré, Frederick. “Obstacles on the Path to Organismic Ethics: Some Second Thoughts.” EE 16

(1989): 231-241. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics198911314.

––––––. “On Matter and Machines.” RPT 18 (1999): 131-142.

––––––. “On Replicating Persons: Ethics and the Technology of Cloning.” JSPT 3 (1997).

http://scholar.lib.vt.edu/ejournals/SPT/v3n2/FERRE.html.

––––––. “Philosophy and Technology after Twenty Years,” SPT 1 (1995): 4-7. doi:

10.5840/techne199511/23.

––––––. “Philosophy and Technology: Another Look 15 Years Later,” Techné: RPT 14 (2010):

23-25. doi: 10.5840/techne20101414.

––––––. “Technology, Nature, and Miracle.” RPT 10 (1990): 281-286.

––––––. “Value, Time, and Nature.” EE 17 (1995): 417-431. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics19951748.

Field, Terri. "Caring Relationships with Natural and Artificial Environments." EE 17 (1995):

307-320. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199517320.

280

Foltz, Bruce. "On Heidegger and the Interpretation of Environmental Crisis." EE 6 (1984): 323-

338. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics1984643.

Frodeman, Robert. "Philosophy Unbound: Environmental Ethics at the End of the World." EE 30

(2008): 313-324.

––––––. “The Policy Turn in Environmental Ethics.” EE 28 (2006): 3-20. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics200628136.

––––––. “Radical Environmentalism and the Political Roots of Postmodernism: Differences that

Make a Difference.” EE 14 (1992): 307-319. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19921443.

––––––. “The Rebirth of Gaia and the Closure of Homo Technologicus.” RPT 18 (1999): 95-113.

Fuller, Steve. “Social Epistemology: A Quarter-Century Itinerary.” Social Epistemology: A

Journal of Knowledge, Culture and Policy 26: 267-283. doi:

10.1080/02691728.2012.714415.

––––––. Sociology of Intellectual Life. London: Sage, 2009.

French, William C. “Against Biospherical Egalitarianism.” EE 17 (1995): 39-57. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics199517135.

Furrow, Dwight. "The Discomforts of Home: Nature and Technology in Hand's End." RPT 15

(1995): 169-175.

Groothuis, Douglas. "Bacon and Pascal on Mastery over Nature." RPT 14 (1994): 191-203.

Grange, Joseph. “Being, Feeling, and Environment.” EE 7 (1985), 351-364. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics19857432.

––––––. “Whitehead and Heidegger on Technological Goodness.” RPT 14 (1994): 161-173.

Gunn, Alastair S. “Engineering Ethics and Hazardous Waste Management.” RPT 12 (1992): 135-

146.

281

––––––. “Environmental Ethics and Tropical Rain Forests: Should Greens Have Standing?” EE

16 (1994): 21-40. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199416139.

––––––. “Rethinking Communities: Environmental Ethics in an Urbanized World.” EE 20

(1998): 341-360. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19982043.

––––––. “The Restoration of Species and Natural Environments.” EE 13 (1991): 291-310. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics199113437.

––––––. “Traditional Ethics and the Moral Status of Animals.” EE 5 (1983): 133-153. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics1983528.

––––––. “Why Should We Care about Rare Species?” EE 2 (1980): 17-37. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics1980217.

Guthrie, W. K. C. A History of Greek Philosophy: The Earlier Presocratics and the

Pythagoreans. Vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1962.

Hargrove, Eugene. “From the Editor: How, When, Where, Why.” EE 1 (1979): 1. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics1979111.

––––––. “New Directions.” EE 3 (1981): 291-292. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics1981341.

Harris, Charles E., Michael S. Pritchard, Michael J. Rabins, Ray James, and Elaine Englehart.

Engineering Ethics: Concepts and Cases. Fifth edition. Boston: Wadsworth, 2014.

Harrison, III, Frank R. "The Judeo-Christian Tradition and Crises in Contemporary Technology."

RPT 10 (1990): 103-118.

Hickman, Larry A. "Doing and Making in a Democracy: Dewey's Experience of Technology."

