+ All Categories
Home > Documents > MillRevenge.pdf

MillRevenge.pdf

Date post: 05-Apr-2018
Category:
Upload: megan-brown
View: 219 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend

of 28

Transcript
  • 8/2/2019 MillRevenge.pdf

    1/28

    Philosophical Papers

    Vol. 39, No. 3 (November 2010): 315-341

    ISSN 0556-8641 print/ISSN 1996-8523 online 2010 The Editorial Board Philosophical Papers

    Justice and RetaliationStephen Darwall

    Abstract: Punishment and Reparations are sometimes held to express retaliatory emotionswhose object is to strike back against a victimizer. I begin by examining a version of this ideain Mills writings about natural resentment and the sense of justice in Chapter V ofUtilitarianism. Mills view is that the natural sentiment of resentment or vengeance that isat the heart of the concept of justice is essentially retaliatory, therefore has nothing moral init, and so must be disciplined or moralized from without by the desire to promote the

    general welfare. I argue to the contrary that if reactive attitudes like resentment and moralblame are understood as Strawson analyzed them, as essentially interpersonal or secondpersonal, they have a different content and function. They implicitly demand respect in a

    way that also expresses respect for the victimizer as a member of mutually accountablecommunity of moral equals. Some implications of this idea are discussed for the expressivetheory of punishment and civil recourse theories of torts.

    Retribution can be conceived within a theory of just punishment or as

    retaliation, as in thelex talionis

    : an eye for an eye, and a tooth for a tooth.1

    Retaliation and retaliatory emotions are not essentially about justice; they

    are about striking back or gaining vengeance, either simpliciter or to

    restore honor. When retribution is conceived as retaliation, retributive

    emotions become retaliatory emotions, a victims wanting to do to his

    victimizer what his victimizer has done to him. In what follows, I argue

    that the states of mind that P. F. Strawson famously termed reactive

    attitudes, through which we hold others and ourselves morally

    responsible, are not essentially retaliatory. To the contrary, reactiveattitudes express reciprocal respect and so mediate relations of mutual

    accountability (Strawson 1968).

    1 The Oxford English Dictionary gives the following use of lex talionis: They take theField with their best Force, not only to recover their Wives, but, Lege Talionis , toplunder the Robbers of theirs. (From P. Kolbens The Present State of the Cape of Good

    Hope, 1731).

  • 8/2/2019 MillRevenge.pdf

    2/28

    316 Stephen Darwall

    In Chapter Five ofUtilitarianism, John Stuart Mill attempts to cope with

    one of the strongest obstacles to a utilitarian theory of right, namely, the

    objection that utilitarianism cannot account for justice (1998: V.1). Mill

    considers various platitudes about justice, which he summarizes by saying

    that the idea of justice supposes two things; a rule of conduct, and a

    sentiment which sanctions the rule (V.23). Mills response to objections

    regarding justice then consists in two mutually reinforcing prongs. The

    more familiar is a rule-utilitarian theory of justice (and of moral

    obligation, more generally). To have a right, and thus something that can

    be infringed only unjustly, Mill says, is to have something which society

    ought to defend me in the possession of (V.25). If, he continues, theobjector goes on to ask, why it ought? I can give him no other reason than

    general utility (V.25).

    The general form of this rule-utilitarian prong is familiar enough.

    Someone has a right to something if, and only if, it would promote utility

    for society to accept rules that appropriately defend everyones having it,

    for example, autonomy, property, or freedom of thought. This accounts

    for the first of the two things that the concept of justice supposes: a rule

    of conduct that assesses acts directly and is itself assessed by

    considerations of utility. But how exactly does the social acceptance of a

    rule defend peoples rights and just claims? This second prong of Mills

    response is less familiar. Although society will of course make use of

    various formal coercive measures through law, Mill says that it is part of

    the idea of justice, that rules of conduct that protect justice and rights are

    sanction[ed] also by a distinctive sentiment, which he calls the sentiment

    of justice.What Mill says about the sentiment of justice is much less frequently

    discussed than is his rule utilitarianism.2 But the two come as a package

    deal. Part of what it is for a rule of conduct to be socially realized

    according to Mill is for there to be a sentiment which sanctions the rule.

    To understand Mills response, it is necessary to ask, therefore, what this

    2 An exception is Crisp 1997: 167-172.

  • 8/2/2019 MillRevenge.pdf

    3/28

    Justice and Retaliation 317

    distinctive sentiment is and how it is to function within a utilitarian theory

    in the defense of rights and justice.

    In retrospect, it is ironic that Mills emphasis on the sentiment of

    justice has been so little discussed. Mill concludes his treatment of

    objections on account of justice by saying that justices conceptual

    connection to the sentiment of justice poses the only real difficulty in the

    utilitarian theory of morals (V.39). It has always been evident, Mill

    continues, that all cases of justice are also cases of expediency.3 The

    problem has been that the sentiments that are distinctively implicated in

    justicemost clearly for victims of injusticedo not respond to

    considerations of expediency, utility, and welfare in the way that, say,sympathy and benevolence do. It follows, in Mills view, that utilitarianism

    can adequately cope with the justice objection only if the sentiment of

    justice can itself be appropriately accommodated within a utilitarian

    theory of justice and rights. And this is precisely what Mill thinks he has

    done by the end of Chapter Five.

    Ultimately, my aim in this essay is not to analyze and assess the resources

    that utilitarianism and Mills version have to deal with justice, although I

    shall suggest along the way that they face a fundamental obstacle that is

    related to the one Mill notes. What I wish to explore, rather, is the relation

    between justice (and moral obligation more generally), on the one hand,

    and retaliation and the retaliatory emotions on the other. By retaliatory

    emotions, I mean emotions whose object essentially includes retaliation of

    some kind (vengeful anger, say). What makes Mill especially relevant to our

    task is that he holds that the natural feeling or sentiment that forms the core

    of the sentiment of justice, resentment, is indeed essentially retaliatory. It isa hard-wired response to strike back and retaliate against injuries that

    human beings share with other animals. At the same time, Mill holds that

    when the natural feeling of resentment is properly moralised, it is not

    essentially tied to retaliation.

    3 He must here mean that justice can be accounted for in terms of the expediency of the

    relevant rules of conduct.

