+ All Categories
Home > Documents > On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts · On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts ......

On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts · On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts ......

Date post: 28-Mar-2020
Category:
Upload: others
View: 4 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend
28
ehaviorology oday Volume 7, Number 2, Fall 2004 (issn 1536–6669) Page 9 On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts Lawrence E. Fraley West Virginia University Editor’s note: Interest in the behaviorological analysis of verbal behavior (Skinner, ) continues to grow. (For an example see the editor’s note to Fraley, , which is Part of this paper. Also see the syllabi for ’s two online verbal behavior courses, –Verbal Behavior I, and –Verbal Behavior II. These syllabi appear, re- spectively, in these issues of Behaviorology Today: Vol- ume , Number , and Volume , Number .) To help support continuing interest in verbal behav- ior, Behaviorology Today presents this four–part series on verbal behavior. The first part appeared in Volume , Number . This is the second part. And the remaining parts will appear in the next two issues. (One part appears in each consecutive issue, beginning with Volume , Number .) All four parts derive from a chapter of the author’s book General Behaviorology: The Natural Science of Human Behavior. (See the “General Behaviorology” page at www.behaviorology.org for more detailed informa- tion on this book.) For each part, the headings hint at the contents: Some interesting headings in Part 1 (Fraley, ) were: Terminological Issues, The Antecedent Control of Verbal Behavior, How Instances of Verbal Behavior are Classified, and The Mand. In Part 2 some interesting headings are: Verbal Behav- ior Under the Control of Verbal Stimuli, The Tact, Abstrac- tion, Private Events, Reality, and Temporal Relations. Some interesting headings in Part 3 are: Autoclitic Verbal Behavior, Descriptive Autoclitics, Autoclitics that Function as Mands, Qualifying Autoclitics, Quantifying Autoclitics, Grammar and Syntax as Autoclitic Processes, and The Nature and Occurrence of Composition. In Part 4 some interesting headings are: The Private Verbal Behavior of Thinking, The Productivity of Thought, The Utility of Thought, Issues of Privacy and Antiquity, The Absence of Thinking, and Nonverbal Consciousness. Here is Part 2.—Ed.* Part 2 Verbal Behavior under the Control of Verbal Stimuli ith an appropriate conditioning history, verbal be- havior may occur under the antecedent stimulus control of other verbal behavior or its products, such as printed text. Such an antecedently functional (evocative) class of verbal behavior may be provided by other persons, as when a teacher speaks the new vocabulary word emulate, and a student repeats the word emulate. However, the vocalizer’s own verbal behavior can also function to evoke the vocalizer’s additional verbal behavior, as when a per- son who is thinking or saying “two, four, six,…” then produces “eight.” Thus, in the major class of verbal be- havior that is discussed in this section, the analytical con- cern is with why the response has occurred rather than with its after–eects. This diers from the analysis of mands, which was carried forward in time to reveal how a mand aected a potential mediator. Examples of Controlling Relations in this Class Suppose that a parent mands a child to say uncle, whereupon the child says uncle. Such a mand is called an instruction, and it may be said that the child has complied with the instruction (although the child’s response was functionally evoked by the mand and was not a willful compliance by a mystical internal child–agent). If we analyze the antecedent controls on the child’s reaction, we can attribute the child’s utterance in general to the manding nature of the parent’s instruction. The child has been conditioned to behave in ways that rein- force the parent and therefore lead to reinforcing reac- tions from the parent. The child is also conditioned to avoid the parent’s punitive reactions, which may follow any noncompliant behavior from the child. In this ex- ample, the parent’s statement in the form of a mand to ...say… controls the utterance of some kind of vocal re- sponse by the child. Say insures that the child’s response will manifest vocally, while uncle controls the form of the vocal response that will be reinforced by the audience. Note that in this section of the chapter our analytical attention is focused on what controlled the mediator’s re- sponse, and of interest is the fact that it was a verbal stimulus (i.e., uncle). In common agential language it is said that those fea- tures of the parental instruction that define it as a mand to speak make clear to the child that a vocal response is now required. Note, however, that mands are not instruments ___________________________________________ *The author’s footnotes are at the end of the paper.
Transcript
Page 1: On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts · On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts ... Interest in the behaviorological analysis of verbal behavior (Skinner, ) continues

�ehaviorology �oday � Volume 7, Number 2, Fall 2004 (issn 1536–6669) Page 9

On Verbal Behavior:The Second of Four Parts

Lawrence E. FraleyWest Virginia University

Editor’s note: Interest in the behaviorological analysis ofverbal behavior (Skinner, ) continues to grow. (Foran example see the editor’s note to Fraley, , which isPart of this paper. Also see the syllabi for ’s two onlineverbal behavior courses, –Verbal Behavior I, and –Verbal Behavior II. These syllabi appear, re-spectively, in these issues of Behaviorology Today: Vol-ume , Number , and Volume , Number .)

To help support continuing interest in verbal behav-ior, Behaviorology Today presents this four–part series onverbal behavior. The first part appeared in Volume ,Number . This is the second part. And the remainingparts will appear in the next two issues. (One part appearsin each consecutive issue, beginning with Volume ,Number .) All four parts derive from a chapter of theauthor’s book General Behaviorology: The Natural Scienceof Human Behavior. (See the “General Behaviorology”page at www.behaviorology.org for more detailed informa-tion on this book.)

For each part, the headings hint at the contents:� Some interesting headings in Part 1 (Fraley, )

were: Terminological Issues, The Antecedent Control ofVerbal Behavior, How Instances of Verbal Behavior areClassified, and The Mand.

� In Part 2 some interesting headings are: Verbal Behav-ior Under the Control of Verbal Stimuli, The Tact, Abstrac-tion, Private Events, Reality, and Temporal Relations.

� Some interesting headings in Part 3 are: AutocliticVerbal Behavior, Descriptive Autoclitics, Autoclitics thatFunction as Mands, Qualifying Autoclitics, QuantifyingAutoclitics, Grammar and Syntax as Autoclitic Processes,and The Nature and Occurrence of Composition.

� In Part 4 some interesting headings are: The PrivateVerbal Behavior of Thinking, The Productivity of Thought,The Utility of Thought, Issues of Privacy and Antiquity,The Absence of Thinking, and Nonverbal Consciousness.

Here is Part 2.—Ed.*

Part 2Verbal Behavior under the Control

of Verbal Stimuli

�ith an appropriate conditioning history, verbal be-havior may occur under the antecedent stimulus controlof other verbal behavior or its products, such as printedtext. Such an antecedently functional (evocative) class ofverbal behavior may be provided by other persons, aswhen a teacher speaks the new vocabulary word emulate,and a student repeats the word emulate. However, thevocalizer’s own verbal behavior can also function to evokethe vocalizer’s additional verbal behavior, as when a per-son who is thinking or saying “two, four, six,…” thenproduces “eight.” Thus, in the major class of verbal be-havior that is discussed in this section, the analytical con-cern is with why the response has occurred rather thanwith its after–effects. This differs from the analysis ofmands, which was carried forward in time to reveal howa mand affected a potential mediator.

Examples of Controlling Relationsin this Class

Suppose that a parent mands a child to say uncle,whereupon the child says uncle. Such a mand is called aninstruction, and it may be said that the child has compliedwith the instruction (although the child’s response wasfunctionally evoked by the mand and was not a willfulcompliance by a mystical internal child–agent).

If we analyze the antecedent controls on the child’sreaction, we can attribute the child’s utterance in generalto the manding nature of the parent’s instruction. Thechild has been conditioned to behave in ways that rein-force the parent and therefore lead to reinforcing reac-tions from the parent. The child is also conditioned toavoid the parent’s punitive reactions, which may followany noncompliant behavior from the child. In this ex-ample, the parent’s statement in the form of a mand to...say… controls the utterance of some kind of vocal re-sponse by the child. Say insures that the child’s responsewill manifest vocally, while uncle controls the form of thevocal response that will be reinforced by the audience.Note that in this section of the chapter our analyticalattention is focused on what controlled the mediator’s re-sponse, and of interest is the fact that it was a verbalstimulus (i.e., uncle).

In common agential language it is said that those fea-tures of the parental instruction that define it as a mandto speak make clear to the child that a vocal response is nowrequired. Note, however, that mands are not instruments

___________________________________________

*The author’s footnotes are at the end of the paper.

Page 2: On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts · On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts ... Interest in the behaviorological analysis of verbal behavior (Skinner, ) continues

Page 10 (issn 1536–6669) �ehaviorology �oday � Volume 7, Number 2, Fall 2004

of persuasion that are directed at the inner child–agent inthe hope that such a residential agent will then deign towill that its host body produce a certain kind of response.Instead, as a result of the past conditioning, the parentalmand and the child’s response are now directly linked ina functional sense. Given that particular mand in thepresence of that appropriately conditioned body, the re-sponse is simply evoked (i.e., it simply happens, and atthat instant it is the only thing that can happen). If therelevant parts of the child’s body are currently in workingorder, but the manded response is not forthcoming, ourassumption about the adequacy of the child’s condition-ing history is thereby revealed to have been unwarranted.

Furthermore, as noted in the case of this particularmand, the form of an adequate response has also beenspecified. That is, the child’s vocal response matches theparent’s vocal stimulus. The child’s response is effectivemerely insofar as it echoes what the parent specifies. Theparent says uncle and the child responds uncle. Thus, theparent’s manded sample and the child’s correct response,considered as a pair of stimuli, exhibit two distinct char-acteristics: (a) what is called a point–to–point correspon-dence and (b) formal similarity.

Let us review the relevant controls: (a) The mandingform of the parent’s statement makes a response probable.(b) The verb say determines the vocal nature of the child’srequired response, and in particular that it be an echoicverbal response. (c) The vocalized term uncle preciselycontrols the form of the child’s echoic verbal response.

The relevant operant conditioning history that pre-pared the child for an appropriate response of this kind(a) increased the probability that the child’s respondingwill comport with any parental instructions, (b) increasedthe probability that the child will respond vocally afterhearing the word say, and (c) increased the probabilitythat the vocal response will have a point–to–point corre-spondence with any vocalized sample that follows theword say in a vocalizer’s mand. With those three kinds ofconditioning in place, the child is ready to perform in themanner featured in this example.1

Let us move on to other examples of behavior thatfall within this major class of verbal behavior. In the caseof textual behavior, the response (usually called reading)occurs under stimulus control of textual products.Someone’s earlier verbal behavior has resulted in a textualproduct that is now controlling the verbal behavior of thereader. During the early operant conditioning of suchtextual behavior (i.e., reading), a student may be pre-sented with a sequence of letters (e.g., ––––), fol-lowing which only the student’s audible sound “hous” isreinforced. The operant conditioning procedure is re-peated until that audible sound follows the presentationof that letter sequence with sufficient reliability. If thespoken word and the printed text are phonetically related

(e.g., the printed word tad and the spoken word tad), thespoken word exhibits a letter–to–sound correspondencewith the text in the sense that each printed letter evokesa distinct sound. Those sounds string together to makethe complete word–sound. Note, however, that such avocalized utterance bears no formal similarity to the se-quence of printed letters (i.e., sound forms and printforms are entirely different kinds of forms).2

During such training, in addition to being mandedto say the word, the student may also be manded to drawthe picture that is privately evoked either by the sequenceof letters or by the audible sound that they evoke. Notethat with respect to the word house, for the child to ren-der the drawing, some additional special conditioningmust have occurred in addition to the conditioning ofgeneral drawing skills. Either (a) the child, previously,must have contacted houses or pictures of houses, whileutterances of the audible sound house were being rein-forced differentially; or (b) the child, previously, musthave contacted houses or pictures of houses, that werepaired with the textual stimulus HOUSE.3

Given that the child has never before responded in agraphic way either to the spoken sound “hous” or to thewritten letters h–o–u–s–e (i.e., by drawing a picture of aconstructed dwelling), if the drawing does occur, its ap-pearance is evidence that prior conditioning of the kinddescribed above has established the stimulus equivalencerelations that are implicitly required for the child’s ex-hibition of the manded pictorial response (i.e., drawing ahouse). Note that in these functional relations, which fea-ture drawing behaviors, the spoken or textual stimulusand the drawn response do not have a point–to–pointcorrespondence (or any approximation thereof ) nor dothey have formal similarity.