Philosophy and Technology: Practical, Historical, and Other Dimensions. P&T 6 (1989):

97-111.

282

–––––––. “Green Pragmatism: Reals without Realism, Ideals without Idealism." RPT 18 (1999):

39-56.

Higgs, Eric. "Musings at the Confluence of the Rivers Techné and Oikos." RPT 12 (1992): 243-

258.

Higgs, Eric, Andrew Light, and David Strong, eds. Introduction. Technology and the Good Life?

Edited by Eric Higgs, Andrew Light, and David Strong. Chicago: University of Chicago

Press, 2000.

Hook, Bill. “The Fate of Skills in the Information Age.” RPT 19 (2000): 101-123.

––––––. “Intrinsic Value: Under the Scrutiny of Information and Evolutionary Theory.” EE 25

(2003): 359-373. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics20032543.

Hottois, Gilbert. “Technoscience.” In the Encyclopedia of Science, Technology, and Ethics. Vol.

4 Edited by Carl Mitcham. 1914-1916. Detroit: Thomson Gale, 2005.

––––––. “Technoscience: Nihilistic Power Versus a New Ethical Consciousness.” P&T 3 (1987):

69-84.

Howard, Don. "Commoner on Reductionism." EE 1 (1979): 159-176. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics19791224.

Humphrey, Peter. "The Ethics of Earthworks." EE 7 (1985): 5-21. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics1985717.

Hurka, Thomas. “Virtuous Act, Virtuous Dispositions.” Analysis 66 (2006): 69-76. doi:

10.1111/j.1467-8284.2006.00591.x.

Ihde, Don. "Phil-Tech Meets Eco-Phil: The Environment." RPT 18 (1999): 27-38.

––––––. "Whole Earth Measurements." JSPT 2 (1996): 91-98. doi: 10.5840/techne19972229.

283

Jonas, Hans. The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for a Technological Age.

Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984.

––––––. The Phenomenon of Life: Toward a Philosophical Biology. Evanston, Illinois:

Northwestern University Press, 2001.

––––––. “Seventeenth Century and After: The Meaning of the Scientific and Technological

Revolution.” In Philoosophical Essays: From Ancient Creed to Technological Man. New

York: Atropos Press, 1980.

––––––. “Technology as a Subject for Ethics.” Social Research 49 (1982): 891-898.

http://www.jstor.org/stable/40971222, accessed 12 February 2015.

Jung, Hwa Yol. “The Genealogy of Technological Rationality in the Human Sciences.” RPT 9

(1989): 59-75.

––––––. “Language, Politics, and Technology.” RPT 5 (1982): 43-63.

––––––. "Marxism, Ecology, and Technology." EE 5 (1983): 169-171. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics1983522.

––––––. “The Orphic Voice and Ecology.” EE 3 (1981): 329-340. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics1981344.

Kant, Immanuel. Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals. Translated by James W. Ellington.

Third edition. Indianapolis: Hackett, 1993.

Katz, Eric. "Artefacts and Functions: A Note on the Value of Nature." EE 18 (1996): 222-224.

doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199618236.

––––––. "The Big Lie: Human Restoration of Nature." RPT 12 (1992): 231-241.

––––––. “The Call of the Wild: The Struggle against Domination and the Technological Fix of

Nature.” EE 14 (1992): 265-273. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199214321.

284

––––––. “Environmental Ethics: A Select Annotated Bibliography, 1983-1987.” RPT 9 (1989):

251-285.

––––––. “Environmental Ethics: A Select Annotated Bibliography II, 1987-1990.” RPT 12

(1992): 287-324.

––––––. "Further Adventures in the Case against Restoration." EE 34 (2012): 67-97. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics20123416.

––––––. “Organism, Community, and the ‘Substitution Problem,’” EE 7 (1985): 241-256. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics19857337.

––––––. "The Place of Nature in the Understanding of Technology: One Critical Reading of

Thinking Through Technology." RPT 16 (1997): 171-178.

––––––. “A Pragmatic Reconsideration of Anthropocentrism.” EE 21 (1999): 377-390. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics19992144.