  • 8/2/2019 MillRevenge.pdf

    4/28

    318 Stephen Darwall

    I agree with Mill both that justice is tied conceptually to the sentiment

    or attitude of resentment4 and that a properly moralized resentment

    should not be understood as essentially retaliatory. However, I believe that

    Mill is mistaken about what it is for resentment to be moralized. Since

    Mill takes resentment in its natural form to be essentially retaliatory, he

    holds that it has nothing moral in it (V.21). To be moralized, therefore,

    resentment must be disciplined by some other motive, sentiment, or

    attitude that is external to it, as Mill sees it, by sympathy responding to

    demands of social good (V.39).

    I shall argue against this Millian claim. I will side rather with P.F.

    Strawson and, as I read him, Adam Smith, who argue that resentment isproperly moralized not by being disciplined by a different motive or

    feeling like sympathetic concern or benevolence. Rather, resentment of

    at least one important form is what Strawson calls a reactive attitude

    whose object is not to retaliate against someone who has injured one, but

    to hold him responsible in a way that expresses respect for him as a

    member of a mutually accountable moral community. So understood,

    what resentment seeks is not getting back, but the others

    acknowledgment of having wrongfully injured one and the others taking

    responsibility for what he has done, for example, through compensation

    and, perhaps, punitive damages. So understood, resentment is

    moralized from the inside through resources that are already present

    within it as a reactive attitude, rather than by some external feeling,

    motive, or attitude.

    Retaliation, vengeance, and honorWe can begin with what Mill says about natural resentment. It is natural,

    Mill says, to resent, and to repel or retaliate, any harm done or attempted

    against ourselves, or against those with whom we sympathise (V.18).

    Similarly, Mill speaks of the natural feeling of retaliation or vengeance

    and, since he thinks we share this response with other animals, the animal

    4 And with Adam Smith who also holds this, as I shall bring out presently.

  • 8/2/2019 MillRevenge.pdf

    5/28

    Justice and Retaliation 319

    desire to repel or retaliate a hurt or damage to oneself, or to those with

    whom one sympathises (V.19,21).

    There is no reason to doubt that human beings have such desires and

    feelings or that resentment is frequently used to refer to them. Even here,

    however, there may be useful distinctions, for example, between what Mill

    calls impulses of self-defence and desires for revenge. More seems to be

    going on in the desire to seek vengeance than just repelling injury.

    Nevertheless, desires of both sorts seem common enough among human

    beings, and resentment can refer to both.

    Since I shall want to contrast resentment of the kind discussed by

    Strawson and Smith5 with retaliatory impulses of both these kinds, it isworth exploring these Millian forms of natural resentment and the

    relations between them further. Notice first an important psychological

    mechanism that Nietzsche and Scheler described that can turn self-

    defensive impulses into a desire for revenge. When someone is unable or

    otherwise not in a position to respond directly to an attack, retaliatory

    impulses are not discharged and may be blocked or even repressed. It is

    checked or repressed retaliation that gives rise to the desire for vengeance.

    Indeed, we only speak of revenge if initial retaliatory impulses have been

    blocked in some way, and a grudge is developed and borne (Scheler 1961:

    27). Nietzsches famous analysis of the development of slave morality out

    of the ressentiment of the weak begins with such a psychic movement. In

    their case, however, the weak cannot so much as bear the feeling of

    personal injury so they repress it, and it is reconstructed in the dark

    workshop of their unconscious as a feeling apparently responding to an

    impersonal injury, thus giving rise to a sense of moral evil. The feelingeats deeply into men of ressentiment, who are incapable even of

    acknowledging it to themselves and whose vengeance takes the form of a

    transvaluation of aristocratic values into moral ones (Nietzsche 2006).

    Retaliatory impulses of self-defense function most obviously to protect

    life and limb, but they also play a role in defending positions in dominance

    5 And also in Darwall 2006, from which I here draw.

  • 8/2/2019 MillRevenge.pdf

    6/28

  • 8/2/2019 MillRevenge.pdf

    7/28

    Justice and Retaliation 321

    Vengeance is frequently, maybe implicitly always, a response to

    perceived insult or contempt that seeks to retaliate or avenge the insult

    and so restore the agents honor (or that of those with whom she

    sympathizes). Owing to the nature of insults and honor, retaliation can

    succeed only by expressing contempt for the insult and so dishonoring the

    insulter. This is an important point of contrast with the kind of second-

    personal, as I will call it, resentment that Strawson and (sometimes) Smith

    discuss.6 Whereas second-personal resentment, and other reactive

    attitudes like indignation and blame, seek to address their objects and

    hold them accountable in a way that respectfully demands respect,

    returning a kind of (second-personal) respect for disrespect, vengeanceand retaliation return (honor) disrespect, that is, contempt, for contempt.

    Since social status and the honor constituting it are not moral ideas, I

    shall assume that Mill is right when he says that the desire for retaliation

    or vengeance has nothing moral in it (V.21). Justice and morality of

    course permit self-defense, but only to the degree necessary to disable or

    repel an attack, not to retaliate or avenge it. Similarly, justice gives victims

    claims to compensation, but this also is different from retaliation or

    vengeance. Finally, although justice warrants punishment of the guilty,

    that differs from retaliation as well. Even if retributivism is correct and just

    punishment involves something proportional to the injustice done, that

    still does not mean that punishment reduces to getting back or even, or

    simply doing to the perpetrator what he did to the victim.7 Mills diagnosis

    stands, or so I shall assume.

    Mill on moralized resentmentMill argues that when resentment is properly moralized, though, itis tied

    to justice, and, moreover, that his rule-utilitarian account of justice can

    6 Presently, I shall argue that Strawsonian reactive attitudes have an ineliminable second-personal element. For extended discussion, see Darwall 2006.7 That does not mean, of course, that practices that have also been called punishment donot involve something like retaliation. The very term lex talionis shows otherwise. The point

    is that punishment as ajust practice does not involve it.

