+ All Categories
Home > Documents > On the way to Socially Responsible Restructuring

On the way to Socially Responsible Restructuring

Date post: 10-Dec-2015
Category:
Upload: api-295309507
View: 13 times
Download: 1 times
Share this document with a friend
Description:
"An Ethical Investigation into some of the Moral Dimensions of Corporate Downsizing" Thesis in the context of the "Master of Advanced Studies in Applied Ethics" at the University of Zurich (class of 2007)
Popular Tags:
42
1 Ethik-Zentrum der Universität Zürich "On the way to Socially Responsible Restructuring” “An Ethical Investigation into some of the Moral Dimensions of Corporate Downsizing” Diplomarbeit Im Rahmen des Nachdiplomstudiengangs 2005 – 2007 Master of Advanced Studies in Applied Ethics (MAE) von Arturo Giovanoli Josefstrasse 176 8005 Zurich January 19, 2007 Erstgutachter: PD Dr. Stefan Grotefeld Zweitgutachter: Prof. Dr. Peter Schaber Tutor: lic. theol. Stefan Gruden
Transcript

1

Ethik-Zentrum der Universität Zürich

"On the way to Socially Responsible Restructuring” “An Ethical Investigation into some of the Moral Dimensions

of Corporate Downsizing”

Diplomarbeit

Im Rahmen des Nachdiplomstudiengangs 2005 – 2007 Master of Advanced Studies in Applied Ethics (MAE)

von

Arturo Giovanoli Josefstrasse 176

8005 Zurich

January 19, 2007

Erstgutachter: PD Dr. Stefan Grotefeld

Zweitgutachter: Prof. Dr. Peter Schaber

Tutor: lic. theol. Stefan Gruden

2

Table of contents

PREFACE .................................................................................................................................. 1

1. Downsizing in context............................................................................................................ 2

1.1 The Economic Environment - An Overview.................................................................... 2 1.2 On Restructuring .............................................................................................................. 2 1.3 On Downsizing................................................................................................................. 4 1.3.1 The Impact of Downsizing on Employees ............................................................ 6 1.3.2 Crisis Management and Downsizing..................................................................... 7 1.3.3 Downsizing Strategies........................................................................................... 8

1.3.3.1 Alternatives to Downsizing Strategies ...................................................... 9 1.4 Conclusion...................................................................................................................... 10

2. Ethical Considerations of Downsizing................................................................................. 12

2.1 Introduction .................................................................................................................... 12 2.2 Socially Responsible Restructuring ............................................................................... 12

2.2.1 Definitions of Corporate Social Responsibility .................................................. 13 2.3 The Theories of Social Responsibility ........................................................................... 14

2.3.1 The Stockholder Theory...................................................................................... 14 2.3.2 The Stakeholder Theory ...................................................................................... 16 2.3.3 Stockholder and Stakeholder Theories on Downsizing ...................................... 18

2.4 The Aspects of Corporate Downsizing .......................................................................... 19 2.4.1 Property Rights.................................................................................................... 19 2.4.2 Fiduciary Duties .................................................................................................. 21 2.4.3 Risk...................................................................................................................... 23 2.4.4 Contracts.............................................................................................................. 24 2.4.5 Other People’s Money......................................................................................... 25 2.4.6 Private vs. Public................................................................................................. 25 2.4.7 The Utilitarian Argument .................................................................................... 26

2.5 Arguments Against Downsizing .................................................................................... 27 2.5.1 Rights and Duties ................................................................................................ 29

2.5.1.1 Introduction ............................................................................................. 29 2.5.1.2 The Rights of Employees ........................................................................ 30 2.5.1.3 The Rights to Job Security and due Process in Firing............................. 30 2.5.1.4 The Right to Information......................................................................... 30 2.5.1.5 The Right to Co-determination ............................................................... 31 2.5.2 Fairness................................................................................................................ 31

2.6 Conclusion...................................................................................................................... 36

3. Overall Conclusion............................................................................................................... 37

4. Bibilography......................................................................................................................... 38

5. Selbständigkeitserklärung .................................................................................................... 40

1

PREFACE

Researchers and thinkers do not always agree that a company has economic, legal, moral and

social responsibilities. Some do not even believe that companies have a moral responsibility;

others believe that moral and social responsibilities come second to economic and legal

responsibilities. This paper sets out to analyze a topic that has received much attention in

recent years, and around which there has been much debate, dispute, and confusion. This

topic, that has direct relevance to the question of corporate social responsibility in the

developed world in general, is corporate downsizing.

Various researchers have proved empirically that downsizing very often does not achieve its

immediate objective, which is to increase the efficiency of the company. It also comes at a

price. At the top of the casualty list stand the employees. In a society where individuals are

what they do, downsizing implying layoffs can inflict irreversible harm to their self-esteem.

In addition to the personal emotional trauma for the employee, it is important to take account

of the negative impact on the families of employees who have experienced downsizing, not

forgetting the economic burden placed on the communities where layoffs have occurred.

Downsizing shatters the belief that good performance leads to reward and positive

recognition.

The first part of this paper will briefly summarize the forces at work. These are the changes in

the external environment which underlie such a dramatic increase in restructuring and the

need for downsizing. The paper will investigate some of the impacts of downsizing on the

human resource element, and will continue by presenting some of the concepts of downsizing

and the approaches most frequently encountered in its application as the most visible form of

restructuring.

The second part is a brief analysis of the concepts of socially responsible restructuring and of

the two theories commonly used in the context of corporate social responsibility. It goes on to

analyse the question of the moral justification of downsizing and also considers some of the

arguments advanced by Orlando1 who dismisses the moral permissibility of certain

downsizing actions, unless being performed in an attempt to prevent the collapse of the

company.

1 Cf. Orlando, J., (1999): “The fourth wave: The ethics of corporate downsizing.” Business Ethics Quarterly,

Volume 9, Issue 2, pp 295-314.

2

I will argue that downsizing is, very often, to be considered morally wrong except if it occurs

uniquely with the aim of safeguarding the survival of the company and escape bankruptcy. I

will make my case by examining the concepts of corporate social responsibility and

dismissing the arguments commonly advanced in justifying the various acts of downsizing as

an attempt to maximize short-term stockholder wealth.

1. Downsizing in context

1.1 The Economic Environment - An Overview

Business leaders throughout the world agree on at least one thing: the new millennium will

bring new challenges along with continuous and rapid change. Globalisation of markets, the

increasing intensity of competition, deregulation and trade liberalisation, a rapid proliferation

of new technology, as well as changing societal expectations and values are combining to

create a turbulent environment in perpetual movement which is becoming increasingly

complex across all sectors of the economy and in all regions of the world. It is hardly

surprising that an increasing number of paradoxes are emerging as countries move from

industrial economies to knowledge and information-based post-industrial economies. At the

same time, many companies working in developing countries or in emerging economies are

moving from being suppliers of basic commodities to being increasingly sophisticated

producers and marketers of products to the developed world.

1.2 On Restructuring

As a result of the volatile and chaotic changes in the external environment, few companies

have escaped the need to restructure. Organizations and their constituents must change in

order to compete and survive in a rapidly changing, globally competitive, dynamic world. In

fact, part of the dilemma which currently faces us is that, increasingly, organizations are

going through these changes, not out of choice, but through necessity. The triggering events

and reasons for restructuring include:

• Survival of the enterprise: There are many reasons why a company may face

bankruptcy or a hostile takeover if immediate survival measures are not taken. Past

profits may have turned into losses, foreign competition may have seized a major

3

share of the market, or the cash flow (including lines of credit) may be inadequate to

finance cash requirements despite the company’s profitability.

• Temporary or permanent shrinking market demand or overcapacity: The

dramatic increase in supply and the drop in demand in the automotive industry have

created a crisis for many suppliers,2 as has overcapacity in certain sectors throughout

the world. Even Asia's huge electronics industry is beginning to react as major

semiconductor producers forge supranational alliances to stay in business. Others are

beginning to outsource, merge, seek out joint ventures and share research and

development costs and risks.

• Competitiveness: Deregulation or a lowering of tariffs can confront many companies

which have benefited in the past from various forms of protection from foreign

competition. Dramatic changes may be required for them to remain viable under new

rules of competition. Such changes as these increasingly require constant adaptation of

company structure and resources to the economical environment.

• Pressure from financial markets and stockholders: A great deal has been written

about the strong influence that financial institutions, analysts and markets bring to bear

on the management of listed companies to adopt very short-term perspectives in their

decision making, although this may be to the detriment of the longer-term

development and competitiveness of the enterprise.

• Poor management: In some cases, the origin of the need to restructure is to be found

in the short-term focus, the poor strategic decisions, and the failure on the part of

management itself to reliably recognise and anticipate the consequences of the

changing environment.

• Privatization: This is a further stimulus to restructuring in cases where companies can

no longer rely on subsidies and the favoured treatment that they once enjoyed as state-

owned companies. In state-owned enterprises, the workforce is often inflated in

relation to market potential and to the competition. Restructuring programmes may be

part of pre-privatization preparation but may well continue once privatization has

occurred.

2 GM’s November 2005 announcement that it would cut 30,000 blue-collar jobs by 2008 came as little surprise.

The company made a tremendous loss of several billion dollars US. It has been predicted that the US “Big Three” and their suppliers could cut as many as 75,000 jobs before this latest round of restructuring is over.

4

• Structural changes: A shift from an individual economy to a knowledge- and

information-based economy is taking place. Human capital is replacing financial

capital as the most important strategic resource. Traditional concepts of work, jobs,

and motivation are being seriously challenged.

Restructuring takes many forms and the term covers a wide variety of different actions3 but

unfortunately, management4 often turns first to the reduction of labour costs. As a result,

restructuring has become synonymous with downsizing, a euphemism for layoffs.

1.3 On Downsizing

Corporate downsizing is a concept that is somewhat elastic. In a general perspective,

however, it is used to describe different types of corporate renewal. In defining downsizing, I

will employ four attributes of downsizing: (1) downsizing is an activity that members of an

organization undertake in a purposeful manner; (2) downsizing typically involves a reduction

in personnel; (3) the focus of the downsizing activity is on improving effectiveness and/or

efficiency in the organization; and (4) downsizing affects the work processes (directly or

indirectly) within an organization.5

Although downsizing was largely associated with the restructuring of heavy industry, thereby

affecting blue-collar workforces, these cutbacks now affect the composition of virtually all

industries, regions, companies and employees at all levels of skill and education. Furthermore,

the practice of downsizing has swept through organizations across the board, both public and

private. Even organizations and companies which had formerly prided themselves on

maintaining employment security for their employees (e.g. Die Post, SBB Schweizerische

Bundesbahnen, Swisscom, Migros Genossenschaftsbund among others) have had to resort to

downsizing to improve efficiency and to change the course of organizational decline. 6

Sometimes, downsizing occurs because it is the proper thing to do in response to the natural

cycles of the economy. When markets shrink, companies and industries must consolidate and

3 For purposes of this paper, I will define restructuring as the deliberate modification of formal relationships

among organizational components. It may also include changing the portfolio of existing businesses (rationalisation, selling off unproductive divisions or activities, entering new businesses either through acquisition or internal growth). Restructuring can also involve and impact various stakeholders such as employees, suppliers and other business partners.