––––––. “Searching for Intrinsic Value: Pragmatism and Despair in Environmental Ethics.” EE 9

(1987): 231-241. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics1987935.

––––––. “Utilitarianism and Preservation.” EE 1 (1979): 357-364. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics19791430.

Katz, Eric and Lauren Oechsli, “Moving beyond Anthropocentrism: Environmental Ethics,

Development, and the Amazon.” EE 15 (1993): 49-59. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics199315139.

Kaufmann, Frederik. "Machines, Sentience, and the Scope of Morality." EE 16 (1994): 57-70.

doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199416142.

King, Roger J. H. "Environmental Ethics and the Built Environment." EE 22 (2000): 115-131.

doi: 10.5840/enviroethics200022230.

285

Klein, Jacob. "On the Nature of Nature." RPT 2 (1979): 173-188.

Koelega, Dick G. A. "Technology, Ecology, Autonomy, and the State." SPT 1 (1995): 62-70.

doi: 10.5840/techne199511/212.

Latour, Bruno. Science in Action. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1987.

Leddy, Thomas. "A Defense of Arts-Based Appreciation of Nature." EE 27 (2005): 299-315.

doi: 10.5840/enviroethics200527318.

Lee, Keekok. “Instrumentalism and the Last Person Argument.” EE 15 (1993): 333-344. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics19931545.

––––––. "Patenting and Transgenic Organisms: A Philosophical Exploration." Techné: JSPT 6

(2003): 166-175. doi: 10.5840/techne20036323.

––––––. “The Source and Locus of Intrinsic Value: A Reexamination.” EE 18(1996): 297-309.

doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199618320.

Lemons, John. “Atmospheric Carbon Dioxide: Environmental Ethics and Environmental Facts.”

EE 5 (1993): 21-32. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19835132.

––––––. “Cooperation and Stability as a Basis for Environmental Ethics.” EE 3 (1981): 219-230.

doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19813320.

Lemons, and Charles Malone, “The Nuclear Waste Policy Act and Its Amendments.” RPT 11

(1991): 5-32.

Lemons, John, Donald A. Brown, and Gary E. Varner, “Congress, Consistency, and

Environmental Law.” EE 12 (1990): 311-327. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199012429.

Leopold, Aldo. “The Land Ethic.” In A Sand County Almanac. 237-264. New York: Ballantine,

1966.

286

Light, Andrew. “Critical Theorist of Technology: Feenberg on Marx and Democracy.” RPT 16

(1996): 131-137.

––––––. “Media, Identity, and Politics: As Critique of Kellner.” RPT 17 (1998): 187-200.

––––––. “The Role of Technology in Environmental Questions.” RPT 12 (1992): 83-104.

––––––. "Three Questions on Hyperreality." RPT 15 (1995): 211-222.

Light, Andrew and Eric Higgs. “The Politics of Ecological Restoration.” EE 18 (1996): 227-247.

doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199618315.

Light, Andrew and David Roberts. “Toward New Foundations in Philosophy of Technology:

Mitcham and Wittgenstein on Descriptions.” RPT 19 (2000): 125-147.

Lo, Yeuk-Sze. "Natural and Artifactual: Restored Nature as Subject." EE 21 (1999): 247-266.

doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199921316.

Lovekin, David. "Rothenberg, Ramelli, and Heidegger: Considerations of Otherness." RPT 15

(1995): 181-190.

Manes, Christopher. "Philosophy and the Environmental Task." EE 10 (1988): 75-82. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics198810124.

Marietta, Don E., Jr. "Decisions Regarding Technology: The Human Factor." RPT 18 (1999):

57-72.

––––––. “Ethical Holism and Individuals,” EE 10 (1988):251-258. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics198810314.

––––––. “The Interrelationship of Ecological Science and Environmental Ethics.” EE 1, no. 3

(1979): 195-207. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19791327.

––––––. “Knowledge and Obligation in Environmental Ethics: A Phenomenological Approach.”

EE 4 (1982): 153-162. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19824221.

287

––––––. “World Views and Moral Decisions: A Reply to Tom Regan.” EE 2 (1980): 369-371.

doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19802429.