  • 8/2/2019 MillRevenge.pdf

    8/28

    322 Stephen Darwall

    explain why this is so. I shall argue that Mills first claim is correct. I shall

    argue also, however, that Mills second claim is unwarranted and that

    when we understand resentment as a Strawsonian reactive attitude, we can

    see that it is appropriately moralized from within rather than from

    without, that is, from a perspective that is itself inherent within reactive

    attitudeswhat I will call a second-person standpointrather than from the

    third-person perspective of sympathetic concern or benevolence.

    First, though, let us consider Mills proposal for how natural

    resentment can be moralized. Mill begins promisingly. It is common

    enough, he says, to feel resentment merely because we have suffered

    pain (V.22). So far, this is natural resentment, not yet moralized. Forsomeones resentment to be really a moral feeling, it must respond to

    whether the act is blamable (V.22). This seems clearly right. And Mill

    plausibly adds that so long as someone considers only how an act affects

    him individually, he is not concerning himself about the justice of his

    actions. So much, he notes, is admitted even by non-utilitarian moralists.

    But non-utilitarian moralists need not, and of course generally do not,

    accept Mills rule-utilitarian standard for justice and hence for how natural

    resentment is appropriately moralized. Mill holds that resentment is

    warranted, and the act that is its object is blamable, just in case a rule

    prohibiting the action would maximally promote utility were it socially

    accepted, where this acceptance itselfincludes the relevant sanctioning

    attitudes of resentment, from victims, and blame, from third parties. Mill

    concludes that a properly moralized resentment, the sentiment of justice,

    consists in the animal desire to repel or retaliate a hurt widened so as

    to include all persons, by the human capacity of enlarged sympathy, andthe human conception of intelligent self-interest (V.21).

    When an injured party feels the desire to retaliate, but then turns her

    view from the way her injurers act affects her to its effect on all

    humankind, or to the effects an act of that kind has on the collective, this

    may moderate her desire, but it is hard to see how, by itself, it can change

    her desires fundamental character. Perhaps she will want to hurt her

    injurer less, or more, depending on the overall effects of the act or of that

  • 8/2/2019 MillRevenge.pdf

    9/28

    Justice and Retaliation 323

    kind of action as a general rule. It could even be that the desire to hurt

    flips over to the desire to benefit when she sees that the hurt to herself

    buys overall benefit, either in the case at hand or in this kind of case in

    general. Either way, she will simply be wanting to return bad for bad or

    good for good (tit for tat), in the first case, on her own behalf, in the latter,

    on everyones behalf.

    It is also hard to see how reflection on benefits and harms, taken in

    themselves, can give someone the idea of conducts justice or injustice. From

    the perspective of the basic psychic mechanism involved in Millian natural

    resentment, we would expect reflection on the overall effects of an act,

    either a particular instance or such actions as a general rule, simply to leadto a desire to hurt or to benefit the agent in proportion to how negative or

    positive those overall effects might be for the agent or all humankind,

    respectively.

    It seems most natural to read Mill, however, as intending that

    sanctioning sentiments should come into the utility assessments

    themselves. When we do the rule-utilitarian calculations, we need to take

    account of the effects of peoples having rule-sanctioning sentiments as

    part of what is involved in the social acceptance of a rule. Indulging a

    desire to retaliate can have bad effectsjust think of the Hatfields and the

    McCoys, not to mention ethnic, tribal, and sectarian strife on a larger

    scale. Reflecting on the costs of retaliatory emotions can lead us to

    moderate how much we want to hurt others, not just in the sense of

    wanting to hurt them less, but in the sense of wanting less to hurt them.

    The Millian view would seem to be that natural resentment is

    moralized by reflection on the benefits and costs of the whole socialpractice of sanctioning rules, where this includes the having of various

    sanctioning attitudes. This is why I say that Mills view treats resentment as

    moralized from the outside rather than from within materials that

    resentment itself provides. What sets one thinking about the overall

    benefits and costs, not only of actions, but of sanctioning attitudes

    themselves as part of practices that discourage actions that are their

    objects, is nothing within resentment, however broadly conceived, but

  • 8/2/2019 MillRevenge.pdf

    10/28

    324 Stephen Darwall

    some desire like universal benevolence that regulates it from the outside.

    Responding to the act itself (or acts of that kind), from the perspective of

    the injured party or parties (in the case of all humankind), we want to

    harm the agent(s) in proportion to the harm caused (again, to oneself or,

    on balance, to all humankind). But it may be a bad thing as a general

    practice for us to give in to these responses. When I reflect on this fact,

    sympathy or concern for all human kind may then lead me to check or

    otherwise moderate both natural (retaliatory) resentment and resentment

    from the perspective of all humankind.

    But precisely for this reason, it is also hard to see how natural

    resentment disciplined in this way by sympathy or benevolence, shoulddeserve to be called a sentiment of justice. The concepts of justice and

    rights are connected analytically to those of valid claims and the standing

    or authority people have to make claims and demands and to hold others

    accountable for responding appropriately to them. As we shall appreciate

    better in the next section, the most that reflection on costs and benefits

    can provide, taken by themselves, are considerations ofdesirability, reasons

    to desire certain things for the sake of those who would be benefited or

    harmed, not reasons tied conceptually to the legitimacy of claims and

    demands. When we reflect on harms and benefits to ourselves, this leads

    us to what is desirable for us, and when we reflect on benefits and harms to

    all humankind, this leads us to what would be desirable for all humankind.

    Nothing has yet been said to put considerations of justice or injustice onto

    the map. Where Mills proposal seems to leave us, therefore, is with the

    animal desire to retaliate being regulated by a benevolence-driven

    psychic process that seems impotent by itself to bring considerations ofjustice even into view.

    Strawson, reactive attitudes, and the second-person standpoint

    The point I have just been making against Mill is an instance of what I call

    Strawsons Point in The Second-Person Standpoint. In his famous essay,

    Freedom and Resentment, Strawson argued influentially against

    consequentialist compatibilist views that hold that determinism poses no

  • 8/2/2019 MillRevenge.pdf

    11/28

    Justice and Retaliation 325

    threat to practices of moral responsibility since the latter can be fully

    justified by their efficacy in regulating behaviour in socially desirable

    ways. (Strawson 1968: 72). According to consequentialists like Mill,

    punishment is justified by its incentive and deterrence effects, and,

    although standard excuses can be given a similar rationale, there is no

    corresponding warrant for excusing an act just because it was caused.

