+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Negation and the Law of Contradiction in Indian Thought.pdf

Negation and the Law of Contradiction in Indian Thought.pdf

Date post: 02-Jun-2018
Category:
Upload: onlineyyk
View: 217 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend

of 20

Transcript
  • 8/10/2019 Negation and the Law of Contradiction in Indian Thought.pdf

    1/20

    NEGATION AND THE

    LAW

    OF

    CONTRADICTION

    IN

    INDIAN

    THOUGHT:

    A

    COMPARATIVE

    STUDY

    By

    J. F.

    STAAL

    N

    the

    fourth

    chapter

    of

    book

    '

    of

    the

    Metaphysica

    Aristotle deals with

    the

    principle

    of

    contradiction. This law

    is

    formulated

    as follows:

    'it

    is

    impossible

    or

    anything

    at

    the same

    time to be

    and not to be '.' Let us

    imagine,

    says

    Aristotle,

    that

    somebody

    wished to

    oppose

    this

    view. Our

    opponent

    cannot

    hold

    a

    view which

    contradicts he law

    of

    contradiction

    without

    assuming

    the

    validity

    of

    this law

    itself: for

    otherwise he

    is not even

    denying

    what we

    are saying. The only alternative for him, then, will be to say nothing. But

    this is

    absurd:

    'for

    such a

    man,

    as

    such,

    is

    from

    the start

    no better

    than

    a

    vegetable

    '.2

    We

    are

    often told

    that Indian

    philosophers

    do

    not

    accept

    the law

    of con-

    tradiction. This

    may

    well be

    one

    of

    the

    causes of the

    neglect

    of

    Indian

    thought

    by

    Western

    philosophers:

    for

    nobody

    desires

    to

    study

    a

    body

    of

    propositions

    when

    he

    is

    at

    the same time told

    that

    their contradictories

    may

    hold

    as well.

    Is

    it

    perhaps

    a

    new-and

    according

    to

    some

    superior-kind

    of

    logic

    to

    which

    we

    are

    invited to

    accustom

    ourselves?

    Many may

    not feel the

    need

    for

    what

    would amount to a radicalconversion. Nevertheless such a requirement eems

    implied

    in

    statements like

    the

    following,

    where

    a

    Western

    scholar

    speaks

    about

    principles

    such

    as the

    law

    of

    contradiction:

    'But

    the

    Eastern

    mind

    is

    con-

    vinced

    that,

    taking

    together

    all the

    circumstances n which we need

    our

    thinking

    to

    give

    us

    adequate guidance,

    t

    would be fatal

    to allow ourselves

    o

    be

    enslaved

    by

    these

    principles

    .3

    After

    stating

    this the

    author

    goes

    on to

    quote

    a Buddhist

    principle

    which

    indeed

    contradicts the law

    of contradiction.6

    The

    question

    arises

    whether 'the

    Eastern

    mind' has

    in its

    entirety

    thrown

    the

    law of

    contradiction

    overboard.

    The aim of the presentstudy is to see how Indian thinkerstreat contradic-

    tions

    and what

    explicit

    rules are

    given

    for the treatment

    of contradictions. If

    1

    Met.,

    r

    4,

    1006

    a

    3-4.

    Other statements of this law have been

    formalized

    by

    I. M.

    Bocheniski,

    Ancient

    formal

    logic,

    Amsterdam,

    1951, 38-40;

    cf. also

    J.

    L.

    Ackrill, Mind,

    LxU,

    1953,

    110-12.

    2

    ibid.,

    14-15;

    cf.

    translation of

    W. D.

    Ross, Oxford,

    1908.

    3

    E. A.

    Burtt,

    'What can

    Western

    philosophy

    learn from India ?

    ',

    Philosophy

    East

    and

    West, v,

    1955-6,

    202.

    4

    The

    principle

    called

    catuscko.ti.

    ee

    P.

    T.

    Raju,

    'The

    principle

    of

    four-cornered

    negation

    in

    Indian

    philosophy',

    Review

    of

    Metaphysics,

    vII,

    1954, 694-713;

    T. R.

    V.

    Murti,

    The

    central

    philosophyof Buddhism,London, 1955, 129-31, 146-8. The earliest occurrenceperhaps in the

    Pali

    canon is

    Majjhima-nikdya,

    autta

    63

    (transl.

    H.

    C.

    Warren,

    Buddhism

    in

    translations,

    Cambridge,

    Mass.,

    1946,

    117-22).

    For a

    formalization

    see:

    H.