4 For the purpose of this paper the term management includes both directors and officers of companies. 5 Cf. Freeman S. J., and Cameron K. S., (1993): “Organizational Downsizing: A Convergence and

Reorientation Framework”. Organization Science, vol. 4, no. 1, pp. 10 - 29. 6 For the purpose of this paper, when I speak of organizational decline, I am referring to a prolonged decrease in

the number of personnel in an organization. This term is closely affiliated with, and sometimes used interchangeably with, downsizing.

5

streamline (though some companies can anticipate and do move into better markets) and

technological changes and globalization can add to the pressure to downsize. Such natural

economic forces have always existed and often led to layoffs, but they alone cannot explain

the magnitude and scope of the widespread downsizing practices today.

The rationale behind downsizing is complex. A thorough discussion of why companies should

downsize can be found in, “Reengineering the Corporation”7. The authors claim that the

payoffs for downsizing include reduced business-related costs in the short-term and increased

customer satisfaction. Downsizing, as a practice to improve organizational performance has

been widely debated. The positive effects suggested in the literature are that downsizing

reduces operating costs, enhance short-term financial performance, eliminates unnecessary

levels of management, enhances the overall effectiveness, make an organization more

competitive, enables management to eliminate redundancies, and may save the company from

continuing financial deterioration and possible bankruptcy.8 The bottom line is that

downsizing increases profits for companies in the short-term because it provides a mechanism

for suppressing wage costs associated with employees. This has led the management perceive

that downsizing is unavoidable and good for the economy. In some cases, the management

claims that mass layoffs are driven by factors beyond their control. For example, lost jobs are

often blamed on technological advances (e.g., machines are simply more efficient and more

cost effective than people) or by more efficient competitors.

However, Greenberg9 reported that 56 % of the more than 700 companies surveyed by the

American Management Association indicated that downsizing was an on-going strategy to

reduce corporate overhead costs in response to current or anticipated business problems. This

trend toward continuous corporate restructuring presents a fundamental, permanent change in

organizational strategy signalling a radical shift in many corporate philosophies and

strategies. Furthermore, he reveals that downsizing generally fails to improve performance,

productivity, or long-term profits. Approximately two-thirds of downsized companies have

not realized productivity gains, and most executives who cut back on personnel report

unanticipated negative side effects. Many reasons are cited for the failure of downsizing, such

7 Cf. Hammer, M., and J. Champy, (1994): “Reengineering the Corporation”, New York: Harper Business. 8 Cf. Cappelli, P., (2000): “ A Market-driven Approach to Retaining Talent”, Harvard Business Review 78, pp.

103-104; and De Meuse, K.P., T.J. Bergmann, P.A. Vanderheiden and C.E. Roraff, (2004): New Evidence Regarding Organizational Downsizing and a Firm’s Financial Performance: A Long-term Analysis”, Journal of Management Issues 16, pp. 155-161.

9 Cf. Greenberg, E., (1996): “AMA Survey on Downsizing Job Elimination and Job Creation”, American Management Association, New York. (www.amanet.org/research/archives.com, January 5, 2007).

6

as a lowering of morale, an exodus of the best people, the loss of organizational memory and

increased conflict.

Furthermore, various studies show that (mostly in the long-term) downsizing affects rather

negatively the companies that have downsized. 10 In the short run, it creates the illusion that

decisions are being made and actions undertaken11 and in the long-term it does not yield any

performance gains 12 and may undermine the company’s competitive advantage. 13

Concepts such as corporate loyalty and lifetime employment are being replaced by new

interpretations of employment-at-will as companies routinely dismiss employees in the name

of organizational survival or simply as a managerial prerogative. This raises many ethical

issues regarding the relationship between a company and its stakeholders, in particular the

relationship with its employees, one of the most important stakeholder groups.

1.3.1 The Impact of Downsizing on Employees

Most people in industrialized countries spend a large percentage of their adult years and

expend a major part of their energy at work. Work experience strongly shapes an individual’s

identity, their sense of self-esteem and the extent to which they can contribute to community.

In other words, their employment not only supplies a livelihood, but structures their lives with

meaningful activity. However, downsizing has changed the ways in which companies and

their employees relate. Traditionally, loyalty was rewarded with security. Hence, as so many

companies downsize, they are no longer able or willing to guarantee lifelong employment.

When companies downsize they often discover that employees have become suspicious and

less productive. When employees feel less loyal, they focus on protecting their self-interests

rather than on working for the purpose of the company.

The many studies focusing on the impact of downsizing on the surviving workforce have

concluded that, depending on in-house and outside environmental conditions, downsizing

may impact a range of work behaviours and attitudes among the survivors. Survivors’ re-

actions to downsizing have potentially important implications on the survival of companies 10 Cf. Budros, A., (1999): “A Conceptual Framework for Analysing Why Organizations Downsize”,

Organization Science 10, pp. 69-83; and Vanderheiden, P.A., K.P., De Meuse, and T.J. Bergmann, (1999): Response to Haar’s Comment- and the Beat Goes on: Corporate Downsizing in the Twenty First Century”, Human Resources Management 38, pp. 261-268.

11 Cf. Glebbeek, A.C. and E.H Bax, (2004): “Is High Employee Turnover Really Harmful?An Empirical Test Using Company Records”, Academy of Management Journal 47, pp.277-286.

12 Cf. Casio, W.F., (2002): “Strategies for Responsible Restructuring”, The Academy of Management Executive 16, pp. 80-91.

13 Cf. Chadwick, C., L.W. Hunter and S.L. Walston, (2004): Effects of Downsizing Practices on the Performance of Hospitals”, Strategic Management Journal 25, pp. 405-427.

7

themselves.14 Empirical research dealing with organizational decline and downsizing has been

associated with low levels of morale15 (due to the loss of leader credibility,16 or increased

uncertainty and ambiguity17), heightened level of mistrust and insecurity,18 and a decrease in

participation and greater emphasis on control. 19 For the most part, the variables cited in these

research papers dealt with the emotional or attitudinal variables pertaining to employees’

relationship to their company.

From this review of the extensive literature , both theoretical and practical, I conclude that, to

a large extent, companies can avoid the need to downsize by adopting more appropriate

strategies as described below in section 1.3.3.1 of this paper.

1.3.2 Crisis Management and Downsizing

Organizational responses to decline fall into two major categories, namely, the strategic

responses designed to cope with conditions of decline20 and the structural responses

consisting of the internal changes that occur within the company itself.21 Literature on

management deals mainly with the effective management of crises in order to minimize (1)

the potential loss to the company, and (2) the adverse impact on the well-being of the

members of the organization, since organizational crises produce individual crises which take

the form of stress.22 Consequently, organizational responses to a crisis23 will depend to a large

extent on how individuals respond to the stress engendered by the crisis, since it is these same

individuals who determine the organization’s responses to the crisis.

14 Cf. Brockner, J., Grover S., O'Mally M., DeWitt R., Reed T., and Glynn M., (1992): "Layoffs, Job Insecurity

and Survivors' Work Effort”, Academy of Management Journal, vol. 35, no. 2, pp. 413-426. The results of the study showed that as job insecurity moved from low to moderate levels, work effort increased. However, as job insecurity moved from moderate to high levels, work effort decreased.

15 Cf. Billings, R. S., Milburn T. W., and Schaalman M. L., (1980): “A Model of Crisis Perception: A Theoretical and Empirical Analysis”, Administrative Science Quarterly, vol. 25, pp. 300-316.

16 Cf. Kantz, J., (1985): “Group Processes under Conditions of Organizational Decline”, Journal of Applied Behavioral Science, vol. 21, pp. 1-17.

17 Cf. Hall, D. T., and Mansfield R.: (1971): “Organizational and Individual Response to External Stress”, Administrative Science Quarterly, vol. 16, pp. 533-547.

18 Cf. Hardy, C., (1987): “Investing in Retrenchment: Avoiding the Hidden Costs”, California Management Review, vol. 4, pp. 111-27.

19 Cf. Cameron, K., (1983): “Strategic Responses to Conditions of Decline”, Journal of Higher Education, vol. 54, no. 4, pp. 359-80.

20 Cf.Cameron: supra note 19. 21 Cf. McKinley, W., (1987): “Complexity and Administrative Intensity: The Case of Declining Organizations”,

Administrative Science Quarterly, vol. 32, pp. 87-105. 22 Cf. Hardy, C.: supra note 18. 23 Crises originate in either the external environment or the internal environment, that is, from within the

organization itself.

8

However, when management makes the strategic decision to downsize, two ethics-related

issues arise concerning (1) the moral obligation of the management to act in the best interests

of the company, and (2) the legal obligation of the management not to violate the legal and

moral rights of employees.

Therefore, in consideration of the above, and if we believe that the way an individual is

treated is important on a moral level, (quite aside from any effects that a company’s attitude

may have on others), management has an obligation to take a moral standpoint towards their

employees. In other words, an individual is regarded as having moral status if, when morally

relevant decisions are made, his/her welfare is taken into account for his/her own sake and not

merely for the company’s, or a third party’s, benefit.

1.3.3 Downsizing Strategies

Companies typically respond to organizational decline by reducing the scale of their

operations, which usually implies cutting the workforce in some way. The two most

commonly used techniques for adjusting the workforce are (1) offering early retirement and

(2) practising forced resignation or layoff, both of which will now be discussed.

All early retirement programs have one element in common: a financial stimulus to retire

before the normal age of retirement. The degree of incentive is determined by the company's

capability to fund the cash requirements, and the amount of personnel trimming needed. A

potential problem with early retirement programs is that valued employees with highly

desired skills may be motivated into leaving the company, which consequently impacts the

management’s moral obligation to act in the best interests of the company.

Layoffs likewise reduce operating costs by trimming the workforce, although the strategies in

this case differ from those of early retirement in that the decision as to who will leave rests

with the company. Layoffs could be viewed as a reactive response to organizational decline,

whereby little regard is given for the human resource element in the company. This

diminished consideration for human resources, which represents a violation of the moral

rights of employees, tends to have a negative impact on individuals’ self-esteem.