    Wrongs done in utter ignorance or under extreme duress are

    appropriately excused, since punishment under those conditions cannot

    deter. But there obviously is no consequentialist justification for treating

    determinism as an excuse generally, so determinism poses no threat to

    moral responsibility.Consequentialist theories of moral responsibility having the same

    shape as Mills are Strawsons target. Against these approaches, Strawson

    argues that social desirability cannot provide a justification of the right

    sort for practices of moral responsibility as we understand them. (1968:

    74) When we seek to hold people accountable, what matters is not whether

    punishment is pragmatically desirable, either in a particular case or in

    general, but whether an agents action was culpable. Desirability is a reason

    of the wrong kind to warrant the attitudes and actions in which holding

    someone responsible consists in their own terms. This is Strawsons Point.

    Strawsons Point is an instance of the wrong kind of reason problem

    (DArms and Jacobson 2000a and 2000b, Rabinowicz and Ronnw-

    Rasmussen 2004, Olson 2004, and Hieronymi 2005). Pragmatic

    considerations for belief do not make a proposition credible; moral

    reasons against being amused do not in themselves undermine a jokes

    humor; and considerations of the desirabilitywhether personal, social,or even moralof holding someone responsible do not make his action

    culpable. In each case, the right kind of reasons for warranting the

    relevant attitude in its own terms must derive from distinctive norms for

    attitudes of that kind: for belief, for amusement, and for the attitudes and

    actions that are distinctively involved in holding people responsible. It

    must be a fact about or feature of an object, appropriate consideration of

    which could provide the basis (someones reason) for a warranted attitude

  • 8/2/2019 MillRevenge.pdf

    12/28

    326 Stephen Darwall

    of that kind toward the object. It is impossible to come to believe some

    propositionp by reflecting on the fact that it would be desirable to believe

    p, (devilishly) impossible to find something unfunny (though possible to

    have ones sense of humor stilled) by considering the moral offensiveness

    of finding it so, and impossible also to feel guilty or to resent a wrong by

    reflecting on the desirability (personal, social, or moral) of having these

    feelings.

    The general point is that normativity and normative reasons always

    concern some specific attitude or other, and reasons that are of the right

    kind for one sort of attitude will not generally be so for another. When the

    issue is whether someone can warrantedly be held responsible for someaction and resented or blamed, this concerns reasons for resenting or

    blaming him, that is, reasons that bear on whether what he did was

    culpable and something to which resentment would be a fitting response.

    The overall costs and benefits of resenting or blaming him, or of resenting

    or blaming acts like his, are reasons for desiring or wishing one could

    resent or blame him or warrantedly do so. They cannot show that

    resentment and blame are warranted in their own terms, that an act

    actually is blameworthy or one to which resentment would be a fitting

    response (DArms and Jacobson 2000b).

    Strawson coined the term reactive attitude to refer to the mental states

    that are distinctively involved in holding people morally accountable,

    whether another person, as in indignation, resentment, or moral blame,

    or oneself, as in the emotion of guilt. Strawson did not give a formal

    definition of these attitudes, but their central features are clear from their

    role in his argument about moral responsibility and freedom of the will.Strawsons central idea is that reactive attitudes essentially involve an

    interpersonal way of regarding the individuals who are their objects that

    commits the holder of the attitude to certain assumptions about the

    individual who is their object and the individuals capacities to regulate

    her will. Unlike objective attitudes, like disdain, disgust, and annoyance,

    reactive attitudes are essentially characterized by involvement or

    participation with others in interpersonal human relationships (Strawson

  • 8/2/2019 MillRevenge.pdf

    13/28

    Justice and Retaliation 327

    1968). There is always an essentially interpersonal or second-personal

    element to reactive attitudes. Through the attitude we hold its object to

    something and thereby implicitly make a demand of him or her. As

    Strawson puts the point, the making of the demand is the proneness to

    such attitudes (Strawson 1968: 92-93).

    The reason that reactive attitudes distinctively implicate freedom of the

    will (the main subject of Strawsons essay and argument), then, is that we

    can intelligibly address a demand to someone to regulate her will

    appropriately only if we suppose that she can so regulate it as a result of

    recognizing our demands legitimacy. That is why it is not just unfair, but

    not fully coherent in its own terms, to hold very young children or theinsane responsible through reactive attitudes. They are in no position to

    answer for themselves or,a fortiori, to regulate their conduct through the

    recognition that they are accountable

    When we feel reactive attitudes like resentment and blame, we

    implicitly address some claim, demand, or expectation to the object of our

    attitude. In this way, reactive attitudes do not merely have objects; they

    have addressees. (This is what makes them second personal.) But though

    reactive attitudes are implicitly directive, they are not merelyor nakedly

    so. They purport not to force or overpower the other, but to direct her

    with authority by addressing some legitimate claim or demand to her. And

    unlike non-reactive attitudes like contempt or the desire to retaliate Mill

    calls natural resentment, they call for recognition of the legitimacy of the

    demand and the authority that its address presupposes. They come with

    an RSVP.

    This, again, is a fundamental difference between reactive attitudesthrough which we hold others answerable and honor respect and

    contempt, as these function in honor cultures. Honor cultures do not

    necessarily involve accountability at all, unless, that is, they are somehow

    overlain on an accountability culture.8 The currency of honor cultures is

    8 I discuss this difference between honor and accountability cultures and the way differentforms of recognition or respect (honor respect and second-personal respect) mediate them

    in Darwall 2008.

  • 8/2/2019 MillRevenge.pdf

    14/28

    328 Stephen Darwall

    deference, honor respect, and contempt, not the essentially second-

    personal respect that, as we shall consider in more detail in the next

    section, is implicit in reactive attitudes and moral accountability.

