+ All Categories
Home > Documents > On the Account for Human Consciousness

On the Account for Human Consciousness

Date post: 10-Feb-2018
Category:
Upload: tuba-naz
View: 215 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend

of 47

Transcript
  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    1/47

    qwertyuiopasdfghjklzxcvbnmqwerty

    opasdfghjklzxcvbnmqwertyuiopasdfg

    klzxcvbnmqwertyuiopasdfghjklzxcvb

    nmqwertyuiopasdfghjklzxcvbnmqwe

    yuiopasdfghjklzxcvbnmqwertyuiopa

    dfghjklzxcvbnmqwertyuiopasdfghjklz

    vbnmqwertyuiopasdfghjklzxcvbnmq

    wertyuiopasdfghjklzxcvbnmqwertyu

    pasdfghjklzxcvbnmqwertyuiopasdfgh

    klzxcvbnmqwertyuiopasdfghjklzxcvbmqwertyuiopasdfghjklzxcvbnmqwer

    uiopasdfghjklzxcvbnmqwertyuiopasd

    ghjklzxcvbnmqwertyuiopasdfghjklzxvbnmqwertyuiopasdfghjklzxcvbnmrt

    uiopasdfghjklzxcvbnmqwertyuiopasd

    ghjklzxcvbnmqwertyuiopasdfghjklzx

    ON THE ACCOUNT FOR HUMAN

    CONSCIOUSNESS

    TUBA NAZ

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    2/47

    2 | P a g e

    TABLEOFCONTENTS

    INTRODUCTIONTOHUMANCONSCIOUSNESS ............................................................................... 1What is Human Consciousness? .......................................................................................................... 1

    Language, Thinking and Consciousness ......................................................................................... 2

    ORIGINS OF THE PROBLEM OF HUMAN CONSCIOUSNESS................................................................. 4

    The Nature of the Problem .................................................................................................................. 5

    THEANCIENTAGE OF HUMANCONSCIOUSNESS ........................................................................8

    The Pre-Socratics: ... 9

    Platos Contribution.12

    Aristotles conception of Soul...13

    THESUBSTANTIALIZINGOF THESUBJECT.15

    The Mind-Body Problem17

    Critical Analysis..18

    Consciousness as Self-awareness..19

    THEINTERNALIZING OF THEOBJECT21

    Lockes Egocentric predicament21

    Descartes and Locke 22

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    3/47

    3 | P a g e

    THEDISTANTIATING OF THESUBJECT FROM ITSMENTALMODES23

    Experience Is the Origin of All Ideas .23

    GEORGE BERKLEY: To be is to be Perceived ..24

    The Skeptical Influence on Human Consciousness.27

    THEEMPIRICIZING OF THEMENTAL.30

    James on Pure Experience ..33

    The Paradox of Consciousness ....34

    The Objectivity of Experience .....34

    Transcendental Ideas ....36

    EXISTENTIALISTVIEW OFCONSCIOUSNESS 39

    Objectivity as Untruth..39

    The Current Understanding of Human Consciousness ..40

    BIBLOGRAPHY 41

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    4/47

    4 | P a g e

    INTRODUCTIONTOHUMANCONSCIOUSNESS

    You go to black and then you have to have a moment of Big Bang and that's the origin

    of everything the origin of thought the origin of consciousness, whatever it is. In that

    moment its like 'from that nothing to everything' is everything.

    -Larry Wachowski

    Consciousness is undeniably real. It is something that practically every rational human freely

    acknowledges. But admitting all of that, turns out to be the easy part. The difficulty arises in

    explaining why? Why consciousness exists? Why it is real? Why it works the way it does? And

    the more important, where does it exist? When it comes to explaining the origin of

    consciousness, the emergence of full consciousness is indeed one of the greatest of miracles

    and also a mystery. The past three decades have witnessed a serious and noticeable increase in

    interest in the subject of consciousness. One would think that since so much has been written

    on the topic of consciousness, surely the definition of this discussed issue would be a

    straightforward one, a simple matter. Scientists and philosophers cannot even agree on the

    definition of the term, much less on the origin of that which they are attempting to define. So

    much has been written to shed light on the issue of consciousness but the difficulties and

    criticisms always blurred this idea. Much work has been done in different domains to clarify the

    concept of consciousness but neither the consensus nor a clear explanation occurred in any

    domain.

    I. What is Human Consciousness?Our English word consciousness has its roots in the Latin conscio, formed by the coalescence

    of cum (meaning with) and scio (meaning know). In its original Latin sense, to be conscious

    of something was to share knowledge of it, with someone else, or with oneself.

    A common definition of consciousness has also been defined as: "the totality of the

    impressions, thoughts, and feelings which make up a person's conscious being." This general

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    5/47

    5 | P a g e

    definition postulates that consciousness is the sum of all which occurs within the mind. The

    American Heritage Dictionary offers an equally vague definition of consciousness, "The state or

    condition of being conscious"; conscious being defined as: "Having an awareness of one's

    environment and one's own existence, sensations, and thoughts."

    More recent definitions of consciousness support the writings of William James. The joint or

    mutual knowledge definition considers consciousness to be an expression closely related to the

    ability to share thoughts with others. Through learnt interaction a person develops the ability

    to be aware of her/himself. Associated with this definition is the radical behaviorists' view

    which claims that without the ability to express one's inner experience with other people,

    sharing of mutual or joint knowledge, self-awareness would not exist. Thus, the expression of

    conscious awareness is a learnt phenomenon dependent upon social interaction and

    conditioning.

    Contrary to the above definition is one in which consciousness is seen as the ability for internal

    knowing. Rather than being considered a social construct consciousness arises from within an

    individual. A combination of the mutual or joint knowledge definition and that of internal

    knowing is the definition that consciousness is a state of awareness. This definition considers

    consciousness to be a state in which knowledge of one's internal domain, as well as the outside

    world coexist. External knowledge is derived from the senses allowing a person to be aware of

    her/his inner and outer worlds.

    II. Language, Thinking and ConsciousnessHuman beings' ability to speak has changed consciousness in several ways. Whereas animals

    learn principally from their own experiences, we can share our subjective experiences with

    each other and so learn from each other. We can build up a body of collective knowledge that

    can be passed down from one generation to another.

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    6/47

    6 | P a g e

    Not only do we use speech to talk to each other, we can talk to ourselves, inside our own

    minds: we can think in words. Of all the significant developments that came from language

    thinking has been the most important.

    Words can conjure up associations to past experiences. The word "elephant" brings back to

    mind images of elephant we have seen, cats we may have known, dolphins we have heard

    about, things we know about them, and a range of other associations. Through words we can

    deliberately bring the past back to mind, independently of what is happening in the present.

    Other creatures may well experience associations to past experiences, like dogs seem to

    remember people who have treated them badly but their associations are almost certainly

    determined by what is going on around them in the present moment.

    Through thinking we can liberate ourselves from this constraint. Not only can we think about

    past experiences, we can entertain thoughts about the future. We can make plans and take

    decisions, and exercise far greater influence over our future that other creatures. Just our

    consciousness has expanded in space to encompass even the edges of the Universe, so too it it

    has expanded in time.

    Thinking has allowed us to ask questions -- "How?" and "Why?", and ponder their solutions.

    Such quests led to science and philosophy, literally, "knowledge" and "the love of wisdom". Our

    consciousness discovered a whole new realm, i.e. understanding. We could look into the heart

    of matter.

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    7/47

    7 | P a g e

    ORIGINSOF THE PROBLEM OFHUMAN CONSCIOUSNESS

    Philosophers argue about whether all thinking is accompanied by or perhaps even constituted

    out of sensory materials (i.e. images), and some champion the idea of a pure thought-consciousness independent of sensory components. In any event, there is no doubt that

    thought is something that often happens consciously and is in some way different from

    perception, sensation or other forms of consciousness. Yet another sort of conscious

    experience is closely associated with the idea of conscious thought but not identical to it:

    epistemological consciousness, or the sense of certainty or doubt we have when consciously

    entertaining a proposition (such as 2 + 3 = 5 or the word eat consists of three letters).

    Descartes famously appealed to such states of consciousness in the method of doubt, that

    reason alone determined knowledge of true reality, independently of the senses. All things

    which I conceive very clearly and very distinctly are true.1

    Still another significant if subtle form of consciousness has sometimes been given the name

    fringe consciousness, which refers to the background of awareness which sets the context for

    experience. An example is our sense of orientation or rightness in a familiar environment

    (consider the change in your state of consciousness when you recognize someones face who at

    first appeared a stranger). Moods present another form of fringe consciousness, with clear links

    to the more overtly conscious emotional states but also clearly distinct from these. But I think

    there is a fundamental commonality to all these different forms of consciousness.