Let us now reconsider text, such as that which youare now reading. Text is a product of previous verbal be-havior and for that reason is usually classed as a verbalstimulus. The person whose verbal behavior is controlledby text is usually called a reader. When reading aloud, avocal sound is produced in response to each functionalstimulus element. The particular graphic form of the tex-tual elements remains an independent variable, so whilea reader who is exhibiting textual verbal behavior may beresponding to printed words, syllables, or even single let-ters, that reader can also be responding to pictures, picto-graphs, or hieroglyphics. The only requirement is thatrepeated presentations of a given mark, or set of marks,reliably evoke the production of the same vocal sound.People refer to the conditioning history that establishesthose controlling relations as learning to read.

Not all reading falls in this major class of verbal be-havior. Here is an example of such an exception: Supposethat many boxes are hauled onto an aircraft. Each boxcontains round, white, –inch diameter disks that are

Page 3: On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts · On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts ... Interest in the behaviorological analysis of verbal behavior (Skinner, ) continues

�ehaviorology �oday � Volume 7, Number 2, Fall 2004 (issn 1536–6669) Page 11

thin but rigid. Later, in flight, one box at a time isdumped out of the aircraft door into the air stream, andthe individual disks from each box flutter to the greenfields below where the disks from each box come to restin a seemingly random cluster. Each such cluster can thenbe seen from the aircraft as a patch of small white dots.

Let us assume that, by chance, the disks from one boxcome to rest in a dot pattern that, if properly connectedby straight lines, would form the letter sequence cow, anda passenger in the aircraft, looking down at that dot pat-tern, utters the vocal sound kou. The person’s utterance ofthe sound kou under stimulus control of those white dotswould represent normal reading. However, the anteced-ent stimulus, consisting of the dot pattern, was not aproduct of verbal behavior, so that vocal utterance wouldclassify as a tact (another major division of verbal behav-ior that will be discussed in a later section of this chap-ter). Although the vocalizer’s utterance of the word cow isverbal behavior of the kind that is commonly called read-ing, in this case that reading does not represent the classof verbal behavior that occurs under stimulus control ofother verbal behavior (or its products).4

Textual behavior is obviously simpler than what isusually implicit in the common term reading. Whenreading, not only are vocal sounds (or their private sub-vocal versions) produced—that is, not only are the wordspublicly or privately spoken—but some additional pri-vate kinds of verbal behavior are occurring to whichpeople generally refer as comprehending. The productionof the sounds that are evoked by the textual elements5 inturn evoke a variety of further private responses—for in-stance, a visualization of an object and visualizations ordescriptions of its relations to other events—that is, thecontext in which it exists or operates. As one’s readingskill matures, the comprehension behaviors can comeunder direct stimulus control of the printed text, and theraw textual behavior extinguishes. In that case, as themature reader’s eyes scan the text, comprehension behav-iors are evoked directly, but the individual vocal or sub-vocal production of the sounds, which previously wereevoked by the textual elements, no longer occurs.

On the other hand, textual behavior can continue tooccur indefinitely without comprehension if the readerhas had an appropriate, if atypical, conditioning history.For example, a person can be conditioned to pronouncecorrectly the printed words in an alien language withouteither those sounds or the textual elements that evokethem ever being related to other particular environmen-tal elements. That precludes the private evocation of anykind of comprehension responses. Thus, a person can be-come a skilled reader of text that is printed in that strangelanguage without experiencing comprehension behaviorswith respect to any of it. As that situation is commonly

described, such persons vocalize the text correctly, butpersonally have no idea what they are saying.

In fact, as the person’s skill becomes refined, such a“reader,” who is actually exhibiting only raw textualbehavior, could theoretically daydream about entirelydifferent events while engaged in such vocal textual be-havior. Raw textual behavior requires, at the minimum,only that the vocal musculature be under direct stimuluscontrol of the printed text. Daydreaming can then occurconcurrently, because it need not involve any of the bodyparts that are preoccupied by such raw textual behavior.However, such a behavioral bifurcation is not possible fora comprehending reader, because the neural body parts withwhich one would daydream are involved in producingcomprehension behaviors and are thereby preoccupied.6

Another subclass of verbal behavior that is controlledby verbal stimuli is called transcription. An example istaking dictation. Recall that vocal verbal behavior in-volves a vocalizer who exhibits an auditory pattern that isreinforced when it affects the listener as an auditory pat-tern. In transcription, a writer creates a visual stimulusthat is consequated after having affected a reader as a vi-sual stimulus. The reader may be a third party. Both thelistener (as transcriber) and the reader of the transcriptiontypically function as mediators of consequences for theverbalizer’s verbal productions.

Consider the behavior of the transcriber. The ante-cedent stimuli that evoke transcribing behavior can beauditory or textual. If a person produces written text inresponse to linguistic stimuli that are being heard, theprocess is called taking dictation. If the antecedent stimuliare in graphic form, the person is said to be copying. Ineither case, the transcription behavior is shaped by itsconsequences, which are normally provided by the read-ers of the written product. If the antecedent graphicstimuli are not linguistic, the transcription process ismore likely to be called drawing than copying, as when anartist who is looking at a tree, draws that tree.

The final subclass to be discussed in this section iscalled intraverbal behavior. Note, in regard to the earlierclasses of this subsection, that in both echoic behavior(saying what one hears), and in writing from copy, thereis a formal correspondence between the evocative stimu-lus and the verbal behavior of concern. That is, in echoicbehavior, the vocalizer is producing sounds that are simi-lar to the sounds being heard. In writing from copy, thewriter is producing records that are similar to those beingcopied. In both cases, the stimuli and behavioral productsare in the same medium (i.e., both are sounds, marks onpaper or on monitors, etc.).7 In cases of reading aloud ortaking dictation, the medium changes insofar as a readerproduces vocal sounds that are evoked by text printed onpaper, and a transcriber produces written text that isevoked by vocal sounds that are produced by a vocalizer.8

Page 4: On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts · On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts ... Interest in the behaviorological analysis of verbal behavior (Skinner, ) continues

Page 12 (issn 1536–6669) �ehaviorology �oday � Volume 7, Number 2, Fall 2004

Note that in all four kinds of behavior that werementioned in the previous paragraph, some approxima-tion of a point–to–point correspondence exists betweenthe stimuli and the behavior or its products (see the ear-lier footnote on the connotations of “point–to–point”).For example, in echoic behavior, the sounds being vo-calized are similar to the sounds being heard, and eachelement of the vocalized stream of sounds correspondsprecisely to a specific element in the stream of sounds be-ing heard. Likewise, in writing from copy, each elementof the written text corresponds precisely to a specific ele-ment in the text being copied. In both textual behaviorand taking dictation, even though the dimensional sys-tem (i.e., the medium of expression) changes withinthose processes, an approximate point–to–point cor-respondence is maintained between the evocative stimuliand the behavior of concern (or its products). Here again,each element of the behavioral product corresponds pre-cisely to a specific element in the stimulus stream thatcontrols the production behavior. For instance, each ele-mental utterance of a reader can be matched precisely toa specific stimulus element in the text that is beingread—hence, the point–to–point (or at least range–to–range) correspondence.

In the intraverbal class, however, that location–basedcorrespondence is missing. That is, in many instances ofverbal behavior that is occurring under stimulus controlof other verbal behavior, no such point–to–point corre-spondence, nor any approximation of it, can be found.The verbal behavior is precisely evoked by other verbalbehavior, but it remains impossible to match a given ele-ment of that verbal behavior to any specific element of theevocative stimuli.

For example, if the presented stimulus is a–b–c–d–e–f… and the response is g, we see no locational cor-respondence between the stimulus (a–b–c–d–e–f… ) andthe response (g). The absence of such locational corre-spondence in verbal–verbal functions defines what B.F.Skinner called the intraverbal subclass of verbal behavior.It features verbal behavior that is occurring under stimu-lus control of other verbal behavior, but the stimulus andits evoked behavioral product lack locational correspon-dence or any approximation thereof (point–to–point,part–to–part, zone–to–zone, etc.).

Another example of intraverbal behavior occurs whena person hears the sound apple and responds with the signfor apple. The audible stimulus apple and the response toit in the form of movements of the arms, hands, fingers,and perhaps the face that together constitute the corre-sponding sign for apple share nothing that can representlocational correspondence between their constituent ele-ments. That is, no point or region in the sound corre-sponds precisely to a point or region in the movements ofthe body parts that are creating the sign for apple.

Intraverbal behavior is readily explicable in terms ofthe conditioning history that has established the relationbetween stimulus and response. We quickly point to sucha conditioning history to explain a person’s saying WorldWar Two when presented with 1939–1945 or a personwriting Pierre Renoir when shown the famous paintingthat is entitled Luncheon of the Boating Party. Likewise,most people are quite familiar with the kind of condi-tioning history that renders probable the response g inthe presence of a stimulus consisting of a–b–c–d–e–f…

Note that, in the case of intraverbal behavior, notonly is there is no point–to–point correspondence be-tween the stimulus and response that it produces, thedimensional system of the stimulus need not match thatof the response or its product. In the previous example inwhich a–b–c–d–e–f… evoked the response …g…, thestimulus could be presented either as printed text thatmust be read, as audible sounds, or as Braille that must befelt tactually. Similarly, regardless of the nature of thatstimulus presentation, the intraverbal response …g…could have been rendered either as text, in spoken form,or as a special array of raised dots. Other unmatchedforms for the stimuli and responses to it are also possible.

Consider another typical example: When one en-counters an acquaintance, one is likely to say How areyou?—a kind of greeting to which the other person mayhave a standard response: Very well, thanks! Such a stan-dard and perfunctory response, when controlledintraverbally, is independent of the actual status of theperson who is responding and may therefore not validlydescribe the status of the person who is responding to theinquiry. Given the question How are you?, the intraver-bally controlled utterance of the standard response Verywell, thanks! is functionally similar to the utterance of g inresponse to the stimulus a–b–c–d–e–f…

The recitation of a lengthy memorized verbal se-quence occurs intraverbally, as in the prior example per-taining to the recitation of the alphabet with eachresponse functioning as the stimulus for the next re-sponse. The process is often called chaining. Each utter-ance in the chain of responses is analogous to a link in amanufactured chain. Far more complex sequences thanthe letters of an alphabet may be featured. For instance,a West African griot recites the ancestral history of thetribe members, which may span hundreds of years. Eachshort passage is evoked intraverbally, mainly by the fea-tures of the previous short passage. Such recitations maynot require any supplementary private verbal stimulationof the various kinds called analysis, problem solving, criti-cal thinking, reflection, or any kind of thought in general.The common descriptive phrase mindless recitation re-flects the absence of such supplements from the an-tecedent controls on intraverbal behavior.

Page 5: On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts · On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts ... Interest in the behaviorological analysis of verbal behavior (Skinner, ) continues

�ehaviorology �oday � Volume 7, Number 2, Fall 2004 (issn 1536–6669) Page 13

However, the control of each link in a chain ofintraverbal responses is not usually under the exclusivecontrol of the previous link. Some of the evocative ca-pacity resides in the preceding sequence of links. Thus, ifinterrupted, the griot may be unable to restart from thepoint of interruption, and may have to resume from anearlier and particularly salient event that is more readilyevoked (in agential language, more easily recalled). Thegriot thus gets a new running start that restores the fullmeasure of intraverbal control over subsequent sectionsof the narrative.