    Consider the difference between a disdainful rolling of the eyes and a

    look that expresses (second-personal) resentment or indignation (looking

    daggers). The latter addresses its object in a way that the former does not

    and calls for a reciprocally recognizing response. A vivid example is the

    staredown that the Italian ice dancer, Barbara Fusar Poli gave her

    partner Maurizio Margaglio (thirty-one seconds by one journalists watch)

    after Margaglio dropped her during the Ice Dancing competition in the

    2006 Winter Olympics. As the Internet edition of the San Diego Union-Tribune had it: Barbara Fusar Poli to partner Maurizio Margaglio: Look

    me in the eye and tell me how you dropped me.9 Suppose, however, that

    Fusar Poli had contemptuously rolled her eyes after the fall and skated off

    in disgust. Any expressive address in that case would most likely have been

    to the cognoscenti off stage. Though its object would still have been

    Margaglio, it would not necessarily have been addressed to him at all. She

    might have been finished with him.

    The second-personal character of reactive attitudes also marks a

    fundamental difference with the desire to retaliate or get even. Like

    contempt, retaliation has no necessary connection to accountability and so

    does not involve any implicit presupposition of authoritative demand or

    any claim for recognition of that authority. It may be that revenge is

    especially sweet when it is at the victims hand, but even then it need not

    purport to hold a perpetrator answerable to the victim in the way that

    second-personal resentment does.Strawson makes an important distinction within reactive attitudes

    between personal and impersonal ones. This can be confusing, since it is

    easy to lose track of the fact that all reactive attitudes, even impersonal

    ones, must be interpersonal, in Strawsons term, or second personal.

    Personal reactive attitudes are those, like resentment and guilt, that are

    9 (http://www.signonsandiego.com/sports/olympics/20060220-9999-lz1x20falls.html)

  • 8/2/2019 MillRevenge.pdf

    15/28

    Justice and Retaliation 329

    felt as if from the perspective of a participant in the events giving rise to it

    (first or second parties), whereas impersonal reactive attitudes, like

    indignation or moral blame, are felt as if from a third partys point of

    view. One cannot resent or forgive injuries to people with whom one lacks

    some personal connection, but this is no impediment to moral blame or

    disapproval. Nevertheless, however impersonal it may be, blame is not an

    objective attitude in Strawsons sense. It is just as interpersonal or second

    personal as personal reactive attitudes like resentment or guilt.10 It cannot

    play its role in Strawsons argument as a reactive attitude unless it is. Thus

    although impersonal reactive attitudes are felt as if from the perspective of

    a third party, they are not third-personal attitudes in the usual sense;they involve the same second-personal element of implicit address as do

    personal ones, only as if from the perspective of a representative person

    rather than from any individuals standpoint.11

    Personal and impersonal reactive attitudes implicate different

    authorities to make the demands they implicitly address. When we feel

    moral disapproval or blame towards people for violating a moral

    obligation, we implicitly address demands not as individuals, but as

    representative persons or members of the moral community and implicitly

    demand that those we blame make the same demand of themselves from

    the same perspective. When, however, someone has violated a right you

    hadagainst him, hence a bipolar obligation he had to you, he has not just

    done wronghe has wrongedyou.12 So you have a distinctive individual

    standing as the victim to hold him answerable, for example, to resent the

    wrong, which you can exercise or not at your discretion. You can seek

    10 The same abnormal light which shows the agent to us as one in respect of whom thepersonal attitudes, the personal demand, are to be suspended, shows him to us also as onein respect of whom the impersonal attitudes, the generalized demand, are to be suspended(Strawson 1968)11 Similarly, second personal does not imply second party. Guilt, like any reactive attitude issecond personal, since it involves implicit address, but it clearly is not a second-partyattitude. In feeling guilt, one implicitly addresses a demand to oneself. Finally, any second-personal attitude is also first personal. Address, whether implicit or explicit, is always fromsomeone (an individual (I) or a collective (we)).

    12 The term bipolar obligation comes from Thompson 2004.

  • 8/2/2019 MillRevenge.pdf

    16/28

    330 Stephen Darwall

    compensation or not, forgive or not, and so on. No one else has the

    standing to do these things, except perhaps to represent you if you have

    authorized them or cannot speak for yourself.

    We can see this in the traditional distinction between the law of torts

    and criminal law. When someone has been wronged, his right violated,

    an injury done, then he has standing to bring a tort action; it is up to

    him whether to bring it or not. If he would prefer to let bygones be

    bygones and is competent to make his own choices, then it is generally

    not within others discretion or that of the state to pursue it on his

    behalf. The criminal law is different. Whether to prosecute a rights

    violation as a crime is not up to the victim alone; it is up to the peopleand their representatives (though they may properly take advice from

    the victim on certain matters). Thus criminal law is to torts, as

    representative authority is to individual authority, as warranted blame

    is to warranted resentment.

    The difference between warranted personal and impersonal reactive

    attitudes tracks the difference between rights, justice, and (bipolar)

    obligations to someone, on the one hand, and moral obligation period, on

    the other (Thompson 2004, Darwall 2010a, 2010b). This, again, is the

    distinction between wronging someone and doing wrong simpliciter,

    between violating a moral obligation to someone and violating a moral

    obligation period.

    When justice is involved, at least in the sense in which we are

    interested, so also are rights and bipolar obligations. Mill states the

    orthodox view when he says that justice implies something which it is not

    only right to do, and wrong not to do, but which some individual personcan claim from us as his moral right (V.15). According to Hohfelds widely

    accepted typology, it is a conceptual truth that (claim) rights entail

    correlative (bipolar) obligations (Hohfeld 1923: 65-75). If you have a claim

    right that I not step on your foot, it just follows that I am obligated to you

    not to step on your foot and that I am distinctively accountable to you for

    not doing so, that is, that you have the individual authority to hold me

    accountable and make the relevant claims of me.

  • 8/2/2019 MillRevenge.pdf

    17/28

    Justice and Retaliation 331

    Recall now Mills claim that in order for resentment to be really a

    moral feeling, it must be responsive to whether the resented act is

    blamable (V.22). Mill here glimpses what we might think of as a

    conceptual principle of warrant for reactive attitudes, one that is certainly

    implicit, if never stated in so many words, in Strawsons Freedom and

    Resentment: a personal reactive attitude can be warranted only if the

    corresponding impersonal reactive attitude would be warranted also. Your

    resentment of me fits what I have done to you only if my stepping on

    your foot is also a fit object of blame. If I have a justification or valid

    excuse for stepping on your foot, then resentment is less warranted. Of

    course, it might still be understandable, or even reasonable under thecircumstances (given human capacities, knowledge, Humean inertia of the

    passions, and so on), but it would nonetheless be less fitting (Hume 1978:

    441).