    Consciousness is distinctive for its subjectivity or its first-person character. There is something

    it is like to be in a conscious state and only the conscious subject has direct access to this way

    of being. There is nothing it is like to be a rock, no subjective aspect to an ashtray. But

    conscious beings are essentially different in this respect. The huge variety in the forms of

    consciousness makes the problem very complex, but the core problem of consciousness

    focuses on the nature of subjectivity.

    1Copleston, F. S.J. vol. IV of A History of Philosophy (London: Burns and Oates Ltd., 1960) pg: 97

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    8/47

    8 | P a g e

    A further source of complexity arises from the range of possible explanatory targets associated

    with the study of consciousness. One might, for instance, primarily focus on the structure or

    contents of consciousness. These would provide a valid answer to one legitimate sense of the

    question what is consciousness. But then again, one might be more interested in how

    consciousness comes into being, either in a developing individual, or in the universe at large. Or

    one might wonder how consciousness, seemingly so different from the purely objective

    properties of the material world studied by physics or chemistry, fits in with the overall

    scientific view of the world. To address all these aspects of the problem of consciousness would

    require volumes upon volumes. The history presented here focuses on what has become

    perhaps the central issue in consciousness studies, which is the problem of integrating

    subjectivity into the scientific view of the world.

    I. The Nature of the ProblemDespite is a huge range of diverse opinion, I think it is fair to say that there is now something of

    a consensus view about the origin of consciousness, which I will call here the mainstream

    view. It is something like the following. The world is a purely physical system created some 13

    billion years ago in the prodigious event Fred Hoyle labeled the big bang. Very shortly after the

    big bang the world was in a primitive, ultra-hot and chaotic state in which normal matter could

    not exist, but as the system cooled the familiar elements of hydrogen and helium, as well as

    some traces of a few heavier elements, could form. Then very interesting things started to

    happen, as stars and galaxies quickly evolved, burned through their hydrogen fuel and went

    nova, in the process creating and spewing forth most of the elements of the periodic table into

    the increasingly rich galactic environments.

    There was not a trace of life, mind or consciousness throughout any of this. That was to come

    later. The mainstream view continues with the creation of planetary systems. At first these

    were poor in heavier elements, but after just a few generations of star creation and destruction

    there were many Earth like planets scattered through the vast perhaps infinite expanse of

    galaxies, and indeed some 7 or 8 billion years after the big bang the Earth itself formed along

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    9/47

    9 | P a g e

    with our solar system. We do not yet understand it very well, but whether in a warm little

    pond, around a deeply submerged hydrothermal vent, amongst the complex interstices of

    some claylike matrix, as a pre-packaged gift from another world, or in some other way of which

    we have no inkling, conditions on the early Earth somehow enabled the special though

    entirely in accord with physical law chemistry necessary for the beginnings of life. But even

    with the presence of life or proto-life, consciousness still did not grace the Earth. The long, slow

    processes of evolution by natural selection took hold and ultimately led at some time,

    somewhere to the first living beings that could feel could feel pain and pleasure, want and

    fear, could experience sensations of light, sound or odors. The mainstream view sees this

    radical development as being conditioned by the evolution of neurological behavior control

    systems in co-evolutionary development with more capable sensory systems. Consciousness

    thus emerged as a product of increasing biological complexity, from non-conscious precursors

    composed of non-conscious components. Here we can raise many of the central questions

    within the problem of consciousness. Imagine we were alien exo-biologists observing the Earth

    around the time of the emergence of consciousness. How would we know that certain

    organisms were, while other organisms were not, conscious? What is it about the conscious

    organisms that explain why they are conscious? Furthermore, the appearance of conscious

    beings looks to be a development that sharply distinguishes them from their precursors, but thematerial processes of evolution are not marked by such radical discontinuities. To be sure, we

    do find striking differences amongst extant organisms. The unique human use of language is

    perhaps the best example of such a difference, but of course the apes exhibit a host of related,

    potentially precursor abilities, as do human beings who lack full language use. Thus we have

    possible models of at least some aspects of our pre-linguistic ancestors which suggest the

    evolutionary path that led to language. But the slightest, most fleeting, spark of feeling is a fully

    fledged instance of consciousness which entirely differentiates its possessor from the realm ofthe non-conscious. Note here dissimilarity to other biological features. Some creatures have

    wings and others do not, and we would expect that in the evolution from wingless to winged

    there would be a hazy region where it just would not be clear whether or not a certain

    creatures appendages would count as wings or not. Similarly, as we consider the evolutionary

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    10/47

    10 | P a g e

    advance from non-conscious to conscious creatures, there would be a range for which we

    would be unclear about whether or not creatures within that range were conscious or not. But

    in this latter case, there is a fact whether or not the creatures in that range are feeling anything,

    however dimly or weakly whereas we do not think there must be a fact about whether a

    certain appendage is or is not a wing (a dim or faint feeling is 100% a kind of consciousness but

    a few feathers on a forelimb is not a kind of wing). It is up to us whether to count a certain sort

    of appendage as a wing or not it makes no difference, so to speak, to the organism what we

    call it. But it is not up to us to decide whether or not organism X does or does not enjoy some

    smidgen of consciousnessit either does or it does not.

    Lurking behind these relatively empirical questions is a more basic theoretical, or metaphysical,

    issue. Given that creatures capable of fairly complex behavior were evolving without

    consciousness, why is consciousness necessary for the continued evolution of more complex

    behavior? Just as wings are an excellent solution to the problem of evolving flight, brains (or

    more generally nervous systems) are wonderful at implementing richly capable sensory systems

    and co-ordinate behavior control systems. But why should these brains be conscious? Although

    perhaps of doubtful coherence, its useful to try to imagine our alien biologists as non-

    conscious beings. Perhaps they are advanced machines well programmed in deduction,

    induction and abduction. Now, why would they ever posit consciousness in addition to, or as a

    feature of, complex sensory and behavioral control systems? As Thomas Huxley said: how it is

    that anything so remarkable as a state of consciousness comes about as a result of irritating

    nervous tissue, is just as unaccountable as the appearance of Djin when Aladdin rubbed his

    lamp (1866, 8, 210). We might, rather fancifully, describe this core philosophical question

    about consciousness as that of how the genie of consciousness gets into the lamp of the brain,

    or why, to use Thomas Nagels famous phrase, there is something it is like to be a conscious

    entity?

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    11/47

    11 | P a g e

    THE ANCIENT AGE OF HUMAN CONSCIOUSNESS

    Of course, the mainstream view has not long been mainstream, for the problem of

    consciousness cannot strike one at all until a fairly advanced scientific understanding of theworld permits development of the materialism presupposed by the mainstream view. A second

    necessary condition is simply the self-recognition that we are conscious beings possessing a

    host of mental attributes. And that has been around for a long time. Our ancestors initiated a

    spectacular leap in conceptual technology by devising what is nowadays called folk

    psychology. The development of the concepts of behavior explaining states such as belief and

    desire, motivating states of pleasure and pain, and information laden states of perceptual

    sensation as well as the complex links amongst these concepts is perhaps the greatest piece of

    theorizing ever produced by human beings.

    An important part of ancient Greek culture was the mystery cults, into which many Greek

    philosophers were initiated. Out of this cultural milieu developed a philosophical tradition that

    was hylozoistic, conceiving of nature as animated or alive; ontological, inquiring into the very

    essence of things; and monistic, seeking to find a single principle to explain all phenomena.

    Now, we will explore the theories of mind and consciousness promulgated by the ancient

    philosophers. Note that their teachings consistently emphasized a unity between the goals of

    philosophy and the practices of living. Numbers were thus seen as a principle that linked the

    symbolic properties of the mind with the mechanisms of the universe. It is precisely this

    Pythagorean notion that forms the backbone of the theoretical models of consciousness. For

    the most ancient of all philosophical-scientific traditions relating consciousness and reality may

    yet prove the most fruitful. If so, it would not be the first time that Pythagorean concepts have

    demonstrated extraordinarily penetrating insights. Pythagoras was the first to suggest that the

    earth was a spherical planet orbiting the sun. The origin of human consciousness was

    understood in the context of this astronomy.