A school child may have a similar problem when re-citing the memorized names of the American states in al-phabetical order. The child may successfully complete thetask after beginning with Alabama…, but if during sucha recitation the child is briefly interrupted—for instance,after Michigan—the child may be unable to continuewith Minnesota… If no prior link has special strengthamong its evocatives that affords a more economical start-ing point, the child may have to restart from the begin-ning with Alabama…

As some previous examples have suggested, we oftenrespond intraverbally to stimuli that we ourselves gener-ate. If an American vocalizer says red, white, and…, thatcomposite verbal sequence tends to evoke blue as thatspeaker’s next response. Similarly, among people whohave been conditioned in an American verbal com-munity, the vocal or subvocal stimulus white is more of-ten followed by the response house than among personsconditioned in the verbal communities of other coun-tries. Upon uttering all but the final syllable of a multi–syllabic word, the vocalizer is likely to emit the finalsyllable under stimulus control of the preceding syllablesof that word. For instance, given the vocal stimuluspo•lar•i•za…, the speaker is likely to complete the wordby uttering the final syllable …•tion.

In the process of pure translation a stimulus in onelanguage evokes a corresponding response in another lan-guage—a special case of intraverbal behavior. In theory,translators need not respond to relations between theirtextual or audible products (in either language) and otherenvironmental events. That is, for example, theoretically,the translator need not be able to define ouk or lur in ei-ther language to produce lur in language when givenouk in language (although in practice translators aretypically skilled in both languages, because they are usu-ally expected to interpret as well as to translate). Giventhe stimulus ouk, either as text or as an audible sound, asimple translator needs only to respond reliably andappropriately under intraverbal control with a textual oraudible rendering of lur. However, satisfactory translationusually requires far more than mere intraverbal control ofthe responding, especially when the differences in the lan-

guages extend beyond words to include structural andcompositional issues.

Conceptual InstabilityAfter Skinner published the seminal book Verbal Be-

havior in , the class of verbal behavior that is dis-cussed in this major chapter subsection (Verbal Behaviorunder the Control of Verbal Stimuli) was subjected tomore redefinition than perhaps any of the other majorclasses of verbal behavior that Skinner delineated. Duringthe final few decades of the twentieth century, two pro-fessors of Skinner’s general concept of verbal behavior,Jack Michael, at Western Michigan University, andErnest Vargas, at West Virginia University, were respec-tively prominent in tweaking the subcategories in thegeneral class that Skinner denoted as verbal behavior un-der the control of verbal stimuli.. Vargas reorganized thewhole class under Skinner’s subclass name intraverbal andthen divided the verbal phenomena in that major verbal–behavior category into three subcategories called codic,duplic, and sequelic. Michael moved codic and duplic ver-bal behavior out of this major class and promoted themto the same kind of major class status that was accordedto mands and tacts.

The Tact

If we divide the behavior–stimulating environment intoverbal and non–verbal events, we can discuss kinds of verbalbehavior that are evoked respectively by each of those stimu-lus classes. Previous sections were devoted to verbal behaviorevoked (a) by stimuli that are characteristic of deprivationor aversive stimulation and (b) by verbal stimuli.

In contrast, this section will focus on verbal behaviors,called tacts. Tacts in some way specify or indicate the stimulithat evoke them, which can be anything in the physicalenvironment. Tacts benefit the listener and are con-sequated by generalized reinforcers (mands, in contrast,benefit the speaker and are consequated with specific re-inforcers that are often specified by that verbalizer). Asimple example of a tact occurs when two lookouts arescanning a landscape, and one of them, upon seeing adistant gray plume, exclaims Smoke! The other personmay respond to the tact Smoke! by saying Well done!

Consider the functional difference between a mandand a tact. If hunger pangs are occurring within a person’sbody, and another person is present who can providefood, the person who is experiencing the hunger pangsmay respond verbally to those pangs by saying Feed me!That request for food is a mand, and it benefits the per-son who has said it. However, that same person may in-stead simply report private contact with that kind ofstimulation by saying I am experiencing hunger pangs.

Page 6: On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts · On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts ... Interest in the behaviorological analysis of verbal behavior (Skinner, ) continues

Page 14 (issn 1536–6669) �ehaviorology �oday � Volume 7, Number 2, Fall 2004

That statement includes the tact hunger pangs. Thus, thepangs, functioning as antecedent stimuli, may evoke amand, a tact, or one or more of each. Note that, in thepresence of someone who has provided food when in-formed that the speaker is hungry, the previous statementmay function as a polite mand to again provide somefood. However, if the mediator obviously will not be pro-viding food, perhaps because, as both parties know, nofood is available, the same statement merely functionsinformatively, but the statement is not a mand for food.

In the general analysis of contingencies under whichverbal behavior is produced, we specify the evocativestimulus, the verbal behavior that is evoked, and thesource and nature of its consequences. When the verbalbehavior in such a relation is a tact, the evocative stimu-lus is some piece of the real or physical environment. Itcan be anything (e.g., a blood cell, a rose, a cow, a distantmountain, a star, or a galaxy). It can also be a relation be-tween or among such environmental events.

Let us consider an example of a behavior–controllingrelation in which the verbal product is a tact. Supposethat an observer is confronted with a vertically orientedwooden shaft that is about six inches in diameter and sixfeet long and exhibits an approximately circular cross sec-tion. Its bottom two feet are sunk into the ground andlateral strands of wire are nailed to its upper exposed seg-ment. If that observer reliably responds to that compos-ite stimulus by saying fence post, that utterance is a tact.

Some people may say, in agential terms, that the per-son has tacted the fence post, but that tact–type of responsewas not initiated by the vocalizer; it was evoked by the post.That is, to speak accurately, the causal nexus of a tact doesnot inhere, as some kind of spontaneous generator, withinthe body of the person that exhibits the tact. Therefore,the person who produces the tact does not do it in thesense of originating it. Rather, that person merely medi-ates the production of that tact. The controlling functionis between the tact as a behavioral event and a detectableand measurable (i.e., real) environmental event.

The post could produce that verbal behavior fencepost, because the body that came into contact with lightreflected from the post had undergone micro–structuralchanges during its operant conditioning history that leftit reactive to such posts by exhibiting that particular kindof verbal operant response to them (viz., the vocal ut-terance of fence post). The capacity for that kind of func-tional relation between fence posts and people inheres intheir respective structures. The kind of operant condi-tioning that is called language training is a way of restruc-turing part of the person’s nervous system forsusceptibility to involvement in such a functional relationduring subsequent encounters with fence posts.

The operant conditioning (neural micro–structuring)of the person is one way to establish the relation that pro-

duces the tact. The other way is to alter the structure ofthe environmental event. In the fence post example, if therespective structures that can sustain this particular envi-ronment–behavior relation (i.e., the tact fence post) aregenerally in place, but the particular post on this occasionhas some salient atypical features, the evocation of thetact fence post may not occur. (It may be said that the ob-server does not recognize that the thing is a fence post.)Instead of tweaking the microstructure of the person’sbody through additional operant conditioning, we mayleave the body alone and restructure the fence post torender it more typical of the kind of fence posts that wereinvolved in the past conditioning of the verbalizer to pro-duce that tact. The tact fence post may then be evoked. Insuch a case, the verbal tact fence post occurred in reactionto a particular environmental structure following a modi-fication of the environmental structure that removed ex-traneous features (and perhaps added some commonfeatures) until the structure of that post came into thestructural range that can evoke the tact fence post by thatparticular body.

When the tact fence post is forthcoming, it may besaid redundantly that the person now recognizes the thing asa fence post. However the current structure–to–structurefunctional interaction occurs naturally whenever bothstructures have the necessary configuration to supportthat particular functional reaction of the one to the other.That natural function does not require the interventionof a person–agent that is superstitiously summoned froma putative spirit world to perform, in some proactive way,the tacting operation. The tact will simply happen natu-rally and inevitably when the necessary conditions “fallinto place” (as they say). That is, the tact happens auto-matically in the same sense that any kind of dependentvariable manifests on the occasion of contact with anappropriate independent variable.

The term stimulus implies an energy transfer from someaspect of the environment to the organic body that, in turn,exhibits a behavioral response. However, the energy thatis transferred from an environmental stimulus to a behav-ing body acts only as a reaction–specific trigger, becausethat energy is insufficient to produce the subsequent be-havioral reaction through conservative energy transforma-tions (light waves from an approaching baseball lack theenergy required to swing a bat). Organic bodies are inher-ently structured to maintain a general dynamic potentialthat releases in the manner that we call behaving. The en-ergy transferred from the environmental event merelytriggers the release of some of that potential energy,which has been stored in the body, to produce a behav-ioral manifestation of the kind that we describe as thebehavioral response to that stimulus. While the specificity ofthe resulting behavior is a function of the properties ofthe small triggering energy that is impinging from the

Page 7: On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts · On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts ... Interest in the behaviorological analysis of verbal behavior (Skinner, ) continues

�ehaviorology �oday � Volume 7, Number 2, Fall 2004 (issn 1536–6669) Page 15

environment, the greater energy that is necessary to pro-duce that behavioral manifestation must be released fromgeneral reserves that have been stored in the body.

Through the processes of behavioral conditioning, aparticular form of the behaving becomes precisely relatedto a particular triggering event. To establish such a rela-tion between an environmental stimulus and a particularbehavior, it is necessary to change the microstructure ofthe body’s nervous system to render it uniquely sensitiveto the properties of that particular environmental stimu-lus. Although that kind of microstructural change couldat least theoretically be accomplished by surgery or drugs,it is instead typically the natural result of a behavior–con-ditioning process.

For a more detailed account of such events, we mustswitch to a different level of analysis and look to the neu-ral physiologists, who, like the behaviorologists, representone of the basic natural sciences (i.e., biology, in the caseof the physiologists). The respective scientific concerns ofthe behaviorologists and the neural physiologists overlapalong certain disciplinary interfaces, the behavioralconditioning process being an obvious example.

However, to provide such a naturalistic account, theneural physiologists will have to divorce their interpreta-tions from the popular but mystical accounts of behaviorthat implicitly accept a mind–body dualism by featuringexplanatory reliance on autonomous or semi–au-tonomous body–dwelling self–agents that can “do thingson their own.” No part of nature can work that way, andthere is no natural way that brain activity, that must al-ways operate reactively, can spontaneously initiate behav-ioral events. Those who assume that brains are somehowengaging proactively, on their own initiative, in the origi-nation of the behavior that the body then exhibits usuallyspeak of minds that putatively are either synonymouswith brains or remain mystical constructs that they con-ceptually superimpose on brains.

A natural science community cannot do good natu-ral science in conjunction with a scientistic communitythat is informed by non–natural philosophy. Substantialprogress can be made only when such a blending of ac-counts occurs between two natural science communities.

Conditioning a TactConsider a person who has never, in any sense, con-

tacted a thromble. It may be said that the person is unfa-miliar with thrombles and has no idea as to their nature.Suppose that we then place a thromble before that personin a way that permits different kinds of contact with it,each involving a different sense. We then descriptively la-bel it by saying This is a thromble. Next, we mand the per-son to identify the item by name, which the person cando easily by repeating the term thromble that we have justspoken. If the person then produces an echoic response

to the nominal part of our mand by saying thromble, letus suppose that we reinforce that response, perhapsmerely by replying You are correct.

To the extent that the consequence was a reinforcingstimulus, the person thereby will have become morelikely to say thromble in the presence of such an item.With successive reiterations of that operant conditioningcycle, the person becomes increasingly likely to exhibitthat response as a tact in the presence of a thromble. Wemay then alter the form of our mands in ways that putthe person under contingencies to become more verballyinvolved with thrombles—thinking, speaking, reading,and writing about thrombles, perhaps while in visual, au-ral, olfactory, and tactile contact with them. During allsuch interactions, we insure that each correct verbal re-sponse pertaining to thrombles is reinforced.

