+ All Categories
Home > Documents > npltncthrgy

npltncthrgy

Date post: 06-Nov-2015
Category:
Upload: mollyalex
View: 7 times
Download: 1 times
Share this document with a friend
Description:
npltncthrgy
Popular Tags:
30
Neoplatonic Theurgy and Dionysius the Areopagite * Gregory Shaw Abstract: Until recently, Neoplatonic theurgy has been defined by scholars as an attempt to manipulate the gods through ritual, and its influence in late antique Platonic circles has been interpreted as evidence for the decline of Greek rationality caused in large part by the teachings of the fourth-century Syrian Platonist, Iamblichus. Although scholarly research on theurgy and Iamblichus has now corrected these misunderstandings, they have left their mark on related areas of research: a notable example is the role of theurgy in the Christian liturgy of Dionysius the Areopagite. This essay argues that the distinction between Iamblichean and Dionsyian theurgyasserted by leading theologians and scholarsis based on a caricature of Iamblichean theurgy. When Iamblichean theurgy is properly understood, the Christian theurgy of Dionysius may be seen as an example of the same kind of theurgy that Iamblichus defined in the De mysteriis. This essay aims to refute the false distinction between "pagan" and Christian theurgy and to suggest that such distinctions reflect more the apologetic interests of scholars than an accurate reading of the evidence. ". . . enlightened with the knowledge of visions, being both consecrated and consecrators of mystical understanding, we shall become luminous and theurgic, perfected and able to bestow perfection." Dionysius (EH 372B) Introduction Why are Christian theologians reluctant to admit that Dionysius was a theurgist? Why do they resist seeing the liturgy as a theurgical rite? And why is it that the term theourgia and its cognates which appear forty- * I would like to thank Stonehill College for a President's Summer Grant to support the preparation of this essay.
Transcript
  • Neoplatonic Theurgy

    and Dionysius the Areopagite*

    Gregory Shaw

    Abstract: Until recently, Neoplatonic theurgy has been defined by

    scholars as an attempt to manipulate the gods through ritual, and its

    influence in late antique Platonic circles has been interpreted as

    evidence for the decline of Greek rationality caused in large part by the

    teachings of the fourth-century Syrian Platonist, Iamblichus. Although

    scholarly research on theurgy and Iamblichus has now corrected these

    misunderstandings, they have left their mark on related areas of

    research: a notable example is the role of theurgy in the Christian

    liturgy of Dionysius the Areopagite.

    This essay argues that the distinction between Iamblichean and

    Dionsyian theurgyasserted by leading theologians and scholarsis based on a caricature of Iamblichean theurgy. When Iamblichean

    theurgy is properly understood, the Christian theurgy of Dionysius may

    be seen as an example of the same kind of theurgy that Iamblichus

    defined in the De mysteriis. This essay aims to refute the false

    distinction between "pagan" and Christian theurgy and to suggest that

    such distinctions reflect more the apologetic interests of scholars than

    an accurate reading of the evidence.

    ". . . enlightened with the knowledge of visions, being both consecrated

    and consecrators of mystical understanding, we shall become luminous

    and theurgic, perfected and able to bestow perfection."

    Dionysius (EH 372B)

    Introduction

    Why are Christian theologians reluctant to admit that Dionysius was a

    theurgist? Why do they resist seeing the liturgy as a theurgical rite? And

    why is it that the term theourgia and its cognates which appear forty-

    * I would like to thank Stonehill College for a President's Summer Grant to

    support the preparation of this essay.

  • seven times in the Dionysian corpus never appear in the Luibheid and Rorem translation, but are explained away in the footnotes?

    1 To suggest

    that Dionysius was a theurgist places one in a volatile arena, for the

    status of the Areopagite and the value of this work continue to be

    matters of heated debate. Recently, Fr. Kenneth Wesche reaffirmed

    Luther's well-known censure that the Areopagite "platonizes more than

    he Christianizes"2 and declares that "we cannot share the view that his

    chief inspiration was the Christian faith. . . . [for] the center of

    Dionysius' 'theoria' is not the christological confession of the Church,

    but 'gnosis.'"3 Wesche maintains that Dionysius was so enthralled by

    Neoplatonic gnosis that it "undercut his understanding of the Christian

    faith,"4 diverted him from the saving work of Christ, and caused him to

    embrace a dualistic Christianity that promoted clericalism.5 Wesche

    concludes:

    . . . because his [Dionysius'] thought is centered on gnosis, rather than

    on the Incarnation, his thought leads on a subtly divergent path that

    radically shifts the focus and distorts the real meaning of Christ.6

    In the eyes of Orthodox Christians like Wesche, Dionysius' spirituality

    was not truly orthodox because of the influence of Neoplatonism,

    specifically that of the fifth-century Neoplatonist Proclus; only when the

    Dionysian writings have been corrected by the commentaries of

    1 Pseudo-Dionysius: The Complete Works, translation by Colm Luibheid;

    foreword, notes, and translation collaboration by Paul Rorem (New York:

    Paulist Press, 1987). It should be noted that, while the translation includes

    helpful footnotes by Rorem and an exhaustive index to biblical "allusions and

    quotations," it includes no index of important Neoplatonic terms. All

    translations and citations in this essay have been checked with the critical text

    of Dionysius, the Corpus Dionysiacum I (the Divine Names edited by B. M.

    Suchla) and II (other writings, including the letters, edited by H. Ritter and G.

    Heil; Berlin: De Gruyter, 1990, 1991). Citations will be given the column and

    number of the Migne text (as appear in the Luibheid and Rorem translation)

    and, when appropriate, the page and line numbers of the critical text in

    parentheses. 2 Kenneth Paul Wesche, "Christological Doctrine and Liturgical Interpretation

    in Pseudo-Dionysius," St. Vladimir's Theological Quarterly 33 (1989): 44. 3 Ibid., 54.

    4 Ibid., 68.

    5 Ibid., 59.

    6 Ibid., 73, my emphasis.

  • Maximus the Confessor and John of Scythopolis do they reflect genuine

    principles of Christian faith. In response to Wesche, Dionysius has been

    defended by Hieromonk Alexander Golitzin along with counter charges

    that his accusers are ignorant of "Greek Christianity" and that our

    understanding of Dionysius generally has been hampered by a Protestant

    bias.7 Golitzin, in his passionate and learned defense of the Areopagite,

    forthrightly admits that scholarship on Dionysius including his own reflects the "confessional presuppositions" and even the temperament of

    individual scholars.8 With a figure as theologically seminal as the

    Areopagite long believed to be Paul's convert (Acts 17.34) this is not surprising. Scholarship on Dionysius often seems to have the unspoken

    agenda of trying to determine whether or not his teachings are in accord

    with one's preferred theology.9 One theme, however, seems to persist

    throughout the polemics: the more Neoplatonic Dionysius appears, the

    less acceptable. This, clearly, is the position of Wesche.10

    The critique

    of Neoplatonism as a merely cerebral spirituality incapable of

    penetrating the mystery of the Incarnation has long been a topos among

    Christian apologists. In a Christian apologetic context, too much

    Neoplatonism is believed to alienate one from the central mystery of

    Christ, and this has had significant consequences on Dionysian

    scholarship. Those who want to preserve the Christian authority of the

    Areopagite must argue, with Vladimir Lossky, that Dionysius'

    dependence on the writings of the Neoplatonists "is limited to outward

    resemblances which do not go to the root of their teaching, and relate

    7 Alexander Golitzin, "On the Other Hand," St. Vladimir's Theological

    Quarterly 34 (1990): 321-22. The Protestant bias has also come to influence

    Orthodox and Roman Catholic scholars (see below, n. 10). 8 Alexander Golitzin, "The Mysticism of Dionysius Areopagita: Platonist or

    Christian," Mystics Quarterly 3 (1993): 98. 9 Golitzin, "On the Other Hand," 306, n. 7.

    10 See n. 3. In a further response to Wesche, Golitzin maintains a far more

    nuanced position, arguing that the well-known distinction between a

    "biblical" and a "platonizing" Christianity is questionable. This distinction,

    Golitzin says, "echoes altogether too clearly the reaction of Roman Catholic

    and Orthodox scholars earlier this century to the late nineteenth and early

    twentieth century thesis of a 'Hellenized' and therefore corrupted Christianity associated in particular with Adolf von Harnack." See Golitzin,

    "Hierarchy Versus Anarchy? Dionyius Areopagita, Symeon the New

    Theologian, Nicetas Stethatos, and Their Common Roots in Ascetical

    Tradition," St. Vladimir's Theological Quarterly 38 (1994): 152-53 n. 95.