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    12/47

    12 | P a g e

    A great concern for exploring consciousness is expressed in the works of Plato, who was a

    student of Socrates. Plato maintains that the world of ideas itself is just as real as the world of

    objects, and that it is through ideas that humanity attains consciousness of the absolute.

    A fruitful way to present the history is in terms of a fundamental divergence in thought that

    arose early and has not yet died out in current debate. This is the contrast between emergence

    and panpsychism. The mainstream view accepts emergence: mind or consciousness appeared

    out of non-conscious precursors and non-conscious components (note there is both a

    synchronic and diachronic sense of emergence). Panpsychism is the alternative view that

    emergence is impossible and mind must be already and always present, in some sense,

    throughout the universe (a panpsychist might allow that mind emerges in the trivial sense that

    the universe may have been created out of nothing and hence out of non -consciousness; the

    characteristically panpsychist position here would be that consciousness must have been

    created along with whatever other fundamental features of the world were put in place at the

    beginning). Of course, this divergence transcends the mind-body problem and reflects a

    fundamental difference in thinking about how the world is structured.

    I. The Pre-Socratics:The Pre-Socratics immediately recognized the basic dilemma: either mind (or, more generally,

    whatever the apparently macroscopic, high-level, or non-fundamental property at issue) is an

    elemental feature of the world or it somehow emerges from, or is conditioned by, such

    features. If one opts for emergence, it is incumbent upon one to at least sketch the means by

    which new features emerge. If one opts for panpsychism (thus broadly construed) then one

    must account for the all too obviously apparent total lack of certain features at the

    fundamental level. For example, Anaxagoras (c. 500-425 BC) flatly denied that emergence was

    possible and instead advanced the view that everything is in everything. Anaxagoras explained

    the obvious contrary appearance by a principle of dominance and latency which asserted that

    some qualities were dominant in their contribution to the behavior and appearance of things.

    However, Anaxagoras views on mind are complex since he apparently regarded it as uniquely

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    13/47

    13 | P a g e

    not containing any measure of other things and thus not fully in accord with his mixing

    principles. Perhaps this can be interpreted as the assertion that mind is ontologically

    fundamental in a special way; Anaxagoras did seem to believe that that everything has some

    portion of mind in it while refraining from the assertion that everything has a mind.

    On the other hand, Empedocles, an almost exact contemporary of Anaxagoras, favored an

    emergents account based upon the famous doctrine of the four elements: earth, air, fire and

    water. All qualities were to be explicated in terms of ratios of these elements. The overall

    distribution of the elements, which were themselves eternal and unchangeable, was controlled

    by love and strife, whose operations are curiously reminiscent of some doctrines of modern

    thermodynamics, in a grand cyclically dynamic universe. It is true that Empedocles is sometimes

    regarded as a panpsychist because of the universal role of love and strife, but there seems little

    of the mental in Empedocles conceptions, which are rather more like forces of aggregation and

    dis-aggregation respectively. The purest form of emergent was propounded by the famed

    atomist Democritus. His principle of emergence was based upon the possibility of multi-shaped,

    invisibly tiny atoms interlocking to form infinity of more complex structures. But Democritus,

    in a way echoing Anaxagoras and perhaps hinting at the later distinction between primary and

    secondary properties, had to admit that the qualities of experience (what philosophers

    nowadays call qualia, the subjective features of conscious experience) could not be accounted

    for in this way and chose, ultimately unsatisfactorily, to relegate them to non-existence: sweet

    exists by convention, bitter by convention, in truth only atoms and the void. Sorely missed is

    Democritus accountof how conventions themselves, the consciously agreed upon means of

    common referenceemerge from the dancing atoms (thus the ideas of Democritus anticipate

    the reflexive problem of modern eliminativist materialists. who would enjoin us to consciously

    accept a view which evidently entails that there is no such thing as conscious acceptance of

    views. What is striking about these early struggles about the proper form of a scientific

    understanding of the world is that the mind and particularly consciousness keep rising as

    special problems. It is sometimes said that the mind-body problem is not an ancient

    philosophical issue on the basis that sensations were complacently regarded as bodily

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    14/47

    14 | P a g e

    phenomena, but it does seem that the problem of consciousness was vexing philosophers 2500

    years ago, and in a form redolent of contemporary worries. Also critically important is the way

    that the problem of consciousness inescapably arises within the context of developing an

    integrated scientific view of the world. The reductionist strain in the Pre-Socratics was not

    favored by the two giants of Greek philosophy, Plato and Aristotle, despite their own radical

    disagreements about how the world should be understood. Plato utterly lacked the naturalizing

    temperament of the Pre-Socratic philosophers, although he was well aware of their efforts. He

    explicitly criticizes Anaxagoras efforts to provide naturalistic, causal explanations of human

    behavior.

    Anaxagoras concept of Nous provided one of themost powerful intuitions . . . in the whole

    course of Pre-Socratic philosophy . . . that the [basic] principle is an infinite reality, separate

    from everything else.2

    All things which have life, both the greater and the less, are ruled by mind. Mind took

    command of the universal revolution, so ad to make (things) revolve at the outset. At

    first things began to revolve from some small point, but now the revolution extends

    over a greater area, and will spread even further. And the things which were mixed

    together, and separated off, and divided, were all understood by mind. And whatever

    they were going to be, and whatever things were then in existence that are not now,

    and all things that now exist and whatever shall existall were arranged by mind, as

    also the revolution now followed by the stars, the sun and moon, and the air and aither

    [ether] which were separated off. . . . And nothing is absolutely separated off or divided

    the one from the other except mind. Mind is all alike, both the greater and the less. But

    nothing else is like anything else.3

    2Reale, pp.114.

    3Anaxagoras, Frg. 12; Reale, pp. 114.

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    15/47

    15 | P a g e

    Anaxagoras believed that in everything there is a portion of everything.4Our eyes and other

    senses are too unrefined to see everything.

    II. Platos ContributionOf course, Plato nonetheless has a significant role in the debate since he advances positive

    arguments in favor of the thesis that mind and body are distinct as well as providing a basic,

    and perpetually influential, tri-component based psychological theory (see Republic, Book 4).

    Platos primary motivation for accepting a dualist account of mind and body presumably stems

    from the doctrine of the forms. These are entities which in some way express the intrinsic

    essence of things. The form of circle is that which our imperfect drawings of circles imitate and

    point to. The mind can grasp this form, even though we have never perceived a true circle, butonly more or less imperfect approximations. The ability of the mind to commune with the

    radically non-physical forms suggests that mind itself cannot be physical.

    In the Phaedo, Plato, putting words in the mouth of Socrates, ridicules the reductionist account

    of Anaxagoras which sees human action as caused by local physical events. In its place, the

    mind is proposed as the final (i.e. teleological) cause of action, merely conditioned or

    constrained by the physical:

    If it were said that without such bones and sinews and all the rest of them I should not

    be able to do what I think is right, it would be true. But to say that is because of them

    that I do what I am doing, and not through choice of what is best although my actions

    are controlled by mind would be a very lax and inaccurate form of expression.

    (Phaedo, 98b ff.)

    In general, Platos arguments for dualism are not very convincing. Heres one:

    Life must come from death, because otherwise, since all living things eventually die,

    everything would eventually be dead. Life can come from death only if there is a distinct

    4Anaxagoras, Frg. 11; Burnet, Early Greek Philosophy. Ed. 4

    th(London, 1930) pp.259.

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    16/47

    16 | P a g e

    component, responsible for something being alive, that persists through the life-death-

    life cycle. That persistent component is soul or mind.(Phaedo 72c-d).

    Another argument which Plato frequently invokes (or presupposes in other argumentation) is

    based on reincarnation. If we grant that reincarnation occurs, it is a reasonable inference that

    something persists which is what is reincarnated. This is a big if to modern readers of a

    scientific bent but the doctrine of reincarnation was widespread throughout ancient times and

    is still taken seriously by large numbers of people. The kernel of a much more powerful

    argument for dualism lurks here as well, which was deployed by Descartes much later.

    III.Aristotles conceptionof SoulAristotle is famously much more naturalistically inclined than Plato. But Aristotles views on

    mind are complex and obscure; certainly not straightforwardly reductionist (the soul is not, for

    example, a particularly subtle kind of matter such as fire). Aristotles metaphysics deployed a

    fundamental distinction between matter and form, and any object necessarily instantiates

    both. A statue of a horse has its matter: bronze, and its form: horse. Aristotle is not using

    Platos conception of form here. The form of something is not another-world separate entitybut something more like the way in which the matter of something is organized or structured.