Furthermore, Hardy 24 argues that there are numerous other methods (for instance, attrition,

severance pay to induce attrition, outplacement assistance, transfers to other locations,

retraining allowances, work sharing, and leaves of absence) of achieving downsizing that

take into consideration the needs of the company, as well as the well-being and self-esteem of 24 Cf. Hardy, C.,: supra note 18

9

employees, both those who leave and those who remain. As such, these methods may be

viewed as being more proactive and they could well reduce many of the uncertainties

associated with layoffs. In turn, the employees remaining in the company might be persuaded

that the actions taken were designed not only to increase efficiency and profitability, but also

in full moral respect of the rights of the employees.25

Outplacement programs afford a means for managers to express their concern for employees

whose employment contract has been terminated. It is common practice today for companies

to provide counselling, coaching, help and advice for job hunting, interview techniques,

career planning, and curriculum vitae writing for the employees they decide to fire. Upwards

of 84% of companies report offering outplacement services to workers displaced due to

downsizing.26 Services such as these can help the downsized employee cope with the

psychological issues surrounding job loss and facilitate an active search for

reemployment. By expediting the search for a new job, the length of unemployment may

be reduced.27 Such assistance may also foster the perception that the management of the

company is genuinely concerned and sincere in its efforts to assist displaced employees.

1.3.3.1 Alternatives to Downsizing Strategies

Other methods beside those described above may be applied in downsizing programs and

these help minimize, and may even eliminate, the negative impact of downsizing on the

employees. These alternative techniques are summarized under the following headings:

• Rightsizing: A company, based on an in-depth assessment of mission-critical work and

its staffing requirements, develops a short- and long-term human resource plan, which is

communicated to the employees. Subsequently, training is given as needed; employees are

moved internally; and new hiring is tightly monitored.28 This type of disciplined human

resource management is a proactive way to restructure the company on an on-going basis.

Constant vigilance of this type helps ensure that the organization does not grow the layers

of "fat" which commonly leads to drastic downsizing activities.

25 Cf. Perry, L. T., (1986): “Least-Cost Alternatives to Layoffs in Declining Industries”, Organizational

Dynamics, vol. 14, no. 4, pp. 48-61. 26 Cf. Greenberg, E. R., (1994): “AMA Survey on Downsizing and Assistance to Displaced Workers”, American

Management Association, New York. (www.amanet.org/research/archives.com, January 5, 2007). 27 Cf. Latack, J. C., and H. G. Kaufman (1988): “Termination and Outplacement Strategies”, in M. London and

E. M. Mone (eds.), Career Growth and Human Resource Strategies (Quorum Books, New York), pp. 289–313. 28 Cf. Morrall, A. Jr., (1998): “A Human Resource Rightsizing Model for the Twenty-First Century”, Human

Resource Development Quarterly, pp. 81-88.

10

• Passive Downsizing: Reich claims that if downsizing is done passively through buyouts

and attrition, the company will end up far better positioned for long-term success. If

layoffs are inevitable, companies should provide outplacement services. Better yet, to

avoid laying off blue-collar workers, companies should re-train them for white-collar jobs,

which are more appropriate in this information age. The pay-off is in the extra effort

(higher productivity and performance) received as a result of the good will, employee

loyalty, and the trust the company has earned. Reich reminds us that the "employees are

closest to customers [. . .] to production processes [. . .] to technology." They are the

people who will make the process improvements and quality enhancements that will

improve productivity and customer satisfaction29 and thereby ultimately ensuring the

survival of the company.

• Combination Approach: Generally, downsizing practices run counter to high-

performance practices. Yet, more and more companies are combining these two

approaches as part of their restructuring programs. Downsizing helps break down the

traditional organization chart, facilitating the introduction of cross-functional teams,

empowerment, and broad job descriptions. This model provides a clear vision for the

employees who remain, tearing down the old system while at the same time erecting a

new, improved structure. Without a clear vision, the future can become rather uncertain

and bleak for the survivors of downsizing.

1.4 Conclusion

Downsizing is hard to resist because it is firmly implanted in business culture and mostly

justified by general beliefs about proper economic policies and norms of practice. The very

nature of a world economy embracing free markets and free enterprises implies constant

change and adaptation to the dynamics of the system. Although there are alternative strategies

and techniques (which take into consideration the interests of the stakeholders, both internal

and external) to restructure a company, management often turns first to reduction of labour

costs. As a result, restructuring has become synonymous with downsizing.

The review of the research on downsizing has proven that the impact of downsizing goes

beyond mere economic considerations. Companies are often caught in a powerful social

movement that compels management to eliminate jobs even when cuts are not fully justified

economically. The method chosen to downsize affects not only the company’s economic

29 Cf. Reich, R., (1996): “Performance Strategies: Q&A”. Successful Meetings, pp.56-61.

11

status but also the self-esteem and well-being of the workforce, the success of current and

future business strategies, and the company’s culture and image. Many reasons are cited for

the failure of downsizing, among which are the lowering of morale, and increased uncertainty,

and ambiguity heightened level of mistrust and insecurity, and a decrease in participation and

greater emphasis on control.

Restructuring implying downsizing is part of the current economic reality but this does not

mean it is morally justified. In my view, what is truly disturbing is first the shift in perception

of layoffs as a last resort to be used only in times of economic desperation, to a first resort

utilized in good times in an attempt to maximize short-term profit; and second the

disrespectful way the management of some companies are treating their employees when

circumstances require them to be let go. However, in no way do I wish to give the impression

that every company has handled downsizing poorly. It should be noted that several have

conducted highly ethical closings.

12

2. Ethical Considerations of Downsizing

2.1 Introduction

Orthodox neoclassical economic theory implies that it is management’s job to employ

efficiency as a means of maximizing stockholder profit. They should optimize the allocation

of the company’s scarce resources in such a way to reach Pareto Optimality.30 This position is

commonly considered to be morally correct in orthodox neoclassical economics. Although, in

my opinion, the principles of efficiency, competition, and profit making are not unethical

when prudently applied, they become quite problematic when a corporate culture ceases to be

morally responsible to its employees and to the community in general. This is specifically the

case when management downsizes for other reasons than purely to ensure the survival of the

company, and generally as a means of maximizing profit. More often than not, acts of

downsizing do not lead to improved performance and productivity, or any sustainable

increase in long-term profit.31

In evaluating whether downsizing that is not intended as a last resort to ensure the survival of

the company is ethically justifiable, I will elucidate the concept of socially responsible

restructuring and then shortly summarize the two theories commonly used in the context of

social responsibilities as a rationale for the moral justification, if any, of downsizing and,

finally, analyze some of the arguments advanced by Orlando32 in arguing the moral

impermissibility of downsizing.

2.2 Socially Responsible Restructuring

The concept of socially responsible enterprise restructuring as promulgated by the

Entrepreneurship and Management Development Branch of the International Labour

Organization (ILO) and the European Bahá'í Business Forum means “restructuring part or all

of an enterprise in a manner that balances and consciously takes into consideration the

interests and concerns of all the stakeholders who are affected by the changes and decisions.

30 The Concept of Pareto Optimality refers to a situation in which nobody can be made better off without making

somebody else worse off. Named after V. Pareto (1843 – 1923), an Italian economist. If an economy’s resources are being used inefficiently, it ought to be possible to make somebody better off without anybody else becoming worse off. In reality, change often produces losers as well as winners. Pareto efficiency does not help judge whether this sort of change is economically good or bad. (Source: www.economist.com/research/Economics/alphabetic.cfm?term=pareto, January 7, 2007).

31 Greenberg, E.,: supra note 9. 32 Orlando, J.,: supra note 1.

13

In practice, the emphasis must be on enhancing the overall ’stakeholder value’ and not be

limited to short term shareholder gains.”33

The concept clearly refers to restructuring, but considering that restructuring very often turns

out to be reduction of labour costs implying layoffs, it is in my opinion appropriate to apply it

to downsizing. So the key issue is often not whether to downsize, but rather how to do it

responsibly, i.e., in a way that takes into account the interests of the stakeholders involved.

Although the definition set out above refers to the stakeholder theory, it does not explicitly

define the concept of corporate social responsibility (CSR). Therefore, I will later provide a

definition of corporate social responsibility and then briefly elucidate the two commonly

referred to theoretical concepts of the social responsibility of the company.

2.2.1 Definitions of Corporate Social Responsibility

A comprehensive definition of corporate social responsibility was provided by Frederick, Post

and Davis. They state: “Corporate social responsibility means that a corporation should be

held accountable for any of its actions that affect people, their communities, and their

environment. It implies that negative business impacts on people and society and should be

acknowledged and corrected if at all possible.” 34

The review of literature on CSR did not identify any challenges to the status of profits in the

context of social responsibility. On the contrary, the notion of profit as the basic economic

mission of business has been a main assumption for almost all authors. The term “socially

profitable business” refers to all types of payoffs necessary to meet the expectations of those

interacting with business, including economic profit expectations.

Steiner and Steiner35 define CSR as follows: “The major social responsibility of a company is

to operate profitably and utilize efficiently the resources at its disposal. While important,

other activities relating to the use of corporate resources to further national goals, employee

and community welfare, or other social interests, are today second to this purpose, and except

for a limited number of cases are pursued to contribute to the achievement of the first purpose

in the short and in the long run.” They also concede that the maximization of profit is no

33 Source: www.ilo.org/dyn/empent/docs/F795877461/Starch_1.pdf, December 31, 2006. 34 Cf. Frederick W., Post J., and Davis K., (1992): “Business and Society: Corporate Strategy, Public Policy,

Ethics”, 7th ed. New York: McGraw-Hill, p. 30. 35 Cf. Steiner G. A., and Steiner J. F., (1994): “Business, Government, and Society: A Managerial Perspective”,

7th ed. New York: McGraw-Hill, pp. 162 -163.

14

longer a workable doctrine for business stating, "the economist's strict concept of profit

maximization is not an acceptable operational goal for today's larger corporation."

For the purpose of this paper, I will agree with the definition of CSR provided by Frederick,

Post, and Davis due to the fact it better considers the fact that companies reacts to prevailing

social norms, values, and performance expectation and therefore should be held accountable

for the ecological, environmental, and social costs directly incurred by their actions.

2.3 The Theories of Social Responsibility

This section contains a short examination of the two widely discussed theories of corporate

social responsibility. In presenting these, consideration will be given to the issue of how each

of the theories responds to the issue of maintaining a proper balance between the economic

and non-economic responsibilities of companies. The main theories that have emerged

regarding corporate social responsibility are the stockholder and the stakeholder theories.