  • only to a vocabulary which was common to the age."11

    Andrew Louth,

    more recently, follows Lossky, noting that all educated men of the fifth

    and sixth centuries Christian or pagan "shared a culture," which accounts for Dionysius sharing many terms with Neoplatonists. Yet, like

    Lossky, Louth argues that the Areopagite's spirituality was distinctively

    Christian, not Neoplatonic.12

    If being too Neoplatonic diminishes Dionysius, then his practice of

    theurgy presents a far more serious problem. Since the time of

    Augustine, theurgy has been condemned by Christians as a diabolical

    attempt to converse with demons and manipulate the gods.13

    Today

    theurgy is not only considered anathema to the Church but to most who

    value rational thought. In an article that continues to shape scholarly

    thinking, E. R. Dodds maintained that theurgy was promoted by the

    fourth-century Neoplatonist Iamblichus, a "superficial" thinker whose

    divine work (theion ergon) was simply an Oriental superstition that

    appealed to human weakness. According to Dodds: "As vulgar magic is

    commonly the last resort of the personally desperate, of those whom

    man and god have alike failed, so theurgy became the refuge of a

    despairing intelligentsia which already felt 'la fascination de l'abme.'"14

    For Dodds and an entire generation of scholars, theurgy exemplified the

    "failure of nerve" and decline of the rationality that we admire in the

    classical Greeks and in ourselves.

    Among Christians specifically, the question of a Dionysian (and

    therefore Christian) theurgy touches a nerve that still separates

    Protestant from Orthodox and Roman Catholic scholars. Orthodox

    scholars like Golitzin, who accept the Areopagite as representative of

    their tradition, see a Protestant bias in the scholarship of those, like Paul

    Rorem, who say the elements of the Eucharist for Dionysius were

    merely symbols of something to be apprehended intellectually.15

    Protestant scholars like Rorem, on the other hand, are reluctant to admit

    11

    Lossky, The Mystical Theology of the Eastern Church (Crestwood, NY: St.

    Vladimir's Seminary Press, 1976), 32. 12

    Louth, Denys the Areopagite (Wilton: Morehouse-Barlow, 1989), 23-24. 13

    Augustine, City of God, Book 10. 14

    E. R. Dodds, The Greeks and the Irrational (Berkeley: University of

    California Press, 1973), 288. 15

    Golitzin, "Mysticism" 106. Louth's statement that the historical divine acts

    are "recalled" in the Eucharist is subject to the same critique.

  • that Dionysius attributed to the sacraments any kind of "magical"

    efficacy, for that would taint him with the superstition of imbuing

    material objects with divine or "theurgical" power.16

    In sum, the charge

    of guilt by association with Neoplatonism, in either its philosophical or

    its theurgical aspects, continues to shape our scholarship on Dionysius.

    If Dionysius practiced theurgy, it would present a serious challenge to

    his "orthodoxy," for to have been a theurgist in the Neoplatonic sense

    would condemn the Areopagite in the eyes of all scholar-apologists. It is

    not surprising, therefore, that his theurgy has been described by two

    leading Dionysian scholars, Andrew Louth and Paul Rorem, as

    fundamentally different from Neoplatonic, i.e. "pagan," theurgy.17

    Before we can evaluate this assessment, however, we must know more

    about Neoplatonic theurgy and how it was practiced. In this essay I hope

    to show that Rorem and Louth's distinction is based on a

    misunderstanding of Iamblichean theurgy. Further, I hope to

    demonstrate that Dionysius' understanding and practice of theurgy,

    while distinctively Christian, was derived from the principles of

    Iamblichus' theurgy as well as from his teachings on the soul. Finally,

    although I agree that Dionysian (Christian) theurgy should be

    distinguished from Iamblichean theurgy, I will argue that the distinction

    ought to be based on grounds other than those proposed by Rorem and

    Louth.

    I. Iamblichean Theurgy

    As noted, Dodds' characterization of theurgy as a corrupt and

    superstitious form of Platonism still carries a great deal of influence

    among scholars. Iamblichus' defense of theurgy in the De mysteriis was

    dismissed by Dodds as "a manifesto of irrationalism, an assertion that

    the road to salvation is found not in reason but in ritual."18

    For a

    Victorian rationalist like Dodds, Iamblichean theurgy was nothing more

    than a superstitious attempt to contact spirits and manipulate gods,

    16

    Paul Rorem, "The Uplifting Spirituality of Pseudo-Dionysius," in Christian

    Spirituality, ed. Bernard McGinn and John Meyendorff (New York:

    Crossroad, 1986), 134. 17

    Andrew Louth, "Pagan Theurgy and Christian Sacramentalism," JTS n.s. 37

    (1986): 432-38; Paul Rorem, Biblical and Liturgical Symbols Within the

    Pseudo-Dionysian Synthesis (Toronto: The Pontifical Institute, 1984), 104-11. 18

    Dodds, Greeks and the Irrational, 287.

  • practices not unlike those seen by Dodds in the spiritualist salons of

    early twentieth-century Europe.19

    It is understandable, therefore, that

    those who accept Dodds' assessment would want to separate Dionysius'

    theurgy from the misguided and possibly nefarious practices of

    Iamblichus. Curiously, however, Dodds' definition of theurgy cannot be

    found in the writings of Iamblichus. Perhaps the brilliance of Dodds as a

    classicist and historian of ideas led many scholars to accept his

    assessment of theurgy without reading the De mysteriis or, if they read

    it, to replace the philosophical context in which it was written with the

    twentieth-century issues that concerned Dodds.20

    Research into

    Iamblichus and theurgy in the last thirty years has yielded much greater

    insight into later Neoplatonism and has now determined that Dodds'

    evaluation of theurgy was wrong.21

    Iamblichus clearly states throughout

    19

    Ibid., 288, 296-97; cf. E. R. Dodds, Missing Persons (Oxford: The

    Clarendon Press, 1977), 55. 20

    Those who have adopted Dodds' characterization of theurgy as an attempt to

    manipulate, influence, or coerce the gods are as impressive as they are

    diverse. They include the Jungian/archetypal psychologist James Hillman,

    Healing Fiction (Dallas: Spring Publications, 1983), 78-79; scholar of Jewish

    mysticism Moshe Idel, Kabbalah: New Perspectives (New Haven: Yale

    University Press, 1988), 157 ff. Idel's work in particular has stimulated an

    entire generation of scholarship on kabbalistic "theurgical" practices despite

    the fact that Idel uses Dodds' twentieth-century definition of theurgy, not

    Iamblichus'!; Bernard McGinn, The Presence of God: A History of Western

    Mysticism, vol. 1 (New York: Crossroad,1994), 57, 172. 21

    Jean Trouillard, "La thurgie," in L'un et l'me selon Proclos (Paris: Les

    Belles Lettres, 1972), 171-89; Iamblichi in Platonis Dialogos

    Commentariorum Fragmenta, tr., edited, with commentary by John Dillon

    (Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1973); B. D. Larsen, Jamblique de Chalcis: Exgte et

    philosophe (Aarhus: Universitetsforlaget, 1972); A. C. Lloyd, "The Later

    Neoplatonists," in The Cambridge History of Later Greek and Early Medieval

    Philosophy, ed. A. H. Armstrong (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

    1967), 269-325; Carlos Steel, The Changing Self: A Study on the Soul in Later

    Neoplatonism: Iamblichus, Damascius and Priscianus, tr. S. Haasl (Brussels:

    Paleis der Academien, 1978); Andrew Smith, Porphyry's Place in the

    Neoplatonic Tradition (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1974), 81-99; Anne

    Sheppard, "Proclus' Attitude to Theurgy," CQ 32 (1982): 212-24; A.

    Sheppard, "Theurgy," Oxford Classical Dictionary (1995); Gregory Shaw,

    "Rituals of Unification in the Neoplatonism of Iamblichus," Traditio 41

    (1985): 1-28; idem, Theurgy and the Soul: The Neoplatonism of Iamblichus

    (University Park: Penn State Press, 1995); Garth Fowden, The Egyptian

  • the De mysteriis that theurgy was not an attempt to influence the gods,

    not only because it would have been impious but impossible. Iamblichus

    is unambiguous on this issue precisely because the De mysteriis was

    written to address it. In response to the charge from his former teacher

    Porphyry that theurgic invocations attempt to coerce the gods,

    Iamblichus replies:

    This sort of invocation does not draw the impassible and pure [Gods]

    down towards what is subject to passions and impure; on the contrary

    it makes us, who through generation are born subject to passions, pure

    and unchangeable.22

    Despite its apparent meaning, an invocation does not call the gods to us,

    it calls us to the gods. An invocation, Iamblichus says,

    does not, as the name (prosklesis; 42.6) seems to indicate, incline the

    intellect of the Gods to men, but according to the truth . . . the

    invocation makes the intelligence of men fit to participate in the Gods,

    elevates it to the Gods, and harmonizes it with them through orderly

    persuasion. (DM 42.9-15)

    If Dodds was wrong, and his spiritualist context has been inappro-

    priately applied to theurgy, then what was the hieratic Neoplatonism of

    Iamblichus, and what issues did it address?

