+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Michel Weber, The Polysemiality of the Concept of “Pure Experience”

Michel Weber, The Polysemiality of the Concept of “Pure Experience”

Date post: 05-Oct-2015
Category:
Upload: infochromatika
View: 8 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend
Description:
« An Argumentation for Contiguism », Streams of William James, Volume 1, Issue 1, Spring 1999, pp. 14-16 & « The Polysemiality of the Concept of “Pure Experience” », Streams of William James, Volume 1, Issue 2, Fall 1999, pp. 4-6.refreshed in Michel Weber, Whitehead’s Pancreativism. Jamesian Applications, Frankfurt / Paris, ontos verlag, 2011 (ISBN 978-386838-103-0).
23
  4 The Polysemiality of the Concept of “Pure Experience” In Whitehead’s Pancreativism—The Basics (2006), polysemiality, interanimation and style have been described as parts of a global convergent movement towards the bare factuality of experience. The point was to suggest how language can open itself to something that remains, to a significant extent,  foreign or opaque to it. Asking how does language  prismatize the ever-changing complexity of reality is to ask how its intentionality works, or: how, after all, can it be a prism—or a vector— rather than a screen? That latter question is not, as we shall soon see, purely rhetorical: language can be used in a mœbian, self-referential, way that short-circuits its constitutive intentionality. 1  The assertion of a primordial experience, both in the sense of a temporal  primacy and of a semantic or existential primacy (“original or pristine character”—  Perry II, pp. 386 sq.) is extremely important for the operationalization of “radical empiricism,” but when the  Essays in Radical  Empiricism introduced the concept of “pure experience,” they did so in the rough. And it is indeed a major characteristic of James’s works that they  propose more willingly a cluster of convergent intuitions only roughly systematised rather than a full-fledged “theory of everything.” The reception of the concept of pure experience has been rather negative and it is not difficult to understand why. 2  On the one hand, James’s vision is “counter-intuitive”—better: non-rational. Its purpose is to draw all the onto-epistemological consequences  of anti-foundationalism and of non- dualism. On the other hand, James’s style is quite surprising and it takes time to organise the intrication of the semantic layers involved. 1  This chapter expands the heuristics of “An Argumentation for Contiguism,” Streams of William James , Volume 1, Issue 1, Spring 1999, pp. 14-16. 2  Eugene I. Taylor and Robert H. Wozniak (Edited and Introduced by),  Pur e  Exp eri ence. The Res pons e t o Wi lli am J ame s, Bristol, Thoemmes Press, 1996.
Transcript
  • 4

    The Polysemiality of the Concept of

    Pure Experience

    In Whiteheads PancreativismThe Basics (2006), polysemiality, interanimation and style have been described as parts of a global convergent movement towards the bare factuality of experience. The point was to suggest how language can open itself to something that remains, to a significant extent, foreign or opaque to it. Asking how does language prismatize the ever-changing complexity of reality is to ask how its intentionality works, or: how, after all, can it be a prismor a vectorrather than a screen? That latter question is not, as we shall soon see, purely rhetorical: language can be used in a mbian, self-referential, way that short-circuits its constitutive intentionality.

    1

    The assertion of a primordial experience, both in the sense of a temporal primacy and of a semantic or existential primacy (original or pristine characterPerry II, pp. 386 sq.) is extremely important for the operationalization of radical empiricism, but when the Essays in Radical Empiricism introduced the concept of pure experience, they did so in the rough. And it is indeed a major characteristic of Jamess works that they propose more willingly a cluster of convergent intuitions only roughly systematised rather than a full-fledged theory of everything.

    The reception of the concept of pure experience has been rather negative and it is not difficult to understand why.

    2 On the one hand, Jamess vision

    is counter-intuitivebetter: non-rational. Its purpose is to draw all the onto-epistemological consequences of anti-foundationalism and of non-dualism. On the other hand, Jamess style is quite surprising and it takes time to organise the intrication of the semantic layers involved.

    1 This chapter expands the heuristics of An Argumentation for Contiguism,

    Streams of William James, Volume 1, Issue 1, Spring 1999, pp. 14-16. 2 Eugene I. Taylor and Robert H. Wozniak (Edited and Introduced by), Pure

    Experience. The Response to William James, Bristol, Thoemmes Press, 1996.

  • 92 Michel Weber

    Before diving into the debated questionthe polysemiality of the concept of pure experience, it is worth to quickly refresh the philosophers overall perspective. According to the late James, what especially matters is the intrinsic unity of the World as well as its dynamic, variegated, character: there is no room for the inveterate dualism in a philosophy that champions an open universe. More precisely speaking, ERE is concerned with the status of consciousnessand its motto is: consciousness stands for a function, not for an entity. It is nothing less than a categoreal mistake to appeal to a trans-experiential agent of unification (ERE 43). The main speculative difficulty is to understand the withness of the subjective and the objective, to delimit the differences of degree that separates-yet-binds them. To do so, James devises the principle of pure experience, which claims that

    nothing shall be admitted as fact [] except what can be

    experienced at some definite time by some experient; and for every

    feature of fact ever so experienced, a definite place must be found

    somewhere in the final system of reality. In other words: Everything

    real must be experienceable somewhere, and every kind of thing

    experienced must be somewhere real. (ERE 160; cf. p. 42 and PU 372)

    Merleau-Ponty, among others, will also later claim that experience has to be total.

    1 Whitehead, for his part, insists:

    the reformed subjectivist principle must be repeated: that apart

    from the experiences of subjects there is nothing, nothing, nothing,

    bare nothingness. (PR 167)

    This is exactly what, in some other circles, has been called a panexperientialism.

    2

    4.1. Pure ExperienceDefinition

    1 Lexprience nest rien ou il faut quelle soit totale. (Maurice Merleau-Ponty,

    Merleau-Ponty, Phnomnologie de la perception, Paris, NRF ditions Gallimard,1945, p. 299.

    2 Griffin was the first to use the conceptwhich has been coined in conversation

    with Cobbin his Whiteheads Philosophy and Some General Notions of Physics and Biology, in John B. Cobb, Jr. & David Ray Griffin (eds.), Mind in Nature. Essays on the Interface of Science and Philosophy, Washington D. C., University Press of America, 1977.