Meyer-Abich, Klaus Michael. “Toward a Practical Philosophy of Nature.” EE 1 (1979): 293-308.

doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19791423.

––––––. “What Sort of Technology Permits the Language of Nature? Conditions for Controlling

Nature-Domination Constitutionally." Philosophy and Technology. Boston Studies in the

Philosophy of Science 80. P&T 1 (1983): 211-232.

Mitcham, Carl. "On Never Being through Thinking through Technology." RPT 16 (1997): 179-

182.

Mitcham, Carl and Robert Mackey, eds., Philosophy and Technology: Readings in the

Philosophical Problems of Technology. New York: Free Press, 1983[1972].

Mitcham, Carl and René von Schomberg. “The Ethics of Engineers: From Occupational Role

Responsibility to Public Co-Responsibility.” RPT 20 (2000): 167-189.

Murphy, Andrew R. "Enviromentalism, Antimodernism, and the Recurrent Rhetoric of Decline."

EE 25 (2003): 79-98. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics200325146.

Nieto, César Cuello. "Toward a Holistic Approach to the Ideal of Sustainability." JSPT 2 (1996):

79-83. doi: 10.5840/techne19972227.

Nietzsche, Friedrich. Beyond Good and Evil. Translated by Judith Norman. Edited by Rolf-Peter

Horstmann and Judith Norman. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002.

Norton, Byron. “Environmental Ethics and Weak Anthropocentrism.” EE 6, no. 2 (Summer

1984): 131-148. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19846233.

Odum, Eugene P. “The Strategy of Ecosystem Development.” Science 164 (1969): 262-270.

288

Paden, Roger, Laurlyn K. Harmon, and Charles R. Milling. "Philosophical Histories of the

Aesthetics of Nature." EE 35 (2013): 57-77. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics20133516.

Palamar, Colette R. “Restorashyn: Ecofeminist Restoration.” EE 28, no. 3 (Fall 2006): 285-301.

doi: 10.5840/enviroethics200628318.

Pinch, Trevor J. and Wiebe E. Bijker. “The Social Construction of Facts and Artifacts: Or How

the Sociology of Science and the Sociology of Technology Might Benefit Each Other.” In

The Social Construction of Technological Systems. Edited by Wiebe E. Bijker, Thomas P.

Hughes, and Trevor J. Pinch. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press, 1987.

Plumwood, Val. Feminism and the Mastery of Nature. New York: Routledge, 1993.

Pohl, Sarah. "Technology and the Wilderness Experience." EE 28 (2006): 147-163. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics200628229.

Post, John F. "On Reenchanting the World." RPT 10 (1990): 243-279.

Preston, Christopher J. “Epistemology and Intrinsic Values: Norton and Callicott’s Critiques of

Rolston.” EE 20 (1998): 409-428. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19982047.

––––––. "The Promise and Threat of Nanotechnology: Can Environmental Ethics Guide Us?"

Hyle 11 (2005): 19-44. http://www.hyle.org/journal/issues/11-1/preston.htm.

Preston, Christopher J. and Steven H. Corey, “Public Health and Environmentalism: Adding

Garbage to the History of Environmental Ethics.” EE 27 (2005): 3-21. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics200527138.

Rapp, Friedrich. "Explosion of Needs, Quality of Life, and the Ecology Problem." SPT 1 (1995):

71-73. doi: 10.5840/techne199511/27.

Regan, Tom. “The Nature and the Possibility of an Environmental Ethic.” EE 3 (1981): 19-34.

doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19813131.

289

Rolston III, Holmes. “Are Values in Nature Subjective or Objective?” EE 4 (1982): 125-151.

doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19824218.

––––––. “Can and Ought We to Follow Nature?” EE 1 (1979): 7-30. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics1979114.

––––––. “Environmental Ethics in Antarctica.” EE 24 (2002): 115-134. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics200224226.

––––––. "A Managed Earth and the End of Nature?" RPT 18 (1999): 143-164.

––––––. “Mountain Majesties above Fruited Plains: Culture, Nature, and Rocky Mountain

Aesthetics.” EE 30 (2008): 3-20. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics200830114.