    The scion of a family of Syrian priest-kings, Iamblichus had been a

    student of the Pythagorean Anatolius and later studied with Porphyry in

    Rome where he was initiated into Plotinian Platonism.23

    Iamblichus,

    however, felt that Porphyry and his teacher Plotinus had diverged from

    traditional Platonic and Pythagorean teachings by inflating the powers

    of the human soul and suggesting that a "higher" part of the soul never

    Hermes: A Historical Approach to the Late Pagan Mind (London: Cambridge

    University Press, 1986), 131-41; Polymnia Athanassiadi, "Dreams, Theurgy

    and Freelance Divination: The Testimony of Iamblichus," JRS 83 (1993):

    115-30. 22

    The standard edition is Jamblique: Les mystres d'Egypte, trans. and ed. E.

    des Places (Paris: Les Belles Lettres, 1966). References to the De mysteriis

    will use the Parthey pagination of des Places' text and will be noted as DM.

    DM 42.2-5 (modified from Fowden's translation, Egyptian Hermes, 133). 23

    For a biographical outline, see John Dillon, "Iamblichus of Chalicis," ANRW

    II.16.2 (1987): 863-78.

  • descends into this world or the body. The Plotinian soul, therefore,

    could withdraw in contemplation to reach its higher, undescended

    essence without the outside support of religious ritual. The conse-

    quences of such a belief are significant both cosmologically and

    socially,24

    and, in response, Iamblichus developed a psychological

    theory and a soteriological praxis in sharp contrast to the positions taken

    by his predecessors. Iamblichus argued that even the highest part of the

    soul descends into a body and is therefore far more subject to corporeal

    experience than Plotinus and Porphyry had allowed.25

    For Iamblichus,

    the human soul, as defined in Plato's Timaeus, unknowingly projects its

    divine logoi outside itself during embodiment and is thereby sewn into

    the fabric of the material world. Although divine and immortal, the

    embodied soul experiences a fundamental change unique among

    immortal entities: human souls must become mortal and subject to

    death. According to Iamblichus,

    the soul is a mean, not only between the divided and undivided, the

    remaining and proceeding, the noetic and irrational, but also between

    the ungenerated and generated. . . . Wherefore, that which is immortal

    in the soul is filled completely with mortality and no longer remains

    only immortal. The ungenerated part of the soul somehow becomes

    generated just as the undivided part of the soul becomes divided.26

    24

    Cosmologically, it negates the role of the cosmos in the soul's paideia;

    socially, it condemns the common man to this "lower" cosmos, leaving

    salvation in the hands of the philosophical elite. It should be noted, however,

    that despite Plotinus' condemnation of matter as "evil itself" (Ennead I.8.3.39-

    40) or his description of the soul as essentially undescended (I.1.12.25-29;

    IV.3.12.5-6), he was not as anticosmic as Iamblichus' polemical writings on

    the soul might suggest. In fact, Iamblichus' theurgy might best be understood

    as an attempt to secure the vision of Plotinus by grounding it in the

    experiences of the embodied soul. See G. Shaw, "Eros and Arithmos:

    Pythagorean Theurgy in Iamblichus and Plotinus," Ancient Philosophy 19

    (1999): 124-25. 25

    This crucial difference between Iamblichean and Plotinian Platonism was

    pointed out by A. C. Lloyd, "The Later Neoplatonists," in Armstrong,

    Cambridge History. See also Shaw, Theurgy and the Soul, 1-15, 61-69. For

    the soteriological consequences of accepting the soul as embodied see Shaw,

    "Theurgy as Demiurgy: Iamblichus' Solution to the Problem of Embodiment,"

    Dionysius 12 (1988): 37-59. 26

    Simplicius (Priscianus?) In libros Aristotelis de anima commentaria [DA]

    89.35-37; 90.21-24 in CAG 9 ed. M. Hayduck (Berlin: G. Reimeri, 1882).

  • The embodied soul, Iamblichus says, "becomes a stranger to itself"27

    and once exiled from its own immortality, the soul must receive

    assistance from the gods to recover its lost divinity.28

    Iamblichus' complex and paradoxical psychology reflected the mystery

    and paradox of One itself as it unfolds into its "other": the multiplicity

    of Beings. While this self-inversion causes no rupture among Higher

    Beings, whose essences are immediately reflected and returned by their

    images, human souls become immersed in a medium that does not allow

    for their immediate reflection and return.29

    Their divinity may be

    recovered only through the medium of mortal bodies and as integral

    parts of the natural world. Therefore, in theurgy the divine and

    mathematical proportions (logoi) of the soul are recovered only when

    the soul ritually appropriates their correspondences (analogoi) in

    Nature. For Iamblichus the cosmos was a living temple, a vast

    theophany, where the soul progressively recovered its divinity in the

    process of unifying itself with the divine powers revealed in the material

    world. An essential element in every theurgic ritual, therefore, was the

    correspondence between the objects used in the rite and their analogues

    in the soul: the outer objects, imbued with divine power, awakened

    correspondences within the soul, provided that the soul was able to

    receive them and had the capacity to contain their power. In effect, the

    disorienting flood of sensation described in the Timaeus (44) was

    appropriated and redirected in rituals that effected the soul's return. The

    material cosmos and sensate experiences were thereby transformed from

    disorienting obstacles into theurgic icons capable of uniting the soul

    with the gods.

    The soul's journey to the One, therefore, incorporated the daimonic

    urges and images which bound the soul to the body, yet, Iamblichus

    27

    DA 223.31: heterousthai pros heauten. 28

    The paradox of embodiment for the Iamblichean soul has been brilliantly

    examined by Carlos Steel, Changing Self. 29

    That all "real beings" descended by producing images of themselves in other

    things was a principle articulated by Plotinus (Enn. III 6.17.12). For a

    discussion of this see Pierre Hadot, Porphyre et Victorinus II (Paris: tudes

    Augustiniennes, 1968), 330-43; for its expression in Iamblichus see

    Simplicius, In cat. 374.6-376.19; Steel, Changing Self, 62; John Finamore,

    Iamblichus and the Theory of the Vehicle of the Soul (Chico: Scholars Press,

    1985), 11-27.

  • argued, since the rulers of these daimons were gods, the proper ritual

    use of their material images allowed the soul to enter directly into their

    power. Iamblichus maintained that the release of this power was a

    divine activity, not human; in a word, it was theurgy, the activity of the

    gods. As souls were progressively freed from their embodied confusion

    they employed ritual objects that were less densely material until, very

    rarely, a soul performed entirely immaterial forms of ritual worship (DM

    226.9-13; 230.15-19). Again, the inner/outer correspondence determined

    the efficacy of the theurgic rite. As Iamblichus put it: "Each attends to

    his sacrifice according to what he is, not according to what he is not;

    therefore the sacrifice should not surpass the proper measure of the one

    who performs the worship" (DM 220.6-9). The kind of theurgic rite one

    performed had to be coordinated with one's spiritual capacity. Intensely

    alienated souls required a denser and more material rite, while more

    unified souls performed a less material form of worship.

    The most distinguishing characteristic of Iamblichus' Platonism was his

    doctrine of the incarnate soul and its correlate, that the soul was unable

    to effect or to comprehend its own deification; this was accomplished

    only by the gods in theurgic rites. Iamblichus explains:

    Intellectual understanding does not connect theurgists with divine

    beings, for what would prevent those who philosophize theoretically

    from having theurgic union with the Gods? But this is not true, rather it

    is the perfect accomplishment of ineffable acts, religiously performed

    and beyond all understanding, and it is the power of ineffable symbols

    comprehended by the Gods alone, that establishes theurgical union. . . .

    In fact, these very symbols, by themselves, perform their own work,

    without our thinking. . . . (DM 96.17-97.6)

    Although Iamblichus sometimes describes theurgical union as noesis or

    gnosis, he was careful to distinguish theurgical gnosis and noesis from

    its human correlates. Theurgy was always the work of the gods, not of

    man.30

    30

    For example, Iamblichus refers to the soul's "innate knowledge" (emphutos

    gnosis) of the gods (DM 7.14) and then says that "in truth, our contact with

    the gods is not knowledge because knowledge is always separated from its

    object," and theurgical union transcends the duality of knowing (DM 8.3-5).

  • II. Dionysian and Iamblichean Theurgy

    In his groundbreaking study of the Dionysian liturgy, Paul Rorem

    presents persuasive evidence that Iamblichus' theory of theurgy

    influenced the Areopagite. There is no patristic precedent, Rorem

    argues, for Dionysius dividing worshipers into three classes: 1) those

    who worship with the aid of obscure (material) images; 2) those who

    need no material aids at all; and 3) "our hierarchy," which stands as a

    "mean between extremes" and thus uses both material and immaterial

    forms of worship.31

    Rorem says that Dionysius borrowed this threefold

    division from Iamblichus, who had distinguished three classes of souls

    and three forms of worship in the De mysteriis.32

    Iamblichus' divisions

    reflect his understanding of the different levels of theurgic capacity in

    human souls. Accordingly his divisions are: 1) the great "herd" who

    follow fate and employ a material form of worship; 2) the rare souls

    who have risen to the level of the divine Nous and who practice an

    immaterial form of worship; and 3) those souls between the extremes

    who practice both material and immaterial forms of worship (DM 224.6-

    225.10). Rorem also credits Iamblichus for influencing Dionysius'

    unique interpretation of the liturgy. Rather than typologically correlating

    the actions of the liturgy to events in Jesus' life and death as was standard patristic practice Dionysius relates liturgical actions to timeless and intelligible realities. This, Rorem notes, is precisely how

    Iamblichus interpreted Egyptian theurgic rites, encouraging his readers as Dionysius did later to elevate themselves to the "intelligible truth" and to abandon the merely visible or aural impressions.