2.3.1 The Stockholder Theory

The probably most famous statement of this theory has been given by Friedman who refers

ironically to this as a social responsibility. As he states, "There is one and only one social

responsibility of business to use its resources and engage in activities designed to increase its

profits so long as it stays within the rules of the game, which is to say, engages in open and

free competition, without deception or fraud.”36

According to the stockholder theory, management is under a strict fiduciary duty to act for the

owners of the company, who advance capital to be utilized only to realize pre-specified

(contractual) goals, and for which they receive an ownership interest in the venture. The

existence of this fiduciary relationship imposes on the management (in their capacity as

officers of the business) the duty not to divert business resources away from the purposes

expressly authorized by the stockholders. Consequently, management’s first obligation is to

the stockholders to protect and promote their economic interests.37 Fundamentally speaking,

the stockholder theory holds that managers are obligated to adhere to the (legal) directions of

the stockholders.

36 Cf. Friedman, M., (1970): “The Social Responsibility of Business is to Increase its Profit”, New York Times

Magazine, September 13, 1970. 37 Cf. Jones T., (1980): “Corporate social responsibility revisited, redefined”, California Management Review,

spring, pp. 59-67.

15

In my opinion it is essential to note that the stockholder theory (as a normative theory) states

that the management are obligated to pursue profit by all legal, non deceptive means, but does

not assert that they may ignore all ethical constraints in the pursuit of profits. According to the

theory, the nature of the business environment itself imposes a basic duty of honest dealing on

business people. However, the theory also claims that if there are to be any more extensive

restrictions on the management, it is the role of society as a whole to impose them through the

legislative process. This approach clearly defines managements' ethical obligations, partially

in terms of their legal obligations, and implies that their ethical obligations will change as the

legislation relevant to the business environment changes. At any particular point in time, the

theory can be understood as asserting that a business or business person must refrain from

engaging in deceptive practices and violating the laws of the land as they exist at that time.

The stockholder theory is often associated with the type of utilitarian argument frequently

advanced by free market economists. Thus, supporting arguments often begin with the claim

that when individual actors pursue private profit in a free market, they are led by Adam

Smith's invisible hand to promote (directly and/or indirectly) the general (social) interest as

well. Consequentially it can be concluded that there is no justification for claiming that

businesses or business persons have any social responsibilities other than to legally and

honestly maximize the profits of the venture. The Smithian view of the market system implies

that the system is allowed to operate according to its own laws and will align – through the

stabilizing equilibration of supply and demand -- selfish interests with common interests.

However, the market system is not completely self-regulating; trade is possible only within a

framework of law and fair dealing and some of the feedback mechanisms (such as the

tendency for resource prices to reflect short-term supply) have destabilizing effects. However,

managing a company is a matter of applying controls in areas where they are needed, and

ethical behavior is one of these areas.

Yet even after rejecting a naive faith in a self-regulating economy and accepting the economic

importance of moral dispositions, one may doubt the need to professionalize business. The

business virtues of industry, honesty, trust, and so forth, are the same for humanity in general.

The key players in business, however, are the individual belonging to the management, and

considering that their decisions collectively make the difference between economic growth

and prosperity on the one hand, and decline and the social decay that inevitably follows on the

other, the reluctance to burden them with obligations beyond those of making a profit and

adhering to the traditional virtues cannot be fully justified.

16

However, Orlando,38 in challenging the assumption that the interests of stockholders take

priority over those of employees, argues for moral equality. This equality implies that, for

downsizing to be permissible, it must be justifiable from a utilitarian perspective, taking into

account the interests of both stockholders and workers. Yet, he argues that the utilitarian case

for downsizing is unproved and that there are at least three moral arguments against it, which

I will summarize in section 2.4 of this paper.

2.3.2 The Stakeholder Theory

According to Sethi, the stakeholder theory holds that there are other constituents than the

stockholders of the company to whom corporate managers are directly responsible.39 These

constituents are groups that are likely to be affected, either directly or indirectly, by the

decisions of the management, thus they are said to have a stake in the company. Therefore,

the theory requires the manager to give balanced consideration to the legitimate interests of all

those who have a stake in the company.

In its normative form, the stakeholder theory asserts that managers have the obligation to

manage the business – understood as a vehicle for coordinating stakeholder interests, with a

management which has a fiduciary relationship to all stakeholders – in the interests of all

stakeholders regardless of the impact on financial performance, and to ensure its survival by

balancing stakeholders’ conflicting claims. Hence, the theory does imply that businesses have

social responsibilities, namely in a richer sense than stated by Friedman.

In order to fulfil their obligations, the management must act in accordance with two distinct

principles of stakeholder management:

1. The principle of corporate legitimacy requiring that the company should be managed for

the benefit of its stakeholders. The rights of these groups must be ensured and, further, the

groups must participate, in some sense, in decisions that substantially affect their

welfare.40

2. The stakeholder fiduciary principle which, according to Goodpaster, states that the

management bears a fiduciary relationship to stakeholders and to the company as an

abstract entity. It must act in the interests of the stakeholders as their agent, and in the 38 Orlando J.: supra note 1. 39 Cf. Sethi P., (1997): “Dimensions of Corporate Social Performance: An Analytical Framework”., In A.

Carroll (ed.), Managing Corporate Social Responsibility Boston: Little, Brown & Company., pp. 69-75. 40 Cf. Evan W.E., and Freeman R.E., (1993): “A Stakeholder Theory of the Firm: Kantian Capitalism”, in

Ethical Theory and Business, ed. Tom L. Beauchamp and Norman E. Bowie (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1993), p. 82.

17

interests of the company to ensure the survival of the firm, safeguarding the long-term

stakes of each group. 41

Two reasons are typically given for the inclusion of non-stockholders among the stakeholders.

Firstly, they have usually entered into an explicit and implicit contractual or contract-like

agreement with the company or its members, or secondly, they are directly affected by the

decisions of the management. There is, however, a difference of opinion among theorists

about who the actual or legitimate constituents of a company are, and this also affects the

definition of stakeholder. Ackoff 42 contends that only those who are directly or primarily

affected by the actions of a company are its stakeholders. Others, like Freeman,43 extend the

definition to anyone who may directly affect the company. The latter definition essentially

makes everyone a stakeholder of a company, even those who are actually non-members,

because nearly everyone can affect company directly or indirectly.44

The most commonly endorsed argument for the stakeholder theory is that concerning

performance, which is advanced by some strategic management theorists such as Ackoff,45

who emphasizes the advantages that company amass in applying the stakeholder approach.

He believes that the long-term survival of a company is improved when it responds to

stakeholder interests as a major part of corporate strategy. Furthermore, he argues that the

various elements of the overall social system function more efficiently and coherently when

management respects the interests of stakeholders.

A principal assumption of those stakeholder theorists who endorse the performance argument

is that corporate managers are only accountable for the direct effects of their corporate

decisions (as it is specifically the case when company downsize). It is agreed, however, that

they cannot be sufficiently informed about the indirect effects of their corporate actions.

41 Cf. Goodpaster K.E., (1991): “Business Ethics and Stakeholder Analysis” in Ethical Issues in Business, ed.

Thomas Donaldson, Patricia H. Werhane and Margaret Cording (Upper Saddle River,: N.J.: Patience Hall , 2002), p. 49-60.

42 Cf. Ackoff R., (1981): “Creating the Corporate Future”, New York: John Wiley and Sons. 43 Cf. Freeman R. E., (1984): “Business Management: A Stakeholder Approach”. Boston: Ballinger. 44 For the purposes of this paper, I will use the term stockholders in its narrowest sense as those groups who are

vital to the survival and success of the corporation, a group which includes employees, customers, suppliers, management, stockholders, and residents of the local community.

45 Cf. Ackoff R.,: supra note 42.

18

2.3.3 Stockholder and Stakeholder Theories on Downsizing

The two theories shortly summarized above approach the problem of downsizing and layoffs

differently. This is not surprising, since the basic premises and hypothetical foundations of the

theories differ sharply.

The stockholder theory states that social responsibility should not be a function of the

management process. Friedman,46 has always maintained that business operates best when it

sticks to its primary mission--ensuring profitability by producing goods and services within

society's legal restrictions. He further argues that the business's exclusive responsibility is to

attempt to maximize returns to shareholders. This principle is of fundamental consideration

when the question of downsizing is raised. In the real world it is the management who has the

final say in determining whether to downsize or not. Consequently, according to the theory

the management should not be under any set of legal requirements to consider the well-being

of the employees. The frequently raised argument of the stockholder theory regarding

downsizing and employee layoff is the efficiency one, and inherently to the theory it is

assumed that there will be more winners than losers as a result of downsizing, due to

efficiency. The winners include most of those who participate in a more efficient market

system and more profits and benefits to shareholders, which in turn might mean more jobs in

future through capital accumulation.

On the other side, stakeholder theory suggests that certain moral and legal conditions be

placed in the hands of the management in order to prevent downsizing and thus consider the

interests of the employees and of all other stakeholders. According to Drucker,47 it is

management's responsibility to lessen the impact of actions outside of its own specific

mission. The question raised here is, what is considered outside management's specific

purpose or mission? In a downsizing decision, undoubtedly the employees who lose their

jobs are directly affected by management's decision. One could also argue that even if the

management are justified in electing to downsize they have to take into consideration the

effect of the decision and to particularly consider the effects of the downsizing on the well-

being and on the welfare of the employees as being the directly impacted stakeholder.

In accordance with the definition of CSR provided above it can be deducted that one of a

company's primary objectives is to operate in a socially responsible manner. Our society gives

considerable freedom to organizations, both public and private. In return, organizations are

46 Friedmann, M.: supra note 36 47 Cf. Drucker, P., (1974): „Management: Tasks, Responsibilities, Practices”, New York, Harper & Row, p 347.

19

expected to function in a manner consistent with society's interests. Social responsibility

refers to the expectation that business companies should act in the public's interest. As a

matter of fact, businesses have always been presumed to provide employment for individuals

and to offer goods and services for clients. Ideally, companies that are socially responsible are

those that are able to operate profitably while simultaneously benefiting society in adopting a

stakeholders' approach to its social responsibility mission.

2.4 The Aspects of Corporate Downsizing

In concluding that downsizing as a means to enhancing profit is often morally wrong,

Orlando48 presents six arguments that challenge the reasons advanced for privileging the

interest of stockholders above all other parties simply because they are who they are. He also

puts forward three arguments against the moral permissibility of (certain acts of) downsizing

and dismisses the utilitarian approach to justify downsizing. However, he does accept that

downsizing intended as a last resort, in order to safeguard the survival of the company, may

be justified.