When an acceptable reliability is attained in each ofthose verbal kinds of behavior–environment functionalrelations, it may be said that the person has come to knowwhat a thromble is, and to know something about them aswell. However, operant conditioning does not educatespirits that are called persons. Operant conditioning estab-lishes functional relations that manifest naturally whenan appropriately structured organic body and a specifi-cally structured environmental elements come intoappropriate contact.

The kind of lone response that simply identifiessomething is sometimes called a raw tact, because it con-sists of nothing more than an unenhanced utterance un-der stimulus control of an environmental event (e.g.,Thromble! when uttered in response to contact with athromble). Raw tacts are common under contingenciesto name or identify whatever is presented. However, theraw tact is often accompanied by other verbal behaviorsthat are functionally controlled in ways to be discussedlater: There is a thromble; It is a thromble; This is athromble; I see a thromble; I think that I feel a thromble.

The strength of the relation that controls a tact, be-ing operantly produced, is subject to reduction throughpunishment or extinction. Presented with an object andmanded to name it, a vocalizer who then says thromblemay find that that response is followed by what seems tobe a punitive consequence supplied by a mediator (e.g.,Wrong! You stupid disgusting dolt!). A subsequent presenta-tion of the item may then be less likely to evoke the tactthromble due to the suppressing effect of its previous aver-sive consequence—an outcome that confirms the puni-tive function of the listener’s reaction. If the response(Thromble!) is simply ignored whenever it occurs, it willalso become less likely to occur, but in that case the de-crease is said to represent extinction. Just as the verbalcommunity can condition the controlling relations forthe production of verbal behavior, the verbal communitycan also reverse the conditioning of such relations.

Page 8: On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts · On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts ... Interest in the behaviorological analysis of verbal behavior (Skinner, ) continues

Page 16 (issn 1536–6669) �ehaviorology �oday � Volume 7, Number 2, Fall 2004

Mands and tacts have different effects on a mediator.Upon hearing a mand, the mediator infers somethingabout the condition of the vocalizer—in particular, thevocalizer’s state of deprivation with respect to the envi-ronmental event specified by the mand. In contrast, uponhearing a tact, the mediator infers something about theenvironment of the vocalizer. For example, compare theeffects on the mediator of hearing Give me a knife andhearing There is a knife. In the former case, the vocalizeris inferred to be deprived of a knife. In the latter case, aknife is inferred to be a stimulus element of the vocalizer’simmediate behavior–controlling environment.

The utility of a tact can be revealed by a simple illus-trative interaction between a verbalizer and a mediator.Suppose that the mediator is knife–deprived and is not incurrent contact with a knife. If the vocalizer then tacts aknife (e.g., There’s a knife), the mediator may benefit fromthe vocalizer’s tact insofar as that tact may function toevoke elements of the mediator’s searching repertoire.That is, the mediator may then start searching for a knife,because, in the past, when verbalizers have provided tactsof that kind, the mediator’s searching behaviors havebeen more likely to be reinforced by contacts with thetacted item. In the present example, the knife–deprivedlistener is more likely to find a knife if a nearby vocalizerindicates a personal contact with a knife. In fact, a verbalcommunity conditions its members to exhibit tacts pre-cisely for such reasons. All parties generally benefit whenan individual indicates to others how he or she is beingaffected by the environment, especially when at leastsome part of that environment is being shared with oth-ers who are also under contingencies to interact with it.

Tacts are often manded by others, which indicates agreater likelihood of their being reinforced. Suppose, forinstance, that two people are confronting the same envi-ronmental event. Person asks What is that?, which toperson is an occasion on which ’s tact will probably bereinforced. If then says It’s an impact crater, person may respond with I think you’re absolutely right! However, may instead punish or extinguish ’s tact if in the past’s different tacts of events with similar features have gen-erally been reinforced. In that case, we may say that Aknows better than to call that thing an impact crater, pro-vided that we have had a conditioning history similar to’s history with respect to such events. On the otherhand, if our conditioning history with respect to suchevents has been similar to ’s history, we would exhibitthe same tact as in the presence of that event, and wemay react to A’s disagreement by concluding that A justdoesn’t get it!

The Stimulus Control of TactsTacts are conditioned operantly, but environmental

events have various properties to which the conditioning

of tacts pertains differentially. Suppose that we present athromble to two persons who have no experience withthrombles. We arrange for both of them to contact thethromble in similar ways. We then announce to bothtrainees that This is a thromble, which is the occasion foran echoic response to our follow–up mand What is this?Suppose that both trainees then respond by saying Athromble, and continue to do so reliably as we repeat themand. We may then conclude that both of those peoplehave learned what a thromble is, or that each of them cannow identify a thromble.

Nevertheless, a question remains as to what stimulihave actually come to control their respective commonresponses. Thrombles have many properties, includingcolor, texture, shape, size, and different kinds of motion.Furthermore, each such property is represented by a par-ticular and unique set of more elemental stimuli. Duringthe operant conditioning that characterized the training,which stimuli, intrinsic to thrombles, were actually gain-ing functional control of the tact? Perhaps more impor-tantly, were the same stimuli gaining control of the tactthromble, which both persons can now utter in commonwhen a thromble is presented. Even when a given el-emental stimulus that constitutes one aspect of athromble comes to share in the evocation of each person’scommon tact thromble, we have no reason to assume thatits share of the control of that tact is equal for both speak-ers. The question of stimulus control–share represents astandard kind of challenge during behaviorological analy-ses of tact–producing functions.

While it is probable that a number of properties sharein evoking each person’s common tact thromble, it re-mains unlikely that any one stimulus element sharesequally in those evocations. Furthermore, it is possiblethat a given stimulus element that shares in defining athromble for person , may have acquired no detectableevocative capacity for the tact thromble by person . Af-ter all, a given person’s susceptibility to conditioning isalways a function of earlier relevant conditioning, so per-sons and cannot be expected to share the same stateof readiness for any given lesson. The implications of thisfact pose a kind of fundamental challenge to all teacherswho must work with groups of students.

It is also possible that certain properties of the set-tings in which thrombles commonly occur may gainsome of the evocative capacity when the tact thromble isreinforced. That is, contextual stimuli that are not intrin-sic to thrombles may have gained some control of the tactthromble. It may then be said that the person’s concept ofa thromble is imprecise or not entirely correct. (Note thatconcept is a fictional construct that substitutes for thetact–producing functional relation between an environ-mental event and a verbal tact.)

Page 9: On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts · On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts ... Interest in the behaviorological analysis of verbal behavior (Skinner, ) continues

�ehaviorology �oday � Volume 7, Number 2, Fall 2004 (issn 1536–6669) Page 17

These various kinds of imprecision in the condition-ing of a tact can leave properties of the environment withunanticipated or disproportional evocative capacities. Incommon agential terms, it may be said that the twospeakers have different reasons for calling the same objecta thromble. The commonalty in the respective controlson their common tact contributes to the socio–culturalintegrity of their verbal community, while the unsus-pected differences may create disconcerting problems. Incommon language, it may be said that one person’s new“knowledge” of thrombles differs from the other person’snew “knowledge” of thrombles even though, outwardly,it may appear at first that both have simply learned toidentify a thromble by name when it is presented.

Suppose, for example, that the conditioning of one ofthe persons has left one or more irrelevant properties inpartial control of the tact thromble. In that case, given athromble that does not feature such irrelevant properties,the person would fail to call it a thromble even thoughothers may reliably do so. Consider a person who haslearned to identify sycamore trees, all previously encoun-tered examples of which have been full grown. That in-dividual may fail to identify a sycamore seedling as asycamore tree, because the conditioning of the functionalrelation between tree and utterance of name has left size(an irrelevant property) in partial but essential control ofthe nominal tact. We allude to that kind of flaw in theconditioning of that tact when we note that size is not adefinitive property of sycamore trees.

People may say that the person’s concept of a sy-camore tree is flawed, but the person does not have a con-cept (flawed or perfect). Instead the person has a neuralmicrostructure that requires some further conditioningtweaks, so that when the person’s body reacts functionallyto sycamore trees by producing the appropriate nominaltact, the range of environmental controls that are evokingthose tacts will be appropriately narrower. Only definitiveproperties must share in evoking the nominal tact, and inthe case of sycamore trees, size is an irrelevant property.That is, little sycamore trees are still sycamore trees.

If a new composite stimulus is encountered thatshares some property with the stimuli that were presentwhen the tact was reinforced, that novel compositestimulus may evoke that same tact in this new and per-haps inappropriate context. In such cases, that singlecommon property exerts a predominant evocative controlover the tact. Often, the result is a familiar kind of mis-take. An example occurs when a person, who is familiaronly with red fire trucks but not with ambulances in gen-eral, is presented with a red ambulance and calls it a firetruck. In some cases, however, the resultant tact isappropriate to the new situation. Such oddly evoked butacceptable tacts are described as extended tacts, and severalsubclasses have been identified.

Let us consider some examples. Suppose that uponencountering a new kind of knife for the first time, a per-son says knife without additional preparatory condition-ing. While that particular knife has some properties notpreviously encountered in other knives, it shares theminimal definitive properties of all knives. We look forthe evocatives of this tact among those previouslystrengthened common definitive properties, not amongthe novel features of this particular knife. This kind ofextension of a tact is called a generic extension. The generi-cally extended tact specifies a class into which the stimu-lus fits. Generic extension is regarded as desirable insofaras it results in a person eventually responding with thetact knife to a large variety of objects that feature one ormore cutting blades.

Thus, generic extensions of a particular tact can rep-resent a worthwhile economy for the verbal community.Within a verbal community, it is generally effective for aperson to emit the tact knife when contacting any givenmember of that class of objects whether or not that per-son has ever encountered a knife with that particular setof irrelevant properties. Peculiar knives are still knives. Itwould be too burdensome if the verbal community hadto condition each person anew to exhibit the generic tactknife in response to each different kind of knife when itwas encountered. When an automobile manufacturerfirst puts a new model on public display, although noneof the public viewers will previously have seen that par-ticular style of car, they are all likely to tact it at once asan automobile. In fact, that kind of generic extension of atact is so widely anticipated that a witness’s pretense thatit is not happening is accepted as humor (e.g., the ques-tion What is that? expressed with mock start and exagger-ated emphasis on the word What).

Properties that are not essential to membership in themajor class can play a role in controlling the tacts of sub–classes within in the major class. For instance, sets ofproperties that may be associated with some but not allknives can be put in control of the adjective that com-pletes the tact of a category of knives (e.g., pen knife,hunting knife, or carving knife). Such a set of propertiesis irrelevant to the basic generic tact knife, but that set ofnon–definitive knife properties is the definitive evocativefactor for the designation of the categorical tact (i.e., pen,hunting, or carving).

Such categorizations, which are based on extraneousproperties of knives per se, are to be distinguished fromgeneric extensions of the tact knife, which occur whencertain definitive properties of knives occur in close com-bination with properties that may bear no relation to fa-miliar knives. Thus, in generic extension, the bow of aship may evoke knife as when a vocalizer describes thebow of a ship as a great knife that slices the water. Here,the critical property (a sharp cutting edge) is not extrane-

Page 10: On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts · On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts ... Interest in the behaviorological analysis of verbal behavior (Skinner, ) continues

Page 18 (issn 1536–6669) �ehaviorology �oday � Volume 7, Number 2, Fall 2004

ous. Rather, it is part of the definitive set of properties forknives, and the bow of a ship functions as a knife to cutthe water. Ships are fitted with big knives called bows, andwhen such a statement first emerges as an original obser-vation it represents a generic extension of the tact knife.

Another kind of extension of the tact is characterizedby metaphor. In a metaphorical extension of a tact theproperty that controls the extended tact is not a propertythat the verbal community respected when originallyconditioning the verbalizer to emit that tact. Ametaphorically extended tact is evoked instead by a prop-erty that was associated with the originally tacted eventbut was not a definitive property of it.