    33

    Rorem explains that, although Dionysius adopted Iamblichus' triadic

    division of worship, he made significant changes. The Areopagite

    distinguished the material order from the intermediate according to the

    mythic chronology of the Church where chronological priority is

    equated with spiritual immaturity. Prior to Christ we lived under the Old

    Law, and the divine was veiled under obscure images which

    nevertheless foreshadowed the divine work, or theurgy, of Christ (EH

    432B). To worship through the "sacred pictures of the scriptures" (EH

    31

    Rorem, Symbols, 106-7; cf. Ecclesiastical Hierarchy [EH] 501C, see

    Luibheid and Rorem, Pseudo-Dionysis, 234 n. 146; Celestial Hierarchy [CH]

    121D-124D, Luibheid and Rorem, Pseudo-Dionysis, 146-47. 32

    Rorem, Symbols, 108-9. 33

    Ibid.

  • 432B), Dionysius says, is appropriate for those bound by greater

    materiality and multiplicity. After the advent of Christ, the less material

    choreography of the Christian liturgy represents a kind of worship

    which Dionysius says "is both celestial and of the Law for it occupies a

    place half way between the two opposites [of spiritual and material

    worship]" (EH 501D). Celestial worship corresponding to the purely immaterial theurgy of Iamblichus was practiced by angels, Dionysius says, not by mortals.

    34 For the Christian community at the intermediate

    level, which Dionysius refers to as "our hierarchy," the theurgies of

    Christ are revealed in the liturgy of the Church.

    While I agree with Rorem's analysis, I believe it can be pressed further.

    I would suggest that the differences between Iamblichus and Dionysius

    on the orders of worship reflect the differences in their respective world-

    views. Iamblichus situated himself within the Pythagorean/Platonic

    myth where, as described in the Timaeus, the cosmos is rooted in a

    divine beneficence that continually reveals itself in mathematical

    proportions. These divine ratios unfold into the heavenly cycles, the

    seasonal rhythms, and are eventually crystalized into the four geometric

    elements that sustain all material bodies.35

    Dionysius, by contrast, was

    situated within the biblical myth and chronology celebrated by the

    Church.36

    This included a divinely given world rejected by souls who

    fall prey to the devil, followed by the descent of a redeemer who enters

    the world to offer salvation from demons through the rites of the

    Church. The Iamblichean soul was also "fallen," but this was caused by

    the disorienting experience of embodiment that was necessary to the

    soul's mediating function. Significantly, while the status of the material

    34

    Dionysius' divergence from Iamblichus as regards "celestial worship"

    (immaterial theurgy) may be nuanced by the fact that Iamblichus says souls

    who perform the noetic/immaterial theurgy "the rarest of all things" are, themselves, "most rare" (DM 219.14-15; 228.2-3), and this immaterial

    worship comes only at the culmination of one's life (228.5-11). Further,

    Iamblichus explains that these rare and most blessed theurgists are elevated to

    the rank of angels (69.12-14). Significantly, Dionysius designates the bishop

    (hierarch) an "angel" because of his likeness to angels and his ability to

    transmit divine power (CH 293A). Thus, immaterial theurgy for both

    Iamblichus and Dionysius is performed by angels or angelic souls. 35

    Timaeus 53c-55c. 36

    Dionysius refers to this sacred history as a record of "theurgies," i.e., the

    actions of the divine "for us" (EH 440BC).

  • cosmos for Christians was ambiguous or demonic, for Iamblichus the

    cosmos was esteemed as a living theophany, a "liturgy" choreographed

    by the Demiurge and built into the substance and patterns of nature.37

    Material theurgy for Iamblichus, therefore, included the use of natural

    objects such as stones, plants, herbs, seeds, animals, and other tokens

    (sunthemata) capable of awakening the soul to its participation in the

    divine.38

    The background for Iamblichean theurgy was the creative

    activity of the gods in nature; for Dionysius it was the activity of Christ

    as recorded by the Church. The consequences of this difference will be

    discussed later.

    Iamblichus' psychology of the divided soul may well have influenced

    Dionysius' understanding of material symbols. According to Iamblichus,

    while heavenly beings possess immediate access to the divine demonstrated by their circular (noetic) movement embodied souls move rectilinearly and must proceed "outside" themselves to reach the

    unity of Nous.39

    Dionysius similarly contrasts the circular movement of

    divine intelligences, who have immediate access to the divine, with the

    rectilinear movement of human souls who must proceed outside

    themselves to be "uplifted by external things."40

    Both Iamblichus and

    Dionysius maintain that the dividedness of human souls requires

    multiple and material forms of worship corresponding to the soul's divisions "until we are brought as far as we can into the unity of deification."

    41 The hieratic use of sensate imagery, essential to

    Neoplatonic theurgy, was thus also essential to Dionysian theurgy, but

    Dionysius draws his symbols from the scriptures and the liturgy, not

    from nature. Iamblichean theurgy is thus narrowed by Dionysius into an

    ecclesiastical context, but in both cases material symbols reveal the

    immaterial presence of the divine. Iamblichus declares that "the gods

    produce signs through nature which serve them in the work of

    generation. . . ."42

    Through the work of attendant daimones, the gods

    37

    Dionysius also participated in the Platonic-Pythagorean myth but, unlike

    Iamblichus, he viewed it through the fall/apocalypse/redeemer mythology of

    the Church. 38

    DM 233.7-16. 39

    In Tim., frag. 49, Dillon, Iamblichi Chalcidensis; on the importance of

    noetic circularity for Iamblichus see Shaw, Theurgy and the Soul, 89-91. 40

    Divine Names [DN] 705B; (Suchla: 154.4). 41

    EH 373B; (Heil/Ritter: 65.12-13), tr. by Luibheid and Rorem, modified. 42

    DM 135.14.

  • manifest their intentions and communicate their ineffable presence

    symbolically through "particular bodies, animals, and everything in the

    world. . . ."43

    For Dionysius, however, this presence is revealed

    specifically through the material symbols of the liturgy. He says:

    It is not possible for the human intellect to be lifted up to the

    immaterial mimesis and contemplation of the heavenly hierarchies

    unless it makes use of the material guide proper to it. The visible

    beauties [of the liturgy] are signs of the invisible beauty, the beautiful

    odors of incense represent the diffusion of the intelligible, and the

    material lights are icons of the immaterial gift of light. . . . Order and

    rank [of the clergy] here below are a sign of the harmonious ordering

    [of the soul] toward divine things, and the reception of the most divine

    Eucharist [an icon] of participation in Jesus. And as many things as are

    given to heavenly beings transcendentally (huperkosmio\s), are given

    to us symbolically.44

    Another Iamblichean influence may be detected in Dionysius'

    imperative to complete one's material worship through biblical imagery

    prior to participation in the liturgy. Dionysius cautions catechumens not

    to proceed to the intermediate rites of "our hierarchy" before completing

    their "incubation in the paternal scriptures." Should they fail to complete

    their material worship, catechumens would emerge from baptism into

    "our hierarchy" like "still-born fetuses" and receive no benefit from the

    liturgy.45

    In the De mysteriis Iamblichus similarly insists that immaterial

    theurgies should not be engaged before one has completed all rites to the

    material gods. He explains:

    According to the art of the priests, it is necessary to begin sacred rites

    from the material Gods. For the ascent to the immaterial Gods will not

    otherwise take place. (DM 217.8-11)

    Failure to perform the material rites puts the soul at odds both with

    material daimones and with the bodily instincts and passions that

    43

    DM 136.2-3. Iamblichus explains that the function of daimones is to give

    concrete expression to the "good will" of the gods, including the binding of

    souls to particular bodies (DM 67.15-68.1); cf. Shaw, Theurgy and the Soul,

    130-33. 44

    CH 121D-124A, translation modified from Lubheid and Rorem and from

    Golitzin, "Hierarchy Versus Anarchy?" 149-50; (Heil/Ritter: 8.19-9.7). 45

    EH 432D-433A.