According to Orlando the moral equality of workers and stockholders 49 implies that for

downsizing to be permissible it must be justifiable from a utilitarian perspective, which takes

into account the interests of both stockholders and workers. The arguments presented in order

to dismiss the assumption of the supremacy of the stockholders parties are summarized and

commented in the following section.

2.4.1 Property Rights

Orlando argues: “First, it must be understood that one cannot justify the position that

shareholder concerns take precedence over all other groups simply by appeal to the fact that

the shareholders are the legal owners of the corporation,”50 and continues referring to the

paradigm that a “legal owner of the corporation has property rights that allow her to dispose

of her property in any manner she sees fit”51, it cannot be asserted that privileging the

stockholder group is morally justified.

48 Orlando J.,: supra note 1 49 Orlando uses the term “shareholder(s)”. However for the purposes of consistency within the context of this

paper, I will use the term “stockholders”. 50 Orlando J.,: supra note 1, p. 297. 51 Orlando J.,: supra note 1, p. 297.

20

Considerations on the stockholder as the legal owner of the company

Generally speaking, property rights refer to any sanctioned behavioural relations among

decision makers in the use of potential resources; such sanctioned behaviours allow people

the right to use resources in a non-prohibited way. The interplay of scale economies,

negotiating cost, externalities and the modification of property rights can be seen in the

exception to the assertion that ownership tends to be an individual affair: the publicly-held

company. Significant economies of scale and the large capital requirements for equity can be

satisfied more advantageously by acquiring the necessary capital from multiple purchasers of

equity shares. This is a fact. While economies of scale in operating a company do exist,

economies of scale in the provision of capital do not. But if all owners participate in every

single decision that needs to be made by such a company, the economies of scale regarding

operations will quickly be overtaken by the negotiating costs. Hence a delegation of authority

for most decisions takes place and, for most of these, a small management group becomes the

de facto owner. Hence, is not the company that stockholder of publicly-held companies really

own, but their shares. Therefore, I am of the opinion that the claim made by some company to

justify the reasons of certain acts of downsizing with the purpose to maximize the

shareholders’ wealth can not be well grounded on the property rights arguments.

Considerations on the stockholder supremacy over all other groups

Evan and Freeman declare, “The reason for paying returns to owners is not that they ‘own’

the firm but that their support is necessary for the survival of the firm, and that they have a

legitimate claim on the firm."52 Therefore, the stockholders are simply one of a number of

groups that might make claims on company resources.

Considerations on the nexus of explicit and implicit contracts (1)

From a legal perspective stockholders are considered to be the only residual claimants. When

the company is considered as a nexus of contracts, the decisions of the management influence

the economic payoffs of the stakeholders of the nexus, sometimes to a greater extent even

than of the stockholders. The claim that stockholders are the company’s only residual

claimants fails to fit economic facts in almost all real-world business circumstances.53 Firstly,

the employees are important residual claimants especially when company-specific human

capital is involved. Secondly, creditors can be important residual claimants and thirdly, 52 Evan, W.E., and Freeman R.E.,: supra note 40. 53 Cf. Pitelis, C.N., (2004): “Corporate Governance, Shareholder Value and Sustainable Economic

Performance”, Corporate Governance 12, pp. 210- 223.

21

complex network relationships among suppliers and customers produce interdependencies

leading to considerable residual gains and losses. The economic view of stockholder

supremacy is the conceptualization of the company as a nexus of explicit contracts in a world

of complete contracting. In such an agency model, there are by definition no residual rights of

control since the nexus of explicit contracts is designed to specify in advance all the future

economic payoff-relevant contingencies. However in the business world, contracts are

typically incomplete due to the fact that complete contracts are impossible to achieve. Hence,

the company has to be considered a nexus of explicit and implicit contracts or contract-like

agreements. This minor change in premise has considerable consequences on how we are to

understand the theory of the firm.54 More generally, from the perspective of the incomplete

contracting theory, there exist other contracting parties besides stockholders who are not fully

protected by explicit contracting, thereby undermining the foundational premise of

stockholders’ supremacy. However, the property rights theory of the firm from a stakeholder

perspective is still under development.55

2.4.2 Fiduciary Duties

According to the stockholder theory, the fiduciary duty of management obliges it to adhere to

the (legal) directions of the stockholders. Orlando’s argument is that “[t]he fiduciary duty (of

the manager toward the shareholders56) does not establish the obligations of the agent; it is

rather prior considerations pertaining to the nature of the relationship that determine the

parameters of that duty”. He is of the opinion, that the term fiduciary duty only describes the

obligations of management. It does not create those duties and therefore, it cannot justify

them. Furthermore, he argues that the legal basis of fiduciary duty – anchored in the

principles of corporate governance - has been drawn up to avoid advancing the self-interests

of management over those of stockholders. This means that, if management also considers the

interests of stakeholders (even at the expense of profits), this does not conflict with their

fiduciary duty to the stockholder.

54 Cf. Baker, G., R. Gibbons, and K.J. Murphy, (2002): “Relational Contracts and the Theory of the Firm”,

Quarterly Journal of Economics 117, pp. 39-83. 55 Cf. Mahoney, J., C.C. Asher, and J. Mahoney, (2004): “Toward a Property Rights Foundation for a

Stakeholder Theory of the Firm”, Academy of Management Policy Strategy (BPS) Division Symposium in New Orleans.

56 Brackets added by A.G.

22

Considerations on fiduciary duties

In accordance with the definition on corporate social responsibility provided above, the most

important duty of the management is probably to be a representative of the company and its

stakeholders. One may define this duty as a combination of both integrity and competence.

Any member of the management must therefore be trustworthy enough to represent the

company with all due diligence, and must act in the best interests of the company.

Within the concept of explicit and implicit contractual or contract-like agreements, the

problem is that representing the company as a whole may put the management at the centre of

a conflict between different classes of stockholder, who expect different things from the

company, or sets it at the centre of a conflict between the different types of stakeholder both

inside and outside the firm. The fiduciary duty of the management toward the company, then,

means that maximization of stockholders' wealth should be less of a concern than

maximization of the company’s value. As I mentioned above, this may cause conflicts within

the firm, and management may well feel their loyalty torn. As a result, management must be

able to aggregate the functions of all stakeholders in the firm using a utilitarian approach. In

smaller companies, where ownership is more concentrated, and where conflicts between

stockholders may be more personal, simply stating that the managements’ fiduciary duty is to

maximize stockholder wealth may miss the point completely.

Even in large companies, maximizing the firm's profits or the stockholders' wealth is a

concept that is still unclear. The simple notion of profit and its impact on stockholder wealth

is not clear because an accountants' notion of profit is a contemporaneous measure of the

firm's wealth, whereas for stockholders, wealth represents the present value of cash flows

generated by the firm against an uncertain future. In particular, investments in workforce or in

research and development do not generate profits in a current annual statement, but may

increase the stockholders' wealth.

The discrepancy between firm profit and stockholder wealth is much larger for companies

that operate in a very risky environment, such as high-tech and biotechnology industries. As a

result, the management’s fiduciary duty in such companies may be even harder to define than

in firms operating in mature industries. The harder it is to define the managements’ fiduciary

duty to the firm and its stockholders, the harder it is to show that the management meets their

obligations.

As if defining profit and stockholder wealth were not difficult enough, the fiduciary duty of

the management also extends to other stakeholders, including employees, clients and to

23

society as a whole. For example, a firm may devote resources to social activities (typically

charities) that in no way directly increases the company's profits or the wealth of its

stockholders; but stockholders are part of society so they will benefit, albeit very indirectly,

from these social activities.

Furthermore, Drucker states that "Friedman's pure position to eschew all social responsibility

is not tenable. [. . .] Business and other institutions of our society [. . .] cannot be pure,

however desirable that may be. Their own self-interest alone forces them to be concerned

with society and community and to be predisposed to shoulder responsibility beyond their

own areas of task and responsibility".57 This statement shows that he acknowledges the

necessity of corporate social responsibility and the following statement tells us that he also

believes that there is a limit to this responsibility. He says, “The first task is to make the

institution . . . perform the function and make the contribution for the sake of which it exists.

[. . .] Performance of its function is the institution's first social responsibility”.58

2.4.3 Risk

Furthermore, Orlando dismisses Maitland’s59 main arguments justifying the assertion that

management has duties to stockholders over those to other parties. Maitland, privileges

stockholders over other parties firstly, because of the risk shouldered by investing into the

company and secondly, for their absorption of any costs of mismanagement.

His argument is that employees, when downsized, also have to absorb the cost of

mismanagement. They risked something in accepting a job opportunity (such as bypassing a

possible better job opportunity, loss of the home purchased in the expectation of a steady

income, loss of societal status) and consequently the position of the employees is not

dissimilar to that of the stockholders. He concludes by pointing out that the only difference

between the risks taken by the two parties is that of degree. The degree of risk assumed will

depend upon the individual situation of each.

The aspect of the risk of the employees will be considered below.

57Cf. Drucker, P., (1974): “Management: Tasks, Responsibilities, Practices”, New York: Harper & Row, p. 349. 58 Drucker, P.: supra note 47. p. 343. 59 Orlando, J,: supra note 1, p. 300.

24

2.4.4 Contracts

Maitland’s argument to justify management’s duties to stockholders over those of other

parties is that company-stakeholder rights and obligations are fundamentally established in a

“freely chosen [. . .].nexus [. . .].of contracts.” 60 Furthermore, he states that the terms of

these contracts have been determined under free, voluntary, and uncoerced bargaining

circumstances and that, when third parties tinker with an agreed arrangement, they violate the

rights to self-determination of the parties involved .

In questioning the veracity of these arguments, Orlando, firstly in reference to Sonderquist

and Vecchio, argues that“ most shareholders expect corporate managers to take into account

the interests of other constituencies when making decisions about the welfare of the

corporation;” 61 and secondly to Boatrights, that stockholders have the tendency to “think of

themselves not as owners of the corporation, but rather as investors in it”62 and therefore

have multitudinous investment opportunities.

Additionally he questions how investors can act under the assumption of an unstated contract

between themselves, the management and the employees. On the other hand, citing Reich, he

adds “employees have traditionally assumed that taking a job meant having it for life as long

as they perform their duties well.”63 Therefore on the basis of the implicit contract and

expectations of the contracting parties the evidence is contrary to the arguments put forward

by Maitland.

Considerations on the nexus of explicit and implicit contracts (2)

The theory of explicit and implicit contractual or contract-like agreements suggests a complex

bargaining process. Stockholders and employees do not bargain directly, but only indirectly

through management. Once we recognize the existence of implicit contracts (and incomplete

contracting) then other stakeholders besides the stockholders are residual claimants and these

stakeholders may need to be protected. It is now not clear whether decision rights should

reside exclusively with stockholders, because the unfettered pursuit of stockholders’ value

maximization may lead to the breach of valuable implicit contracts as it would be the case

when downsizing is contemplated.