  • Polysemiality of the Concept of Pure Experience 93

    In the lines that follow, we exploit a tripartite grid to organise the layers of meaning of the concept. By doing so, we take advantage of the very categories that need to be bypassed. James desperately seeks to avoid the subject/object dualism, not the distinction of the subject and of the object:

    the bank cant say, I made the river, any more than the river can

    say, I made the bank. The right leg cant say, I do the walking any

    more than the left leg can.1

    Here lies the fatum of process thought: to depict a radical onto-epistemological renewaland thereby arouse a modification of consciousnesscan only be achieved through the use of specialized everyday language, i.e., a language that is substantialistic-dualistic at heart (exactly what needs to be reformedif not destroyed).

    Wrestling with the status of the marrow of experience, James coins the concept of pure experience in order to name what cannot bear names, in order to point to what remains of the order of bare factuality, i.e., of pre-predication. Out of the intricacy of the various meanings he confers to the concept, three dimensions can be isolated for the sake of analysis, and articulated for the sake of synthesis.

    The understanding of the implicated order of the panexperientialist working hypothesis necessitates the distinction of three complementary perspectives: subjective, objective and unitive. The analysis itself belongs to the domain of abstractions: for the sake of a wider understanding of the various levels of connexities every being enjoys with its environment, the philosopher wagers on the pulling apart of what is intuitively given to us as an immediate unity. By doing so, it is hoped that each layer of meaning will disclose fruitful speculative nuances.

    4.1.1. Subjective Flux of Life

    From the subjective, or inner point of view, pure experience is the immediate flux of life in which feelings inflame the whole experiencing being. It is the prepredicative penumbra of new-born babes (or intoxicated adults) who intuit a that which is not yet any definite what.

    2 One could

    1 Letter of James to Warner Fite, 1906, quoted by Perry II, p. 392.

    2 Cf. ERE 92-94; cf. PP I 488 and II 32. Of course, Jamess claims are to be read as

    primarily metaphorical: developmental psychology has shown more or less convincingly that the new-born is not a tabula rasa; and the recent advances in the understanding of the status of hypnosis offer interesting complementary approaches to this question. (Cf., e.g., Daniel N. Stern, The Interpersonal World

  • 94 Michel Weber

    speak, in other words, of a bare sense of presence characterized by a state of primordial innocence ignorant of (hopefully fruitful) distinctions. In the penumbra of pure or direct experience, experience is just as it is, without the least addition of deliberative discrimination, to say it with Nishidas words.

    1

    What this perspective uncovers is twofold. First, it shows the centrality of the subject of experience in general, and of the subjectivity of the philosopher in particular: our own experience is the unavoidable ground of any speculation. This has been acknowledged, reluctantly or not, by every philosophy. Second, it sketches the construction of reality by language. Out of a perceptual chaos (a concept James is fond of), we bring forth a world: when we conceptualise, we cut out and fix, and exclude everything but what we have fixed. A concept means a that-and-no-other. It is another issue to understand how this world (my world or Umwelt, like etho-phenomenologists say) can overlap, as it factually does, with other worlds.

    And here is the obvious conflictexploited ad nauseam by deconstructive postmodernism

    2between the radical eventfulness of a

    truly open universe, and the static profiles conceptual understanding cannot but provide. This apparent unreconciliabilty of the torrential kosmos with the necrosing conceptualisation process has led, for instance, the late Heidegger to advocate a poetry of thinking. Pushed to the hilt, such a philosophical approach claims only to utter eventful concepts, in the very same way reality is a weaving of never-recurring events.

    4.1.2. Objective Primal Stuff

    of the Infant. A View from Psychoanalysis and Developmental Psychology, New York, Basic Book, 1985; Lon Chertok, L'Hypnose. Thorie, pratique et technique. Prface de Henry Ey. dition remanie et augmente, Paris, ditions Payot, 1989; Franois Roustang, Qu'est-ce que l'hypnose?, Paris, ditions de Minuit, 1994.)

    1 Nishida Kitaro, An Inquiry into the Good [Zen no Kenkyu, 1911]. Translated by

    Masao Abe, New Haven, Yale University Press, 1990, pp. 3-4. See infra the remarks on the difference between James and Nishida.

    2 Griffin makes a useful distinction between deconstructive or eliminative

    postmodernism and constructive or revisionary postmodernism. See David Ray Griffin (ed.), The Reenchantment of Science. Postmodern Proposals, Albany, New York, State University of New York Press, 1988, p. x.

  • Polysemiality of the Concept of Pure Experience 95

    From the objective, or outer point of view, pure experience is the primal stuff or materia prima of the world.

    1 Experience as a whole is self-

    containing and leans on nothing (ERE 193). Everything that is real is experiencing, full stop. James is not only saying that a non-experiencing or non-experienceable something would institute an awkward enclave in the uni-verse, but that such an ontological pocket is purely and simply impossible: it is logically inconsistent and totally incoherent with the key-categories of radical empiricism.

    Basically, the question of the primal stuff is the one of (realistic) pluralism; without some objective something standing out there, we end up volens nolens with a form of solipsistic idealism; the many collapses, once and for all, into an all-embracing one. This is definitely not the case in the normal state of consciousness. Jamess vision speaks for a pluralism that does not insulate the different actors of the ontological scene. There are co-dependant yet possess their intrinsic weight. Common sense does not claim anything else.

    It is to be noticed that James uses the concept of stuff in various analogical ways: positively as well as derogatorily. Positive occurrences aim at the full thickness of the concrete, at its overall chaosmic structure;

    2

    derogative occurrences denounce the understanding of realitys core as a permanent substance underlying changes (cf., e.g., ERE 3, 26).

    4.1.3. Emotional Reconciliation

    From the unitive, or in-between point of view, pure experience is the ineffable union (ERE 121) that sees the unison of the experiencing and the experienced. The immediate flux of life is intertwined, or even dissolved, in the universal experiencing tissue; one undifferentiated whole reaches meta-consciousness. In a typically Bergsonian fashion, James asks to put ourselves in the making by a stroke of intuitive sympathy with the thing (PU 263; cf. VRE 501). We should struggle to reach an ontological intuition, lying beyond the power of words to tell of.

    3 The Will to Believe

    has even more adventurous utterings (besides the fact that it still speaks of a mind):

    1 Cf. the note 35 on Aristotelian hylemorphism.

    2 See, e.g., ERE 4, 37, 78, 138.

    3 William James, Review of The Ansthetic Revelation and the Gist of

    Philosophy, The Atlantic Monthly, November 1874, Volume 33, No. 205, pp. 627-628.