  • correspond to them. Theurgists ascended to the noetic gods only by

    assimilating themselves first to "everything in the world." As

    Iamblichus put it, "the ascent to the One is not possible unless the soul

    coordinates itself to the All and, with the All, moves toward the

    universal principle of all things."46

    Souls who have not yet coordinated

    their passions with the powers of the natural world must complete the

    material theurgies or "they will utterly fail to attain immaterial or

    material blessings. . . ."47

    On the other hand, Iamblichus says that

    he who celebrates all these powers and offers to each gifts that are

    pleasing and honors that are as similar to them as possible, will always

    remain secure and infallible since he has properly completed, perfect

    and whole, the receptacle of the divine choir.48

    The Iamblichean theurgist who becomes the receptacle of the divine

    choir by bringing his or her soul into correspondence with the theurgic

    powers of nature seems to have been the model for the Dionysian

    hierarch. "If you talk of hierarchy," Dionysius says, "you are referring in

    effect to the arrangement of all the sacred realities. Thus, whoever says

    'hierarch' indicates an inspired and divine man learned in all sacred

    knowledge, and in whom his own hierarchy is completely perfected and

    made known."49

    If one accepts Golitzin's argument that the bishop must

    bring the "interior" hierarchy within his soul into correspondence with the outer hierarchy revealed in the liturgy, then we see a Christian

    transposition of the principles of Iamblichean theurgy. For both

    Dionysius and Iamblichus the human soul is transformed and deified in

    theurgic rites and in the same way: the powers of the soul are brought

    into correspondence with divine archetypes by means of their symbolic

    icons.

    Is Dionysian theurgy, then, a specifically Christian expression of

    Iamblichean theurgy? As Rorem has demonstrated, Dionysius borrowed

    his triadic division for worship from Iamblichus. Indeed, the triads and

    mean terms that can be found throughout the Dionysian corpus are also

    46

    Quoted by Damascius, Dubitationes et solutiones I.79.12-14, ed. by Ruelle

    (Paris: 1889). 47

    DM 220.5. 48

    DM 229.3-7. 49

    EH 373C; (Heil/Ritter: 66.2-5). See Golitzin's translation and comments on

    this passage in "Hierarchy Versus Anarchy?" 148.

  • borrowed at least indirectly from the Syrian Neoplatonist.50 Iamblichus' rationale for the theurgic use of material symbols is adopted

    by Dionysius, as is Iamblichus' imperative that one must complete

    material rites before proceeding to less material theurgies. It would seem

    that Dionysius simply adapted the principles and some of the

    terminology of Iamblichus' psychology and theurgy to complete his

    hieratic vision of the Church.51

    In light of the evidence it is hard not to

    see Dionysius as kind of "Christian Iamblichus" who succeeded where Iamblichus himself had failed in building a theurgic society.52

    III. Who is the Subject of the Ergon Theou?

    Despite the wealth of evidence pointing to an Iamblichean influence on

    Dionysius, Paul Rorem who is largely responsible for uncovering this evidence maintains that Dionysian theurgy was fundamentally different from the theurgy of Iamblichus. Rorem acknowledges that

    Dionysius' use of the term theurgy derived from Iamblichus but claims

    that the Areopagite transformed its meaning. He writes:

    Our author used the term "theurgy" to mean "work of God," not as an

    objective genitive indicating a work addressed to God (as in

    50

    That Iamblichus was responsible for introducing the mean term and triadic

    structures into Neoplatonic vocabulary see E. R. Dodds, Proclus: The

    Elements of Theology (Oxford: Clarendon Press, [1933] 1992), xxi-xxii. 51

    Consider, for example, Dionysius' use of the term sunthema to describe the

    "solid food" and the "table" used in the celebration of the Eucharist (Letter 9

    [1109A, 1112A]; Heil/Ritter: 200.12; 203.7). Sunthema was a technical term

    in the Chaldean Oracles to denote the hidden names of the gods that allow

    theurgists to ascend to the divine; see The Chaldean Oracles, text, translation

    and commentary by Ruth Majercik (Leiden: Brill, 1989), 141. The term

    appears throughout the De mysteriis; see Shaw, Theurgy and the Soul, 48-50,

    267. For other theurgical terms in the Dionysian corpus see H. D. Saffrey,

    "New Objective Links Between the Pseudo-Dionysius and Proclus,"

    Neoplatonism and Christian Thought, ed. Dominic O'Meara (Norfolk, VA:

    International Society for Neoplatonic Studies, 1982), 64-75, 246-48. 52

    On this suggestion, see the very interesting essay by John Rist, "Pseudo-

    Dionysius, Neoplatonism and the Weakness of the Soul," From Athens to

    Chartres: Neoplatonism and Medieval Thought, ed. H. J. Westra (Leiden:

    Brill, 1992), 144-45.

  • Iamblichus, e.g. de Mysteriis I, 2, 7:2-6) but as a subjective genitive

    meaning God's own work . . . especially in the incarnation.53

    Another important difference, Rorem says, is that while Iamblichus

    believed that the theurgical symbols themselves elevated the soul, for

    Dionysius "the uplifting does not occur by virtue of the rites or symbols

    by themselves but rather in their interpretation. . . ."54

    Andrew Louth accepts Rorem's distinctions, but with some quail-

    fications. Like Rorem, Louth characterizes Neoplatonic theurgy as if it

    were an objective genitive so that the ergon theou is "a work concerned

    with the gods: human beings accomplished a work which affected the

    divine realm,"55

    yet Louth then seems to nuance (or contradict) his

    point, saying that Iamblichus did not believe the gods were affected by

    human actions but that "theurgic action made humans responsive to the

    divine."56

    With Rorem, Louth agrees that the ergon theou for Dionysius

    is a subjective genitive, the work of god, specifically the divine works of

    the incarnate Christ.57

    He maintains that for Dionysius the term

    theourgia "seems never to be used of religious rituals"58

    but refers only

    to the "historical divine acts recalled in liturgical celebration."59

    Concerning the anagogic power of theurgical symbols, Louth argues

    that, although for Dionysius generally it is our interpretation of symbols

    and not the symbols themselves that elevates the soul, there are

    significant exceptions as, for example, when Dionysius says that many

    of the mysteries of the sacraments are beyond our understanding (EH 568A).

    60

    53

    Lubheid and Rorem, Pseudo-Dionysius, 52 n. 11. Cf. Rorem, Symbols, 14-

    15, and Rorem, Pseudo-Dionysius: A Commentary on the Texts and an

    Introduction to Their Influence (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993),

    120. 54

    Rorem, Symbols, 116. 55

    Louth, Denys, 73. 56

    Ibid., 74. Rorem also explains that "theurgic invocations do not actually call

    down the gods but rather elevate the human soul toward the divine. . . ."

    Symbols, 108. 57

    Ibid., 74; Andrew Louth, "Pagan Theurgy," 434. 58

    Ibid., 434. 59

    Ibid., 435. 60

    Ibid., 437-38.

  • Rorem refers to the De mysteriis (I.2; 7.2-6) to support his claim that

    Iamblichean theurgy was an objective genitive, a "work addressed to

    God" and not "God's own work," yet the passage cited by Rorem merely

    describes Iamblichus' methodology in responding to Porphyry's

    questions about theology, theurgy, and philosophy. Iamblichus says:

    We will explain to you appropriately what is germane to all questions:

    we will answer theological topics theologically, theurgical topics

    theurgically, and together with you we will examine philosophical

    issues. (DM 7.2-6)

    One must assume that Rorem erred in citing this passage, for there is

    nothing in it that supports his contention that the ergon theou for

    Iamblichus was an objective genitive, that is, a human activity

    concerning and directed to the gods.61

    Annick Charles-Saget has recently analyzed the components of the term

    "theurgy" (theos/ergon) in the De mysteriis, focusing precisely on the

    "question of the subject of the ergon."62

    Charles-Saget argues that, for

    Iamblichus, the subject of the ergon cannot be a human being because of

    the profound change suffered by the soul in its embodiment, or as John

    Rist recently put it, because of the "weakness of the soul."63

    To be

    effective, theurgic rituals must be empowered by the gods and convey

    their good will by ritually recapitulating the gods' work of creation.64

    Iamblichus says:

    61

    Andrew Smith has discussed the passage cited by Rorem, "Iamblichus'

    Views on the Relationship of Philosophy to Religion in De Mysteriis," The

    Divine Iamblichus: Philosopher and Man of Gods, ed. H. J. Blumenthal and

    G. Clark (London: Bristol Classical Press, 1993), 74-86, and explains that

    Iamblichus makes "constant use of discursive argument" on theurgical issues

    (78). This should not be taken to mean that Iamblichus understood his

    discursive argument to be theurgy! 62

    Annick Charles-Saget, "La thurgie, nouvelle figure de l'ergon dans la vie

    philosophique," Divine Iamblichus, 107. 63

    Rist, Pseudo-Dionysius, 141-44. Iamblichus often emphasizes the weakness

    of the soul, e.g.: "The human race is weak and small, it sees but little and is

    possessed by a congenital nothingness" (DM 144.12-14). 64

    See DM 44.11-14 where the good will of the gods is mingled with their

    necessity; 141.6-13 where all forms of divination manifest one beneficent

  • Is not every sacred rite legislated noetically from first principles

    according to the laws of the Gods? For each rite imitates the order of

    the Gods, both the intelligible and the celestial Gods, and each

    possesses the eternal measures of the universe and wondrous signs

    which have been sent down here by the Demiurge and Father of all

    things, and through which the unspeakable is expressed through

    ineffable symbols. . . . (DM 65.6-9)