60 Orlando, J,: supra note 1, p. 300. 61 Orlando, J,: supra note 1, p. 301. 62 Orlando, J,: supra note 1, p. 301. 63 Orlando, J,: supra note 1, p. 301.

25

2.4.5 Other People’s Money

Fiedman argues that "the corporation is an instrument of the stockholders who own it,”64 and

thus says that to divert business financial resources for public interest away from the purposes

expressly authorized by the stockholders represents an impermissible use of those resources.

In answer to this point of view, Orlando replies that such an act, to be considered

impermissible, must be unauthorized and he adds (see above) that most stockholders expect

managers to take into account considerations beyond maximizing profits. He concludes that

“it is a generally accepted principle that moral duties "transfer through" from principal to

agent, such that if it is morally forbidden for me to do something, then it is forbidden for me

to enlist an agent to act on my behalf.”65 Thus, an act of downsizing, by virtue of the fact that

it is performed by the management as an agent of, and in the interests of, the stockholders,

must be considered wrong.

Considerations on other people’s money

At the heart of stakeholder theory lays the distribution of the benefits created by joint effort

(e.g. pooled contributions). As Boatright points out, there is nothing inherently special about

stakeholders in a joint effort situation and he states that what’s special is who contributes

capital, given the economic value of that contribution.66 By the same logic, there is nothing

special about any class of stakeholders in that situation, and this includes employees. But if

employees exit, the company fails. The opposite is also true: if the company fails, employees

will suffer a loss impacting the own well-being. However, assuming that contributions are

variable but taking no account of relative power, two possibilities exist: either all stakeholders

should receive equal benefits, or each stakeholder should receive a share of benefits in

proportion to his/her own contribution.

2.4.6 Private vs. Public

Friedman states that, in requiring the company to perform supererogatory duties (e.g. advance

social goals that exceed the legal requirements) in ways that have not been authorized by the

stockholders, the management would not only break the moral obligation derived from

fiduciary duty and accordingly violate the autonomy of the stockholders, but also usurp the

political function and disrupt the private/public distinction which is at the heart of the free

64 Orlando, J,: supra note 1, p. 302. 65 Orlando, J,: supra note 1, p. 302. 66 Cf. Boatright, J., (1994): “Fiduciary Duties and the Shareholder-management Relation: Or, What’s so Special

about Shareholders”, Business Ethics Quarterly 4, pp. 393-407.

26

market system.67 Orlando’s arguments against this are twofold. Firstly, the existence of a

company is an entity permitted by the state to serve the public good rather than to allow

individuals the right to self-enrichment. Secondly, Friedman’s argument cannot be applied in

the case of downsizing due to the fact that there is no public sector analogous to the service

being demanded of companies.

Considerations on private vs. public

Furthermore it must be noted, that a company by virtue of its implantation in a community,

becomes a member of this community, implying a certain degree of social responsibility. That

means that its stockholders and management have an obligation to support the structure

needed by the community to promote the welfare of its members.

2.4.7 The Utilitarian Argument

Using the arguments presented above in order to demonstrate the moral equality of employees

and stockholders, and in the absence of any adequate defence of downsizing, Orlando

challenges the utilitarian arguments commonly used to justify downsizing performed with the

scope to maximize stockholder’s wealth.

Utilitarianism focuses on the consequences that actions and policies have on the well-being

(utility) of all persons directly and directly affected by those actions or policies. The moral

principle holds that the moral correct course of action in any situation is the one that produces

the greatest balance of benefits over harm for all those affected. Thus, it could be argued that

downsizing benefits the majority of the population and, although some individuals will

necessarily fall by the wayside, the benefit to the whole outweighs the harm done to the few.

Orlando doubts whether downsizing has generated a net gain in utility and refers to a study by

Cascio,68 which demonstrates that when downsizings are performed for the sole purpose of

lowering costs, and are not accompanied by a careful restructuring of the company, this has

always negatively impacted the productivity of the company. To corroborate his doubts he

refers again to Reich,69 who notes that employee loyalty in the United States has decreased as

a consequence of downsizing and that this will negatively impact the company’s overall

performance. Considering the inconclusive evidence that downsizing improves net utility in

the long term, and dismissing the equation of well-being with financial gain, since the harm

67 Orlando, J,: supra note 1, p. 302. 68 Orlando, J,: supra note 1, p. 305. 69 Orlando, J,: supra note 1, p. 305.

27

caused by unemployment cannot be measured in term of pecuniary considerations, he

concludes that utilitarian considerations do not clearly support the rationale of downsizing.

Utilitarian considerations on downsizing as last resort to save the company

If the company, and with it the jobs of remaining employees, can only be saved be reducing

the workforce, then, from a utilitarian point of view, the benefits of employment for all those

who remain justifies the harm of those laid off. Further benefits can be found in the happiness

of other stakeholders, who otherwise would be harmed by the company’s bankruptcy. Given

this situation, the utilitarian approach would, in my opinion, clearly condone layoffs as the

moral thing to do. However, the situation is intriguing because, when a company in serious

distress, there is usually a perceived need to act quickly. Considerations of other possible

alternatives are often not possible due to time constraints and to limited financial resources.

Layoffs can be organized quickly but will not guarantee the survival of the company unless

reorganization is properly carried out. The only way to know for sure whether a company is in

a downsizing situation, or whether it is actually in the process of going out of business, is to

wait and see. Yet this knowledge would be of very little comfort to management and

employees to find out, only afterwards, that layoffs had been required to escape bankruptcy

and that inaction would have resulted in the loss of all employment. However, the luxury of

waiting for the definite answer is, in reality, simply not a viable option.

2.5 Arguments Against Downsizing

The first argument presented by Orlando is based on “the widely held intuition that is wrong

to subject individuals to certain type of harms in order to benefit others” or, as he explains

later, “that causing a great harm for a lesser benefit, even to the great number of people,

cannot be morally justified”. Furthermore, he adds that there are some who believe that “no

amount of harm to an individual can be justified on grounds that it will benefit others, since

harms and benefits are incommensurable commodities.” 70

Applying the cited arguments to an example where the management of a company downsizes

with the unique purpose of maximizing the wealth of the stockholders, he concludes that the

negative consequences (harm) supported by the employees (unemployment) cannot justify the

benefits earned by the stockholders. This is because harm (as elucidated in the example

above) is not a simple by-product of an act which independently brings benefit, but rather is

the means to that benefit. 70 Orlando, J,: supra note 1, p. 305.

28

The second argument refers to the legitimate expectations of the individuals involved. In a

first step, Orlando enumerates the expectations of the employees, who have made plans for

their own as well for their family’s well-being under the assumption of a steady source of

income. In a second step, he analyzes the expectations of the stockholders, who were aware of

the inherent risks when entering into the stock market, summarizing and concluding as

follows: (1) no reasonable investor would use his/her home or other important items to back

the future performance of a security; (2) expectations of a certain long-term rate of return; (3)

the premise that a company has obligations to parties other than themselves.

Comments on investor expectations

At the base of the various investment instruments is an expanding ethical investor group that

relies on the information presented in annual company reports in order to make investment

decisions. The ethical investor bases investment decisions not only on economic

considerations but also on social, ecological or ethical considerations. Many believe that

ethical investors form a clientele that responds to a demonstration of social concerns.

Investors of this type tend to avoid particular investments for entirely ethical reasons and

would prefer to favour socially responsible company in their portfolios. Those social investors

are not necessarily sacrificing their economic well-being. As a matter of fact, an emerging

theory of social investments proposes that social and economic values can be maximized

together, and that this creative synergy is the practical direction taken by social investors

today.71 This type of investor is assumed to contribute to the development of an economy

geared to promoting social values and companies as well as self-interests.

Comments on the legitimate expectations of the employees and community

A company that establishes an operation in a community, especially when not as a result of

political incentives, surely understands that its employees and the members of the community

have some legitimate long-term economic expectations. They expect to exercise their right to

access resources. The company cannot exist purely to generate profits for the stockholder; in

the wider social context it is a mechanism for people other than the stockholders to meet their

economic needs. The management of the company knows full well that the community will

incur long-term costs in terms of the infrastructure that will serve the operation. So, while a

company may not enter an explicit contract with the community that it will remain in a

location for a long period of time, it can be assumed that makes an implicit contract to stay

71 Cf. Bruyn, S. T., (1987): “The Field of Social Investment”, Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

29

there as long as it is profitable. Unless the company has explicitly declared from the

beginning that its operation will last for a limited time in a specific location, a company does

have some long-term commitment to its employees and the community in which it operates,

so long as it can sustain a reasonable level of profitability. It would be morally questionable,

therefore, for a company to close an operation just because it could benefit more in some

other location and could better maximize the profit of its stockholders as a result.

Stockholders, as one of the residual claimants do have a right to a profit, to access resources

for their benefit through their company, but that right is limited by the larger context of social

and distributive justice in a free-market economic system.

Employees may not be the legal owner of a company, but the full moral respect of their rights

and the respect for their dignity as people demands that they have some say in decisions

profoundly affecting their lives and well-being. That means that, in the case of a downsizing

as a last resort to save the company, they need, at the very least, sufficient advance notice of a

contemplated downsizing in order to be able to make plans to cope with it. The company

should, at least, listen to the employees’ objections, consider their economic needs and listen

to proposed alternatives. There may be some legal obligation to relocate employees willing to

move to other companies at the company’s expense, to assist employees with losses caused

by a depressed real-estate market, and to offer retraining and re-employment services for

those employees who cannot move.

2.5.1 Rights and Duties

2.5.1.1 Introduction

Rights are entitlements, by virtue of which, one person justifiably lays claim to an object or

state of being against another person who has an obligation to respect that claim. One respects

a claim by providing the object claimed, assisting in the achievement of the state which is

being claimed, or, at the very least, not standing in the way of the obtainment of the object or

the achievement of the state of being.72 Therefore, a right can be defined as either a capacity,

possession, or condition of existence, which entitles either an individual or a group to the

enjoyment of some object or state of being. Of course, if one person has a right, another

person must necessarily have an obligation to respect that right. Hence, a right is a relational

entity.

72 Cf. Duska, R., (2002): “Employee Rights “, A Companion to Business Ethics”, Blackwell Publishers 2002, pp.

257-268.