  • 96 Michel Weber

    The key-note of the experience is the tremendously exciting sense

    of an intense metaphysical illumination. Truth lies open to the view in

    depth beneath depth of almost blinding evidence. The mind sees all the

    logical relations of being with an apparent subtlety and instantaneity to

    which its normal consciousness offers no parallel []. The center and

    periphery of things seem to come together. The ego and its objects, the

    meeum and the tuum, are one. (WB 294)

    The world of pure experience is the world in which there occurs an immense emotional sense of atonement and reconciliation; it is the world in which every opposition vanishes to the benefit of the law of togetherness of events in a common world. This emotional awareness embodies the fact that there are no differences but differences of degree between different degrees of difference and no difference. (WB 297) James exemplifies it with two main cases: religious rapture and chemical intoxication.

    Pure experience names the radical eventfulness (i.e., the asubstantialism) of the inner and outer worlds, as well as their unison. What really matters here is Jamess panexperientialism: every feature of the World is either an experiencing or an experienced. Experience is what actually holds the world together: not only are relations experienced, but they are themselves experience. Since everything is experience, there is no more dichotomy between, on the one hand, a substance that is experiencing and unextended and, on the other, a substance that is unexperiencing and extended (remember Descartes bicameral substantialism). Radical empiricism is first and foremost a radical constructivism.

    It is now possible to rephrase our earlier question: how can a world conditioned by opposites be the surface effect of a reconciliated world? The fundamental law of sharing (if any such a law exists) must belong to a level of consciousness that has not been selected for everyday purposes, and various reasons can be put forward: from a natural perspective, the everyday level of consciousness is determined by the features of human beings habitat and embodiment; from a cultural perspective, it is determined by contingent habits of language and ritualization. On the one hand, the biological evolution of humanity has selected some particular ways of relation and awareness in a sharp competitive context with other species; on the other, sub-evolutionary processes have led groups of humans to adopt their own languages and rituals to customise the world. As a result, two complementary filters stands out of this quick analysis: sense perception and education. Any individuals perspective is moulded by the peculiarities of his/her perceptual system and cultural interpretative grid. In conclusion, the obliteration of the unitive world by its partition into

  • Polysemiality of the Concept of Pure Experience 97

    a subject and various objects has proven to be a necessity for survival and for action purposes. And the link can now be made with a last difficulty: why should we translate experience from a more concrete or pure into more intellectualised form? (ERE 96)and thereby install bifurcations in the natural tissue. The paradoxical answer is: to attain to dwelling.

    A closer look at this third layer of meaning reveals that the concept necessitates furthermore a complementary analysis in terms of levels of consciousness. If the principle of pure experience holds, how is it, indeed, that it is totally denied by common-sense? In other words: if pure experience describes the ultimate feature of our world, if, per se, it is the awareness brought about by an ineffable union, why is it so foreign to everyday life? The very first thing to notice is that pure or direct experience does not mean direct sensorial experience. Buddhism has heavily insisted on this, but the question is not foreign to Western philosophy at all. Because of textual evidences, Platos concept of theoria can be said to be the starting point of a build-in contemplative trend in philosophy, trend that will be later exploited, through its Neo-Platonic interpretation, by the entire Medieval philosophy. But the problem these speculations face is the (ab)use they make of the metaphor of vision: Jonas has shown very straightforwardly the inevitable bias of the theoretic concept, mainly in terms of the neutralisation of time and causation. To say it in one word: the metaphor of vision imposes the idea of the spectator-subject, i.e., of a totally passive onlooker factually unaffected by the scenery.

    1 Anyway, the XXth century has seen three major thinkersJames,

    Bergson and Whiteheadclarifying the issue of experience, acutely distinguishing (but not bifurcating) sensory perception from its ontological roots. Sense perception is actually a very simplified (though sophisticated) projection established on the wealth of data in which the subject is immersedbetter, that constitutes the subject.

    We have used, explicitly or not, contrapunctic parallels with Nishidas interpretation of Jamess concept of pure experience. It is now time to define how far such a conceptual togetherness with the immediate envisioning of being in its suchness and thusness is fair. Suchness or thusness means viewing things as they are; the absolute experience is made of oneness and purposelessness, it makes plain that there was actually nothing to reconcile in the first place, just a seamless eventful tapestry.

    2 To

    go to the core of the matter, we have to acknowledge that experience is not 1 Hans Jonas, The Phenomenon of Life, op. cit.

    2 Cf., e.g., Ames Van Meter, Zen and Pragmatism, Philosophy East and West 3,

    n 1, 1954, pp. 19-33.

  • 98 Michel Weber

    understood in the same way by the two philosophers: James understands it as a plenum, whereas Nishida sees it as a vacuum.

    1 The fullness, full-

    bodiedness, of the Jamesian universe is replaced by the emptiness of the latter. Now, from a speculative point of view, one could frame an argumentation bringing the two conceptual extremes closer, but it is to be feared that such an abstract exercise will never do justice to the idiosyncratic experiencein the strong sense of the termof our protagonists. To take a more concrete exemplification: even when he understands consciousness as a function, James acknowledges some sort of egoity to the subject. Nishida, on the contrary, pushes as far as possible the negation of any dichotomies. It is the case indeed that Zen does not teach absorption, identification, or union, for all these ideas are derived from a dualistic conception of life and the world. In Zen there is a wholeness of things, which refuses to be analyzed or separated into antitheses of all kinds.

    2

    Having said this, let us go back to the tripartition of the concept of pure experience in order to close our discussion. The three steps used to depict the facets of pure experience highlight the epicentre of Jamess symbolic space: his subjectivist method. The claimed ground of his speculations is his own experience, generalized first to other human beings, and second to the rest of realitythe trick being, naturally, to frame concepts elastic enough to endure such a stretching without installing gaps in the cosmic tissue. Furthermore, at the epistemological level, that method allows the dismissal of a conclusion for the very motive that it contradicts our intimate feelings and desires.

    3 Quite obviously, this is a radical empiricism.

    4.2. A Developmental Contiguism

    1 Cf., e.g., David A. Dilworth, The Initial Formations of Pure Experience in

    Nishida Kitaro and William James, Monumenta Nipponica, XXIV, 1-2, Tokyo, Sophia University Press, 1969, pp. 93-111.