Consider, for example, the statement The old crab hadnothing nice to say and just stood there with a sour look onhis face. Let us analyze the tact crab in that statement.First, we note that his indicates that crab refers to a maleand, because only humans normally talk, we infer thatthe crab in this sentence is a human male. While (a) thisparticular man and (b) crabs in general both share certainbehavioral patterns when provoked, note that those kindsof behaviors by crabs were not the definitive properties ofcrabs respected by the verbal community when it wasconditioning this speaker to tact certain kinds of organ-isms as crabs. Regardless of how a crab is behaving, it isstill a crab. That even remains true when the crab is dead.Nothing that a crab does behaviorally bears in any wayon its membership in the crab class.

Therefore, when first being conditioned to producethe tact crab on appropriate occasions, the verbalizer’stacts had to be freed of control by any behavioral eventsthat are associated with crabs. To accomplish that, theverbal community had to vary the irrelevant behavior–related properties of crabs that appeared along with theminimum definitive set of properties while reliably rein-forcing each correct expression, and only correct expres-sions, of the tact crab.

The man in this example was tacted as a crab understimulus control of a behavior pattern that is often asso-ciated with crabs (but not definitive of crabs). That sortof control of the verbalizer’s utterance (by a frequentlycrab–related but non–definitive property) rendered it ametaphorical extension of the tact crab.

Another example of the metaphorical extension of atact occurs in the lyrics of an old but well known song: Youare my sunshine, my only sunshine. You make me happy whenskies are gray. You’ll never know dear how much I love you.Please don’t take my sunshine away. The person about whomthe song is sung is designated by the extended tact sunshine.

When the verbalizer was originally being conditionedto produce the utterance sunshine as a valid tact, nothingabout the electromagnetic radiation emanating from aparticular stellar source included behavior–related prop-erties. The contingencies arranged by the verbal commu-

nity to condition valid tacts of that phenomenon kept theverbalizer’s tacting free of control by behavior–related events.

However, sunshine does commonly evoke certain be-havioral reactions that have reinforcing properties. “Sun-shine makes me feel good!” is an old and familiarexpression. Obviously, one’s emotional reactions to sun-shine are not definitive properties that should controlvalid tacts of solar light energy. However, when anotherperson’s behavior evokes one’s behavior that is similar tothat evoked by sunshine, one may then exhibit the tactsunshine under stimulus control of that person’s behavior.Linguistically, that person is said to be sunshine, which,of course, is not true as all parties recognize. Such an ut-terance is said to represent a metaphorical extension ofthe tact sunshine.

Suppose that, for the first time, a vocalizer describesa narrow projection of land that extends into a lake as afinger of land—never before having read nor heard ofsuch a piece of land being described as a finger. Such anelongated projection of land into a large body of waterand a finger that is attached to a hand share somegeometrical and relational properties. Although thosegeometrical properties of appendages to hands and landmasses are shared, those were not strictly definitive prop-erties of fingers that served as criteria for the verbalcommunity’s reinforcement of the tact finger. Short,stubby, and round–shaped appendages could also validlyhave evoked that tact finger if other more definitive prop-erties were also present.

When the verbal community is conditioning itsmembers to utter the tact finger, the limited subset ofgeometrical properties typically occurs as an intrinsiccharacteristic along with a larger variety of properties thatcharacterize such appendages to peoples’ hands. That is,when conditioning its members to say finger, the verbalcommunity reinforces the relations between the tact fin-ger and properties that include connection to a biologicalhand, protrusion from that hand, physiological factorsthat characterize organic tissues, articulated joints, andperhaps the capacity for movement that enables variousbehaviors that are characteristic of fingers. In the verbalcommunity, a finger is one of those five, similar, elon-gated, and triple jointed biological parts that extend fromthe palm of a hand. Pronounced elongation is typicallyexhibited along with the other properties of those ap-pendages. However, that elongation is simply not a tech-nically definitive property, and a carefully managedprogram of conditioning of the tact finger would excludethat geometrical property from the contingent relationsin which the general tact finger manifests. Short, bulgingor stubby fingers are still called fingers.

However, during that conditioning, the evocativecapacity of some of the irrelevant general geometricproperties of fingers may have been strengthened

Page 11: On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts · On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts ... Interest in the behaviorological analysis of verbal behavior (Skinner, ) continues

�ehaviorology �oday � Volume 7, Number 2, Fall 2004 (issn 1536–6669) Page 19

inadvertently simply because those geometric propertieswere often paired with the properties upon which theconditioning was focused. Thereafter, those geometricalproperties may evoke the tact finger even when they ap-pear in a part of the environment that has many othersalient properties that are unassociated with fingers. Anexample is a narrow extension of land projecting out intoa body of water.

When such a piece of land first evokes the tact finger,that utterance is said to represent a metaphorical extensionof the tact finger. The capacity of the land mass to evokethe extended tact finger inheres in geometrical propertiesthat are shared with most organic fingers. Such vocalizersmay say that such projections of land remind them of fin-gers, but events that occur in the normal operantconditioning of the tact finger account for its relativelyrare metaphorical manifestations in such novel contextswithout explanatory recourse to mental agents that haveto be re–minded. Another similar example of the meta-phorical extension of a tact is provided by original refer-ences to Italy as a boot.

To distinguish between generic and metaphorical ex-tensions of tacts, note that in a generic extension of a tactthe new stimulus that has come to evoke that tact repre-sents a valid member of the evocative class. Consider anewly encountered substance that for the first time istacted as coffee. If that has indeed occurred through ge-neric extension, the new substance is actually a kind ofcoffee. The minimal set of properties that are definitive ofcoffee were the ones that evoked the extension of the tactcoffee, and that is what rendered that extension generic.

In a metaphorical extension of a tact the functionalcontrol is exerted by a set of properties that are insuffi-cient to establish a valid generic extension of the tact. Toexperience a complete appreciation of a metaphorical ex-tension of a tact, a mediator must recognize both thecommonalty and the shortfall in the evocative propertiesthat control the verbalizer’s statement. Both definitiveand non–definitive properties may be involved in con-trolling a metaphorical extension of a tact, but the set ofproperties that are controlling it do not include the mini-mal definitive set of properties for the tact that is under-going the extension.

For instance, when, for the first time, the phrase thejutting chin of Gilasitan is uttered in response to a penin-sula on the human head shaped island of Gilasitan, thelistener does not react as if that peninsula is really a chin.Note that the metaphorical extension of the tact chin didoccur in response to certain geometrical and relationalproperties that are shared with real chins. While the pre-cise shape of the peninsula probably does not match thatof any real chin and only approximates the general shapeof human chins, the relational property of a rotated pro-trusion from a central mass is closer to a definitive prop-

erty of a human chin. However, additional properties ofother kinds are also necessary to complete the minimalqualification as a human chin.

Nevertheless, the qualitative success of a metaphori-cal extension of a tact is a function of reliable common-alty of the stimuli that are in control of both the normaloccurrences of the tact and its metaphorical extension.Consider a person who encounters a grove of red mapletrees on a sunny autumn day when the leaves are a brightred color. Suppose that this person describes the scene astrees of knives. That statement seems to be some sort ofmetaphorical reference, but most listeners would be per-plexed, and may punish the statement as an unskillfullyrendered linguistic product.

Suppose that analysis reveals that the verbalizer hadundergone an insufficient program of conditioning of thetact knife, perhaps being exposed only to knives that hadbright red handles. That salient red hue was common toall of the knives that were encountered by this verbalizerduring the conditioning of the tact knife. Although an ir-relevant property of knives per se, the bright red handlecolor was paired with the definitive properties of eachgiven knife on every occasion during the operant condi-tioning of the tact. That circumstance permitted someassociated respondent conditioning that brought the tactknife under stimulus control of the bright red color. Al-lowing that sort of thing to happen is a common kind ofteaching mistake.

Thus, the verbalizer in this example was well pre-pared for an extension of that tact in response to thebright red patches of color presented by the autumn foli-age of red maple trees. To the verbalizer, it was a genericextension (however faulty)—that is, the red leaves wereknives too. However, most if not all of the potential me-diators in that person’s verbal community were condi-tioned to respond to the tact knife only when utteredunder a composite stimulus control that excludes color–related properties. In this example the speaker is sayingknife exclusively under control of a red hue, while the au-dience disregards color as a relevant property of knives,having failed to contact redness among the constituentproperties of many of the knives with which they are fa-miliar. During their conditioning of the tact knife, red-ness and knives were too infrequently paired to sustainthe metaphorical extension uttered by this particular ver-balizer, and they do not reinforce its production.

As this example illustrates, in a generic extension of atact, more and more collateral properties may be broughtinto the range of properties that control the tact, ofteninadvertently. In the agential language that ignores envi-ronmental control and instead regards tacts as evidence ofinternal constructs called concepts, the display of an in-valid generic extension such as the tact of red leaves asknives is said to reflect a faulty concept. If the invalid ge-

Page 12: On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts · On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts ... Interest in the behaviorological analysis of verbal behavior (Skinner, ) continues

Page 20 (issn 1536–6669) �ehaviorology �oday � Volume 7, Number 2, Fall 2004

neric tact is instead interpreted by a member of the audi-ence as a metaphorical extension, that audience memberwould be assuming that the speaker “knew that the leaveswere not really knives.” However, for the previously de-scribed reasons, that metaphorical reference to leaves asknives would fail to qualify as a worthwhile metaphor.People would tend to say that the implicit relation ofknives to leaves seems too vague, a condition that con-demns the metaphor to ineffectiveness.

In valid generic extensions of a tact, the new stimu-lus that comes to control the tact possesses all of the de-finitive properties that collectively or elementally couldcontrol the original tact. We say that a newly recognizedhammer is indeed a hammer, although its collateral prop-erties may control a further tact that manifests as a quali-fying adjective (e.g., a sledge hammer or a tack hammer).

In contrast, in metaphorical extensions of tacts, thenew stimulus that comes to control the tact does not in-clude the complete set of definitive properties that canshare in the control of the valid original tact. For ex-ample, when a verbalizer refers to the largest watermelonin a garden as the “Jupiter of the patch,” we do not reactas if that statement had occurred under stimulus controlof the largest solar planet. That is because the only prop-erty of Jupiter that is exhibited by that melon is the rela-tional property of largest in a set. All other properties ofa watermelon and the planet Jupiter evoke uncommonresponses—or, as we say on that basis, that particular wa-termelon and Jupiter are defined by entirely differentproperties (except for the one common property onwhich the metaphor relies).

Some metaphorical extensions of tacts cannot be re-lated to any property that is exhibited in common by(a) the traditional kind of evocative stimulus and (b) thenew evocative stimulus. Consider, for example, the state-ment “your book is a breath of fresh air,” uttered by areader to the author of that book. Detailed examinationof the book and of wafts of fresh air are unlikely to revealany common properties, yet the metaphor may seem tobe effective. In such cases, the commonalty is not be-tween properties in the respective evocative stimuli, butin the speaker’s responses to them. That is, the book andfresh air, although composed of entirely different stimuli,share the capacity to evoke a common emotional re-sponse by the verbalizer, and the metaphor is based onthat commonalty in the responses to the entirely dispar-ate sets of stimuli that are specified in the metaphoricalstatement (viz., book and fresh air).

When certain properties of narrow terrestrial projec-tions into bodies of water came to evoke the tact finger,that metaphorical extension relied on two properties, onegeometric and one relational (i.e., elongated shape andcontact, along a shorter side, with a large area). Except for

those two properties, fingers and land masses share few ifany other properties.