    It is frustrating that Iamblichus does not provide concrete details to

    exemplify what he means, but his explanation of theurgic prayer comes

    closer and again addresses the question of the subject of the ergon. He says:

    If anyone would consider the hieratic prayers, how they are sent down

    to men from the Gods and are symbols of the Gods, how they are

    known only to the Gods and possess in a certain way the same power

    as the Gods, how could anyone rightly believe that this sort of prayer is

    derived from our empirical sense and is not divine and spiritual? (DM

    48.5-11)

    Strictly speaking, a theurgical prayer was not an address to the gods but

    a way of entering the power of their voice and awakening a

    corresponding voice in one's soul.65

    Unless one is constrained by

    "confessional pre-suppositions" to overlook what Iamblichus himself

    says, it would be difficult to read the De mysteriis and conclude that

    Iamblichus believed a theurgic rite was man addressing (or affecting)

    the gods rather than what Iamblichus says it is: the gods addressing man,

    calling us back to divinity through rituals designed by the Demiurge

    himself in the act of creation.66

    The question of the subject of the ergon, however, is exceedingly

    complex for, after all, it is a human being who performs the ritual. How

    then can he or she not be the "subject" of the ergon? Charles-Saget

    will; 209.14-17 where all forms of life are said to preserve the will of their

    creator. 65

    Iamblichus refers to this divine aspect in the soul as the "one in us." See

    Shaw, Theurgy and the Soul, Chapter 11: "Eros and the One of the Soul,"

    118-26. 66

    For a critique of Rorem's objective/subjective genitive distinction

    concerning theurgy, see Thomas Tomasic's review in Speculum 62 (1987):

    178-82; Tomasic characterizes Rorem's Biblical and Liturgical Symbols as an

    exercise in "belief justification" rather than an "objective, historical analysis."

  • acknowledges that a theurgic ritual appears to be a human activity, one

    that includes gestures and symbols, but she explains that the visible

    activity serves only to make the soul receptive to the invisible activity of

    the gods. If the soul has been properly purified and is sufficiently

    receptive, the ineffable symbols in the rite are awakened and act through

    the soul, even if they are not conceptually understood.67

    In this

    awakening, Iamblichus says, "the soul is then entirely separated from

    those things which bind it to the generated world, and it flies from the

    inferior and exchanges one life for another. It gives itself to another

    order, having entirely abandoned its former existence" (DM 270.15-

    19).68

    Thus, in theurgy human activity becomes the vehicle for a divine

    activity measured by the receptive capacity (epitedeiotes)69

    of a soul that

    experiences a "secret sumpatheia" with divine powers.70

    Charles-Saget

    concludes:

    Thus, there are not two incompatible meanings of theourgia: the actor

    of the human rite, in his ritual effacement, imitates in his order the

    communication of the indivisible and the divisible that the divine

    demiurgy accomplishes at every moment.71

    To receive, to enact, and to be elevated by theurgic symbols was to enter

    the hidden activity of the Demiurge and become a cocreator. Rather than

    escaping from the cosmos, as Porphyry had encouraged, the theurgist

    embraced it by entering a demiurgic dimension where even his own

    body was transformed into an icon of the divine. In theurgy, Iamblichus

    designed a praxis that not only saved the soul but also solved the

    Platonic problem of embodiment that had so vexed Plotinus.72

    In the act

    of theurgy the soul was simultaneously human and divine, mortal and

    immortal, united in the One and divided in the body, all within an

    activity that embraced and transcended the oppositions. Iamblichus

    explains:

    67

    Charles-Saget, "Thurgie," 111-12. 68

    The particular soul, however, never ceases to remain soul even as it

    becomes the participant in a divine and universal action (DM 69.5-19). 69

    On the importance of epitedeiotes in theurgy see Shaw, Theurgy and the

    Soul, 86-87. 70

    Charles-Saget, "Thurgie," 113. 71

    Ibid., 113, my emphasis. 72

    Shaw, "Theurgy as Demiurgy."

  • All of theurgy has two aspects. One is that it is a rite conducted by men

    which preserves our natural order in the universe; the other is that it is

    empowered by divine symbols, is raised up through them to be joined

    on high with the Gods, and is led harmoniously round to their order.

    This latter aspect rightly assumes the shape of the Gods. (DM 184.1-8)

    If the ergon theou of Iamblichean theurgy is more accurately described

    as a subjective genitive, "god's own work,"73

    then what would

    distinguish the theurgy of Dionysius from that of Iamblichus? Rorem

    contends that Iamblichus connected the soul's ascent in theurgy "to the

    force of the rituals per se" while Dionysius linked the ascent of the soul

    to a "spiritual process of understanding the ritual and never to the rites

    themselves."74

    Clearly, Iamblichus was more concerned than the

    Areopagite not to reduce the transcendent power of ritual to a

    conceptual schema, for it was precisely the purpose of the De mysteriis

    to respond to the overly rationalized Platonism that Iamblichus saw in

    Porphyry's school. Yet, despite the polemical tone of the De mysteriis in

    this regard, Iamblichus maintains that without "our thinking" the ritual

    henosis of theurgy cannot occur (DM 98.8-10). In short, the mind played

    a necessary auxiliary role to prepare the soul for theurgy.75

    However,

    because of the soul's embodied condition, "our thinking" can never

    effect the soul's henosis.

    Dionysius would certainly have agreed with Iamblichus' insistence on

    approaching the divine through symbols.76

    And, although the Areopagite

    says that the contemplation of symbols elevates the soul, this

    contemplation was not merely a human theoria, "certainly no detached

    knowledge of specific facts,"77

    but a theoria shaped, inspired, and

    prepared by the divine through the images of scripture and sacramental

    rites. Rorem says that for Dionysius, theoria can indicate a "spiritual

    73

    Smyth #1330-1331 clearly distinguishes the objective genitive from the

    subjective, which makes it all the more surprising that Rorem and Louth give

    to Iamblichean theurgy the sense of an objective genitive, as if the gods were

    the passive objects of man's activity, a point that Iamblichus denies

    throughout the De mysteriis. See Herbert Weir Smyth, Greek Grammar,

    revised by Gordon M. Messing (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1976). 74

    Rorem, Symbols, 109. 75

    On this point see Andrew Smith, "Iamblichus' Views," 74-86. 76

    See Rorem, Symbols, 105-6; CH 121CD. 77

    Ibid., 110.

  • perception of the highest order,"78

    so to characterize it as an

    "interpretation" may be misleading.79

    For if the material elements of the

    liturgy do not convey the divine presence but need, rather, to be

    interpreted to grasp their "conceptual" meanings, then Dionysius would

    rightly be subject to the kind of critique offered by Wesche.80

    Dionysian

    theoria was not, however, a conceptual interpretation, it was more a

    direct and performative experience.81

    Although Dionysius clearly is

    freer in his use of the term theoria than Iamblichus, I believe that this

    was probably due more to the difference in their intellectual milieux

    than to an essential difference in their conceptions of theurgy. When the

    Areopagite wants to emphasize the transcendence of the divine beyond

    human understanding he sounds very much like Iamblichus. Describing

    his ineffable union with god, Dionysius says that the "theurgic lights" he

    received from both the scriptures and divinely inspired masters (DN 592B) initiated him into experiences beyond thought. He explains:

    We call a halt to the activities of our minds and, to the extent that is

    proper, we approach the ray which transcends being. Here, in a manner

    no words can describe, preexist all the goals of all knowledge and it is

    of a kind that neither intelligence nor speech can lay hold of nor can it

    78

    Ibid., 114. As Rorem notes, angels themselves engage in the theoria of God

    in an immediate (and circular) way, CH 205C. 79

    The problem here may simply be one of translation, by no means an easy

    task! However, when Luibheid translates the Greek noetos as "conceptual"

    throughout the corpus it tends to obscure rather than illuminate the meaning

    of the text. Most readers would not characterize nondiscursive intuition as

    "conceptual." Golitzin seems to have the same concern with Rorem's

    language, but in a liturgical context. He says: "It is difficult, for me at least, to

    avoid the impression that Christ's presence here is meant to be more than

    merely 'conceptual'" (Golitzin, "Mysticism," 106-7). 80

    Wesche, "Christological Doctrine," 68. 81

    The apophatic exercises in Dionysius might be better characterized as

    "performative" than "conceptual," for only the former allows the "utterly

    transcendent to be revealed as utterly immanent. . . ." See Michael Sells,

    Mystical Languages of Unsaying (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,

    1994), 1-10. To engage the transcendent ritually through immanent objects

    was neither opposed to, nor a prerequisite for, the exercise of negative

    theology; it was, rather, the direct result of and correlate to apophasis. This

    point is explained, with references to Dionysius, by A. H. Armstrong,

    "Negative Theology," Downside Review 95 (1977): 176-89.