    2 Daisetz Teitaro Suzuki, An Interpretation of Zen Experience, in Charles

    Alexander Moore (With the Assistance of Aldyth V. Morris), The Japanese Mind. Essentials of Japanese Philosophy and Culture (East-West Philosophers' Conference), Honolulu, East-West Center Press, University of Hawa Press, 1967, pp. 122-142, p. 139.

    3 Repousser une conclusion par ce seul motif qu'elle contrarie nos sentiments

    intimes et nos dsirs, c'est faire emploi de la mthode subjective. (James, Quelques considrations sur la mthode subjective, in EP 23)

  • Polysemiality of the Concept of Pure Experience 99

    The concept of pure experience constitutes the focal point of Jamess radical empiricism while radical empiricism is itself arguably the very core of his works, both historically and conceptually.

    1

    Historically, radical empiricism was introduced in the Preface of the Will to Believe (1897) and unfolded in the Meaning of Truth (1909), but it clearly articulates earlier articles such as On Some Omissions of Introspective Psychology (1884). For its part, pure experience takes form in the articles published between July 1904 and February 1905 and posthumously gathered in the celebrated Essays in Radical Empiricism (1912).

    Conceptually, radical empiricism is the keystone of James vision in so far as he has always sought to take account of all experiences and especially of relations. I submit that James has always been a radical empiricist and that it is only the explicitation or thematization of this standpoint that can be more or less precisely pinpointed. Here is Jamess mature statement with that regard:

    Radical empiricism consists first of a postulate, next of a statement

    of fact, and finally of a generalized conclusion. The postulate is that

    the only things that shall be debatable among philosophers shall be

    things definable in terms drawn from experience. [Things of an

    unexperienceable nature may exist ad libitum, but they form no part of

    the material for philosophic debate.] The statement of fact is that the

    relations between things, conjunctive as well as disjunctive, are just as

    much matters of direct particular experience, neither more so nor less

    so, than the things themselves. The generalized conclusion is that

    therefore the parts of experience hold together from next to next by

    relations that are themselves parts of experience. The directly

    apprehended universe needs, in short, no extraneous trans-empirical

    connective support, but possesses in its own right a concatenated or

    continuous structure. (MT xii-xiii)

    If no experience should be excluded from the undifferentiated field of the present, we have to integrate disjunctive and conjunctive relations in our systematic attempts and these have to be understood with the same experiential categories.

    1 For an historical review of the concept, see John J. McDermotts first-rate

    Introduction to the Frederick H. Burkhardt edition of ERE (Harvard University Press, 1978).

  • 100 Michel Weber

    So far, we have questioned the continuous-discontinuous dialectic in Jamess works and organized the main semantic layers of his concept of pure experience. The attentive reader will have noticed that the various moments of these two separate arguments bear an intended family resemblance that is now expedient to exploit. We will do so in the following manner: first, the key points of our past twin arguments are contextualized; second we specify two epistemological questions underlying the threefold structure activated in both papers; third, we examine the announced synergy between the concepts of pure experience and of contiguism.

    4.2.1. A Continuity of Inquiries

    On the one hand, there is in Jamess psycho-phenomenological inquiries an emphasis on the continuity of experience: from a subjectiveor innerpoint of view, each and everyone of us has the strong feeling that experience is a stream, i.e., that it has no breaches or cracks. Although the existence of resting places is granted as well as the existence of thresholds of perception, experience is subordinated to that all-embracing and everlasting flux.

    On the other, when the late James digs further into the epistemological field andespeciallyinto the ontological one, he is ipso facto displacing his focus point from the weaving of phenomenological facts to the systematization of their rational requirements. Reason is the means by which one comes to a decision on the status of the objectivethe price to pay for the intended level of generality or objectivity being precisely to sail away (carefully or not) from the evidences of personal experience. The continuity in the flux is then replaced by a tempered discontinuity: there are breaches, but no gaps. The places of flights have become the superficial effect of a temporal (or historical) trajectory of ontological drops.

    The unitive moment sees the synergy of the phenomenological (psychological if you like) discontinuous continuity and the epistemo-metaphysical continuous discontinuity. Here again, the question of the possibility of the awareness of such a structure is profiling itself. What matters is that, out of the somewhat conflicting respective interests of experience and reason (or individuality and universality), the need for both continuous and discontinuous categories remains insistent. To lock a speculative system featuring only one of the two aspects would be to denaturate mundane eventfulness, and especially to undermine the very possibility of a meaningful existence. Authenticity or ethicality asks for the stability of the cosmic figures as well as for the possibility of revolutionising them.

  • Polysemiality of the Concept of Pure Experience 101

    Since the Greeks, it was commonly accepted that only one principle (arch) should be evoked to understand reality. The metaphor of the source was very explicit in that regard.

    1 Through the insistent influence

    of Scholastics2 in our culture, it the hydra of all possible heresiesand

    especially of Manicheismhas been furthermore fought. Neither the regression ad infinitum nor the ambivalent counter-tension of two co-eternal principles are rationally acceptable. But is it reasonable to do so? The ananke stenai (we have to stop) envisioned by Aristotle in the context of a closed and strictly hierarchized worlda cosmos, in order to prevent an infinite regress, has actually lost most of its relevance in a chaosmos that is so to speak infinite in all directions (spatial, temporal and consciential), it makes sense more than ever to treat any feud pragmatically. As James claims, pragmatism is but a new name for some old ways of thinking; to a certain extent, it is a return to Socrates.

    4.2.2. Objectivity and Rationality

    Before envisaging the mutual insemination of the two litigious categories, it is enlightening to linger over two interdependent logico-epistemological questions lying in the background of our respective arguments. We have repeatedly encountered the concept of bare factuality and its complementary, reason. As Kant saw very clearly, both poles are necessary to gain access to objectivity: on the one hand, there are raw sensory experiences, and on the other, rational categories that coat them, so to speak, with an understandable form. But there are three immediate problems from the perspective of radical empiricism: the subject creates its world less than it is created by it, categories are historical, and they are culturally tainted. It is rather obvious that what is rational from the perspective of a given system of thought, might not be from the perspective of another oneand hence, objectivity varies for different cultures and even for different subcultures: not only a Melanesian does not have the same world as a Bantu or an Asian-American, but among the latter, there are various Weltanschauungen.