––––––. “Values in Nature.” EE 3 (1981): 113-128. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19813245.

––––––. “Valuing Wildlands.” EE 7, no. 1 (1985): 23-48. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19857111.

Ross, W. D. The Foundations of Ethics. London: Clarendon Press, 1939.

––––––. The Right and the Good, edited by Philip Stratton-Lake. Oxford: Oxford University

Press, 2002.

Rothenberg, David. "Feet on the Ground: Responses to Hand's End." RPT 15 (1995): 191-198.

Saito, Yuriko. "Appreciating Nature on Its Own Terms." EE 20 (1998): 135-149. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics199820228.

––––––. "Ecological Design: Promises and Challenges." EE 24 (2002): 243-261. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics200224314.

Sassower, Raphael. "Intellectual Responsibility for an Ecology Agenda." SPT 1 (1995): 74-82.

doi: 10.5840/techne199511/214.

Schadewaldt, Wolfgang. "The Concepts of Nature and Technique According to the Greeks."

RPT 2 (1979): 159-171.

290

Schiemann, Gregor. "Nanotechnology and Nature: On Two Criteria for Understanding their

Relationship." Hyle 8 (2005). http://www.hyle.org/journal/issues/11-1/schiemann.htm.

Schirmacher, Wolfgang. "Eco-Sophia." RPT 9 (1989): 125-134.

––––––. “Homo Generator: The Challenge of Gene Technology." Translated by Viriginia

Cutrufelli. Technology and Responsibility. P&T 3 (1987): 203-225.

Sellars, Wilfrid. “Philosophy and the Scientific Image of Man.” In In the Space of Reasons:

Selected Essays of Wilfrid Sellars. Edited by Kevin Scharp and Robert B. Brandom. 369-

408. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 2007.

Shrader-Frechette, Kristin. "Adam Smith and Alma Mater: Technology and the Threat to

Academic Freedom." Europe, America, and Technology: Philosophical Perspectives.

P&T 8 (1991): 175-189.

––––––. “Adams, Inhaber, and Risk-Benefit Analysis: Ethical and Methodological Problems

with Two Recent Assessments of Nuclear Power.” RPT 3 (1980): 343-365.

––––––. “Calibrating Assessors of Technological and Environmental Risk.” RPT 12 (1992): 147-

155.

––––––. “Environmental Impact Assessment and the Fallacy of Unfinished Business.” EE 4

(1982): 37-47. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19824138.

––––––. “Environmental Impact Analysis, Technology Assessment, and the Problem of

Geographical Equity.” RPT 5 (1982): 115-130.

––––––. “Ethical Dilemmas and Radioactive Waste: A Survey of the Issues.” EE 13 (1991): 327-

343. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199113438.

––––––. “Individualism, Holism, and Environmental Ethics,” Ethics and the Environment 1

(1996): 55-69. http://www.jstor.org/stable/40338929.

291

––––––. “The Plutonium Economy: Technological Links and Epistemological Problems.” RPT 8

(1985): 189-220.

––––––. "Public and Occupational Risk: The Double Standard." Technology and Contemporary

Life. P&T 4 (1988): 257-277.

––––––. "The Real Risks of Risk-Cost-Benefit Analysis." Technology and Responsibility. P&T 3

(1987): 343-357.

––––––. “Reductionist Philosophy of Technology: Stones Thrown from Inside a Glass House.”

Techné: JSPT 5 (2000): 21-28. doi: 10.5840/techne20015115.

––––––. “Risk and Technology Transfer: Equal Protection across National Borders."

Technological Transformation: Contextual and Conceptual Implications. P&T 5 (1999):

259-275.

––––––. "Technology Assessment and the Problem of Quantification.” Philosophy and

Technology. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 80. P&T 1 (1983): 151-164.

––––––. “Technology Assessment, Expert Disagreement, and Democratic Procedures.” RPT 8

(1985): 103-129.

––––––. "Technology, Bayesian Policymaking, and Democratic Process." Democracy in a

Technological Society. P&T 9 (1992): 123-137.

––––––. “Technology, Public Policy, and the Price-Anderson Act.” RPT 3 (1980): 313-342.