    Nor by matter does Aristotle mean the fundamental physical stuff we refer to by that word;

    matter is whatever relatively unstructured stuff is enformed to make an object (English retains

    something of this notion in its use of matter to mean topic), so bronze is the matter of a

    statue, but soldiers would be the matter of an army. Objects can differ in matter but agree in

    form (two identical pictures, one on paper another on a computer screen) or vice versa. More

    abstractly, Aristotle regarded life as the form of plants and animals and named the form ofliving things soul (the form of a natural body having life potentially within it (De Anima, bk. 2,

    ch. 1). Aristotles views have some affinity both with modern biologys conception of life and

    the doctrine of psycho-physical functionalism insofar as he stresses that soul is not a separate

    thing requiring another ontological realm, but also cannot be reduced to mere matter since the

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    17/47

    17 | P a g e

    essential attribute is function and organization. Yet there are elements of Aristotles account

    that are not very naturalistic.

    Early in the De Anima, Aristotle raises the possibility that the relation between the body and

    the mind is analogous to that between sailor and ship, which would imply that mind, is

    independent of body. Later Aristotle apparently endorses this possibility where he discusses,

    notoriously obscurely, the active intellect the part of the soul capable of rational thought.5

    Aristotle clearly states that the active intellect is separable from body and can exist without it.

    For Aristotle, like Plato, the problematic feature of mind was its capacity for abstract thought

    and not consciousness per se, although of course these thinkers were implicitly discussing

    conscious thought and had no conception of mind apart from consciousness. Discussion of one

    particular, and highly interesting if perennially controversial, feature of consciousness can

    perhaps be traced to Aristotle. This is the self-intimating or self- representing nature of all

    conscious states. Many thinkers have regarded it as axiomatic that one could not be in a

    conscious state without being aware of that state and Aristotle makes some remarks that

    suggest he may belong to this school of thought. For example, in Book Three of De Anima

    Aristotle presents, rather swiftly, the following regress argument: Since we perceive that we

    see and hear, it is necessarily either by means of the seeing that one perceives that one sees or

    by another [perception]. But the same [perception] will be both of the seeing and of the color

    that underlies it, with the result that either two [perceptions] will be of the same thing, or it

    (perception) will be of itself. Further, if the perception of seeing is a different (perception),

    either this will proceed to infinity or some (perception) will be of itself; so that we ought to

    posit this in the first instance.

    Aristotles argument appears to be that if it is essential to a conscious state that it be

    consciously apprehended then conscious states must be self-representing on pain of an infinite

    regress of states each representing (and hence enabling conscious apprehension of) the

    previous state in the series. The crucial premise that all mental states must be conscious is

    5De Anima, bk. 3, ch. 4-5

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    18/47

    18 | P a g e

    formally necessary for the regress and modern representational accounts of consciousness

    which accept that conscious states are self-intimating, such as the Higher Order Thought

    theory, can block the regress by positing non-conscious thoughts which make lower order

    thoughts conscious by being about them.

    THESUBSTANTIALIZINGOF THESUBJECT

    In Aristotles hylomorphic account there is no substantial soul or mind. Th e human

    being is a special kind of organism, a rational animal; and what we now refer to as the

    mind is the range of capacities an organism of that kind is goof for. In Aristotelian

    terms the human soul id the form of the matter that has these capacities, and the

    capacities themselves, and so also the soul, can be witnessed both by observers and by

    the organisms themselves with no special privilege attached to the point of view of

    those actually exercising them.6

    According to Aristotle things exist according to some pattern, some form. The Greek term for

    soul is psyche, and we get the term psychology from it. For Aristotle, soul is the form of the

    body. Just as we cannot even imagine a soul going to Atlanta without a body, so too, once body

    is not a human being without a human soul, in Aristotles view.

    Soul is entelechy. For Aristotle, it is impossible to affect the body without affecting the soul or

    to a fact the soul without affecting the body. There is no way to reach the soul except through

    the bodily organs (including the brain/mind), and there is no way for the soul to act or

    communicate except bodily. Recently, some scientists have lent support to the view that the

    mind plays a role in a altering the course of various autoimmune diseases, that laughter and

    positive attitude has healing power. Such idea reflects Aristotles insistence on the organic,

    holistic, inseparable union of body and the natural soul. African, Amazonian, Native American

    6Alastair Hannay, Human Consciousness(Great Britain: George Allen & Unwin Ltd., 1970) pp. 21.

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    19/47

    19 | P a g e

    and other tribal cultures have long accepted this as a fact. Human beings are not only besouled

    creatures, and each kind of substance requires a different kind of study.

    A great concern for exploring consciousness is expressed in the works of Plato, who was a

    student of Socrates. Plato maintains that the world of ideas itself is just as real as the world of

    objects, and that it is through ideas that humanity attains consciousness of the absolute. In

    Neoplatonist and Platonian versions, the human being is an independent self, an ego, in touch

    with the spiritual world which is its real home and therefore eternal even when finite.

    The substantializing of the rational faculties is usually associated with Descartes

    dualism, in which (anticipating current trends in cognitive science) the biological, and

    also (it might be claimed) merely psychological, functions are reduced to mechanisms

    belonging to physical substance, while the human spirit, the specifically human soul,

    becomes the thinker of potentially rational thoughts, which if concerned with rational

    ends must then be transformed by will into action against the weight of natural

    disinclination. Notes pg. 22 top

    Descartes was one of the dangerous philosophers in philosophical tradition whose impact

    remained imprinted on after generations. Cartesian dualism refers to Descartes statement that

    human beings are a mysterious union of mind (soul) and body, of incorporeal substance and

    corporeal substance, with each realm operating according to separate sets of laws. The mind is

    independent and free, except it follows the laws of reason. Where, the body is governed but

    the laws of physics and falls under the rule of cause and effect: the human body is no freer than

    any other material thing. The soul is somehow scattered to all parts of the body but, according

    to Descartes, thinking enters the brain through the pineal gland.

    And as a clock composed of wheels and counter-weights no less exactly observes the

    laws of nature if I consider the body of a man as being a sort of machine so built up

    and composed of nerves, muscles, veins, blood, and skin, that though there were no

    mind in it at all, it would not cease to have made the same motions as a present,

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    20/47

    20 | P a g e

    exception being made of those movements which are due to the direction of the will,

    and in consequence depends upon the mind.7

    We can understand thinking without ever referring to the body, and we can understand the

    body without ever referring to the mind/soul. So, Descartes concluded, minds and bodies are

    essentially independent of each other. Science can study bodies and the natural world without

    ever get involved in theology.

    Initially, this rationale seems satisfactory. Overall, it fits the common sense view of Christian

    theology and ordinary experience. Cartesian dualism allows for the doctrine of the souls

    continued existence after the death of the body. Further, Descartes defined himself as a

    thinking substance rather than corporeal, he reaffirms the primacy of the soul over the body.

    So, the conclusion is drawn that human beings are essentially spiritual beings who happen to

    inhabit bodies. As a scientist, he gave a great contribution and freed science to progress

    without church interference, since scientific discoveries are about the body and have no real

    interest on the nature of the soul.

    I. The Mind-Body ProblemDualism generates one of the most tenacious timeless (and timely) questions: what is therelationship of the mind to the body? This issue has been very appealing to philosophers,

    psychologists, and most of the rest of us. The contemporary philosopher Gilbert Ryle refers this

    issue, in his influential and controversial book The Concept of Mind, as the official doctrine.

    Ryle says:

    The official doctrine, which hails chiefly from Descartes, is something like this. With the

    doubtful exceptions of idiots and infants in arms every human being has both a body

    and a mind. Some would prefer to say that every human being is both a body and a

    7Descartes, Meditation VI, in Philosophical Works, vol. 1, p. 185.

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    21/47

    21 | P a g e

    mind. His body and his mind are ordinarily harnessed together, but after the death of

    the body, his mind may continue to exist and function.8

    Versions of the official doctrine are obvious in beliefs about the immortality of the soul and

    reincarnation. It is implicit in psychological theories that the mind is something other than the

    brain, and that differentiate mental states from bodily conditions and behavior. It is also

    reflected in our ordinary language when we feel as if we are somehow in our bodies.

    Dualism seems consistent with certain common experiences, but inconsistent with others. For

    instance, if I hit my thumb with a hammer, I experience no mind-body separation. Yet there are

    serious consequences if we reject dualism in favor of a materialistic or behavioristic monism.

    The fact that millions of people believe something does not make it real or true. Cartesian

    dualism stands in direct opposition to another major modern philosophical archetype i.e. the

    skeptical questioner who turns to experience rather than to the mind for knowledge.