    3 A golf player does not work with the same

    mental picture as a nuclear scientist; a Gymnasium kid does not sympathise in the same way with the world as a gardener or an agricultural engineer. What becomes apparent here is precisely the scattered worldview in the

    1 Cf. Aristotle, Metaphysics, Book Delta.

    2 The term is not used derogatorily.

    3 Cf., e.g., Edward Sapir, Benjamin Lee Whorf, Edward E. Evans-Pritchard, Paul

    K. Feyerabend, etc.

  • 102 Michel Weber

    civilized West: on the one hand the world of life, on the other, the world(s) of science. There is no mystery as to why meaning was given in traditional societies, and is pulled apart in modern ones: the process of individuation is now a process of conformization that provides only a fake form of solidarity. Atomism and the grand narrative of terror prevent common sense to exercise its political mandate.

    To be as straightforward as possible: the way an individual cuts out reality depends on his/her way of positioning him/herself in front of the Totality. It depends, in other words, on a metaphysical decision that can be reduced, from the perspective of the history of (Western) philosophy, to substance or flux.

    1 Needless to say that substance ontology has so far

    installed itself as the paradigmatic worldview, more precisely setting into movement Modernity and its trail of pitiful bankruptcies. Hence the baffling claim that can be found in some Nietzschean thinkersand especially in Nishida and Whitehead: the substance-predicate ontology is at the root of all evils, in the strong sense of the term.

    The distinction between rational, irrational and nonrational enables us to name that relativity while preserving a healthy realism. We can see as well why non-rationality as total opacity finds a proper framework with the concept of pure experience. Since pure experience attempts to depict the original experiential plenum, it gives us a beautiful tool to make sense out of that nocturnal and tactual experience (a touching in the night).

    2

    Whereas the categories congenial with diurnal and visual experience break down, this limit concept still holds because it defines itself as the only asymptotical approach to the state of dissolutive relationality that is so characteristic of religiousness.

    The paradox of the philosophical enterprise should be discussed at this point: by the very fact that it names what has always already escaped its discursive reasoning (the ineffable), philosophy puts some grip on itand yet lets it go. Suffice it to say that that paradoxanexteriority, which is as old as philosophical speculation, has never discouraged the quest for the holistic transfiguration. Better, it has been thematized as such in Platos Parmenides or with the Kantian difference between Schranke and Grenze). Anyway, the concept of pure experience gives us the minimal

    1 More fundamentaly, the way the individual trusts the World should be pictured

    with the help of the Husserlian concept of Urdoxa and its merleaupontian cartography.

    2 [] in a personal relation of contact with the mysterious power (VRE 464

    quoting Auguste Sabatier); contact with the only absolute realities (VRE 503).

  • Polysemiality of the Concept of Pure Experience 103

    polysemantic technicalities to deal with Jamess impressive suggestions, such as this one:

    Looking back on my own experiences, they all converge towards a

    kind of insight to which I cannot help ascribing some metaphysical

    significance. The keynote of it is invariably a reconciliation. It is as if

    the opposites of the world, whose contradictoriness and conflict make

    all our difficulties and troubles, were melted into unity. (VRE 388)1

    Total opacity topples into clear light during the rapture because dualism is replaced by relationalism. When it ends, there only remains semantic lineaments with which it is quite difficult to make sense unless one accepts the reformation of our everyday categories.

    Let us finally remark that the concept of pure experience reintroduces a form of onto-logism: of course, its ontology shapes only a (non-rational) chaosmos, but it embodies an archeological hypothesis that obviously has a theoretical (contemplative) dimension: The peace of rationality may be sought through ecstasy when logic fails. (EP 62)

    The epilogue shows how this extremization of the concept of non-rationality is completed and operationalized by the ontology of pure experience. Even though one could claim that pragmatisms reversal of the Greek onto-logism is basically instrumented by its refusal to cross the gates of metaphysics, James, for one, has been quickly aware of the fact that empirical facts without metaphysics will always make a confusion and a muddle.

    2

    4.2.3. The Included Middle

    In all these pages, we have been looking for a third alternative, for an included middle lying beyond subjectivity and objectivity, beyond continuity and discontinuity. Beyond, ultimately, the verdict of rationality or irrationality delivered from the finite perspective of a given system of thought. It has been suggested that the keystone to dichotomies is the shared level of consciousness between human beings qua that level is locked by everyday language. We have to go back to the thickness of the concrete itself, to its nonrationality. With regard to the status of language, two simple complementary remarks need thus to be made.

    1 The passage is quoted entirely in 5.3.

    2 James to Ribot, 1888, cited by Perry, In the Spirit of William James, p. 58.

  • 104 Michel Weber

    One, by sharing a common language, human beings share a common world. We have just seen that the process of learning a language corresponds to the learning of a certain way of cutting out reality. Philosophers and theologians have repeatedly said that everyday language is more or less useless for the purpose of speaking of the Ultimate. Interestingly enough, it is only at the edge of the twentieth century that scientists have begun to hammer the very same point: Bohr, Heisenberg, and Einstein, to pin point some of the most known figures of the quantic revolution, came very quickly to realize that common sense language is totally overcome by their theoretical breakthroughs. Bohr has even confided to Heisenberg that a modification of the internal structure of thought needs to be spurred if one wishes to grasp the full depths of quantic theory.

    1 It is a change of a rational system that is indeed required (cf.

    Birkhoff and Neumann).

    Two, it is often forgotten that the semantic structure of language is intrinsically intentional. The words, as well as their organization in discourses, aim at pointing to a state of affairs. Fallacies quickly make irruption in arguments that claim a total abstractedness from stubborn facts. In such a case, language is no longer a vector, a shallow gauze through which the shimmering concreteness is still given, but a screen, whose opacity is mistook for a reassuring baroque curtain. Adequately manipulated, however, language can direct our attention towards the nonrational.

    4.3. The Contiguism of Pure Feeling

    Let us now address the question of the real discontinuity (no pun intended, but appropriate) existingor notbetween two Jamesian concepts: the stream of thought, on the one hand; and the drops of experience, on the other. It is indisputable that the former belongs to a period when William James was primarily concerned with psychology; whereas the latter is explicitly dealing with ontological matters. But the two fields have always been closely intertwined in his works, and, as Perry says: if he was ever a philosopher, he was always a philosopher. Furthermore, in both cases the

    1 Niels Bohr, in a conversation quoted by Werner Heisenberg in Physics and

    Beyond. Encounters and Conversations. Translated from the German by Arnold J. Pomerans [Der Teil und das Ganze. Gesprche in Umkreis ser Atomphysik, Mnchen, Piper Verlag, 1959], New York, Harper & Row, Publishers, 1971. Cf. also Niels Bohr, Atomic Physics and Human Knowledge, New York / London, John Wiley & Sons, Inc. / Chapman & Hall, Limited, 1958.