Simus, Jason. "Environmental Art and Ecological Citizenship." EE 30 (2008): 21-36. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics200830115.

Skakoon, Elizabeth. "Nature and Human Identity." EE 30 (2008): 37-49. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics200830116.

292

Strijbos, Sytse. "Computer and World Picture: A Critical Appraisal of Herbert A. Simondon."

Broad and Narrow Interpretations of Philosophy of Technology. P&T 7 (1990): 67-86.

Strong, David. "Challenging Technology." RPT 14 (1994): 69-92.

––––––. "Disclosive Discourse, Ecology, and Technology." EE 16 (1994): 89-102. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics199416144.

––––––. "The Implications for Nature of Borgmann's Theory of Technology." RPT 13 (1993):

223-252.

––––––. "The Technological Subversion of Environmental Ethics." RPT 12 (1992): 33-66.

Swanson, Don R. “On the Fragmentation of Knowledge, the Connection Explosion, and

Assembling Other People’s Ideas.” Bulletin of the American Society for Information

Science and Technology 27 (2001). http://www.asis.org/Bulletin/Mar-01/swanson.html.

Tabachnick, David E. "Techne, Technology, and Tragedy." Techné: RPT 7 (2004): 90-111.

Taylor, Paul W. Respect for Nature: A Theory of Environmental Ethics. Princeton: Princeton

University Press, 1986.

Thompson, Janna. "Aesthetics and the Value of Nature." EE 17 (1995): 291-305. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics199517319.

Thompson, Paul B. “Need and Safety: The Nuclear Power Debate.” EE 6 (1984): 57-69. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics19846121.

––––––. “Putting Pragmatism to Work?” Techné: JSPT 7 (2003): 41-44. doi:

10.5840/techne20037116.

––––––. "Sustainability as a Norm." JSPT 2 (1996): 99-110. doi: 10.5840/techne19972230.

––––––. "Technological Values in the Applied Science Laboratory." New Directions in the

Philosophy of Technology. P&T 11 (1995): 139-151.

293

––––––. “Theorizing Technological and Institutional Change: Alienability, Rivalry and

Exclusion Cost,” Techné: RPT 11, no. 1 (2007): 19-31. doi: 10.5840/techne20071113.

––––––. “Thinking About Thinking About Technology,” Techné: Journal of the Society for

Philosophy and Technology 5 (2000): 29-34. doi: 10.5840/techne20015116.

––––––. “Uncertainty Arguments in Environmental Issues.” EE 8 (1986): 59-75. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics19868118.

Vallor, Shannon. “New Social Media and the Virtues.” In The Good Life in a Technological Age.

Edited by Philip Brey, Adam Briggle, and Ed Spence. 193-202. New York: Routledge,

2012.

Van Dijk, Paul. “Environmental Ethics and the Recovery of Culture.” RPT 17 (1998): 25-43.

Verbeek, Peter-Paul. Moralizing Technology: Understanding and Designing the Morality of

Things. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2011.

Vogel, Steven. “Environmental Philosophy after the End of Nature.” EE 24 (2002): 23-39. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics200224139.

––––––. "New Science, New Nature: The Habermas-Marcuse Debate Revisited." RPT 11 (1991):

157-178.

––––––. “On Michael Zimmerman’s Contesting Earth’s Future.” RPT 18 (1999), 189-198.

––––––. "The Nature of Artifacts." EE 25 (2003): 149-168. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics200325230.

Waks, Leonard J. “Environmental Claims and Citizen Rights.” EE 18 (1996): 133-148. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics199618228.

––––––. “Ivan Illich and Deschooling Society: A Reappraisal." Europe, America, and

Technology: Philosophical Perspectives. P&T 8 (1991): 57-73.

294

––––––. "Ivan Illich's Philosophy of Technology: Introduction." Europe, America, and

Technology: Philosophical Perspectives. P&T 8 (1991): 15-16.

––––––. "The Oil in the Machine: Jacques Ellul on Human Techniques in the Technological

Society." RPT 9 (1989): 155-170.

––––––. "Public Intellectuals and Interdisciplinary Studies." RPT 16 (1997): 61-70.