30

2.5.1.2 The Rights of Employees

The comments that I make concerning the moral rights of employees will be based on the

perception of the relationship between employee and company. From a moral perspective the

employee –company relationship can be viewed as reciprocal, and it is a relationship in which

moral obligation exists by virtue of this relationship. Because the two parties will have

different views of what their relationship is, or ought to be, this will lead to their making

different claims as concerns their rights and obligations.

For the purpose of this paper I will summarize and analyse only those employee rights which

in my opinion are directly affected by downsizing as a last resort with the purpose to save the

company from bankruptcy.

2.5.1.3 The Rights to Job Security and due Process in Firing

Considering the inherent reciprocal relationship involving interdependencies between the

employee and the company, explicit or implicit agreements and promises are entered into

when employment is offered and accepted. Hence, it can be deducted that there is a right to

job security, which means the employee has the right to keep the job so long as there is no

good reason for terminating the agreement. Therefore, it is incumbent on the employer to

allow the employee the right to due process when making decisions concerning the latter’s

welfare. Such decisions involve a redefinition and a renegotiation of the original

understanding implied at the outset.

2.5.1.4 The Right to Information

The concept of rights suggests that employees have the right to as much information as

possible about the company they work for, their job, the possibilities of continued

employment, and any other information necessary for job enrichment and development. 73

In downsizing situations, particularly during the process of communicating to employees the

aspects of the downsizing that will personally affect them and their jobs, violations of this

concept often occur. Pompa states that deontologically, if withholding information constitutes

deception which limits employees’ informed choice about their work status, then it violates

73 Cf. Werhane, P. H., (1985): “Persons, Rights and Corporation”, Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, NJ.

31

the Kantian imperative to treat others as ends in themselves, not merely as means.74 With

respect to downsizing, the concept of rights means that it can be argued that employees have

rights (i.e. the right to be informed) that must not be violated during the formulation and

implementation of downsizing procedures. If employees are denied these rights, they are

likely to perceive that ethical violations have occurred.

Organizational downsizing demands that management communicate a great deal with

employees. The primary focus of this communication is downwards; specifically, explaining

the rationale for the changes that have to be made. But companies should ensure the

opportunity for upward communication to allow employees to vent their fears and

frustrations, and to receive answers to their questions.

2.5.1.5 The Right to Co-determination

If one recognizes that human beings are the source and the purpose of economics, and that

labour not only serves the production of goods and services but also the development of the

person, then the employee must have a say in the shaping of his activity. Accordingly, in

those matters which seriously affect employees, co-determination in deciding their own fate is

seen as a right.

Although the right to participate in matters affecting workers is controversial, the fact

becomes tenable if the asymmetry of power between the employee and the company and its

impact on the negotiation of employment agreements is recognised. This right can be seen as

a protection against the potential abuse of power that can develop from such asymmetry.

Furthermore, for both explicit and implicit contracts to be morally binding, they need to be

based on informed mutual consent and, if need be, they should be redefined accordingly.

2.5.2 Fairness

In Orlando’s opinion, fairness is the fact that “the arbitrary conditions of one's situation ought

not to count against one's life prospects. The idea here is that the individual does not deserve

the rewards or punishments that come via things for which she is not responsible”.75

Excluding dismissals due to employee incompetence, and which should not be considered as

downsizing, he concludes that the cases of downsizing that are carried out with the aim of

overall profitability are most likely imputable to causes of mismanagement than to the fault of

74 Cf. Pompa, V., (1992): “Managerial Secrecy. An Ethical Examination”, Journal of Business Ethics 11, pp.

147 – 156. 75 Orlando J.,: supra note 1, p. 308.

32

the employees. Therefore, since the employees are not at fault for mismanagement but have to

absorb the adverse consequences, an act of downsizing must be considered unfair.

Furthermore, he adds that the stockholders cannot claim to deserve the increase in the value of

their investments due solely to laying off employees.

Comments on fairness

In certain cases, the psychological effects of downsizing are aggravated by excessive

management compensation. Theoretically, management compensation is neutral and should

not influence, or be influenced by, downsizing. Nevertheless, management tend to take all the

credit for profitability and blame employees for all the red ink. If downsizing is indeed the

best solution to a problem, it makes no sense to reward the management with undue

generosity for doing precisely what they were hired to do. Is one to presume that they were

hired to run their companies into the ground, and that they should get a bonus if they do not?

If it is the responsibility of the management to maintain an efficient organization, they should

be paid their regular salaries if they do so and punished if they do not. A bonus for doing the

ordinary makes no sense.

Downsizing as a last resort to save the company

In this specific case, when considering the fairness of downsizing, both distributive and

procedural justice are important.76 Distributive justice is related to what is decided, whereas

procedural justice is related to how decisions are made. With downsizing, both the end result

and the determining process need to be fair. It has been found that procedural justice is

closely related to attitudes toward the organization and its authorities (e.g. trust in supervision

and organizational commitment), whereas distributive justice is a better predictor of

satisfaction. Satisfaction with supervision strongly correlates with good citizenship. Both

distributive and procedural justice determined satisfaction, while organizational commitment

was determined by perception of procedural fairness. If employees can be guaranteed fair

procedural treatment, they are more likely to stay with the company and become loyal

members. If the events associated with allocation (the means) are just, it is more difficult to

question outcomes (the end). On the other hand, if procedural justice is determined to be

unfair, then employees are more likely to retaliate by using destructive tactics against the

management. This tactics may be harmful to other people, to the management and to the

public.

76 Cf. Cropanzano, R., and Folger R., (1991): “Procedural Justice and Worker Motivation”. R.M. Steers &

L.W.Porter (eds). Motivation and work behaviour New York, pp. 302-317.

33

A review of the literature relating to the effects of downsizing lead me to conclude that those

affected by a downsizing decision will likely perceive the decision to be unethical unless it is

communicated at an inappropriate time, in an inappropriate way, and the communication

about the downsizing contains no information perceived as critical. Each of these dimensions

(timing, method, and content) is discussed below.

• Timing of the downsizing communiqué

The impact of providing advance warning of a reduction in the workforce has

received substantial attention among researchers. Numerous studies have shown that

advance warning can greatly benefit a person facing a job loss and translates into

fewer weeks of unemployment and less reported stress and anger toward the

organization,77 and less financial strain.78

Advance warning may also give an employee time to deal psychologically with the

event and to develop coping strategies to reduce the stress associated with job loss.79

Such active coping strategies appear to be very important in overcoming the

emotional trauma of job loss.80 Therefore, in addition to suffering less financially,

individuals who receive advance warning of dismissal may be more likely to report

emotional acceptance of the job loss, rather than reactions such as depression or

anger.

• Method of communicating downsizing

The ethical dimension of downsizing takes into account the importance of the method

that a company uses to inform employees of an impending downsizing. The manner in

77 Cf. Feldman, D. C. and C. R. Leana, (1989): “Managing Layoffs: Experiences at the Challenger Disaster Site

and the Pittsburgh Steel Mills”, Organizational Dynamics 18, pp. 52–64.; and Kinicki, A. J., (1985): “Personal Consequences of Plant Closings: A Model and Preliminary Test”, Human Relations 38, pp, 197–212.

78 Cf. Love, D. O. and W. D. Torrence, (1989): “The Value of Advance Notice of Worker Displacement” Southern Economic Journal, pp. 626–643.; and Popma, V.,: supra note 74.

79 Cf. Kinicki, A. J.,: supra note 77.; and Latack, J. C., A. J. Kinicki and G. A. Prussia, (1995): “An Integrative Process Model of Coping with Job Loss”, Academy of Management Journal 20, pp. 311–342.

80 Cf. Leana, C. R. and D. C. Feldman, (1994): “The Psychology of Job Loss”, in G. R. Ferris (ed.), Research in Personnel and Human Resources Management (JAI Press, Greenwich), pp. 271–302.

34

which dismissals are communicated to employees also appears to be important.81

Following job loss, an employee may feel as if the transactional contract of job

security and the relational contract of reciprocal goodwill have been violated.

Perceptions of violated contracts may be magnified if the termination decision is

communicated in such a way that is inconsistent with the employee’s self-esteem.82

In the absence of communication of the dismissal by a supervisor and the provision of

a rationale for dismissal, feelings of outrage and resentment on the part of dismissed

employees may make emotional acceptance of the job loss much more difficult.83

Thus, by providing an external attribution for the decision (e.g., poor corporate

performance), both of these actions may help dismissed employees regain a sense of

control and afford them a chance to openly discuss the decision with their

supervisor.84

Furthermore, when learning about downsizing decisions, employees are likely to

perceive that the own rights (e.g. breach of the implied agreement) have been violated

if they first hear about the downsizing from outside sources rather than from formal

organizational channels within the company. This likelihood is supported by Pompa’s 85 study on managerial secrecy and the ethical implications of withholding information

about impending downsizings. In such cases, employees are likely to feel that they are

being manipulated or controlled, tricked, or at the very least subjected to impersonal,

uncaring treatment by their respective employer.

• Content of the downsizing communiqué

This ethical dimension of downsizing considers whether employees are provided with

a reason for the downsizing and other relevant information. According to Conrad, one

of the most consistent findings in research on organizational communications is that

81 Cf. Latack, J. C. and J. B. Dozier, (1986): “After the Ax Falls: Job Loss as a Career Transition”, Academy of

Management Journal 11, 375–392.; and Smeltzer, L. R. and M. E. Zener, (1992): “Development of a Model for Announcing Major Layoffs”, Group and Organization Management 17, pp. 446–472.

82 Cf. Latack, J. C. and J. B. Dozie,: see supra note 81. 83 Cf. Latack, J. C. and J. B. Dozier: supra note 81.; And Leana, C. R. andJ. M. Ivancevich, (1987): “Involuntary

Job Loss: Institutional Interventions and Research Agenda”, Academy of Management Journal 12, pp. 301–312.

84 Cf. Latack, J. C. and J. B. Dozier: supra note 81.; and Miller, M. V. And S. K. Hoppe, (1994): “Attributions for Job Termination and Psychological Distress” Human Relations 47, pp. 307–327.

85 Pompa, V.: supra note 74.

35

employees feel that they receive too little relevant and useful information about events

which directly affect them and their jobs.86

Furthermore, if dismissal is communicated to the employee by someone other than

the employee’s immediate supervisor, it may be particularly dehumanizing and

stressful. 87 The stress of job loss may also be exacerbated if the supervisor fails to

provide a rationale for dismissal. A legitimate explanation may help to buffer the

shock of dismissal and help the employee to come to terms with the decision, rather

than harboring feelings of self-doubt and victimization.88

Brockner89 recommends that organizations take time to provide an adequate,

unambiguous explanation for an impending downsizing, and he also suggests that the

content of the explanation include valid arguments for the necessity of the downsizing,

which employees may not have previously considered.