  • Polysemiality of the Concept of Pure Experience 105

    underlying question is the status of what is immediately given and the rational answer does not spell itself simply in terms of the opposition of continuous and discontinuous approaches.

    We will briefly examine the stream of thought and the drops of experience respectively, before showing the common features of these two specular concepts, and eventually concluding with a contiguist perspective.

    1

    4.3.1. Stream of Events

    The stream of thought metaphor obviously intends to put forward the continuous flow of consciousness as it is introspected. In chapter IX of his Principles of Psychology, in the making since 1884 or so, James defines continuous as that which is without breach, crack, or division (PP 231). In spite of interruptions, time-gaps or quality breaks, consciousness remains an essentially continuous phenomenon: it does not appear to itself chopped up in bits (PP 233). In most cases, it manifests itself as an endless semi-conscious soliloquy.

    Nevertheless, two subjective states can be distinguished within that flux: consciousness, like a birds life [] seems to be made of an alternation of flights and perchings, of places of flightsor transitive partsand resting-placesor substantive parts (PP 236). The former is a dynamic relational thinking, whereas the latter is a comparatively restful and stable contemplative state. Let us notice Jamess use of the expression comparatively restful, which alleviatesif not destroysBergsons repeated critique of the Jamesian binomial.

    James pictures here a real differentiated rhythmic structure of consciousness whose major tone is continuity in the flux. There are no breaches as such, only variations in intensity. By definition, all moments of the stream interpenetrate and melt together. This description invites a parallel understanding of the eventful world as a seamless tapestry out of which, for pragmatic reasons, one identifies recurrent knots. In both cases, the evidence of relations plays an essential role. Bergson will soon adopt the same stance:

    the intuition of our duration, far from leaving us suspended in the

    void as pure analysis would do, puts us in contact with a whole

    1 Interestingly, a similar argument could be made with Bergson: cf. Pete A. Y.

    Gunter, Bergson, Mathematics, and Creativity, Process Studies, 28/3-4, 1999, 268-287.

  • 106 Michel Weber

    continuity of durations which we should try to follow either

    downwardly or upwardly: in both cases we can dilate ourselves

    indefinitely by a more and more vigorous effort, in both cases we

    transcend ourselves. In the first case, we advance toward a duration

    more and more scattered, whose palpitations, more rapid than ours,

    dividing our simple sensation, dilute its quality into quantity: at the

    limit would be the pure homogeneous, the pure repetition by which we

    shall define materiality. In advancing in the other direction, we go

    toward a duration which stretches, tightens, and becomes more and

    more intensified: at the limit would be eternity. This time not

    conceptual eternity, which would be an eternity of death, but an

    eternity of life. It would be a living and still moving eternity where our

    own duration would find itself like the vibrations in light, and which

    would be the concretion of duration as materiality is its dispersion.

    Between these two extreme limits moves intuition and this movement

    is metaphysics itself.1

    Similarly, James claims that our lived, immediate presentthat he calls specious presentis no knife-edge but saddle-like (PP I 609).

    4.3.2. Drops of Experience

    On the other hand, the drops of experience concept, constituting the focal point of the tenth chapter of the posthumous Some Problems of Philosophy, primarily puts forward discontinuity in our conscious and pre-conscious experience. Granting that the bulk of the argument relies upon Zenos antinomies, James claims for the obvious discontinuity of direct perceptual experience as well: we either receive nothing, or something already there in sensible amount. (SPP 155) There are two complementary issues: macroscopic and microscopic.

    The former is on the agenda of psychology since Gustav Fechner framed, in his Elemente der Psychophysik (1860),

    2 the concepts of absolute

    1 Bergson, The Creative Mind. 4th Ed. Trans, Mabelle L. Andison, New York,

    Philosophical Library, 1946, p. 221 (uvres, p. 1419). 2 The co-emergence of the concepts of threshold and unconscious has of course a

    more complex history: Herbart (1824), Weber (1829), Helmoltz (1859), Fechner (1860), Wundt (1878); then Lotze (1884), Ward (1886), Mnsterberg (1889) and eventually Myers, in the years 18891895. Furthermore, Fechner himself has relativized his psychophysics with a panpsychic cosmopsychology (Zend-Avesta,

  • Polysemiality of the Concept of Pure Experience 107

    threshold, discrimination threshold and scaling in order to understand why some stimuli are not perceived. It is underlying the stream of consciousness discussion that is thus less straightforward on the issue of continuity than one could expect. Throughout the Principles, James often speaks of integral and sectional pulse of subjectivity, pulse of consciousness or pulse of thought:

    Each pulse of cognitive consciousness, each Thought, dies away

    and is replaced by another. The other, among the things it knows,

    knows its own predecessor, and finding it warm, in the way we have

    described, greets it, saying: Thou art mine, and part of the same self

    with me. (PP I 339; cf. 278, 337, 500, 651)

    The later addresses the question of the possibility the irruption of novelty in the world and of free decisions of human beings. Introspection is here somewhat less important than the requirements of reason: the problem is as to which is the more rational supposition, that of continuous or that of discontinuous additions to whatever amount or kind of reality already exists. (SPP 154) In other words, our acquaintance with reality grows literally by buds or drops of perception. Intellectually and on reflection you can divide these into components, but as immediately given, they come totally or not at all. (SPP 155) Reality grows thus by abrupt increments of novelty (SPP 187): these increments, drops, buds, or steps, are characterized by some (microscopic) duration and extension; they are the building blocks of our (macroscopic) world.

    To repeat, two levels of the argument have to be distinguished: on the one hand, the epistemological question of sensory perception; on the other, the properly meta-physical question of the ontological structure of the Whole. Let us question further the latter, which grounds the former. To put it even more straightforwardly, the point is here that

    nature doesnt make eggs by making first half an egg, then a

    quarter, then an eighth, etc., and adding them together. She either

    makes a whole egg at once or none at all, and so of all other units.