––––––. "STS Education and the Paradox of Green Studies." Europe, America, and Technology:

Philosophical Perspectives. P&T 8 (1991): 247-257.

––––––. "Symposium on Education in Science, Technology, and Values: Introduction." Europe,

America, and Technology: Philosophical Perspectives. P&T 8 (1991): 193-195.

––––––. Technology's School: The Challenge to Philosophy. RPT Supplement 3 (1995): 1-267.

Warren, Karen J. “Environmental Justice: Some Ecofeminist Worries about a Distributive

Model.” EE 21 (1999): 151-161. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199921228.

––––––. “Feminism and Ecology: Making Connections.” EE 9 (1987): 3-20. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics19879113.

––––––. “The Power and the Promise of Ecological Feminism.” EE 12 (1990): 125-146. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics199012221.

––––––. "Women, Nature, and Technology: An Ecofeminist Philosophical Perspective." RPT 13

(1993): 13-29.

Warren, Karen J. and Jim Cheney, “Ecosystem Ecology and Metaphysical Ecology: A Case

Study.” EE 15 (1993): 99-116. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199315226.

Watson, Walter. The Architectonics of Meaning: Foundations of the New Pluralism. Albany,

New York: State University of New York Press, 1985.

295

Wenz, Peter S. “Ethics, Energy Policy, and Future Generations.” EE 5 (1983): 195-209. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics19835321.

––––––. “Minimal, Moderate, and Extreme Moral Pluralism.” EE 15 (1993): 61-74. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics199315140.

Weston, Anthony. “Before Environmental Ethics.” EE 14 (1992): 321-338. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics19921444.

––––––. “Beyond Intrinsic Value: Pragmatism in Environmental Ethics.” EE 7 (1985): 321-339.

doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19857431.

––––––. “Forms of Gaian Ethics.” EE 9 (1987): 217-230. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics1987933.

––––––. “Ivan Illich and the Radical Critique of Tools.” RPT 9 (1989): 171-182.

––––––. “Multicentrism: A Manifesto.” EE 26 (2004): 25-40. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics200426139.

––––––. “Self-Validating Reduction: Toward a Theory of Environmental Devaluation.” EE 18

(1996): 115-132. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics199618227.

––––––. “Universal Consideration as an Originary Practice.” EE 20 (1998): 279-289. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics199820319.

Whitney, Elspeth. "Lynn White, Ecotheology, and History." EE 15 (1993): 151-169. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics199315229.

––––––. "The Lynn White Thesis: Reception and Legacy." EE 35 (2013): 313-331. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics201335328.

Wiley, Karen B. "The Evolution of ‘Wetlands’ as a Regulatory Concept." RPT 17 (1998): 141-

159.

296

Winner, Langdon. “Do Artifacts Have Politics?” Daedalus 109 (1980): 121-136.

http://www.jstor.org/stable/20024652.

Wishloff, Jim. "Patenting and Transgenic Organisms: A Reply to Lee." Techné: JSPT 6 (2003):

176-180. doi: 10.5840/techne20036324.

Zimmerman, Michael E. “Feminism, Deep Ecology, and Environmental Ethics.” EE 9 (1987):

21-44. doi: 10.5840/enviroethics19879112.

––––––. “Heidegger and Marcuse: Technology as Ideology.” RPT 2 (1979): 245-261.

––––––. "Humanism, Ontology, and the Nuclear Arms Race." RPT 6 (1983): 157-172.

––––––. “Quantum Theory, Intrinsic Value, and Panentheism.” EE 10, (1988): 3-30. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics198810126.

––––––. “Recognizing the Limits of Contesting Earth’s Future.” RPT 18 (1999): 199-216.

––––––. “Rethinking the Heidegger-Deep Ecology Relationship.” EE 15 (1993): 195-224. doi:

10.5840/enviroethics199315316.

––––––. “Technological Culture and the End of Philosophy.” RPT 2 (1979): 137-145.

––––––. “Toward a Heideggerian Ethos for Radical Environmentalism.” EE 5 (1983): 99-131.

doi: 10.5840/enviroethics1983524.


Recommended