    Nakamura,

    'Buddhist

    logic

    expounded

    by

    means of

    symbolic logic',

    Journal

    of

    Indian

    and Buddhist

    Studies, vII, 1958,

    384-5. The same

    formalization

    n an

    earlier

    Japanese

    version

    (in Indogaku

    Bukky3galku

    kenkyfi,

    III,

    1954,

    223-31)

    was criticized

    by

    R. H.

    Robinson,

    '

    Some

    logical aspects

    of

    Niglrjuna's

    system

    ',

    Philosophy

    East

    and

    West,

    vi,

    1957,

    302.

    The

    validity

    of this criticism

    may

    be

    questioned.

  • 8/10/2019 Negation and the Law of Contradiction in Indian Thought.pdf

    2/20

    NEGATION

    AND THE LAW

    OF

    CONTRADICTION

    1N

    INDIAN

    THOUGHT

    53

    Indian

    philosophers

    are either unaware of contradiction

    or

    deny

    the

    validity

    of

    the

    principle

    of

    contradiction,

    he

    structure

    of Indian

    logic

    would

    seem to be

    so

    fundamentally

    different from

    the

    structure

    of Western

    logic,

    that the

    possi-

    bility

    of mutual

    understanding

    may

    become

    questionable.

    If, on the otherhand,

    the

    principle

    of contradiction

    s

    either

    applied

    mplicitly

    or laid down

    explicitly,

    this

    may

    be

    variously interpreted

    there

    may

    be historical

    connexions

    between

    India and the

    West which account for

    certain

    influences;

    there

    may

    be

    a

    connexionbetween the

    logical

    law and the

    structure

    of

    Indo-European,

    manifest

    in

    both

    Greek

    and

    Sanskrit;

    there

    may

    be

    a

    general linguistic background

    o

    the law of

    contradiction;

    or

    finally,

    the law

    may

    be a universal

    logical

    law-

    whatever that

    may

    mean. A

    discussion

    of the

    question,

    whether

    Indian

    philosophers

    are to be considered

    vegetables, may

    therefore

    constitute

    a

    chapter

    of comparativelogic.

    The

    Sanskrit

    term

    which seems to

    correspond

    most

    closely

    to the

    Western

    term

    contradiction

    s

    derived from a

    root sidh-

    meaning

    '

    to

    keep away

    '.

    The

    noun sedha derived from

    this root denotes

    'keeping away

    ',

    and the nouns

    nisedha

    and

    pratisedha

    have a

    similar

    meaning,

    which

    can be sometimesfurther

    specified

    as

    'prohibition,

    negation'.

    The

    latter term leads to

    the

    formation

    of

    the

    noun

    vipratisedha

    meaning

    '

    mutual

    prohibition

    or

    '

    contradiction .

    An

    early

    technical

    or

    semi-technical use of the

    term

    vipratisedha

    occurs in

    Apastamba's

    Srauta-sitra

    (between

    400

    and

    200

    B.c.),

    where

    during

    the

    offering

    the Vedas are assigned to the various sacrificers n the following manner1:

    'The

    hotr

    sacrifices with the

    1Rgveda;

    the

    ud~it.r

    with

    the

    Samaveda;

    the

    adhvaryu

    with

    the

    Yajurveda

    ;

    the

    brahman

    with

    all.

    When it is

    expressly

    said,

    or in

    case of contradiction

    (vipratisedha),

    another

    (priest)

    may

    sacrifice

    .

    Instead

    of

    vipratisedhdt

    he

    partly parallel

    text

    of

    Hirainyakesin's

    rauta-siitra

    has

    asa.mbhav9t

    'if it is

    impossible

    . Both

    passages

    refer to cases where a

    priest

    is

    unable

    to

    sacrifice

    in

    accordancewith what is

    prescribed

    or

    him on

    account of one

    rule

    or one

    established

    practice,

    because he

    is

    already

    engaged

    on

    account of

    another

    rule

    or other

    rules.2

    The last

    sAtra,

    herefore,

    ormulates

    a principle which holds in cases of mutual contradiction between two rules

    applicable

    to the same

    situation.

    It is a

    rule for

    the

    manipulation

    of other

    rules,

    a

    paribhas

    '

    meta-rule

    ',

    and it is

    accordingly

    placed

    in

    the

    last

    part

    of

    the

    Apastamba-irauta-sAtra,

    hich consists of

    the

    yaj3Fa-paribhasI-sietrdni

    '

    meta-rules

    regarding

    the

    sacrifice . The

    term

    vipratisedha

    s a

    term

    which

    applies

    to

    the contradictions between

    formulated

    rules,

    and not

    for

    instance

    between

    entities.