    Critical Analysis

    The dualist might respond that the problem of how an immaterial substance can cause physical

    events is not much obscurer than the problem of how one physical event can cause another.

    Yet there is an important difference: there are many clear cases of physical causation but notone clear case of nonphysical causation. Physical interaction is something philosophers, like all

    other people, have to live with. Nonphysical interaction, however, may be no more than an

    artifact of the immaterialist construal of the mental. Most philosophers now agree that no

    argument has successfully demonstrated why mind-body causation should not be regarded as a

    species of physical causation.

    Dualism is also incompatible with the practices of working psychologists. The psychologist

    frequently applies the experimental methods of the physical sciences to the study of the mind.

    If mental processes were different in kind from physical processes, there would be no reason to

    8Gilbert Ryle, The Concept of Mind(New York: Harper & Row, 1941), p.11.

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    22/47

    22 | P a g e

    expect these methods to work in the realm of the mental. In order to justify their experimental

    methods many psychologists urgently sought an alternative to dualism.

    II. Consciousness as Self-awarenessLockes notion of consciousness is that of the minds reflective awareness of its own

    operations (perceiving, thinking, doubting, believing, reasoning, knowing, willing, etc.).

    This can be labeled the minds self-awareness. Notes pg. 22 end

    Consciousness, however, has become a rather ambiguous term in its everyday usage. It can

    refer to: (1) a waking state; (2) experience; and (3) the possession of any mental state. It may

    be helpful to the reader to provide an example of each of these three usages: (1) the injured

    worker fall into unconsciousness; (2) the criminal became conscious of a terrible sense of dread

    at the thought of being apprehended; and (3) I am conscious of the fact that sometimes I hurt

    your feelings. Anthony OHear, in his book, Beyond Evolution: Human Nature and the Limits of

    Evolutionary Explanation, suggested:

    In being conscious of myself as myself, I see myself as separate from what is not

    myself. In being conscious, a being reacts to the world with feeling, with pleasure and

    pain, and responds on the basis of felt needs.... Consciousness involves reacting to

    stimuli and feeling stimuli.

    Notice how often consciousness seems to be tied to awareness (or self-consciousness to

    self-awareness)? Theres a reason for that: the two frequently are used interchangeably in

    the scientific and philosophical literature.

    Consciousness refers to your individual awareness of your unique thoughts, memories, feelings,

    sensations and environment. Your conscious experiences are constantly shifting and changing.

    For example, in one moment you may be focused on reading this article. Your consciousness

    may then shift to the memory of a conversation you had earlier with a co-worker. Next, you

    might notice how uncomfortable your chair is or maybe you are mentally planning dinner. This

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    23/47

    23 | P a g e

    ever-shifting stream of thoughts can change dramatically from one moment to the next, but

    your experience of it seems smooth and effortless.

    In Hegels Geist,Kierkegaards Aand, implicitly in Heideggers Dasein, and according to

    Heidegger himself explicitly in Husserl, the reflexivity of the human mind is the notion of

    the human spirit (and in Kierkegaards case the self), which in general is the ability of

    the human being or mind to come up with specifications of its own nature; that is self-

    understandings in the form of appraisals of the overall standing or worth of its own

    mental and practical operations, in Kierkegaards case not least the worth of its

    volitions.9

    In general, consciousness as self-awareness here forms a definitive crack in the causal structure

    of nature. The self-conscious subject is represented as a substance aware of its changing modes

    and therefore somehow separated from them. In rationalist versions, the selfs repertoire

    includes the ability also to subject its own response patterns to control from above in the form

    of freely adopted principles, values, or goals which then govern the overall performance in a

    way that raises the subject above the deterministic influence of natural laws.

    9Alastair Hannay, Human Consciousness(Great Britain: George Allen & Unwin Ltd., 1970) pp. 23.

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    24/47

    24 | P a g e

    THEINTERNALIZINGOF THEOBJECT

    I. Lockes Egocentric predicamentLocke holds a position known as epistemological dualism. According to his view, knowing

    contains two distinct aspects: the knower and the known. The basic empiricist argument that all

    knowledge comes from our own ideas, which in turn are based on our own sensations and

    perceptions, epistemological dualism presents us with a fundamental problem: If all knowledge

    comes from my own ideas which are based on sense data, how can I verify the existence of

    anything external to the sensations that constitute sense data?

    This problem has been termed as Lockes Egocentric predicament because Lockes copy theoryseems to put us in the egocentric position of being able to know only a word of our own mental

    construction, a self- limited world. If there is no external world, can be there be any mind

    other than my own? How could I know? How could I distinguish another mind from my own, if

    all I ever know are my own subjective perceptions?

    And if, as Locke suggest, all true ideas are based on sense data that correspond to something

    else, how can we ever verify the objective, independent existence of an external reality? How

    can we ever apply Lockes own standards of verification to his notion of primary qualities?

    At this point, it seems as if all I can know are my own perceptions (i.e. secondary qualities). As

    soon as I am aware of them, I have labeled and organized them. That is, even if external objects

    exist, the process of perceiving sense data is a process of becoming aware of my own ideas. I

    dont ever seem to be able to actually experience thing themselves. If, as Locke claims , my

    ideas are messages from my senses, how can I, or anyone, verify that the messages come

    from independently existing things? Locke himself asks, How shall the mind, when it perceivesnothing but its own ideas, no that they agree with things themselves?

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    25/47

    25 | P a g e

    Locke tries to avoid the egocentric predicament by asserting that we somehow know that

    mental and physical substances and an objective external reality exist. We just dont have a

    clear idea of the difference between mind and bodies or other aspects of ultimate reality:

    Sensation convinces us that there are solid extended substances [matter and bodies];

    and reflection that there are thinking once [minds, souls], experience assures us of the

    existence of such beings; and that once has the power to move body my impulse, the

    other by though; this we cannot have any doubt of. Experience, I say, every moment

    furnishes us with clear ideas both of one and of the other. But beyond these ideas, as

    received from their proper sources, our faculties will not reach.10

    In other words, Locke holds on to both a commonsense view of reality and his copy theory of

    truth, even though he cannot verify either by appealing to the copy theory.

    II. Descartes and Locke:In spite of his major differences with Descartes, he draws surprisingly similar conclusions for

    similar reasons. Both Locke and Descartes shied away from pursuing the logical consequences

    of their basic premises. Descartes was able to establish the momentary certainty of the cogito

    but had difficulty moving beyond his own mind when he attempted to provide a certainfoundation for the external world and Gods existence. Locke was able to demonstrate the

    importance of experience as an element of knowledge and show that many of our ideas are

    based on sensation and experience. He was also able to show the inadequacy of pure reason as

    a foundation for all knowledge. But, like Descartes, he was unable to move from direct

    knowledge of his own ideas to direct knowledge of external reality.

    Pursued to its logical conclusion, Lockes empiricism does not seem to end in the egocentric

    predicament. If it does, not only are we denied knowledge of an external, independent reality,

    we are denied the possibility of knowing God, for what simple sensations and experiences can

    10John Locke, The Art of Medicine (a paper written in 1669), quoted in Fox Bourne, vol.1 p, 224, and John Locke,

    An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. A.C. Fraser (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1894), bk. 2, ch. 23, sec. 29.

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    26/47

    26 | P a g e

    there be on which the idea of God rests? Locke chose, in the end, to affirm certain beliefs at the

    expense of philosophical consistency.

    THE DISTANTIATING OF THE SUBJECT FROM ITS MENTAL MODES

    I. Experience Is the Origin of All IdeasAccording to Locke, all ideas originate in sensation and reflection. He says we can think about

    things only after we have experiences them. In other words, all ideas originate from sense data.

    For example, according to this theory no one born blind can ever have an idea of color. Those of

    us who are sighted the idea of color in abstraction from specific sense data by reflecting on, for

    instance red, green, yellow and blue circles. In doing so, we note that they have two commonqualities, circularity and color. Our blind friend can trace their shape, and thus acquire

    sensation of circulation, but color, which is only perceived through sight, will remain unknown

    to him.

    As part of his empirical inquiry into the nature of human understanding, Locke attempted to

    explain and classify different kinds of ideas and the ways we combine and reorganize sense

    data from simple into increasing complex and abstract ideas. He insisted that all ideas are

    copies of the things that caused the basic sensations on which they rest. Ideas, then, are less

    intense copies or images of sensations. Your idea, for example, of a pen is a copy of the set of

    sensations and impressions you have received from seeing and handling actual pen. If your idea

    of a pen includes the shape of a cube, it is a poor copy because it does not correspond to

    reality.