Moreover, the mere fact that time and effort was taken to provide an explanation and

other information about the downsizing symbolizes to employees that they are being

treated in a dignified and respectful way.90 Perceiving that they are being treated as

such, employees are likely to judge the downsizing process as fairer and be less prone

to seeing it as unethical.

The message here is that the ethical, or at least proper, handling of a downsizing is a

significant measure of management fairness and credibility. Viewed as such by employees,

they are likely to consider a downsizing and the manner in which it is carried out to be

ethical if (1) they are told of the downsizing by management rather than learning about it in

the press; (2) they are given sufficient advance notice and are informed of their personal

status in order to be able to take steps to adjust their personal plans accordingly; and (3)

they are provided with a clear corporate message that explains the reasons for the

downsizing.

86 Cf. Conrad, C., (1985): “Strategic Organizational Communication: Cultures, Situations, and Adaptation” ,

Holt, Rinehart and Winston, New York. 87 Latack, J. C. and J. B. Dozier: supra note 81. 88 Feldman, D. C. and C. R. Leana: supra note 78. And Latack, J. C. and J. B. Dozier: supra note 81 89 Cf. Brockner J.: “Managing the Effects of Layoffs on Survivors”, California Management Review, pp. 9-28. 90 Cf. Tyler, T. R. and R. J. Bies, (1990): “Beyond Formal Procedures: The Interpersonal Context of

Procedural justice”, in J. S. Carrol (ed.), Applied Social Psychology and Organizational Settings, Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ.

36

2.6 Conclusion

In analysing the issue of the moral permissibility of downsizing in I have first briefly

elucidated the two widely discussed theories of corporate social responsibility encompassing

the stockholder and stakeholder theories on the background of the socially responsible

restructuring concept. Subsequently I have summarized and commented some of the

arguments presented by John Orlando in challenging the reasons advanced for privileging the

interest of stockholders above all other parties and found no disagreement with. Finally, in

using the three basic theories commonly used in managerial ethics, which are the utilitarian,

the rights and duties, and the justice and fairness approaches I have analyzed the issue of the

morality of layoffs. The views of these three basic theories generally coincide.

Where downsizings are contemplated in an attempt to change a company that is already

performing well and which does not appear to be in danger with the sole purpose of

maximizing stockholder wealth in accordance with the stockholder theory, none of the three

approaches supports the conclusion that such an act is permissible from an ethical point of

view. This situation does not achieve the greatest good for the greatest number due to the fact

that is wrong to subject individuals to certain type of harm in order to benefits others. The

right and duties approach suggests that the rights of the employees to job security and due

process in firing are violated due to fact that there are no good reasons for terminating the

employment agreement. Finally the justice and fairness approach, does not find layoffs to be

moral, because they lack proportionality between the individuals behaviour (good

performance) and the resulting action (termination of employment).

In the extreme case where downsizing is the only way to save the company, I am of the

opinion that the utilitarian approach finds the decision to conduct layoffs to be moral justified,

because layoffs generate the most good for the greatest number of utilities. The rights and

duties approach requires that downsizing be conducted in a fair and just manner because

employees do have a right to be treated fairly. Finally the justice and fairness approach, find

layoffs to be at least permissible from a moral stand point, if the welfare of the employees is

seriously considered and the necessary procedural steps are properly implemented.

37

3. Overall Conclusion

In today's company, professional amorality turns into economic morality. When the screws of

the performance control systems are turned tight, economic morality can turn into social

immorality.91

This is exactly the situation when companies decide to downsize, citing inherent necessity and

economic realities as the main reason. However, strategic decisions, such as the decision to

downsize, ultimately encompass social as well as economic outcomes that are positively

interrelated. The breach of promise to society is perhaps the most serious implication of all

because everyone is hurt as a result. The rationale commonly used to describe the benefits of

a particular cost management effort appears flawed, not only in terms of its return to the

company, but to the society in which it operates as well. Continuous implementations of

restructuring efforts that do not appear to have focus are evidence of this rationale, which

continues to cause damage to employees’ lives and to the company itself. The reduction of the

workforce for the singular purpose of reduced cost and to maximize profit for the

stockholders is not only morally wrong, but also breaches the integrity of the company in

relation to the quality of its contribution to the overall health of society. A profit oriented

approach simply leads to a restriction of a company’s definition of goals and an indifference

to the means by which these goals are pursued.

91 Cf. Mintzberg H., Quinn J., and Voyer J., (1995): “The strategy process”. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice

Hall, p. 213.

38

4. Bibilography

Ackoff R., (1981) Creating the Corporate Future. New York: John Wiley and

Sons. Billings, R. S., Milburn T. W., and Schaalman M. L., (1980)

Administrative Science Quarterly, vol. 25.

Boatright, J., (1994) Business Ethics Quarterly 4. Bruyn, S. T., (1987) The Field of Social Investment, Cambridge. MA: Cambridge

University Press. Brockner, J., (1992) Managing the Effects of Layoffs on Survivors. California

Management Review. Brockner, J., Grover S., O'Mally M., DeWitt R., Reed T., (1992)

Academy of Management Journal, vol. 35, no. 2, pp. 413-426.

Budros, A., (1999) Organization Science 10, pp. 69-83. Cameron, K., (1983) Journal of Higher Education, vol. 54, no. 4. Cappelli, P., (2000) A Market-driven Approach to Retaining Talent. Harvard

Business Review 78, pp. 103-104. Casio, W.F., (2002) The Academy of Management Executive. Chadwick, C., L.W. Hunter and S.L. Walston, (2004)

Strategic Management Journal 25, pp. 405-427.

Conrad, C., (1985) Strategic organizational communication: Cultures, situations, and adaptation. Holt, Rinehart and Winston, New York.

Cropanzano, R., and Folger R., (1991)

Procedural Justice and Worker Motivation. R.M. Steers & L.W.Porter (eds). Motivation and work behaviour NY.

De Meuse, K.P., T.J. Bergmann, P.A. Vanderheiden and C.E. Roraff, (2004)

New Evidence Regarding Organizational Downsizing and a Firm’s Financial Performance: A Long-term Analysis. Journal of Management Issues 16

Drucker, P., (1974) Management: Tasks, Responsibilities, Practices. New York: Harper & Row.

Duska, R., (2002) A Companion to Business Ethics. Blackwell Publishers 2002 Evan W.E., and Freeman R.E., (1993)

Ethical Theory and Business. ed. Tom L. Beauchamp and Norman E. Bowie, Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.

Feldman, D. C. and C. R. Leana, (1989)

Organizational Dynamics vol. 18.

Freeman, S. J., and Cameron K. S., (1993)

Organizational Downsizing: A Convergence and Reorientation Framework. Organization Science, vol. 4.

Freeman R. E., (1984) Business Management: A Stakeholder Approach. Boston: Ballinger.

Frederick, W., Post J., and Davis K., (1992)

7th ed. New York: McGraw-Hill.

Friedman, M., (1970) New York Times Magazine, September 13, 1970. Glebbeek, A.C. and E.H Bax, (2004) Academy of Management Journal 47, pp.277-286. Goodpaster, K.E., (2002) Ethical Issues in Business. ed. Thomas Donaldson, Patricia H.

Werhane and Margaret Cording, Upper Saddle River,: N.J. Hall, D. T., and Mansfield R.: (1971) Administrative Science Quarterly, vol. 16. Hammer, M., and J. Champy, (1994) Reengineering the Corporation. New York: Harper Business.

39

Hardy, C., (1987) California Management Review, vol. 4. Homepage American Management Association, New York.

www.amanet.org/research Homepage Management Development Branch of the International

Labour Organization (ILO) and the European Bahá'í Business Forum www.ilo.org

Homepage The Economist. www.economist.com/research Jones T., (1980) California Management Review, spring. Kantz, J., (1985) Journal of Applied Behavioral Science, vol. 21 Latack, J. C., and H. G. Kaufman (1988)

M. London and E. M. Mone (eds.), Career Growth and Human Resource Strategies, Quorum Books, New York.

Latack, J. C., A. J. Kinicki and G. A. Prussia, (1995):

Academy of Management Journal vol. 20.

Leana, C. R. and D. C. Feldman, (1994)

The psychology of job loss. in G. R. Ferris (ed.), Research in Personnel and Human Resources Management, JAI Press, Greenwich.

Leana, C. R. and J. M. Ivancevich, (1987)

Involuntary Job Loss: Institutional Interventions and Research Agenda. Academy of Management Journal vol. 12.

Mahoney, J., C.C. Asher, and J. Mahoney, (2004)

Academy of Management Policy Strategy (BPS) Division Symposium in New Orleans.

Morrall, A. Jr., (1998) Human Resource Development Quarterly. McKinley, W., (1987) Administrative Science Quarterly, vol. 32. Newman, K. S., (1988) Falling From Grace: The Experience of Downward Mobility in

the American Middle Class. The Free Press, NY. Orlando, J., (1999) The fourth wave: The ethics of corporate downsizing. Business

Ethics Quarterly, Volume 9. Perry, L. T., (1986) Organizational Dynamics, vol. 14. Pitelis C.N., (2004) Corporate Governance 12. Pompa, V., (1992) Managerial Secrecy. An Ethical Examination. Journal of

Business Ethics 11. Smeltzer, L. R. and M. E. Zener, (1992)

Development of a Model for Announcing Major Layoffs. Group and Organization Management 17.

Tyler, T. R. and R. J. Bies, (1990) Beyond formal procedures: The interpersonal context of procedural justice. J. S. Carrol (ed.), Applied Social Psychology and Organizational Settings, Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ.

Steiner G. A., and Steiner J. F., (1994)

ed. New York: McGraw-Hill

Sethi P., (1997) Managing Corporate Social Responsibility. Boston, Little, Brown & Company.

Vanderheiden, P.A., K.P., De Meuse, and T.J. Bergmann, (1999)

Human Resources Management 38, pp. 261-268.

Werhane, P. H., (1985): Persons, rights and corporation. Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, NJ.

40

5. Selbständigkeitserklärung

“Ich erkläre hiermit, dass ich diese Arbeit selbständig verfasst und keine anderen als die

angegebenen Hilfsmittel benutzt habe. Alle Stellen, die wörtlich oder sinngemäss aus Quellen

übernommen wurden, habe ich als solche kenntlich gemacht. Mir ist bekannt, dass adernfalls

der Senat gemäss dem Gestz über die Universität zum Entzug des auf Grund dieser Arbeit

verliehenen Titels berechtigt ist.“

Zürich den 20. Januar 2007

Arturo Giovanoli


Recommended