    (PU 230)

    That all-at-once-ness or abruptness is furthermore of primary importance to grant the possibility of genuine novelty, which itself conditions the meaningfulness of life. So far so good.

    oder, ber die Dinge des Himmels und des Jenseits vom Standpunkt der Naturbetrachtung, Hamburg/Leipzig, L. Voss, 1851) that James discovered in the years 1900. Wundt, Lotze and Clifford were also panpsychists of sorts.

  • 108 Michel Weber

    But the meaningfulness of life appears to the philosophers eye as being directly correlated not only with genuine novelty, but with mundane stability and continuity as well. It is the actual togetherness of continuous and discontinuous ontological features that hasurgentlyto be thought of. This is all the more so since challenging that novelty seems to violate continuity [and] continuity seems to involve infinitely shaded gradation. (SPP 153) So how to solve the conundrum, if not by building the world of the subject (expression which is susceptible of a strict ontological understanding as well) with an uninterrupted series of buds of experience? In conclusion: there are breaches, but they are not gaps. Reality is a plenum, each and every one of its quanta impregnate and fertilize the others, thereby constructing the arrow of time. What adumbrates itself hereperhaps even more clearly than in the case of the streamis the powerful concept of internal relations. This is the road Whiteheads argument will take.

    4.3.3. Contiguum

    Our dialectic moment is itself three-fold: once the concept of contiguum is introduced, we raise the question of the development of Jamess ideas, and conclude with some remarks on Whiteheads development.

    On the one hand, we have shown that the stream is susceptible to a dissection; but that partition does not disclose separateexternalelements:

    I say of these time-parts that we cannot take any one of them so

    short that it will not after some fashion or other be a thought of the

    whole object the pack of cards is on the table. They melt into each

    other like dissolving view []. (PP 269)

    In other words, there is an internal relationship between them that preserves the whole without killing the parts. On the other, we have seen that the buds have to be understood as building a continuum. As SPP 187 claims, there is absolutely nothing between the buds. Each occurrence is at the same time something unprecedented and something acquainted with the universe in which it bursted. Sameness bring forth otherness. The image that is consequently projected in both casesthrough the concept of internal relationsis that of a contiguum which preserves both continuity and discontinuity, internal and external relations. What James claims of percepts and concepts can be said of continuity and discontinuity: neither, taken alone, knows reality in its completeness. We need them both, as we need both our legs to walk with. (SPP 53)

  • Polysemiality of the Concept of Pure Experience 109

    The remaining problem is that of the nature of the shift that James endures between the Principles of Psychology (1890) and the Problems of Philosophy (1911). Actually, the concept of buds or drops, already present in the Pluralistic Universe lectures (1908), was in gestation since Jamess reading of Bergsons Essai sur les donnes immdiates de la conscience (1889translated as Time and Free Will. An Essay on the Immediate Data of Consciousness) and Matire et mmoire (1896translated as Matter and Memory), sometime in 1902. Although there is no doubt that the importance of the discontinuist argument is linked with Jamess awareness of the Zenonian Bergson, we can find in the Principles somewhat quantic expressions: a kind of jointing and separateness, sudden contrasts in the quality (PP 233). Hence the necessity of re-examining the whole idea of a real shift in his thought: why could it not be simply a difference of emphasis? The subsidiary question is the timing of his progressive abandonment of dualism: for PP 233 things are still discrete and discontinuous; but as early as 1902, James praises Bergson for his complete demolition of dualism and of the old subject-object distinction in perception.

    1

    Eventually, all this needs to be put in perspective with the help of the constant knowledge James shows of the weaknesses of our insights and of the deficiencies of our languages. Both stand inexorably on our way towards truth. Language, like sight, prefers clear-cut distinctions, independent entities, external relationships. It is worth quoting once again Jamess apophthegm: when we conceptualize, we cut out and fix, and exclude everything but what we have fixed. A concept means a that-and-no-other. (PU 265) Reality, on the contrary, is in the making.

    Three points have been made so far: our mental experience, as James sees it, is above all, continuous; if we peruse the conditions of possibility of this experience, we have to acknowledge its actual discontinuity; the concept of contiguity enables us to think these two dimensions together. Now, the same pattern can be applied to Whitehead.

    On the one hand, Whiteheads philosophy of nature emphasizes the notion of a pure eventful continuity while protecting the evidence of punctual existences; on the other, his late metaphysics crystallises around the idea of a pure feeling constituting not only the immediacy of the subject, but the primal stuff of the World as well as the condition of the dynamic togetherness of the subjects and the objects (panexperientialist

    1 [] dmolition dfinitive du dualisme et de la vieille distinction du sujet et de

    lobjet dans la perception. (Letter to Bergson, 14 dcembre 1902, in Henri Bergson, Mlanges, pp. 566-568)

  • 110 Michel Weber

    wager). Sketching PRs ontological atomism should now allow a better insight of the synergy of these two traits.

    When Whitehead decides to throw a match into the powder magazine, he introduces a concept inspired by Jamess drops of experience: the actual entity. Actual entities are the final real things of which the world is made up. There is no going behind actual entities to find anything more real. [] The final facts are, all alike, actual entities; and these actual entities are drops of experience, complex and interdependent. (PR 18) The conscious experience of a subject is thus actually made of a consecution (string or sequence) of atomic events, each being a particular mode of togetherness of the universe. As a result, his ontology systematically studies three main areas: the becoming, the being, and the relatedness of actual entities (PR xiii).

    The becomingor concrescenceof actual entities is the crux of the matter in so far as vivid privatei.e., subjectiveexperience is concerned. When the many become one it is ipso facto accompanied by subjective immediacy and enjoyment. To put it another way, the process of concrescence names the ontological mystery itself: at the confluence of God and the World,

    1 a totally new mode of togetherness of all past events is

    actualised, thereby creating new value, new enjoyment. When a genetic analysis of the actual entity subject is lead, it concentrates on prehensions: one speculates then on the selective appropriation, contrast, and contrast of contrast of the various prehended data. The mighty image Whitehead uses is feeling of feelings: in his technicalities, a feeling is a positive prehension of the feeling(s) of other actualities. Of course, the concept has been purified in order to be applicable to any actual entity, whatever its grade. The higher grade of mental activity human beings testify are in continuity with lower grades; there is no difference in kind, only (huge) difference in degree.

    What really exists is not things made but things in the making.