    This position known as the copy theory or representation theory, or, most recently,

    correspondence theory of truth, a term attributed to contemporary philosopher BertrandRussell. The correspondence theory of truth is a truth test that holds that an idea (or belief or

    thought) is true if whatever it refers to actually exist. In other words, an idea is defined as true

    if it corresponds to a fact. The producer for checking the truth of an idea is called confirmation

    or verification.

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    27/47

    27 | P a g e

    Favored by empiricist, the correspondence theory if truth is in direct contrast with the

    coherence theory of truth favored by rationalist and differs from the other major truth theory,

    the pragmatic theory of truth.

    Lets see what happened when Locke applied his empirical truth test to one of the foundations

    of continental rationalism, innate ideas- ideas that by their very nature are not copies of

    external experience.

    Leibnitz felt that all matter is alive and animated throughout with monads. The monad is the

    principle of continuity between the physical and the psychological realms. The same principle

    that expresses itself within our minds is active in inanimate matter, in plants, and in animals.

    Thus the nature of the monad is best understood by studying the spiritual and psychic forceswithin ourselves.

    Monads themselves vary in the amount of consciousness or clarity of their perceptions. Certain

    physical facts, such as the principle of least action, indicated to Leibnitz intelligence within the

    most basic particles in creation. On the other hand, the findings of psychology have indicated

    that there are areas of the mind that are unconscious in their nature. In the lowest monads

    everything is obscure and confused, resembling sleep. While in humanity, consciousness attains

    a state of apperception -- a reflexive knowledge of the self.

    II. GEORGE BERKLEY: To be is to be PerceivedFrom a commonsense point of view it may seem absurd to seem the existence of a material

    world, but Berkley pointed out that on closer examination it makes more sense to deny the

    existence of matter than it does to affirm it. Taking empiricism a logical step further than Locke,

    Berkley argues that the material world doesnt exist. Only ideas exist, and ideas are mentalstates, not material objects. This makes Berkley an idealist or immaterialist: the idea of the

    matter existing without mental properties is self-contradictory, for this there is no way to

    conceive of what an unperceived, inexperience existence would consist of. We can conceive of

    things only in terms of perceptions (ideas) we have of them.

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    28/47

    28 | P a g e

    Berkley challenged Lockes copy theory of truth by pointing out that the so-called objects Locke

    thought our ideas correspond to lack any fixed nature. They are constantly changing. There is

    no thing to copy, Berkley said, only a cluster of constantly changing perception:

    [Some hold that] real thing, it is plain, have a fixed and real nature, which remain the

    same notwithstanding any change in our senses or in the posture and motion of our

    bodies; which indeed may affect the ideas in our minds, but it were absurd to think they

    had the same effect on things existing without the mind.

    How then is it possible that things perpetually fleeting and variable as our ideas

    should be copies or images of anything fixed and constant? Or, in other words, since all

    sensible qualities, as figure, size, color, etc., that is, our ideas, are continually changing

    upon every alteration in the distance, medium, or instruments of sensation, how can

    any determinate, material objects be properly represented or painted forth by several

    distinct thing each of which is so different from an unlike the rest? Or if you say it

    resembles someone only of our ideas, how shall we be able to distinguish the true copy

    from all the false once?11

    According to Berkeley, all of .the qualities we assign to material objects are relative to the

    perceiver, what Locke called secondary qualities. For example, the coffee I am drinking is hot

    or cold depending on my perception of it. It is absurd to ask if it is really hot or cold. But, you

    might point out, it has an objective temperature, say 120 degree Fahrenheit. Only, however,

    when someone measures it, that is, only when someone perceives thermometer registering

    120 degrees Fahrenhiet. Even so, youre probably tempted to respond, it does have a certain

    temperature regardless of whether or not someone is aware of it.

    Does it? What kind of temperature is it if no one anywhere is aware of it? We can know things

    only in terms of some perception of them through the senses, or as idead perceived by the

    11George Berkley, Three Dialogues Between Hylas and Philonous, in Selections, ed. Mary W. Calkins (New York:

    Scribners, 1957), pp. 268-269.

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    29/47

    29 | P a g e

    mind. Berkley points out that there is no difference between sound as perceived by us and

    sound as it is itself. We may define sound in terms of what is perceived: sensations,

    atmospheric disturbances, decibels, waves marks on a graph, or whatever, but in all cases

    sound remains something that is perceived.

    Berkley takes the radical, but logically correct step of concluding that this is true of everything.

    We know things only as different kinds of ideas about them. Berkeleian ideas imply

    consciousness, perception. It is self-contradictory to discuss ideas we do not know we have.

    The implications of this position for psychological theories of the unconscious mind: if an

    unconscious mind exists, it can have nothing to do with us. Moods and emotional states like

    guilt or self-hate exist only as we perceive them; they, too, are ideas in Berkeleys sense. When

    we do not perceive them, they do not exist. The notion of an unconscious mind is self-

    contradictory, since by definition a mind is a thinking, perceiving, hence conscious, thing.

    It is equally absurd to posit an independent, external reality, for if it exists, we cannot have

    anything to do with it. If we accept Lockes starting point that all knowledge derives from

    experience, Berkeley reasons, we must conclude that all knowledge is limited to ideas, because

    we experience things only as ideas. So-called material or physical states are perceptions, mental

    acts. Pain is a perception; sweet and sour are perceptions, the moon is a perception; my own

    body is known to me only as a series of perceptions. Esse est percipi: To be is to be perceived.

    Heading

    As for the mind-independent world itself, or Descartes res extensa, the alternatives are

    Berkeleys expedient of dying its existence, Humean skepticism about the existence of

    an external world, or some form of representational theory like Descartes own in which

    mind-independent world is reflected in the individual mind in what would nowadays be

    called a world-model, a construct whose correspondence with reality Descartes himself

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    30/47

    30 | P a g e

    tried to vindicate by logical reasoning from certain premises, famously including the

    certainty that God exists and cannot deceive.12

    Descartes argument is crucial to the Cartesian Genesis. His conception of God as a perfect being

    includes the qualities of all-knowing, all-powerful, all-loving, all-good. Descartes posits that such

    a God would not let him be constantly deceived by either himself or some evil genius. If, the

    argument goes God gave us reason and faculties of perception, they must be basically accurate

    and reliable.

    . . . But, since God is no deceiver, it is very manifest that He does not communicate to

    me these ideas immediately and by Himself. . . . I do not see how He could be defended

    from the accusation of deceit if these ideas were produced by causes other than

    corporeal objects. Hence we must allow that corporeal things exist.13

    Descartes reasoned that his own ideas of body and mind be basically sound, since God allowed

    him to know clearly and distinctly that he is both.

    III.The Skeptical Influence on Human ConsciousnessAccording to Hume, no proof exists in support of cause and effect relationships within the

    universe. This is the case because through habitual observation, one infers a relationship

    between two independent events. Since one cannot experience the necessary connection

    between two events such as, the Law of Gravity, one cannot necessarily prove that event A

    caused event B. Therefore, even though experience and reasoning indicate that objects act in

    a predictable way, this fails to necessarily prove how objects will act in the future based upon

    previous interactions.

    12Alastair Hannay, Human Consciousness(Great Britain: George Allen & Unwin Ltd., 1970) pp. 24.

    13Descartes, Meditation VI, in Philosophical Works, vol. 1, p. 191.

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    31/47

    31 | P a g e

    Hume thought that Locke was correct in claiming that thought is a faithful mirror, and copies

    objects truly. But he reminds us not to overlook a vital fact: the copies are always duller and

    fainter than the original perceptions they are based on.

    Hume proposes that we distinguish ideas from impressions:

    Here therefore we may divide all perceptions of the mind into two classes or species,

    which are distinguished by their different degrees of force and vivacity. The less forcible

    and lively are commonly denominated Thoughts or Ideas. The other species wants a

    name in our language, and most others. . . . Let us, therefore, use a little freedom, and

    call them Impressions;employing that word in a sense somewhat different from usual.

