+ All Categories
Home > Education > Measuring social preferences

Measuring social preferences

Date post: 15-Apr-2017
Category:
Upload: richard-tol
View: 141 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend
20
Preferences Optimal climate policy depends on how we define better and best We may want to take advise from Socrates, Jesus, Mohammed, Lord Stern or Lady Gaga We may also want to measure people’s time preference risk aversion inequity aversion But how?
Transcript
Page 1: Measuring social preferences

Preferences• Optimal climate policy depends on how

we define better and best• We may want to take advise from

Socrates, Jesus, Mohammed, Lord Stern or Lady Gaga

• We may also want to measure people’s– time preference– risk aversion– inequity aversion

• But how?

Page 2: Measuring social preferences

Risk preference• Micro (von Neumann-Morgenstern)

• Prospect theory (Kahneman-Tversky)

• Latter approximates former• Simon would suggest people don’t

bother to be rational in low stake lottery

Page 3: Measuring social preferences

Ask for choice between two lotteries because peoplemay be biased towards sure things.

Page 4: Measuring social preferences

If someone accepts Lottery 2 for £750, then her risksensitivity must be greater than 0.9

If someone rejects Lottery 2 for £625, then her risksensitivity must be smaller than 1.2

If both, risk sensitivity lies between 0.9 and 1.2

0.1 0.2 0.3 0.4 0.5 0.6 0.7 0.8 0.9 1.0 1.1 1.2 1.3 1.4 1.5 1.6 1.7 1.8 1.9 2.0 2.1 2.2 2.3 2.4 2.5340 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 1 1 1375 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 1 1 1 1 1 1415 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1465 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1530 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1625 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1750 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1925 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 11100 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 11500 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 12000 -1 -1 -1 -1 -1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 15000 -1 -1 -1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 18500 -1 -1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1

-1: Lott 1 is the better deal; 1: Lott 2 is the better deal

Page 5: Measuring social preferences
Page 6: Measuring social preferences
Page 7: Measuring social preferences

Risk preference• Prospect theory with Prelec risk bias

• Loss aversion

• So, three parameters to be estimated

Page 8: Measuring social preferences

Risk preference• Voors et al., AER, 2012

– Discrete choice, 3 alternatives– Variations in pay-offs, but not probabilities– 2 lotteries: 2 obs/person

• Tanaka et al., AER, 2010– Discrete choice, 14/14/7 alternatives– Variations in pay-offs, probabilities– 3 lotteries: 3 obs/person, 1 obs/par

• Voors do not distinguish between risk aversion and amplification

• Tanaka show urns with balls to represent chances, not sure whether this captures risk amplification, eye-sight or numeracy

Page 9: Measuring social preferences

10

20

30

40

50

60

70

80

90

100

0 2 4 6 8 10 12 14 16 18 20 22 24 26 28 30

disc

ount

fact

or

time

geometricpresent biashyperbolic

Time preference

Page 10: Measuring social preferences

10

100

0 2 4 6 8 10 12 14 16 18 20 22 24 26 28 30

disc

ount

fact

or

time

geometricpresent biashyperbolic

Time preference

Page 11: Measuring social preferences

10

20

30

40

50

60

70

80

90

100

0 2 4 6 8 10 12 14 16 18 20 22 24 26 28 30

disc

ount

fact

or

time

geometricpresent biashyperbolic

Time preference

𝐷𝐹=(1+𝑟𝑡 )− 1 , 𝛽=1∧𝜗=2

𝐷𝐹=𝑒−𝑟𝑡 , 𝛽=𝜗=1

𝐷𝐹=𝛽 (1− (1−𝜗 )𝑟𝑡 )1/1−𝜗

Page 12: Measuring social preferences

Time preference• Benhabib, Bisin & Schotter (2010, GEB) discount

function has 3 parameters• Voors et al., AER, 2012

– Discrete choice, 6 alternatives– 1 period, 1 sum: 1 observation per person

• Tanaka et al., AER, 2010– Discrete choice, 5 alternatives– 3 periods, 5 sums: 15 obs/person, 5 obs/par

• Ifcher & Zarghamee, AER, 2011– Open choice– 6 periods, 5 sums: 30 obs/person, 10 obs/par

• No distinction between utility, consumption, risk, time

• Commitment device implies short time horizons

Page 13: Measuring social preferences
Page 14: Measuring social preferences
Page 15: Measuring social preferences

Two are indifferent, presumably because of transfers

Two apply discount to child, heavier to grandchild

One applies discount to child, but not to grandchild

Page 16: Measuring social preferences

Inequity aversion• There is a lot of literature on fairness

– How to divide a windfall among a group of people?• Much less on equity

– What is the best income distribution in a population?• Choice experiment with leaky bucket• Any amount of risk aversion would imply an

egalitarian solution– {10000, 15000, 20000} – {9.2, 9.6, 9.9}– {12000, 15000, 18000} – {9.4, 9.6, 9.8}

• Okun: Imperfect income transfer– {10000, 15000, 20000} – {9.2, 9.6, 9.9}– {12000, 15000, 17000} – {9.4, 9.6, 9.7}

• Administration costs, incentives to work

Page 17: Measuring social preferences

Inequity aversion• Bergson-Samuelson

– No distinction between risk and inequity aversion

• Creedy (HARA) – Inequity aversion varies with average income

• Sen – Strong inequity aversion

• Forster – Weak inequity aversion

Page 18: Measuring social preferences
Page 19: Measuring social preferences

Sussex economists are egalitarians

Income distribution matters more for poorer societies

Page 20: Measuring social preferences

Wrap-up• Experiments and surveys reveal a lot about

our attitudes• But not necessarily in a tidy way that neatly

fits our theory• Revealed preferences overcome the issues

with low stakes, poor representativeness, but are always messy

• Investments in education, health, climate, pensions– Uncertain returns– Future returns– Disproportionate returns for some


Recommended