    It

    is

    characteristic

    or

    Indian

    thought

    that at an

    early

    stage

    of

    development

    the

    distinction between

    language

    and

    meta-language

    was

    made.

    This

    is con-

    nected with the fact that the subject-matter or variouskinds of investigations

    1

    AIasta

    mba-a-rausa-t~ra,

    24.1.16-20.

    s

    W.

    Caland

    n

    his

    translation

    ad

    loc.

    specifies

    this

    by

    the

    following example:

    'Z.

    B.

    muse ein

    anderer

    als

    der

    Adhvaryu,

    da

    dieser

    beschiftigt

    ist,

    das

    Opfertier

    osbinden'.

    VOL.

    xxv.

    PART

    1.

    5

  • 8/10/2019 Negation and the Law of Contradiction in Indian Thought.pdf

    3/20

    54

    J.

    F.

    STAAL

    was

    a

    large

    body

    of

    linguistic

    material,

    the

    Vedic

    texts

    which

    were

    considered

    transcendent

    and revealed

    (iruti).

    The sitra

    literature

    on the

    one

    hand

    embodies

    Vedic passagesand continues to prescribe ormsof activity in a Vedic fashion,

    and on

    the

    other

    hand

    interprets

    Vedic

    passages.

    This

    literature

    thereforedoes

    not

    only

    deal with ritual

    activity,

    but deals

    also

    with

    statements

    regarding

    ritual

    activity.

    In the

    first

    respect

    it

    constitutes

    a

    language

    dealing

    with

    the

    ritual as

    object

    material,

    in

    the second

    respect

    it

    constitutes

    a

    meta-language

    dealing

    with the

    language

    which deals

    with the

    ritual.

    The

    paribhds

    rules,

    more

    specifically,

    were

    explicit

    meta-linguistic

    rules for

    the

    manipulation

    of

    Vedic

    passages.

    With the

    development

    of

    grammar

    here

    is

    a

    shift in

    two

    respects.

    On

    the

    one

    hand the object material s new : it is neitherthe ritual,nor Vedicpassages

    dealing

    with the

    ritual,

    but

    it

    is

    the

    spoken

    language

    (bhd.s)

    and,

    to a limited

    extent,

    the

    Vedic

    language

    (chandas).1

    On

    the

    other

    hand it is not

    Vedic

    passages,

    but

    the

    rules

    of

    grammar

    hemselves

    which are the

    subject

    of a meta-

    linguistic investigation.

    The same

    term,

    paribhtad,

    applies

    to

    rules

    of this

    meta-

    language.

    The

    importance

    of

    these meta-rules ncreases when

    the rules of

    the

    grammar

    of

    Pan~ini

    re

    accepted

    as authoritative.

    In

    dealing

    with

    linguistic problems

    the

    grammatical description

    is

    mainly

    confinedto the

    analysis

    of words

    (pada)

    and

    grammar

    has

    thereforebeen called

    pada-mimd.msa

    'investigation into words'. While it is sometimes rightly

    stressed

    that the Sanskrit

    grammarians

    neglected

    or

    paid

    little

    attention

    to

    syntax,

    it is not

    always

    realized

    hat

    grammar

    was

    in

    this

    respect supplemented

    by

    the

    vakya-mimu.msd

    'investigation

    into

    sentences',

    another name

    for the

    most orthodox

    among

    the

    systems

    of

    philosophy,

    more

    generally

    known as

    Pfirva-mlmimss

    Karma-mimi~ims,

    or

    merely

    Mim~ins.2

    Some

    syntactical

    principles

    of

    Mimims

    will

    occupy

    us

    here.

    This

    philosophical

    system

    is the

    direct

    successor to the

    sitra

    literature,

    for

    it

    systematizes

    the

    interpretation

    of Vedic sentences and evolves

    general

    canons of

    interpretation.3

    Also

    here

    general

    rules

    of

    a

    meta-linguistic nature, dealing

    with

    the

    interpretation

    of

    Vedic

    statements,

    are

    given.

    Such meta-rules are often called

    nydya.

    These

    rules are

    further

    used

    and

    developed

    in

    dharmaidstra.

    The

    term

    nydya

    is later

    commonly

    used to denote

    logic

    and the

    system

    of

    logic.