    By the term impression, then, I mean all our more lively perceptions, when we hear, or

    see, or feel, or love, or hate, or desire, or will. And impressions are distinguished from

    ideas, which are the less lively perceptions, of which we are conscious, when we reflect

    on any of those sensations or movements above mentioned.14

    To establish these claims, Hume puts forth the notion that causal relationships belong to two

    types of knowledge: relations of ideas and matters of fact. Relations of ideas refer to a priori

    knowledge, or knowledge learned sans experience. They include anything that may be true by

    definition or discovered by mere thought. In order for anything to represent a relation of ideas,its contrary must be self-contradictory or inconceivable. For example, mathematical truths

    belong in the relations of ideas category because the opposite of 2 + 2 = 4 is inconceivable.

    Additionally, a square could never be circle because it is inconceivable nor could one conceive

    of the contrary to the statement a triangle has three sides. Since relations of ideas are known

    through reason alone, they are vacuous because they do not assert anything about the world.

    While causes and effects may be discoverable by experience, they may not be discoverable by

    reason alone. Every effect is distinct from its cause, and every cause is distinct from its effect.

    14David Hume,An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge (Oxford: Clarendon Press,

    1894), sec. 2.

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    32/47

    32 | P a g e

    Therefore, an effect cannot be discovered in a causal object or event merely by a priori

    reasoning.

    On the contrary, with matters of fact, one may contain certainty, but will not intuitively or

    demonstratively possess it. Matters of fact include a posteriori knowledge, or knowledge

    learned through experience. As such, the contrary of a matter of fact is conceivable and

    represent substantive statements, which are about the world. While one cannot make

    assertions about causal relationships through relations of ideas, matters of fact may account for

    causal relationships based upon experience alone. Since causal relationships are based upon

    ones experience of two independent events, it cannot be known with certainty that event A

    necessarily causes event B. Hume claims that an individual observes two independent events,

    then infers a causal relationship through habitual observation.

    The strengths of Humes theory rest in the fact that experience cannot grasp the causal

    connection, which occurs between event A and event B. One cannot experience the Law of

    Gravity and thus, may only infer that a causal relationship exists. This conclusion opens the

    gates for Skepticism to enter and establishes an astonishing claim that the occurrence of future

    events is never guaranteed. Even the statement the sun will rise tomorrow bears a

    probabilistic claim based on inferred causal events in the past. I think this points to the

    existence of faith within every worldview, for no one can prove with 100% certainty the

    following: causal events, the existence or non-existence of God, or the existence of the external

    world. On the same token, the notion of probability plays a crucial role in philosophy and

    science, so just because one cannot experience certain immaterial/material objects or states of

    affairs does not mean that they do not exist or will not occur. However, Humes causal theory is

    correct in that objectively proving causal relationships remains unsolvable. The answer to this

    dilemma brings up an important weakness of this theory.

    In the end, Hume compared full-blown skepticism to doubting the existence of an external

    reality, pointing out that the issue cannot be settled logically and rationally. No one can actually

    live as a skeptic:

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    33/47

    33 | P a g e

    To whatever length anyone may push his speculative principles of skepticism, he must

    act . . . and live, and converse like other men. . . . It is impossible for him to persevere in

    total skepticism, or make it appear in his conduct for a few hours.15

    The weakness of Humes causal theory lies in the notion that one must not dwell in skepticism

    merely because most truth claims rest upon experience, probabilistic claims, or inductive

    reasoning. When a skeptic such as Hume claims that we cannot objectively prove causal

    relationships, and therefore we should adopt a skeptical outlook, leads Hume into a form of

    dogmatism with this approach. If a skeptic claims we cannot know causal relations merely

    because we cannot experience the connection, does not indicate that the object in question

    does not exist or that we cannot know of its existence. Furthermore, just because one cannot

    prove causal relationships does not mean skepticism reigns above probabilistic reasoning or

    conclusions. I think one can probabilistically know the necessary causal connection when

    understanding scientific evidence. Indeed, a dose of skepticism is always healthy within the

    pursuit of truth however, holding skepticism above probabilistic evidence short changes the

    fact that humanity can arrive at truth about reality without relying upon sense experience.

    THEEMPIRICIZING OF THEMENTAL

    William James praised empiricists for making the Slef an empirical and verifiable thing, but

    complained that they had neglected certain more subtle aspects of the Unity of

    Consciousness In experience itself we have no sense of isolated parts but of indeterminate

    continuity. Moments of consciousness occur to us as continuations of narritives that have

    begun in the past. And because consciousness is a continuous stream, no phase in it can be

    separated entirely from its predecessors and successors.16

    The two states of consciousness are objectively unified when they are directed at the same

    object. For example, when we look at a red ball, we have an experience of redness, and an

    15Hume, Dialogues, parts 10, 11.

    16Alastair Hannay, Human Consciousness(Great Britain: George Allen & Unwin Ltd., 1970) pp. 35.

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    34/47

    34 | P a g e

    experience of circularity. The color experience and the shape experience here are unified in a

    particularly strong way. They are present in my consciousness as directed at a single entity that

    is a ball. The same goes for my experience of a blue car moving down the street. Here I

    experience color, shape, and motion, all of which are unified by being directed at the same

    object. I might even have an auditory experience of the car's engine, and also experience this as

    directed at the same object. So there can be objective unity across different sensory domains.

    For two experiences to be objectively unified, their object need not actually exist. What if I had

    hallucinated a red ball, then my experiences of redness and of circularity will be objectivel

    unified, despite the ball's non-existence. On the other side of the coin, two experiences can be

    experiences of the same object without being objectively unified. I might see a car's shape and

    hear its noise, without anything in my conscious state tying the noise to the car. Perhaps I

    perceive the noise as behind me, coming from some grass cutting machine or anything else. If

    so, the experiences are not objectively unified. For objective unity, what matters is that two

    states are experienced as being directed at a common object.

    The notion of objective unity is closely tied to a central issue in cognitive psychology and

    neurophysiology. When I look at a red square, the color and the shape may be represented in

    different parts of my visual system. But somehow these separate pieces of information are

    brought together so that I experience a single red square, so that I can identity and report a red

    square, and so on. This phenomenon is often referred to as binding, and the question of how it

    is achieved is often referred to as the binding problem.

    Objective unity is an important phenomenon, but it will not be central for our purposes. Where

    objective unity is concerned, the unity thesis is almost certainly false. While some sets of

    experiences are objective unified with each other, it seems that most sets are not. For example,

    my experience of the color of the ball and of the shape of the car is not objective unified, but

    they are experienced as being directed at different objects. My experiences of a bird singing

    and of a sharp pain do not seem to be directed at the same object at all. If so, then objective

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    35/47

    35 | P a g e

    unity cannot unify all of a subject's conscious states. For such a notion of unity, we must look

    elsewhere. Although James wrote:

    I believe that consciousness is the name of a nonentity and has no right to a

    place among first principle, he meant not that the term had no empirical reference but

    that it had come to mean a mere echo, a pure consciousness behind the verifiable

    facts, or, if you like, a kind of medium this side of the facts into which the facts do not

    reach and so lose their verifiability- that one should look instead to its pragmatic

    equivalent in realities of experience.17

    What James meant by pragmatic equivalent in realities of experience is to look for the side of

    reality that works for you. The concept of consciousness is real and penetrated in literature and

    in our lives but it can be verifiable with empirical references, but this doesnt make the

    consciousness issue to lose its importance.

    James believed that these realities could best be captured by introducing the conception of a

    primal stuff, to be called pure experience, so that knowing can easily be explained as a

    particular sort of relation towards one another into which portions of pure experience may

    enter, and where the relation itself is a part of the experience.-pg. 35 second para

    The notion of "pure experience" is one of the most intriguing and simultaneously perplexing

    features of William James's writings. There seems to be little consensus in the secondary

    literature as to how to understand this notion, and precisely what function it serves within the

    overall structure of James's thought. Yet James himself regards this idea as the cornerstone of

    his radical empiricism. And the latter, James felt, was his unique contribution to the history of

    philosophy; he believed that philosophy "was on the eve of a considerable rearrangement"

    when his essay "A World of Pure Experience" was first published in 1904.

    17Alastair Hannay, Human Consciousness(Great Britain: George Allen & Unwin Ltd., 1970) pp.35.

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    36/47

    36 | P a g e

    I. James on Pure ExperienceThe starting point of James's thought is a deeply, though not exclusively empirical concern. His

    work as a whole is founded upon a consideration of concrete experience means the world as

    experienced by an embodied, embedded, and acting agent. The "pre-philosophic" attitude

    through which we initially face the world is captured in James's development of the concept of

    "pure experience" as the foundation of his radical empiricism.