  • at all be contemplated since it surpasses everything and is wholly

    beyond our capacity to know it.82

    If the role of theoria in Dionysius is not, perhaps, as foreign to

    Iamblichean theurgy as the term might suggest, and if the

    subjective/objective genitive distinction is incorrect, then what would

    distinguish Dionysian from Iamblichean theurgy? Louth contends that

    Dionysian theurgy differs from the Iamblichean in that divine acts for

    Dionysius refer only to the acts of Christ and never to ritual acts.83

    Here,

    I believe, Louth draws too firm a line between the historical acts of

    Jesus and their expression in the liturgy. For, if the purpose of the

    liturgy is to deify its members, this would require direct participation in

    the theurgies, and this could hardly be effected by simply recalling (or

    interpreting) the acts of the historical Jesus.84

    While Dionysian theurgy

    is distinctively Christian with Christ as the "principle and essence of every theurgy" (EH 372A) Dionysius understood that Jesus' transmission of "theurgic mysteries" (ta theourga musteria)

    85 in the

    Eucharist required the hierarch, in performing these rites, to be

    assimilated to these theurgies and communicate their deifying power to

    others. Louth's insistence that theurgies be confined to the activities of

    Jesus "recalled" in the liturgy,86

    simply cannot account for this deifying

    activity nor for the diversity of other evidence.87

    The kinds of theurgic

    experience that Louth does not discuss include the "theurgic lights"

    visited upon angels and holy men (CH 208C, 340B), the "theurgic

    82

    DN 592D; (Suchla: 115.9-13), translation by Lubheid and Rorem, modified

    slightly. 83

    Louth, "Pagan Theurgy," 434. 84

    In any case, the theurgy of Jesus' incarnation is more often described by

    Dionysius in terms of a metaphysical unfolding than as a concrete record of

    historical events. The incarnation is a movement from wholeness to

    fragmentation, from simplicity to complexity, from eternity to temporality

    (DN 592A), and from indivisible unity to divided plurality (EH 429A). These

    are the same definitions that Iamblichus used to characterize the effects of

    embodiment on the soul! 85

    Letter 9 (1108A); (Heil/Ritter: 198.4). 86

    Louth, "Pagan Theurgy," 435. 87

    Louth is responding, he says, to "the common view that Denys' Christianity

    has been swamped by his enthusiasm for Neoplatonism. . . ." ("Pagan

    Theurgy," 434). In an effort to insure Dionysius' "orthodoxy," despite his

    theurgical language, it seems that Louth interprets the evidence to avoid

    Neoplatonic, or worse, theurgical contamination.

  • gnosis" desired and received by angels (CH 309A-C, EH 501 B), the

    "theurgic measures" by which we receive God's presence (EH 477D),

    the perfecting power of "every theurgic holiness in us" (EH 484D), and

    the "theurgic lights" (theourgika phota) that Dionysius says he received

    from holy men (DN 592B). These exemplify more than our recalling or

    celebrating the divine works of the historical Jesus; they describe a

    direct transmission and experience of deifying activity: theurgy. John of

    Scythopolis explained Dionysius' use of theourgikos phos as follows:

    "He calls theurgic lights the teachings of the saints, in so far as they

    produce a light of knowledge and make gods of those who believe."88

    When Dionysius states that the purpose for members of "our hierarchy"

    is to become "luminous and theurgic, perfected and able to bestow

    perfection" (EH 372B), he is describing the deifying power that priests experience and transmit in the liturgy and initiations.

    It may be more correct to see Dionysian theurgy as a specific expression

    of the theurgy that Iamblichus described in general terms. The De

    mysteriis tells us almost nothing about the actual performance of rituals,

    while Dionysius outlines specific rites in detail. The principal outlines of

    Iamblichus' theory of theurgy might, in fact, be applied to any religious

    community that receives and enacts divine power through religious

    ritual. In Dionysius' Christian theurgy, Hierotheus provides a model for

    "experiencing communion with the things praised" (i.e., the theurgies of

    Christ), an experience that Dionysius describes as a kind of ecstasy.89

    He says of Hierotheus:

    He was so caught up, so taken out of himself (existamenos heautou)

    experiencing communion with the things praised, that everyone who

    heard him, everyone who saw him . . . considered him to be inspired,

    to be speaking divine praises.90

    88

    Translation by H. D. Saffrey, who says that John of Scythopolis "offers us

    an explanation altogether pagan and without any basis in the Christian

    tradition" ("New Objective Links," 71-72). 89

    See Rist, "Pseudo-Dionysius," 148, who notes liturgical comparisons to

    Hierotheus's experience in EH 425D, 440B, 444A. For the role of ecstasy in

    Iamblichean theurgy see Shaw, Theurgy and the Soul, 234-36. 90

    DN 681D-684A; (Suchla: 141.11-14), tr. by Lubheid and Rorem.

  • This was possible to Hierotheus because he, like the Egyptian theurgists

    of Iamblichus,91

    "not only learned but also experienced divine things,

    for he had a sumpatheia with these things" (DN 648B). Sumpatheia or

    homoiosis with divine theurgies was the Dionysian norm, not the

    exception. Consider his description of the eucharistic mystery:

    After the hierarch sings the holy theurgies, he performs the most sacred

    actions and lifts up into view the celebrated objects through the

    sacredly displayed symbols. And having revealed the gifts of the

    theurgies he himself enters into communion (koinonia) with them and

    exhorts the others to follow. (EH 425D)

    As in Iamblichean theurgy, the hierarch united with divine theurgies no longer acts only as a man but as a god, or, in this case, the god-man

    Christ, and he exhorts others to share in this deification. Indeed, if a

    priest does not enter into koinonia with these theurgies, if he remains

    unilluminated and untheurgic, he has no light to pass on to others and

    should be expelled from the priestly orders.92

    For Dionysius, the liturgy

    is more than a human ritual, it is "god's own work," an invitation to

    enter theurgies that "make gods of those who believe." As Iamblichus

    put it:

    If these things were only human customs and received their authority

    from our legal institutions one might say that the worship of the Gods

    was the invention of our ideas. But in fact God is the leader of these

    things . . . and each nation on earth is alloted a certain common

    guardian by him, and every temple is similarly alloted its particular

    overseer. (DM 236.1-8)

    IV. Conclusion: Theurgy Cosmocentric or Anthropocentric?

    Like Iamblichus, Dionysius believed that god was present in the liturgy

    and leading the rites, which explained their deifying power. Did

    Dionysius, then, simply transpose the principles of Iamblichean theurgy

    into his ekklesia? Did he create a theurgic society, as Rist suggests, in a

    91

    Speaking of the veneration of star gods, Iambichus says: "The Egyptians do

    not simply contemplate these things theoretically, but by means of sacred

    theurgy they report that they ascend to higher and more universal realms. . . ."

    (DM 267.6-9). 92

    Letter 8 (1092B); Dionysius' idealistic views of the Church are in sharp

    contrast to those of Augustine; see Rist, "Pseudo-Dionysius," 158.

  • manner that was more politically successful than anything Iamblichus or

    other Neoplatonists were able to achieve?93

    The effort of theologians to

    deny this by making a caricature of Iambichean theurgy and then finding

    substantial differences to distinguish the theurgy of the Church from the

    "pagan" theurgy of Iamblichus is, quite simply, contradicted by the

    evidence. To suggest that Dionysian theurgy was not different in kind,

    but only in specific expression, from Iamblichean theurgy should not be

    reason to condemn the Areopagite. It simply recognizes that in the

    fourth to the sixth centuries, particularly among Syrian theologians both Christian and non-Christian there was a pronounced interest in experiencing the divine rather than merely thinking and talking about it,

    and Iamblichus was the first to provide a comprehensive rationale for

    doing so.94

    Unless we choose to dismiss the role of experience in the

    rites of the Church, we must follow Dionysius in seeing the liturgy as

    theurgy, a rite that effects a cognitive, perceptual, and ontological shift

    so profound in receptive participants that it culminates in theosis, the

    deification of the soul. For both Iamblichus and Dionysius this

    deification was effected in rites that united the "fallen" soul with divine

    activities (ta theia energeia), and scholars of Neoplatonic theurgy could

    learn a great deal from Dionysius about the specifics of theurgic ritual

    that Iamblichus does not discuss.

    Despite the profound similarity between the theurgies of Iamblichus and

    Dionysius, there is at least one very significant, perhaps crucial

    difference: the role of nature and the material cosmos in their respective

    systems. As R. T. Wallis explained: "Neoplatonic 'sacramentalism'

    differs from its Christian counterpart in that it depends solely on the

    world's basic god-given laws, not on a supernatural intervention over

    and above those laws."95

    A simple point with far-reaching conse-

    quences.