    It follows that individual authority is constrained by representative

    authority. Someone can hold another accountable for something

    individually only if the act is the kind of thing that he was morally

    obligated not to do period, hence the kind of thing that he is accountable

    to the moral community (or representative third parties) not to do.13

    Warranted resentment is thus regulated by warranted blame, just as

    Mill said. But I hope it is now clear also why I said before that although on

    Mills account natural resentment can be moralized only when it is

    regulated from the outside, by third-personal sympathy or benevolence,

    on a Strawsonian view, reactive attitudes like resentment are appropriately

    regulated from materials that are already present within them. Both

    personal and impersonal reactive attitudes are second personal in thesense of being felt from a second-person perspective. Personal reactive

    attitudes like resentment, felt from a first or second partys vantage point,

    and impersonal reactive attitudes like moral blame, felt from a third

    13 This oversimplifies somewhat. There are cases where a right is infringed andcompensation owed though without wrongdoing. Nonetheless the following, morecomplex, conceptual connection holds. Someone has a right to something only if acting

    against would be wrong, lacking a justification, and then, blameworthy, lacking an excuse.

  • 8/2/2019 MillRevenge.pdf

    18/28

    332 Stephen Darwall

    partys perspective, are equally second personal. Since resentment can be

    warranted only if blame is, appropriately regulated or moralized

    resentment corresponds with warranted third-party blame, that is, with the

    equally second-personal demands that would be made from an impartial

    version of the second-person perspective, demands one would make as a

    representative person.

    Reactive attitudes, respect, and mutual accountability

    In this section, I wish to work toward the claim that whereas retaliatory

    emotions, and so Mills natural resentment, seek to harm or get back at

    their objects, Strawsonian reactive attitudes like resentment andindignation or moral blame, do not. To the contrary, reactive attitudes

    express a distinctively second-personal form ofrespect and seek reciprocal

    recognition of the dignity, not just of the person holding the attitude, but

    also of whomever is (ultimately, of whomever can be) the attitudes objects.

    Although I will be relying further on Strawson in this section, I want to

    begin by consolidating some points just made in the last section by

    considering some ideas of Adam Smiths. We have, actually, already been

    making use of a central Smithian idea when we have noted that not all

    reasons for an attitude are of the right kind in the sense of bearing on the

    issue of whether the attitude is fitting to its object. Smiths term for this

    concept of fittingness is propriety. The central normative question for

    Smith always concerns whether some attitude, motive, or action is proper,

    in the sense of being fitting to its object.

    Smith believed that we judge whether this is so by what he called

    sympathy (Smith 1982).14 We project ourselves into others shoes, facingthe circumstances they themselves face, to judge whether the attitude,

    motive, or action of theirs that we are judging is proper to its object

    (viewed as it would be from the perspective of the person into whose shoes

    we have placed ourselves). Smiths notion of the impartial spectator is the

    idea that we judge this by imaginatively projecting neitheras ourselves, nor

    14 I draw here from Darwall 1999 and 2004.

  • 8/2/2019 MillRevenge.pdf

    19/28

    Justice and Retaliation 333

    as the person we are judging, nor indeed, as any other specific individual,

    but just as someone who is in the shoes of whomevers attitude, action, or

    motive we are judging. If the attitude, motive, or action we come to by this

    imaginative exercise corresponds with the one we take the person actually

    to have, if wesympathize in this way with the person whose mental state we

    are assessing, then we judge his mental state proper in the sense of fitting

    to its purported object.

    Now back to justice. Injustice, for Smith, is essentially tied to fitting or

    proper resentment. It is not simply improper conduct but improper

    conduct to which the proper response is a second-personal reactive feeling

    to challenge or hold the agent accountable in some way (Smith 1982: 79).So on Smiths view, injustice can be judged only by projecting ourselves

    impartially into the agents and, crucially, intoaffected parties points of view

    and deliberating out whether to feel resentment from that perspective.

    This individual-patient-regarding character of justice leads Smith to

    oppose utilitarian tradeoffs and to hold that resistance to injustice is

    warranted not by considerations of overall utility but by concern for the

    very individual who would be injured. (Smith 1982: 90, 138)

    Moreover, what we consider from the standpoint of affected parties is

    whether to respond with a distinctive feeling that itself presupposes

    mutual accountability between persons, namely, with a Strawsonian

    reactive attitude. Sympathy with victims sense of injury involves,

    according to Smith, not simply sharing their sense of having been

    wronged. It also involves recognition of their authority to challenge the

    wrong by resisting it, or, failing that, to demand some form of

    compensation or punishment. It recognizes their second-personalauthority to address demands of justice.15 We can only judge whether

    something is properly resented or resisted, therefore, by imagining being

    in the shoes of the affected parties and considering whether any of us, if

    15 Consider in this connection what Smith says about those who feel guilt for havingunjustly injured others. Even when their victims are ignorant of the crime, the guilty maybe moved to confess their guilt and submit themselves to the resentment of their offended

    fellow-citizens, in the hopes of some form of reconciliation. (Smith 1982: 118-119.)

  • 8/2/2019 MillRevenge.pdf

    20/28

  • 8/2/2019 MillRevenge.pdf

    21/28

    Justice and Retaliation 335

    respect, they also implicitly accord it. To have a reactive attitude towards

    someone amounts to continuing to view him as a member of the moral

    community, only as one who has offended against its demands (Strawson

    1968: 95-96). Reactive attitudes thus do not simply hold the other

    accountable, they do so as one to whom the person holding them is

    accountable as well, both as a representative person and as an individual.

    So second-personal resentment seeks not just to make the other feel ones

    dignity, but to feel his as well. The two are a package deal.

    Torts and crimes: accountability, not retaliation

    In this last section, I would like to extend the second-personal, non-retaliatory analysis of reactive attitudes of the last two sections and

    compare it to some recent proposals regarding tort and criminal law,

    respectively, that give these attitudes a more retaliatory dimension.