    Once made, they are dead, and an infinite number of alternative

    conceptual decompositions can be used in defining them. (PU 263)2

    That Jamesian claim definitely resonates in the ontology of Harvard. When the process of concrescence has reached its end, when out of a mere multiplicity a new unity has crystallised, the actual entity topples into

    1 The introduction of the concept of god, an essential feature of Whiteheads

    ontology, cannot be approached here. 2 Cf. PU 256 on the conceptual decomposition of life and PU 232 on the ideal

    decomposition of the drops.

  • Polysemiality of the Concept of Pure Experience 111

    objectivity; from actual entity-subject, it turns into actual entity-object. So, through concrescence, the many become one and, through transition, the many are increased by one (PR 21). The actuality-subject exists; is in determination; the actuality-object is, is determined. Genetic analysis is not possible here, but instead a coordinate analysis is required: processes of integration and of reintegration are so to speak replaced by a pure position in being (more precisely, the analysis is carried on the extensive standpoint occupied by the actuality-subject). What really matters for our argument is summarized in the principle of process: how an actual entity becomes constitutes what that actual entity is; [] its being is constituted by its becoming. (PR 23) In other words, subjectivity constitutes, again and again, objectivity. The concept of substance is replaced by various societies, the simplest one being the enduring object, which is made of a continuous line of inheritance among successive actual entities. There is a trajectory of actualities-object crowned by an actuality-subject, soon to topple into objectivity and to be followed by a new concrescence. That never-ending innovatory unrest is what Whitehead names the creative advance.

    A quick glance at the relatedness of actual entities will disclose the contiguism at work here. Rather than injecting in the discussion the binomial physical pole/mental pole, we use the old opposition between external and internal relations. To make a long story short, let us say that Whitehead claims for his societies of actualities subject and object both types of relations. The actuality-subject, i.e., the actuality in determination is externally related, it constitutes a separate quantum of existence, and internally related to the universe, the power of the past is active at the nucleus of the concrescence. The key is once again the subject-object difference: among subjectsand among objectsthere can be only external relations; but the relation subject-object is more subtle. Given a subject prehending an object, the vector-like relation instituted is external from the perspective of the (prehended) object and internal from the perspective of the (prehending) subject. The concrescence of any one actual entity necessarily involves the other actual entities among its components, but these actualities-object constitute a complete whole.

    All this is strikingly very close to the Buddhist image of moments of consciousness as a string of pearls, provided that the string is not understood as a support or medium (in the sense of the Greek hupokeimenon or the Latin subjectum), but as a way of suggesting the continuous discontinuity of the primordial experience. Now, it is quite amazing to remark that Nishida (18701945)the Japanese scholar whose thought has been mainly influenced by James, Bergson and Husserl,

  • 112 Michel Weber

    together with a constant practice of Zen Buddhismunderstands the true self as a series of moments of pure experience, i.e., as a continuity of discontinuities.

    1 The true self is the authentic or enlightened self; it is the

    awakening to the Buddha nature (satori). The unity of subjectivity and objectivity occurs furthermore at the standpoint of emotion, which reminds us of Jamess immense emotional sense of atonement and reconciliation.

    In conclusion, the atomism of Whiteheads Harvard epoch is far from being monadological; concrescing actualities have windows and are thus Janus-like: on the one hand, they constitute a quantum (or drop) of existence; on the other, they are the product and the actor of a continuous innovatory process. The continuous features of the universe are generated quantically and every act of becoming must have an immediate successor (PR 69). That tight intermingling of continuity and discontinuity fully deserve the contiguist label. It is a contiguism of pure feeling because of the prehensions involved in the processes of concrescence and of transition, and especially because of their emotional tone. These are remote from the edges of normal consciousness, and convey the primordial form of ontological enjoyment.

    Radical empiricism is neither a nave realism nor a nave constructivism. For the former, the absolute steadiness of being allows the quest for one single Truth; for the latter, it is doubtful that any escape from solipsistic/pluralistic perception is possible. The pragmatic conception of truth, for its part, realizes something like a processualization of the old correspondence theory of truth. By interpreting truth in terms of action and power of adaptation, it makes the adequatio rei et intellectu more subtle and adequate.

    Pure experience occurs in buds; and since these buds occupy only a limited spatio-temporal slab (this needs to be qualified from a strict Whiteheadian perspective), it is their uninterrupted succession that builds the continuous features of our world. Pure experience, in other words, structures itself in a contiguum. Pure experience, in the strong sense of the term, names the event that is the unison between the experiencing and the experienced. It is a bare ethereal experiential tuning in which subjectivity and objectivity have become irrelevant tags. Useful in everyday life, these

    1 Kitar Nishida, An Inquiry into the Good. Translated by Masao Abe and

    Christopher Ives, New Haven and London, Yale University Press, 1990, chap. I. (The original title is Zen no Kenky, 1911.) Cf. Keiji Nishitani, Nishida Kitar. Translated by Yamamoto Seisaku and James W. Heisig. Introduction by D. S. Clarke, Jr., Berkeley, University of California Press, 1991.

  • Polysemiality of the Concept of Pure Experience 113

    complementary concepts have reached, together with the substantialism they properly speaking materialise, their breaking point. It is here that the unavoidable idea of a ladder of consciousness intervenes: the level of consciousness at which human beings are attending to their affairs is definitely not the level at which the awareness of pure experiences contiguity is possible; it is the analogon of the visible part of the spectrum. To insulate everyday consciousness would be a mistake as heavy as Kants noumenalization of the ultimate concreteness.

    Ontologyone could even dare to say lived ontologynecessitates a thought bypassing the principle of excluded middle. The continuous-discontinuous dialectic does not ask for an either or choice. Similarly, the polysemiality of Jamess concepts is not a handicap. It is not only possible to organise (i.e., analyse) the various semantic layers involved, but it is through the activation of their synergy (i.e., syntheses) that we can make the concrete speak. The internal dynamic of the semantic nebulae that characterizes his major categories has the virtue of pointing to the ineffable. The rational womb has given birth to the nonrational.

    When the commentators look for a strict univocality in Jamess prose, they only carve a Procustean definition destructive of the total cosmic experience imbedded in the texts. Pure experience is the emotional vividness of the nonrational. Since there is neither distance nor distantiation involved in pure experience, language is nothing but irrelevant. (This is especially obvious from the perspective of its intentional structure.) Jamess conceptual efforts to recover the integrity of experience, however radical, ask again and again for their experiential actualization. How and why the experiential contiguum does not belong to everyday consciousness still need further explorations.


Recommended