Suppose that, in the experience of a particular verbal-izer, such fingers of land that project into bodies of waterhave always been covered with vegetation having aparticular green shade. Further suppose that that indi-vidual is a passenger in an aircraft that is flying over asimilarly colored but not elongated patch of vegetation inthe middle of a large forest far from any bodies of water.When that somewhat circular patch of green is viewedfrom overhead by this individual, it may evoke the tactfinger. For instance, that person may mand a companionto look at that finger of vegetation (in this case, a finger ofvegetation within a larger forest).

Here, however, only color and complete isolation bycontrast are the critical evocative properties for the ex-tended tact finger. Geometric factors are no longer shar-ing in the control. (For most people, such a set ofproperties more commonly evokes the tact patch than fin-ger, and the metaphor may be ineffective with such an au-dience). However, it may be effective in this case if theverbalizer’s companion has shared this verbalizer’s condi-tioning history with respect to the initial extension of thetact finger under the control of a certain kind of landmass that consistently happened to feature vegetation ofthe particular green hue that has become functional.

Note that this example illustrates the metaphoricalextension of what is already a metaphorical extension.That is, it features a second order metaphorical extensioninsofar as the phrase finger of land already represented ametaphorical extension of the tact finger before the finalmetaphorical extension occurred under control of justthe color and its isolation.

Consider another example: Suppose that, in the samegeographical region featured in the previous example, bigcrops of watermelons are produced, but they are grownonly on such fingers of land that extend into bodies ofwater. Further suppose that all watermelon patches inthat person’s experience have been located on elongatedstretches of land that extend outward into bodies of wa-ter and that all such peninsulas that this verbalizer knowscontain patches of watermelons. Such a verbalizer maythen report his or her location by saying that he or she isnow “on a melon patch about miles west of town,”when he or she is miles west of town on a projectionof land that extends into a body of water.

When reporting the location as a melon patch, theverbalizer may not, at that moment, be in contact withan actual watermelon patch, although he or she is on thekind of peninsula on which watermelons are invariablyproduced. Such an expression of position is, of course,effective only with a mediator whose conditioning historyhas prepared that person to respond to “melon patch” in

Page 13: On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts · On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts ... Interest in the behaviorological analysis of verbal behavior (Skinner, ) continues

�ehaviorology �oday � Volume 7, Number 2, Fall 2004 (issn 1536–6669) Page 21

the same way that people in general respond to “peninsula”or merely to the metaphorical phrase “finger of land.”

From this example we see that tacts are thus extendedin yet another way, called metonymical extension, in whichthe form of the tact is changed. This kind of extensionoccurs when a stimulus that reliably accompanies thestimulus that controls a tact also gains control of thattact, which emerges in a new form. Functionally, it is thesame tact, but a different word or phrase is vocalized.Such an extension is exemplified by the famous ex-clamation transmitted by Navy Captain James A. Lovell,Jr., commander of the Apollo lunar mission, fol-lowing an on–board explosion in space while en route tothe moon: Houston, we have a problem!

Lovell was not speaking to the city of Houston,Texas, but was instead speaking to a flight controller atthe mission control center that was located in Houston.The essential fact is that the mission control facility fromwhich that flight controller spoke was located within thearea to which people refer as Houston. In the past, when-ever more direct tacts of that controller had been re-inforced, the proximal city shared in the conditioningeffects of those reinforcements. Once the city name beganto replace the controller’s usual designator as the tact, therelation between the controller and the speaker’s tactHouston began to absorb the main reinforcing effect ofthe reinforcing consequences, and that metonymical ex-tension of the original tact therefore became increasinglyprobable during subsequent transmissions. The naturalmetonymical extension of what originally may have beena nominal tact (e.g., Jack) or a generic tact (e.g., FlightController), as described above, actually occurred histori-cally before Lovell’s time in space and thereafter was sim-ply taught to new astronauts, Lovell included.

Many other common examples can be cited. Accord-ing to the New York Times… is not a reference to a news-paper that writes itself. It is a reference to some textwritten by some author that was published in that news-paper. Through a metonymical extension of the tact ofthat author’s name, the name of the newspaper has be-come the tact. When we read that the rank and file ofmusket advanced behind the charge of twenty horse, we re-spond as if we are being informed that a group of footsoldiers advanced behind twenty cavalrymen who led theway with a horse mounted charge. The appearance of thetact musket in place of foot soldiers, and horse in place ofcavalrymen, represent metonymical extensions of thoserespective tacts. The conspicuous omission of the con-ventional plural …s from musket and horse in the printedreport is a stimulus tweak that helps alert the reader to themetonymical nature of those tacts within the statement.

Metonymical extensions of tacts may occur acciden-tally and surprise both speakers and listeners. They mayalso emerge under contingencies to exhibit novel forms

of speech. They sometimes gain strength as negatively re-inforced escape behaviors as, for example, when a vocalizer,unable to identify the mediator, resorts instead to a met-onymical extension. For example, suppose that a personhas placed a telephone call to the Chief of Police to report acrime, but when Chief Badger answers, the excited callercannot recall the Chief ’s name (i.e., Badger). The callermay say Hello, Police Department, I want to report a theftin progress. However, the caller is actually talking only tothe Chief Badger, not to the whole police department.

Note that this extension of the tact is metonymicalbecause of the change in form. In the earlier metaphori-cal extension, the finger of a hand became a finger of land;the verbal form of the tact finger survived the extension.However, when Flight Controller became Houston, andwhen Chief Badger became Police Department, the origi-nal forms of the tact did not survive the extension. Thus,the latter examples represented metonymical extensions.

In metonymical extensions of a tact, the paired stimulus,which gains control of the tact in the functional sense, isalready in control of a different nominal tact, so, as theysay (invalidly), “the vocalizer starts saying a different name.”Functionally, it is an equivalent tact in terms of what itaccomplishes, but the transfer of control to the new pairedstimulus results in a new nomination. That is, the sameflight controller that previously may have evoked “Joe”now evokes “Houston”; the same person that previouslyevoked “Chief Badger” now evokes “Police Department.”The new nomination is determined by the stimulus thatis paired with what remains the functional referent.

In yet another kind of extension of a tact, known asa solecistic extension, the shared property that gains con-trol is only remotely related to the definitive propertyupon which standard reinforcements are contingent or itbears only an irrelevant relation to it. For example, a per-son who runs from a burning building may exclaim that“the whole place is inflated!” The term inflated bears someobvious resemblance to the term inflamed and to thephrase in flames. However, we must still account for thecurious transformation, the salience of which pertainsboth to its rarity and its vague hint of the curious rela-tions by which it has emerged.

First, the entire phrase (i.e., “the whole place is inflated!”)is similar to the more common phrase, “the whole placeis going up in flames,” or more briefly, “the whole placeis in flames.” A somewhat tenuous relation exists betweenthe facts that both flames and inflated things (e.g., bal-loons) often “go up.” If the speaker is particularly famil-iar with balloons and if effective instances of the terminflated have been reinforced strongly in that conext,some of that strengthening may have accrued to the up-ward motion of the balloons that got inflated. That canhappen when upward movement is reliably paired withinflation. Upon later encountering flames that also move

Page 14: On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts · On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts ... Interest in the behaviorological analysis of verbal behavior (Skinner, ) continues

Page 22 (issn 1536–6669) �ehaviorology �oday � Volume 7, Number 2, Fall 2004

upward, the stimulus control exerted by the flames maybe faulty insofar as the speaker, responding under the in-appropriately restricted control of the previouslymisconditioned property of upward motion, exclaimsthat “the whole place is inflated.” This particular se-quence of historical events is not the only way that theterm inflated could have been prepared for emergence inthe instance that is featured in this example. Other se-quences of historical conditioning could have preparedthe speaker to exclaim that “the whole place is inflated.”However, if it happens as a result of the kind of condi-tioning history that has been described in this example,the emergence of the term inflated represents a solecisticextension of a tact.

Solecistic extensions of tacts are seldom appropriateand hence are typically extinguished or even punishedwithin a verbal community. Solecistic extensions have of-ten been assumed to reflect some kind of neurologicaldisorder. However, while any pattern of unusual behaviorcould be rendered more probable by an unusual kind ofphysiological state that we call a disorder, we can accountfor the general occurrence of solecistic extensions of tactsthrough explanatory recourse only to behavioral condi-tioning in conjunction with current circumstances. Somesolecistic extensions can be useful for their humorouseffects and on that basis may be reinforced.

Although the term tact often describes a response in iso-lation, a tact is more correctly construed to be the behavior–environment functional relation in which that response ismerely the dependent variable. Thus, given a response thatcould be a tact, we complete the diagnostic analysis by seek-ing and specifying the relevant antecedent stimulus anddemonstrating the functional relation between the two vari-ables. As we have seen in this section, we can then furthercategorize a tact on the basis of how it was conditioned andthe history of changes in how it is controlled.

AbstractionAbstraction is often attributed to special mental pow-

ers, and examples of abstraction are adduced as evidenceof what are assumed to be cognitive activities initiativelydemonstrated by a mental agent (i.e., a creative mind atwork). However, the process of abstraction, by whichultimately a response can be brought under control of asingle stimulus property, is a natural process. The processof abstraction has been demonstrated, not only in humanbehavior, but in the behavior of other species as well.

Normally, when a particular response is reinforced inthe presence of some stimulus, that stimulus will actuallybe a composite set of stimuli. During a conditioning pro-cess, those stimulus elements take on different evocativestrengths with respect to the subsequent response. For ex-ample, given an experimental subject, let us begin by pre-senting a stimulus consisting of a large yellow beach ball

and manding an utterance of sphere. Suppose that, as weconduct repeated trials of this procedure, we reinforce onlythe vocal response sphere in the presence of this stimulus.Such conditioning of the tact sphere may render that relationreliable, but what exactly is then evoking the responsesphere in the presence of this large yellow beach ball?

The salient properties of this particular ball includesize (e.g., relatively large), and color (yellow), as well asthe additional set of properties that define beach balls,only one of which is spherical shape (others include elas-ticity, surface texture, overall density, construction seams,etc.). The capacity to evoke the response sphere, whichthe operant conditioning has imparted to this beach ball,has been distributed among the various properties of thisball, and among various combinations of those proper-ties, all in proportions that remain unknown. Although,as a result of the previously described program of condi-tioning, our subject now responds reliably with the tactsphere to presentations of this large yellow beach ball, weremain unable to specify, in terms of the specific proper-ties of that ball, the precise controlling function, or func-tions, through which the tact sphere is being evoked.

People may say that we cannot be sure that our sub-ject has “learned the true concept” of sphere, but more ac-curately, we cannot identify the properties that are nowin control of the tact sphere. We may find that our subjectnow identifies as a sphere any relatively large object thatis yellow in color regardless of its shape. In that case, thatresponse would be under the shared evocative control ofrelative size and yellow color, neither of which are amongthe definitive properties of a sphere.

The technical definition of a sphere has nothing to dowith size, color, construction materials, or applications.To avoid the undesirable extensions of tacts that leavethem under the control of such irrelevant properties, themembers of a verbal community, especially teachers, willcounter such potential extensions by confining re-inforcement to tacts that are more narrowly evoked.

For instance, in the current example, the evocativecontrol of the tact sphere by irrelevant factors can beeliminated if on some occasions we present those ir-relevant properties in the absence of the properties thatdefine a sphere. On the occasions of such presentationswe would extinguish manifestations of the tact sphere,while reinforcing that tact on all other occasions whenthe definitive properties of a sphere are present. Althoughteachers deliberately pursue such procedures under thecontrolled conditions of formal education, such narrow-ing of the controls on tacts also occurs naturally if some-what imprecisely across the years of informal languageconditioning within a verbal community.