    In a line of recent papers, Benjamin Zipursky and his collaborator

    John Goldberg have defended a theory of torts they call civil recourse

    theory.17 I can hardly lay out civil recourse theory adequately here, not to

    mention the debate about the foundations of tort law into which it enters.

    The aspect of the theory on which I wish to focus can be presented fairly

    quickly, however. Civil recourse theory stands against corrective justice

    theories that argue that compensating an injured victim is a matter of

    legally enforcing a duty of repair that the tortfeasor has to make her victim

    whole (e.g., Coleman 1992). On the latter theories, when someone has

    been wronged, an injustice has been done, and the person who committed

    the injustice incurs an obligation to compensate the person he has

    wronged. Tort law is a legal mechanism through which this duty can belegally enforced.

    Against this, civil recourse theory argues, I think, to some extent

    correctly, that simply focusing on the correction of an injustice fails

    adequately to appreciate the distinctive authority or standing that the

    wronged individual has. As I argued above, right holders have an

    17 I will focus mainly on Zipursky 2003.

  • 8/2/2019 MillRevenge.pdf

    22/28

    336 Stephen Darwall

    individual authority to hold those who have violated their rights

    accountable to them in a way that is not adequately captured by anything

    that the people and their representatives can do, even indeed on their

    behalf. Although criminal law and prosecution for the wrong or injustice

    done are indeed matters for the state and the people from whom it gains

    its legitimacy, issues of tort compensation are not. If, again, an injured

    party would prefer not to pursue a tort action, it is not up to the state or

    the people to pursue it for him. That would be paternalistic, a usurping of

    the autonomy rights of the injured party.

    However, I believe that civil recourse theory, at least as Zipursky and

    Goldberg have developed it, have mislocated the way in which tort lawshould be understood as recognizing the victims standing or authority. As

    civil recourse theory conceives it, tort law gives wronged individuals

    standing to use force and take vengeance against those who have wronged

    them in ways they would otherwise be forbidden to do as private

    individuals (Zipursky 2003: 733-735,749-751). Within a community of

    mutually accountable equals, as I conceive it, however, individuals never

    have the moral standing to retaliate or take vengeance. As private

    individuals we do give up a right ofpunishment, which we would otherwise

    have had as representative persons, to the state. And we give up also rights

    to seek compensation through extra-judicial means. But we never had the

    right to vengeance, or to retaliate except to the extent necessary for self-

    defense, so the state need provide citizens no legal forum to act against

    other private individuals in return for giving up these private rights.

    According to Zipursky, however, when claimaints are awarded punitive

    damages, tort law gives victims standing to vindicate their rights by beingvindictive and acting in revenge for the wrong done to them by the

    defendant (Zipursky 2003: 749-750). This is not quite retaliation, since

    victims who prove their case are not permitted to do to the defendant

    exactly what he did to them. But civil recourse theory as Zipursky advances

    it does nonetheless hold that part of the recourse that tort law gives

  • 8/2/2019 MillRevenge.pdf

    23/28

    Justice and Retaliation 337

    claimants is a kind of revenge.18 On the Strawsonian view I have been

    urging, however, accountability to the victim isalways implicitly mutual, so

    revenge and retaliation seem precisely the wrong categories for torts, even

    for punitive damages.

    Similar issues arise in expressive retributivist theories of punishment,

    at least as these have been advanced by Joel Feinberg and Jean Hampton.

    Since Hamptons views are somewhat more systematic, I shall begin with

    her. Hampton rightly points out that crimes having victims always involve

    an element of disrespect amounting to a kind of devaluing of the victim

    and that punishment is best conceived as a response to, and correction of,

    this devaluing. However, as I read her, Hampton conceives of thisresponse in terms that are more appropriate to a culture of honor than to

    one of accountability. Those who violate others rights presume a kind of

    authority over others. They act towards others as though others have lesser

    value and as though, therefore, they can legitimately act towards others in

    ways that others cannot legitimately act toward them. They arrogate a

    kind of lordship over others and seek to establish this by making others

    submit to the indignity involved in their crime (Hampton 1998: 124).

    According to Hampton, the retributive idea then is that the appropriate

    response to such attempted diminishment and defeat of the victim, is to

    turn tables and force the wrongdoers submission, thereby defeating him

    and reconfirming or vindicating the victims value. Accordingly,

    Hampton says that the most general and accurate definition of

    punishment is: the experience of defeat at the hands of the victim (either

    directly or indirectly through a legal authority) (Hampton 1998: 126).

    As I see it, there are two major problems with this analysis. First, asopposed to torts, criminal punishment is best conceived of as expressing

    impersonal rather than personal reactive attitudes, which hold the criminal

    accountable not to the victim or to any other individual, but to the moral

    community or representative persons as a whole. It is because criminal law

    18 However, Zipursky makes clear that his aim is descriptive rather than normative, to

    interpret tort law as it actually functions rather than to justify or defend it normatively.

  • 8/2/2019 MillRevenge.pdf

    24/28

    338 Stephen Darwall

    concernsrepresentative rather thanindividualauthority that it is a matter for

    the people and their representatives rather than for the victim.

    We should agree with Hampton that part of what the moral community

    expresses through punishment of victimization is commitment to the

    equal dignity of all persons and the victims right as a person not to be

    treated in the way she has been treated. But if there is any defeat or

    submission here, it should be viewed as a submission to the authority of

    the moral community as a whole, not to the victim.

    But neither, and this is the second point, is punishment properly

    viewed in terms of submission and defeat at all. If the criminal had actually

    lowered the victims value and thereby established his superiority over her,in the way that honor disrespect affects relative status in an honor culture,

    then it would be necessary to restore her status in some public way. And

    since the dishonoring lowering was at the criminals hands, it would be

    necessary for a reversal of that defeat and consequent change in relative

    status to come somehow at the victims hands. Of course, a public tribunal

    might find that the criminals presumptions of superior value are simply

    false and thereby simultaneously restore both victims and criminals status

    to the status quo ante. But that defies the logic of an honor culture in

    which vengeance must be exacted at the hands of the victim or of someone

    who represents her.