    Iamblichus maintained that Egyptian theurgy "imitated the nature of the

    universe and the creative activity of the Gods" (DM 249.14-250.1). To

    perform a theurgic ritual, therefore, was to participate in this "creative

    activity" according to the soul's receptive capacity (epitedeiotes).

    93

    Rist, "Pseudo-Dionysius," 144, 156. 94

    See Golitzin's reference to the "current of thought" among fourth-century

    thinkers in Syria-Palestine as regards the soul's liturgical experience

    ("Hierarchy Versus Anarchy?" 172-73 n. 164). 95

    R. T. Wallis, Neoplatonism (New York: Scribner, 1972), 121.

  • Following traditional Platonic and Pythagorean teachings, the cosmos

    was seen as the supreme icon of divinity, and Iamblichus honored those

    "sacred races" who preserved rituals that mimetically reflected the

    unchanging demiurgy of the gods (DM VII.5; 259.1-260.1).

    Theoretically, any society could be theurgic as long as its rituals and

    prayers preserved the "eternal measures" of creation (DM 65.6), which

    is perhaps why the emperor Julian could see Judaism as a "theurgic"

    religion.96

    It is important to note that, for Iamblichus, theurgic activity

    was always in analogia cosmogonic activity, and this is precisely what distinguished theurgy from sorcery (goeteia).

    97 Although sorcerers,

    like theurgists, exercised a knowledge of cosmic sympathies, their spells

    did not "preserve the analogy with divine creation" (DM 168.15-16) and

    thus failed to be theurgic. Theurgists aligned themselves with the divine

    currents of the cosmos while sorcerers, like parasites, drew these same

    powers to themselves and eventually to their own destruction (DM 182.13-16).

    Iamblichus' theurgy was cosmocentric and could not be adapted to the

    selfish practices of sorcerers nor, rightly, to the hegemonic vision of a

    single religion, for the diversity of peoples, climates, and geography

    would naturally require diversified forms of theurgic worship. Each

    sacred community Egyptian, Assyrian, or Chaldean practiced a different form of theurgy yet, according to Iamblichus, to be genuinely

    theurgic the rites of each cult had to be in "analogia with creation." The

    theurgies of each sacred race, therefore, manifested the gods, each was a

    living sunthema of the divine. In Dionysius' terms, these sacred races

    would have been designated "hierarchies," revealing the divine and

    leading souls into deification. For the Areopagite, however, there was

    but one human hierarchy as required by the Christian myth, while for

    Iamblichus there would have been many, for Neoplatonic theurgy was

    imagined within a polytheistic and pluralistic cosmos. The embodied

    variety of the material cosmos required a corresponding variety of

    theurgic societies, and this too was consistent with Iamblichean

    metaphysics where the utterly ineffable One can be "known" only in the

    Many: each henophany both veiling and revealing its ineffable source.

    In order to create one universal and theurgic "church," the Pythagorean

    myth of cosmogony-as-theurgy had to be changed, and this was initiated

    96

    Jay Bregman, "Judaism as Theurgy in the Religious Thought of the Emperor

    Julian," The Ancient World 26 (1995): 135-49. 97

    DM 168.13-16; cf. Shaw, Theurgy and the Soul, 169.

  • by the Areopagite, who shifted theurgy's center of gravity from the

    cosmos to man.

    James Miller has pointed out that, while Dionysius preserved the

    Neoplatonic dynamics of prohodos and epistrophe that are ritually

    enacted in Iamblichean theurgy, in its Dionysian form the natural

    cosmos is replaced by ecclesiastic and angelic orders.98

    This means that

    Dionysian theurgy is no longer an extension of the act of creation (in

    analogia with divine creation) but becomes something beyond or beside

    nature, in what the Church calls the "new creation": the supernatural

    orders of the Church and its angels.99

    Theurgical symbols for Dionysius

    are no longer found in the natural world but in the ecclesiastical world:

    its scriptural images and cultic rites. Miller argues that, by eliminating

    nature and the heavenly bodies from Christian theurgy, Dionysius

    achieved far greater clarity and increased the Church's political authority

    for, in Christian theurgy, the ekklesia assumes the divine status ascribed

    to the physical cosmos in pagan theurgy.100

    A. H. Armstrong notes this

    shift from the natural to the ecclesiastical cosmos. He says:

    It is only in the Church that material things become means of

    revelation and salvation through being understood in the light of

    Scripture and Church tradition and used by God's human ministers in

    the celebration of the Church's sacraments. It is the ecclesiastical

    cosmos, not the natural cosmos, which appears to be of primary

    98

    James Miller, Measures of Wisdom: The Cosmic Dance in Classical and

    Christian Antiquity (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1986), 461. 99

    Iamblichean theurgy was also supernatural. Indeed, A. H. Armstrong

    suggests that Iamblichus was the first to use huperphues as a term meaning

    above nature (A. H. Armstrong, "Iamblichus and Egypt," Les Etudes

    philosophiques 2-3 [1987]: 186-87). Yet huperphues for Iamblichus was

    never removed from nature or creation for, as a Pythagorean, Iamblichus

    imagined theurgy according to arithmological principles. The transcendent

    power of the gods is in matter and in nature, just as simple numbers reside in

    and support their complex derivatives without being affected by them. Huper

    phusis (above nature) could never be equated by Iamblichus with para phusis

    (against nature) for anything opposed to nature was opposed to the

    manifesting gods (DM 158.14-159.3). For Dionysius, however, huper phusis

    is synonymous with para phusis (DN 648A). This, I believe, reflects the

    transformation of Neoplatonic principles within the context of the Christian

    myth. 100

    Miller, Measures of Wisdom, 461.

  • religious importance for the Christian. There is here a new and radical

    sort of religious anthropocentricism, which may have had far-reaching

    consequences.101

    It is interesting that the consequence most disturbing to Armstrong was

    also feared by Iamblichus. To Porphyry's remark that the gods were too

    elevated to be contacted in material rites Iamblichus replied that his

    opinion "amounts to saying . . . that this lower region is a desert, without

    the Gods" (DM 28.9-11). Outside of the "new creation" of the Church,

    this lower region does become a desert, deprived of the presence of true

    divinity. Armstrong continues:

    It is easy to see how the anthropocentrism, with all its consequences,

    has outlasted the dominance of the Church. In so far as the Church

    became the only theophany, when it ceased to be an effective

    theophany, (as it has long ceased to be for most Europeans), there was

    no theophany left for the majority of men, no divine self-manifestation

    here below.102

    Dionysius can hardly be held responsible for our "wholly profane,

    desacralized non-human world" lamented by Armstrong.103

    Indeed,

    Dionysius followed Origen and Gregory of Nyssa in their positive

    evaluation of nature, yet while Origen recognized sacred symbols within

    the natural world, Dionysius placed them solely within the Church,104

    and by shifting the context of theurgy from the natural to an ecclesiastic

    world he necessarily changed the very nature of the "divine work."105

    101

    A. H. Armstrong, "Man in the Cosmos: A Study of Some Differences

    Between Pagan Neoplatonism and Christianity," in Romanitas et

    Christianitas, ed. W. den Boer et al. (London: North Holland, 1973), 11. 102

    Ibid., 11-12. 103

    Ibid., 12. 104

    Golitzin, contrasting Dionysius' system with that of Evagrius says: ". . .

    Dionysius has put the Church and its organized worship in the place of

    Evagrius' providential cosmos." See Hieromonk Alexander (Golitzin), Et

    Introibo ad Altare Dei: The Mystagogy of Dionysius Areopagita, with Special

    Reference to its Predecessors in the Eastern Christian Tradition

    (Thessalonika, 1994), 346. 105

    The shift away from cosmocentric theurgy, however, was gradual. In

    Maximus' Mystagogia, a commentary on the EH of Dionysius, he says that

    the church is an "image of the sensible world" and "the world can be thought

    of as a church." See The Church, the Liturgy and the Soul of Man: The

    Mystagogia of St. Maximus the Confessor, tr. with historical note and

  • Ancient theurgists worked within the parameters of nature and sought to

    unify themselves with its Creator through natural symbols; the Christian

    theurgist, by contrast, worked within the parameters of the institutional

    Church and sought to achieve union with Christ through the ritual

    enactments of a myth that asserted an entirely "new creation" and

    liberation from the "old world" that had become the domain and

    instrument of Satan. This, I would argue, is the most significant

    difference between the theurgy of Iamblichus and the theurgy of

    Dionysius, a difference with consequences we have only begun to

    explore.

    Gregory Shaw is Professor of Religious Studies at Stonehill College, North

    Easton, Massachusetts

    commentary by Dom Julian Stead (Still River: St. Bede's Publications, 1982),

    71. The world as church or temple is perfectly consistent with the principles

    of Iamblichean theurgy, so long as our church is not the only church.