Eventually, regardless of whether irrelevant propertiesare also present, only those that define a sphere will beleft in control of the tact sphere. At that point, any sphere

Page 15: On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts · On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts ... Interest in the behaviorological analysis of verbal behavior (Skinner, ) continues

�ehaviorology �oday � Volume 7, Number 2, Fall 2004 (issn 1536–6669) Page 23

will be tacted as such, regardless of its superfluous prop-erties. It may be said invalidly that the subject has men-tally abstracted the concept of sphere, but we completelyaccount for the phenomenon of abstraction by consider-ing only that the stimulus controls on the tact sphere havebeen narrowed to the minimal definitive set of propertiesfor a sphere.

Tacts of Private EventsThe stimuli that collectively constitute the real physi-

cal world are not confined to the realm beyond the skin.In pursuing our analyses of behavior–controlling func-tions, we do not cross into a mystical domain simply be-cause we begin to investigate the behavior–controllingcapacities of stimuli that are located within the body ofthe behaving organism. Many contingencies of rein-forcement involve stimuli that occur within the body thatis exhibiting the behavior of concern. As often noted, theenvironment pervades the body, and the naturalness offunctions between environment and behavior is not de-pendent on where in the world the functional antecedentstimuli are located. It matters only that behavior–control-ling stimuli are measurable events, although the relativelyinaccessible location of some such stimuli pose substan-tial challenges to those who are under contingencies tomeasure them. The tact tree and the tact pain may beequally valid even though the evocative stimulus for theformer is in public view on a remote mountain side andthe evocative stimulus for the latter is deep within theknee of the vocalizer.

Stimuli that arise within the body are usually privatein the sense that other people seldom have access to them.That problem of access is not limited to others. We our-selves seldom see, and only occasionally hear, eventswithin our own body, nor can we usually touch, taste, orsmell them. Many of our senses are biologically evolvedto facilitate contacts with the outside environment and areof limited help in making contact with internal stimuli.

However, we do have interoceptive nervous systemsof limited range by which we privately contact certainkinds, although not all kinds, of internal events. Suchcontacts enable speakers to produce tacts that are evokedby certain kinds of events within their own bodies. Thus,a person may tact such internal events as hunger pangs,pains, various pulses, and the kinds of systemic after–effect of glandular chemical discharges into the bloodstream that we know, in general, as emotional arousal.

The privacy of the kind of behavior–controlling re-lations that feature internal stimuli creates problems for averbal community. Those problems pertain to access, butthe privacy of those functions does not preclude the po-tential reality of their constituent events. Although themembers of the verbal community must supply the be-havior–changing consequences of verbal behavior (i.e.,

the postcedent stimuli), they cannot accurately and pre-cisely do so when they cannot share in contacting what-ever has evoked an instance of public verbal behavior. Ifthe mediator is reliably to provide timely and appropriateconsequences for a vocalizer’s response, the antecedentstimulus for that response must affect both the vocalizerand the mediator.

In cases of a vocalizer’s tact–like response that seemsto have been evoked by a private stimulus that has arisenwithin that vocalizer (a stimulus to which a mediatorcannot be privy), a given kind of consequence that is thensupplied by the mediator may not be appropriate. That isbecause, from the mediator’s limited perspective, thatspecific instance of the vocalizer’s verbal behavior may ormay not represent a valid tact of the private event ofwhich it is a prima facie description. If a vocalizer says Ihave a headache, that statement may be occurring in re-sponse to stimuli that are entirely unrelated to pain–gen-erating events within the speaker’s head.

Let us further consider that kind of important dis-tinction. If a person produces the vocal utterance bird asan apparent tact, a member of the verbal community canoften determine independently whether a bird is presentbefore providing consequences. In that way the mediatorreinforces only appropriately controlled responses by thevocalizer. If, on the other hand, the utterance is headache,a mediator may have no way to confirm the reality of theimplicit stimulus. In fact, the feigned headache is a com-mon social ploy of avoidance when the verbalizer wouldprefer not to describe the impending events, therebyaborted, as aversive in general.

When consequating a statement that tacts a privateevent, the mediator may have to rely on indirect evi-dence, however tenuous, or simply follow the general so-cial prescription, common within the culture, for how toreact on such occasions. An example is the common prac-tice of politely giving the benefit of the doubt to a personwho claims to have a headache. Speakers thus have somelatitude to manipulate the behavior of their listeners byfalsely reporting private events, while listeners cannot beheld strictly accountable for inappropriately consequatingwhat seems superficially to be a speaker’s tact of a privateevent occurring within his or her own body.

One solution to the mediator’s problem of limited ac-cess is the use of special equipment to expose events thatoccur within the vocalizer’s body, thus making thoseevents publicly detectable. Modern medical facilities fea-ture a wide variety of such devices. A patient who saysthat a strange sensation is being felt in the abdomen maybe vocalizing that tact to a doctor who is looking at animage of that patient’s internal organs and seeing a metalshard lodged in the wall of the small intestine. That doc-tor is thus prepared to consequate the patient’s report ina way that comports with a valid tact.

Page 16: On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts · On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts ... Interest in the behaviorological analysis of verbal behavior (Skinner, ) continues

Page 24 (issn 1536–6669) �ehaviorology �oday � Volume 7, Number 2, Fall 2004

In addition to the use of special equipment, a media-tor may simply probe the body of the vocalizer tactilely,as when a mediator feels for a suspicious lump of whichthat vocalizer claims to be aware within some part of hisor her own body. Note that the patient and the doctor donot contact, in the same way, an event that is occurringwithin the patient. The patient may be responding topain or pressure sensations that manifest in response totransmission along the interoceptive nervous system,while the doctor is responding to the feel of the lumpthat is generated by tactile probing from without. How-ever, when the respectively detected events seem to sharea common location, they tend to be accepted by bothparties as the same event. Thus, the patient’s tact lumpand the doctor’s tact lump may depend respectively oncontrol by different properties of what both parties treatas the same event.

Note that the tact of a pain is necessarily a responseto certain properties of the arriving energy and not a re-sponse to the latent properties of the source from whichthat energy emanated. One’s response can pertain to thelocation from which the energy began its neural trans-mission, and the response may comport with aversivestimulation. Thus, a person may report a pain in the rightelbow or an ache in the left calf muscle, yet remain un-able to respond to any other potential independent vari-ables that may define the events that are occurring atthose locations. In agential terms it may be said that theverbalizer could not provide more detail, because onlypain is available to control the responses.

An external analogy would be a person’s report of analmost blindingly bright light shining directly into theperson’s eyes. The person’s tact may occur under exclusivecontrol of the impinging light and be vocally descriptiveonly of its direction, wavelength, and intensity. Certainproperties of that response may comport with aversivestimulation, but, as with the private pain, the person mayremain unable to respond to additional independent vari-ables and thus provide a more detailed account. That is,this person may be unable to say anything more aboutthe external light source just as the other person could saynothing more about the internal source of the pain.

In the frequent absence of special help for listeners incontacting private stimuli that are implicit in tacts thatare uttered by speakers, listeners are not always helpless inproducing appropriate responses to those speakers’ state-ments. Many private events have non–behavioral pub-licly detectable accompaniments. The person who saysMy left leg hurts may have a visible wound or bruise onthat leg of a kind that, in the past, has produced pain forthe listener. The potential mediator is not privy to the vo-calizer’s pain but is contacting a kind of non–behavioralevent that has accompanied pain sensations in thatmediator’s own experience. That correlation increases the

probability that consequences relevant to pain, suppliedby the mediator, will be strengthening what was a validtact by the vocalizer.

Another kind of indirect confirmation of the validityof a private tact involves collateral responses, which may benonverbal, yet are also exhibited by the vocalizer alongwith that tact. If the vocalizer who is reporting a privatepain in the left leg is also holding or rubbing that leg—and perhaps exhibiting a grimacing facial expression, thelistener is more likely to consequate the verbal utteranceas if it is a valid tact of a private event. Such rein-forcement of the vocalizer’s audible report conditions thevocalizer to report future pains on such occasions, thusestablishing that tact in the vocalizer’s verbal repertoire9.The reinforcers of the tact also incidentally strengthenthe correlated practices of manipulating the sore spot andgrimacing. Thus, in general, the private event that evokesa publicly audible verbal response may also be evokingother kinds of public responses—a multiplicity of de-pendent behavioral variables that together increase theverisimilitude of their hidden, implicit, and commonlyshared, independent variable.

A mediator may comprehend a vocalizer’s tact of aprivate event if, within the verbal community, that tacthas been strengthened in public contexts. The vocalizer ismerely extending that tact to a private event that sharessome properties with whatever has evoked that same tactwhen it has been uttered and reinforced in public contexts.

Suppose, for example, that a vocalizer describes thefeeling that is generated by a private emotional state asfrothing. The term frothing describes the exuding of foam,often correlated with agitated states of fluids, and, in thecase of animals, with the aggressive madness that maycharacterize rabies. A vocalizer who is emotionallyaroused under aversive stimulation, especially when thatstimulation has been arranged by an identifiable party,may exhibit agitated, aggressive, and hostile patterns ofbehavior that share some properties with the kind of cir-cumstances that produce froth. If that aroused personvocally tacts his or her private state as frothing, the listenermay have no difficulty in reacting appropriately to thevocalizer’s remark. It could still be an invalid tact, but atleast the mediator is not confused about the general na-ture of the internal state that the vocalizer is putativelydescribing in that metaphorical way.

As we have seen in the previous discussion, listenersare not always exclusively reliant on a vocalizer’s tacts ofprivate events. Additional evidence may be available tosupport or contradict what implicitly is a tact of a privateevent. However, even with such additional evidence, themediator’s response to such a tact will always be occur-ring under less than complete control. (Put agentially, themediator’s confidence in the vocalizer’s tact is always lessthan complete.) A person’s request to be excused from an

Page 17: On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts · On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts ... Interest in the behaviorological analysis of verbal behavior (Skinner, ) continues

�ehaviorology �oday � Volume 7, Number 2, Fall 2004 (issn 1536–6669) Page 25

activity because of a toothache may not be occurring inresponse to such pain, and that may still be true eventhough the vocalizer exhibits publicly visible damage to atooth, holds the jaw in one hand, displays a grimacingfacial expression, and describes the pain as piercing.

Tacts and RealitySpecial analytical problems arise when a tact of an

implicitly external event occurs in the public absence ofthe kind of event that normally evokes that tact. A personsaying blue while looking at the daylight sky poses noproblem. However, suppose that a person, in the completeabsence of any stimuli that evoke the tact blue by othermembers of the verbal community, says I see blue. Oneimmediate issue is what, if anything, is evoking that re-sponse as a tact. Perhaps it is an extended tact of some kind.

If the statement presents a tact of a real on–goingevent, which currently is not also affecting any potentialmediators (i.e., they don’t detect it), then the evocation ofthat complete statement (i.e., I see blue) is being shared by(a) some privately detected general seeing behavior as wellas (b) the properties of the particular private vision thatis occurring. That is, in that case, the vocalizer who saysI see blue is responding to the behavior of seeing (i.e., Isee…) as well as to a property of the vision that is occur-ring (i.e., …blue). That blueness may also be regarded asa property of an environmental event that implicitly is thesource of the impinging energy (e.g., a piece of blue pa-per, a patch of sky, or the open flower of a morning glory).

With respect to the issue of blueness, blue is a behav-ior in the class that is commonly called visual conscious-ness or visual awareness. When the verbal tact blue is beingconditioned, the blue visual behavior that is being tactedtends to happen when light of a certain range of wave-lengths impinges upon the eyes of the behaving organismas well as the eyes of those who provide consequences forthe tact. We cannot confirm that contact with light ofconsistent wavelength results in exactly the same privatebehavioral manifestation within each person in the verbalcommunity. That is, we cannot be sure that how you be-have blue is identical to how I behave blue.

Nevertheless, given common access to wavelengths oflight impinging from the same environmental direction,individuals becomes conditioned to tact their private re-spective visions as blue. The commonalty that supportsinterpersonal communication pertinent to these ongoingevents thus inheres in the incoming wavelengths and inthe resulting tacts; it does not necessarily inhere in theparticulars of the private behavioral manifestations thatare evoked by that incoming energy.