    Such a public dishonoring, however, whether at the victims or the

    communitys hands, would not amount to holding the victimizer

    answerable. If criminal justice is to express genuine reactive attitudes, like

    moral blame, it must implicitly address the criminal in a way that both

    demands and expresses a form of respect that, unlike honor respect, isintrinsically second personal. It must demand respect respectfully. So

    although it is certainly true that punishment, so conceived, will implicitly

    claim the criminals acknowledgment of the victims dignity, it will do so

    in a way that acknowledges the criminals dignity as well. Criminal and

    victim are persons alike, accountable to one another, both as individuals

    and as representative persons or fellow members of the moral

    community.

  • 8/2/2019 MillRevenge.pdf

    25/28

    Justice and Retaliation 339

    Feinbergs elaboration of an expressive theory is tied less to vindicating

    the victim and more to the expression of the communitys resentment and

    vengefulness (Feinberg 1970: 100). Punishment, Feinberg says, is a

    symbolic way of getting back at the criminal, expressing a kind of

    vindictive resentment (Feinberg 1970: 100). He then quotes with approval

    J. F. Stephens celebrated remark that The criminal law stands to the

    passion of revenge in much the same relation as marriage to the sexual

    appetite (Feinberg 1970: 100-101).

    There are no doubt different ways to take Stephens analogy, but, at

    best, we seem to be left with the Millian idea that justice and the criminal

    law are tied to an animal natural resentment that lacks intrinsic moralrelevance but that can nonetheless be moralised by an external principle

    like impartial benevolence. I have been arguing here, however, that there

    is a form of resentment that is not a retaliatory emotion. Strawsonian

    reactive attitudes, whether personal, like resentment, or impersonal, like

    indignation and moral blame, have an inherently second-personal

    structure that enables them to be critically revised from within. If an

    expressive theory were to hold that punishment expresses these attitudes,

    what punishment would then be held to express is what the criminal would

    have to accept to hold himself properly accountable to himself and others

    as fellow members of the moral community.

    Yale University

    [email protected]

    References

    Coleman, Jules L. (1992). Risks and Wrongs. Cambridge: Cambridge

    University Press.

    Crisp, Roger (1997).Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Mill on Utilitarianism.

    New York: Routledge.

    DArms, Justin and Daniel Jacobson (2000a). The Moralistic Fallacy: On

    the Appropriateness of Emotions, Philosophy and Phenomenological

    Research, 61: 65-90.

  • 8/2/2019 MillRevenge.pdf

    26/28

    340 Stephen Darwall

    DArms, Justin and Daniel Jacobson (2000b). Sentiment and Value,Ethics

    110: 722-748.

    Darwall, Stephen (1999). Sympathetic Liberalism, Philosophy & Public

    Affairs, 28: 139-164.

    Darwall, Stephen (2006). The Second-Person Standpoint: Morality, Respect,

    and Accountability. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Darwall, Stephen (2004). Equal Dignity in Adam Smith, Adam Smith

    Review 1: 129-134.

    Darwall, Stephen (2008). Two Kinds of Recognition Respect for Persons.

    Trans. into Italian as Due tipi di rispetto come riconoscimento per le

    persone. InEguale Rispetto, Ian Carter, ed. Bruno Mondadori, Milan.Darwall, Stephen (2010a). But It Would Be Wrong, Moral Obligation,

    Ellen Frankel Paul, ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Darwall, Stephen (2010b). Moral Obligation: Form and Substance,

    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society.

    Darwall, Stephen (2010c). Smiths Ambivalence About Honor,Adam Smith

    Review 5. Feinberg, Joel (1970). The Expressive Function of

    Punishment. InDoing & Deserving: Essays in the Theory of Responsibility.

    Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Pp. 95-118.

    Gofman, Erving (1959). The Presentation of Self in Everyday Life. New York:

    Anchor Books.

    Hampton, Jean (1998). The Retributive Idea, in Jeffrie G. Murphy and

    Jean Hampton. Forgiveness and Mercy. Cambridge: Cambridge

    University Press.

    Hieronymi, Pamela (2005). The Wrong Kind of Reason, The Journal of

    Philosophy, 102: 437-457.Hohfeld, Wesley Newcomb (1923). Fundamental Legal Conceptions, Walter

    Wheeler Cook, ed. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Hume, David (1978). A Treatise of Human Nature, ed L. A. Selby-Bigge,

    second edition, with revisions by P. H. Nidditch. Oxford: Oxford

    University Press, 1978.

    Mill, John Stuart (1998). Utilitarianism, ed. Roger Crisp. Oxford: Oxford

    University Press.

  • 8/2/2019 MillRevenge.pdf

    27/28

    Justice and Retaliation 341

    Nietzsche (2006). On the Genealogy of Morals and Other Writings: Revised

    Student Edition. Keith Ansell-Pearson, ed. Carol Diethe, trans.

    Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Olson, Jonas (2004). Buck-Passing and the Wrong Kind of Reasons, The

    Philosophical Quarterly, 54: 295-300.

    Rabinowicz, Wlodek and Toni Ronnw-Rasmussen (2004). The Strike of

    the Demon: On Fitting Pro-Attitudes and Value,Ethics, 114: 391-423.

    Scheler, Max (1961). Ressentiment. Lewis A. Coser, ed. William W.

    Holdheim. trans. New York: Free Press of Glencoe.

    Strawson, P.F. (1968). Freedom and Resentment, in Studies in the

    Philosophy of Thought and Action. London: Oxford University Press.Thompson, Michael (2004). What Is It To Wrong Someone?: A Puzzle

    About Justice, In Reason and Value: Themes from the Philosophy of Joseph

    Raz, eds., R. Jay Wallace, Philip Pettit, Samuel Scheffler, Michael

    Smith. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Watson, Gary (1987). Responsibility and the Limits of Evil: Variations on

    a Strawsonian Theme, inResponsibility, Character, and the Emotions: New

    Essays in Moral Psychology, ed. F. D. Schoeman. Cambridge: Cambridge

    University Press.

    Zipursky, Benjamin (2003). Civil Recourse, not Corrective Justice,

    Georgetown Law Journal 91: 695-756.

  • 8/2/2019 MillRevenge.pdf

    28/28

    Copyright of Philosophical Papers is the property of Routledge and its content may not be copied or emailed to

    multiple sites or posted to a listserv without the copyright holder's express written permission. However, users

    may print, download, or email articles for individual use.