    We have

    emphasized

    elsewhere

    that

    the

    early

    use of the term

    nydya

    as

    synonymous

    with

    paribhdsi

    may

    be

    an

    indication that elements

    and laws of Indian

    logic

    can

    be

    traced

    back

    to

    the

    discussion

    on

    problems

    of

    language

    and

    meta-language

    n

    earlier

    systems

    and

    especially

    in

    grammar.4

    1 See especially P. Thieme, Pdttini and the Veda,Allahabad, 1935, 67 sq.; L. Renou, La

    Durghatavrtti

    de

    Saranadeva,

    I,

    1

    (introduction),

    Paris, 1940,

    7-8.

    2

    cf.

    L.

    Renou,

    ttudes

    vediques

    et

    pan.indennes,

    vi

    (Le

    destin

    du

    V6da

    dans

    1'Inde),

    Paris,

    1960,

    66.

    3

    Mim.msd

    is

    closest to the

    paribh4ds

    sections

    of

    the

    si8tras.

    See

    D.

    V.

    Garge,

    Citations

    in

    Sabara-bhdsya,

    Poona, 1952,

    50

    sq.

    4

    J.

    F.

    Staal,

    'The

    theory

    of

    definition in Indian

    logic

    ',

    JAOS,

    LXXXI, , 1961,

    124.

  • 8/10/2019 Negation and the Law of Contradiction in Indian Thought.pdf

    4/20

    NEGATION

    AND THE

    LAW

    OF CONTRADICTION

    IN INDIAN THOUGHT

    55

    Problems of contradiction

    are

    dealt

    with

    in

    this

    meta-linguistic

    context

    in

    grammar

    as well

    as

    in

    Mimdi.sa.1

    P.nini

    (c.

    350

    B.C.)

    gives

    the

    following

    meta-rule: 'in case of contradiction

    (between

    two

    rules)

    the later

    (rule)

    is to be applied

    '.2

    Here 'later rule' denotes a rule which occurs later in the

    sequence

    of rules in

    Pinini's

    grammar.3

    Patanijali

    (?

    second

    century

    B.C.)

    discusses this

    s&tra

    n the

    Mahcbhdsya

    and

    pays

    special

    attention

    to the term

    vipratisedha.

    After

    giving

    the

    etymology

    he

    explains

    it

    by

    itaretara-pratisedha

    and

    anyo'nya-pratisedha

    mutual

    prohibition'.

    He

    proceeds

    to

    quote

    the

    following

    vdrttika dvau

    prasatgadv

    nydrthdv

    kasmin

    sa

    vipratisedhah

    if

    two

    rules

    with

    different

    meaning apply

    to one

    (word)

    this is

    vipratisedha

    .6

    He adds

    that this

    application

    should

    be

    possible

    '

    at the same time

    '

    (yugapad)

    and

    gives

    the

    following

    example. According

    to

    Panini, 7.3.102,

    long

    d

    is

    substituted

    for

    final a of a nominal stem before terminationsbeginningwith y or bh.6 This

    enables

    us to

    form

    v.rksya

    'to the

    tree

    ',

    v.rtykbhydm

    'to both trees

    ',

    and

    apparently

    *vrkfdbhyah

    to

    trees

    ',

    from the nominal

    stem

    vrksa- 'tree'.

    The

    following

    saUra,

    7.3.103,

    prescribes

    the substitution

    of

    e

    for this

    a before

    a

    plural

    termination

    beginning

    with

    bh

    or s. This accounts

    for the

    formation

    of

    v.rksesu

    among

    trees

    '. But

    as

    -bhyah

    is a

    plural

    termination,

    the

    second

    siura

    applies

    also

    to this

    case

    and

    enables

    us

    to

    form

    vrksebhya4

    to trees'.

    The

    two rules

    form

    in this

    respect

    a

    vipratisedha

    'contradiction'.

    Then,

    according

    to

    the

    paribh4id,

    as the

    second

    rule comes after

    the

    first,

    the

    second

    prevailsand vrksebhya4s explainedwhile

    *vrksd.bhyah

    is not. We are perhaps

    inclined

    to

    regard

    he second

    rule

    as

    an

    exception (apavdda)

    o the

    first,

    but

    this

    does also

    produce

    he

    same

    result

    : for there

    is

    a

    paribhs.d

    which states

    that the

    exception

    is

    stronger

    than

    the

    general

    rule.7

    The

    above

    discussion

    can be formalized

    along

    the

    following

    lines.

    Let the

    siUras,

    which

    are

    propositions,

    be

    ordered

    as

    they

    are in

    P.nini)

    and be

    denoted

    by

    ~,

    #2,

    .

    .

    .

    ,

    and

    let

    01


Recommended