    James's version of radical empiricism therefore looks to ground his empirical philosophy on the

    raw material of experience as given. Of this methodological principle he writes:

    "The postulate is that the only things that shall be debatable among philosophers shall be

    things definable in terms drawn from experience."18

    With his distinctive notion of pure experience, James looked to investigate what he perceived

    to be the underlying experiential unity behind language and reflective or conceptual thought.

    James argued that conceptual analysis could never provide an exhaustive account of human

    experience in its phenomenal richness. James insists that many of our basic experiences harbor

    non-conceptual content. That is, many of our experiences have a rich phenomenal content that

    is too fine-grained and sensuously detailed to lend itself to an exhaustive conceptual analysis.For example, we can have visual experiences of colors and shapes of things for which we lack

    the relevant concepts (a previously unfamiliar shade of magenta or a chiliagon). And this ability

    holds for other sensory modalities as well. For our ability to describe or report a wide-range of

    tastes and smells lags far behind our capacity to actually have an experience of a nearly infinite

    spectrum of tastes and smells. In other words, the deliverances of our senses continually run

    ahead of both our descriptive vocabularies as well as our conceptual abilities. Though James

    does not address the notion of non-conceptual content as explicitly as many contemporaryphilosophers of mind, and furthermore, it's not clear that he's entirely consistent on this point.

    18James, Pragmatism, and Four Essays from the Meaning of Truth, ed. Ralph Barton Perry (New York: Meridian

    Books, 1955), p. 199.

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    37/47

    37 | P a g e

    II. The Paradox of Consciousness

    The conscious human mind is capable of great good and equally extraordinary evil. It is only for

    the sake of simplicity that we talk of levels in the form of tiers with an upward hierarchy. In fact,

    consciousness, while rooted in causal linearity (within the Darwinian evolutionary framework) is

    dynamic, free moving and nonlinear. The greatest discoveries and inventions were arrived at

    intuitively. The genius sees what we all see except that s/he thinks about it differently. The evil

    genius does exactly the same.

    Kierkegaard says: "The supreme paradox of all thought is the attempt to discover something

    that thought cannot think." A conscious human knows something and he knows that he knows

    it (ad infinitum). The paradox of consciousness is not that we are aware of ourselves but of

    other things as well, including those that do not constitute the 'real world'. Of course, when we

    'conceive' or imagine something 'unreal' even our farthest imagination cannot transcend

    'known' symbolism, which is why there are some things that defy definition. One of these is

    'consciousness' itself.

    III.The Objectivity of ExperienceIn very simple terms, Kants complex project attempts to show that experience is possible only

    under the certain general condition, objectivity. In other word, if there is to be any experience

    at all(if we can experience anything), then, Kant argues, the world must be objective relative

    to the perceiver. There must be a real distinction between how the world seems to me and how

    the world is in order for me to have any experience at all.19

    Crudely put, if there were no difference between the world and me, I could not even have an

    idea of having an experience. But I do have experience. Indeed, the skeptical argument of

    whom only make sense if whom (or any skeptic) understands that he has experience. but

    19Roger Scruton, The Rationalists and Kant, in Philosophy: A Guide Through The Subject, ed. A. C. Grayling

    (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995), p. 475.

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    38/47

    38 | P a g e

    experience itself presuppose precisely what the skeptic doubts: his own independent

    experience as a unified, continuing self that is part of an objective order, subject to causal

    laws.20

    Although commentators on Kant understandably disagree over the precise nature of his

    argument here, the disagreement seems to center on the concept of the self, which Kant calls

    the transcendental unity of apperception. This is the unity of self that allows me to say (and

    experience) that this thought or this sensation belongs to me, belongs to one thing, belongs to

    a unity that exist prior to any empirical verification. For Kant, such a transcendental unity of

    apperception is necessary in order for me to have any experience- and, of course, without me

    the whole world ceases to exist.

    And this awareness of transcendental unity is possible because I am aware of my own existence

    and identity through time. And I can only be aware of my identity through time because I

    situate or locate myself in a world of actually existing things, things that endure through time.

    Thus, these things have the capacity to be other than I perceive them. That is, they are not

    merely my perception. Thus, they must exist objectively.

    Kant himself is inconsistent in his treatment of the noumenal world and regulative ideas,

    sometimes talking about them as mental construct and other times suggesting they are existing

    entities. Thats not surprising either, since, if he is correct, the human need for unity and

    transcendence is very strong. One defense of Kants inconsistencies might be the force and

    power of regulative ideas. They may not give us new empirical knowledge, but they allow us to

    meet our persistent metaphysical longings for an ordered, objective world.

    One of the great weaknesses of the strictest empirical theories of knowledge is that by ruling

    out knowledge of the existence of God, mind (soul), and other transcendental metaphysical

    20Roger Scruton, The Rationalists and Kant, in Philosophy: A Guide Through The Subject, ed. A. C. Grayling

    (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995), p. 475-476.

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    39/47

    39 | P a g e

    believes, they fail to satisfy deep, nearly universal needs. they are sometimes said to rob live of

    its specialness or mystery. Kant deserves credit for recognizing and respecting these needs, and

    for offering a rigorous and sustained explanation and defense of the kind of thinking that

    springs from them. Of course, longing for something to be true does not mean that it is true.

    And as philosophers, we do not want to accept as true whatever be deeply long for just

    because we long for it. So the timeless questions remain.

    IV.Transcendental IdeasKant theorized that neither reason by itself nor sensation by itself can give us knowledge of the

    external world. Knowledge is the result of the interaction between the mind and sensation.

    Knowledge and experience are shaped, structured or formed by special regulative ideas calledcategories. This theory is known as Kantian formalism, or Kantian idealism, or transcendental

    idealism.

    Kant noted that Descartes principal error began with a failure to understand scientific method.

    Galileo had changed science by establishing a common plan of procedure, a method for

    studying phenomena. Thought Descartes had understood the importance of method, he had

    not fully understood that the scientific method is both empirical and rational. Kant realized that

    the empiricist were guilty of a similar error of incompleteness by discounting the importance of

    reason. Knowledge, as the scientific method shows, consist of both a rational and perceptual

    (empirical) component. It requires both a subject (a knowing mind) and an object (that which is

    known).

    The common believe during Kants time, however, was that truth occurs when ideas in the

    mind agree with external conditions or objects, the copy theory.21

    For example, if I think this

    book has a red cover, my idea is true if the cover actually is red. But as Kant realized, if allknowledge fits that model, we could never discover general laws of nature. We could discover

    21John Locke, The Art of Medicine (a paper written in 1669), quoted in Fox Bourne, vol.1 p, 224, and John Locke,

    An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. A.C. Fraser (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1894), bk. 2, ch. 23, sec. 29.

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    40/47

    40 | P a g e

    only that this apple falls, not that all bodies are subject to gravity, because we never experience

    all bodies. Hume understood this but was willing to limit the domain of knowledge the

    particulars, in the end asserting that we could only believe in the most important aspects of our

    experience: the regularity of experience, the existence of an external world, the experience of a

    unified self, cause and effect, and a moral order.

    If we accept Humes initial premises, his conclusions follow. However, close inspection of the

    way science is actually done shows that scientists make precisely the kinds of generalization

    Humes theory says we cannot make. As Kantpointed out, when a theory results in conclusions

    that are clearly in consistent with experience, real-world evidence must outweigh theoretical

    consistency. And everyday experience shows that knowledge of causes and effects, the external

    world, the self, and so on exist.

    The scientific method is obviously more reliable and complete than Humes philosophy. How do

    they differ? Kant pointed out that scientific thinking involves the activity of asking questions

    and framing hypotheses. It is not merely the passive recording of whatever happens; it requires

    the active setting up of controlled experimental conditions.22

    And this suggests that knowledge

    is a kind of interaction, a two-way street between the knower (the subject) and the known (the

    object).

    Hume has insisted that all knowledge begins in experience with sense impressions. But Hume

    confused knowledge that is triggered by experience with knowledge that is based on

    experience. Kant raised the possibility that our faculty of knowledge (mind, for short)might at

    something to the raw data of experience Because experience triggers and hence accompanies

    all knowledge, we may fail to notice the effects the mind has on experience:

    But thought all our knowledge begins with experience, it does not follow that it all arises

    out of our experience. For it may well be the even our empirical knowledge is made up

    of what we receive through impressions and of what our own faculty of knowledge

    22See Jones, Kant and the Nineteenth Century,pg. 19ff.

  • 7/22/2019 On the Account for Human Consciousness

    41/47

    41 | P a g e

    (sensible knowledge serving merely as the occasion) supplies from itself. If our faculty of

    knowledge makes a


Recommended