The capacity to produce behaviorally the privatemanifestation of blue is apparently a biological endow-ment. Taking that into account, we simply expect privateblue behaviors, which manifest neurally, to occur

automatically in the presence of appropriate stimulation.That being the case, the private neural behavior describedas blueness would occur respondently and do so simplybecause its manifestation is physiologically capacitated bygenetically endowed structure. That is to say that, giventhe appropriate eliciting stimulation, the private neuralbehavior called blue occurs automatically. However, itstacts (such as calling it blue and reporting that it is oc-curring [I see blue]) are verbal operants that must be con-ditioned by a verbal community. That is also true of thenonverbal classes of discriminative responding to thatprivate neural behavior.

Actually, among behavior scientists, the question ofwhether the visual awareness of blue precedes theconditioning of the tact blue (and other kinds of dis-criminative behavior) has long been debated. Is the veryawareness of blue a product of conditioning? As the ques-tion is often posed, is one aware of blue before beingconditioned to talk about it? That is, at issue is whether ablue sensational behavior (i.e., a visual awareness of blue-ness) is a predecessor or a correlated product of the oper-ant conditioning of discriminative behavior with respectto blue. Put another way, given the environmental inputof light having a particular range of wavelengths, must anew person’s first private blue visual awareness responsebe prompted in some way before it can occur—or does ithappen automatically?

Some organisms that have no physiological capacityfor verbal behavior and little if any capacity for con-sciousness nevertheless respond differently in nonverbalways to contacts with respectively different wavelengthsof light. This could be occurring respondently, or it couldbe occurring operantly under direct stimulus control—ineither case without the additional neural behavior ofcolor awareness.

Something similar can occur in the case of humans ifthe capacities to behave consciously are sufficiently preoc-cupied. For instance, a person who is given batches ofmarbles each containing a mix of blue and red marblescan be trained to sort them by color while daydreamingabout entirely different events. The training need onlycontinue long enough for the extinction of the variousbehaviors of consciousness that are evoked by the sort-ing–related events, so that the alternative behavior ofdaydreaming can emerge prepotently and thus preoccupythat behavioral capacity While engaged in that sortingduring such daydreams, the person is not visually awareof the marbles or their colors.

Likewise, the right foot of a daydreaming automobiledriver may discriminatively alternate between pressingthe throttle and the brake in respective response tochanging events in the external driving environmentwithout any concurrent behaviors of awareness beingproduced by the driving–related events. (In such in-

Page 18: On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts · On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts ... Interest in the behaviorological analysis of verbal behavior (Skinner, ) continues

Page 26 (issn 1536–6669) �ehaviorology �oday � Volume 7, Number 2, Fall 2004

stances that feature humans, the body parts that exhibitthe behavior of awareness are preoccupied; in many otherspecies the body does not include neural parts that canexhibit awareness–type responses.)

At issue is how that neural behavior of color aware-ness (or any kind of awareness) first arises. As the ques-tion has often been posed, is an awareness that manifestsas blue a respondent behavior that occurs automaticallyin response to certain wavelengths of light and, upon oc-curring, can then evoke whatever verbal behaviors a ver-bal organism becomes conditioned operantly to exhibitin the presence of that kind of visual awareness? …Or, isan awareness of blue an operant neural behavior the pri-mal manifestations of which must somehow be teasedinto operant occurrence? One must be conditioned oper-antly to talk and think about one’s visual awareness ofblue, but what about the origins of that kind of awarenessbehavior per se?

All verbal behavior is based on awareness behavior inthe sense that verbal behaviors consists of responses toawareness behaviors. Eliminate awareness, and a state ofultimate oblivion ensures—a state in which, for all verbalbehavior, the functional connection with the behavior–controlling environment has been severed by the removalof one of its critical internal links. Organisms that suc-cessfully interact with their environments exclusively un-der direct stimulus control (echinoderms, for example),not surprisingly, exhibit no kind of verbal behavior.

Evolution operates by the selection mechanism, andevolutionary progress can be made only in the presenceof variations from which selection can occur. The class ofevents that exhibits the variation must already be present,and in addition, certain of the variations must portend agreater survival advantage than others.

As we attempt to relate these principles to the physi-cal capacity for awareness behavior, a relevant family ofquestions lingers: Do awareness behaviors happen auto-matically in a respondent mode even before we reactoperantly to them in further discriminative ways? Or, arethey already operant responses that we have had to ac-quire through some kind of operant conditioning? Is thecapacity for awareness behavior an essential element inthe mediation of unconsciously occurring behaviors inresponse to sensory inputs—or, is the capacity for visualawareness not in the linkage of such mediation? That is,do the structures that exhibit awareness behavior have tobe in place even for direct stimulus control to occur, eventhough in such cases those structures would not be ex-hibiting awareness behaviors? If that is so, the structuralcapacity for awareness behavior would at least be avail-able to “come under operant control” whether that im-plies some further biological evolutionary tweaking ormerely their subjection to some new kinds of behavior–

controlling arrangements within the scope of operantconditioning (or both).

This issue of how a private neural behavior such asblue can first arise is somewhat peripheral in the field ofbehaviorology. It is more central to the concerns of evo-lutionary physiologists, who bring the appropriately rel-evant scientific repertoire to such issues.

Logically, it seems as though a person must behaveblue privately before being conditioned by a verbal com-munity to call it blue, otherwise there would be nothingto talk about. We remain less sure about the need to be-have blue before responding discriminatively to it in non-verbal ways under natural contingencies. For instance, avisual awareness of colors may not be relevant to the dis-criminative approach of an insect to blue flowers in thepresence of both red and blue flowers even when the dis-criminative responding is controlled by the wavelength ofthe impinging light. Here we allude to a direct stimuluscontrol of the approach behaviors. That is, if visualawareness is a separate behavior in response to impinginglight waves of a certain frequency, that kind of behaviormay not be a necessary link in the control of the discrimi-native behavior of approaching certain flowers but notothers even if the behavioral elements of approach arecontrolled by those light waves via the visual sense. Suchcontrol would be direct, just as the daydreaming driver’scar–steering behavior is controlled by light impingingfrom the scene that is ahead of the car, although that lightis failing to evoke any concomitant seeing behavior.

In the case of verbal organisms, we assume that theprivate behavioral sensation that comes to be tacted asblue must precede the operant conditioning of its tact,and people have usually extended that reasoning to otherkinds of discriminative operant responding to the incom-ing wavelength of light such a pressing a blue key but nota red one. Yet the basic question remains: Is the humanbodily structure entirely prepared, as a matter of geneticendowment, to produce the behaviors of awareness in thesame sense that the body is genetically structured to pro-duce a wide variety of other respondent behaviors, giventhe appropriate antecedent stimulation? …Or, must thebody undergo further micro–structuring through somekind of behavioral conditioning before it is ready to ex-hibit awareness behaviors?10

Knowing per se is a behavioral phenomenon. To beaware of, or to know of, a distinction (e.g., the presencevs. the absence of a given stimulus, or stimulus as differ-ent from stimulus ) is already to behave discriminatively.We say that that awareness behavior occurs under the re-spective alternative environmental conditions. The know-ing of the distinction, which is but one class ofdiscriminative behavior, can manifest only as discrimina-tive behavior (that is simply the nature of knowing perse). That is, we are constrained to behave our knowing

Page 19: On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts · On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts ... Interest in the behaviorological analysis of verbal behavior (Skinner, ) continues

�ehaviorology �oday � Volume 7, Number 2, Fall 2004 (issn 1536–6669) Page 27

just as we are constrained to behave our elbow bends.When we posit environmental reality beyond the behav-ior of knowing it, that reality is necessarily a speculativeinference (i.e., just more of our private verbal behaving).Our knowing of a remote mountain (or of a private feel-ing) consists of discriminative behavior, and our furtherinsistence that either of those events is “really there” is butmore behavior in response to that behavior. Thus, theclosest that we can come to the environment is our owndiscriminative behavior, presumably in response to thatposited environment. We are trapped on one side ofthose posited functional relations, because “we” are butone side of those functional relations.

A person’s verbal behavior has many characteristicsthat can evoke that individual’s own further discrimina-tive verbal behavior. For example, we have discussed howpeople respond overtly to the covert nature of their pri-vate verbal behavior (e.g., the audibly vocalized statementI am thinking about you). In addition, people often re-spond to characteristics of the functional relations thatcontrol their behaviors, verbal or nonverbal. For instance,the currency of their behavior may evoke I am running.They may also respond both to the historical nature oftheir behavior (I ran yesterday) and to the environmentalfactors that determine the probability of their future be-havior (If a fire starts, I will run).

In the case of a statement that is rendered in thepresent tense, the identification of the evocative stimuliby a listener typically presents relatively few if any ana-lytical problems. For instance, when another person saysThere’s a car, we look around in ways that, in the past,have resulted in car–seeing behavior, and often, as a resultof looking, we experience the behavior that is describedas seeing it. That contact (of a sort) is the basis for oursubsequent conclusion that the vocalizer’s statement(There’s a car) was valid. Obviously, the car is known onlyin the sense that we have behaved it.

However, the evocative stimuli for statements cast inthe past and future tenses can seem more illusive. A state-ment such as I ran yesterday is often described as amemory. However, the independent variables remain uni-dentified. Those functional independent variables mustbe present currently, because current behavior is evokedonly by current stimuli. However, the body that is cur-rently vocalizing in the past tense about running is notcurrently exhibiting the behavior that is being described.The stimuli that shared in defining yesterday do not leapforward in time to evoke the future behavior that sharesin defining today. At best, they are links in chains offunctionally determined events that account for what hasbecome the current environment.

The behavioral events of yesterday produced, at thattime, structural changes in both the body and its envi-ronment that may remain in place to capacitate the cur-

rent evocation of the statement I ran yesterday. For exam-ple, a current stimulus pertinent to running may nowevoke a covert vision of yesterday’s running episode, be-cause the body has been left, since yesterday’s condition-ing episode, with the structural capacity to produce thatkind of seeing behavior in response to certain stimuli thatmay remain available a day later. However, although trig-gered by a current stimulus (i.e., by an element of thecurrent environment), the constituent events of that vi-sion are out of context in the current environment as awhole (in the sense that the current environment is notevoking running behavior, but is evoking only a vision ofyesterday’s running behavior).

We are linguistically conditioned by our verbalcommunity to speak of such visions, which are incongru-ous with the current environment, in the past tense, justas we are conditioned to call them memories. That condi-tioned grammatical nuance along with our subsequentresponses to it, constitutes our knowing that such cur-rently re–stimulated visions pertain to originals that haveoccurred in prior contexts. That is the essence of oursense of past. Behaviorally, we exist only in our present,and current behavioral re–visitations of our past are ac-tually always new behaviors that are occurring in ourpresent in response to stimuli that also are present. Thus,the reality of the past is always necessarily a currently pro-duced inference that is evoked by the kind of current be-havior–controlling circumstance that is described above.

The residual issue for analysis is why some currentrunning–related stimulus so readily evokes a new visionsimilar to a vision that occurred in the presumed past.That, of course, is not a difficult question, at least at thetheoretical level, because it is answered by explanatory re-course to the physiological implications of the basicmodel of operant conditioning: The original vision of thebehavior was reinforced, which left the bodyreconfigured, at a microstructural level, to more readilybehave in that way whenever an appropriate evocativestimulus is again contacted.

Thus, today, contact between a body and a running–related stimulus is, to describe it more precisely, a run-ning–related stimulus in contact with a body that is nowbetter configured to reproduce a similar episode of visualawareness. A response now occurs in the presence of therunning–related stimulus, which by its very mani-festation defines the currency of that vision–type of re-sponse, but the context of the vision that is now beingevoked is not current (i.e., is not now present in the sensethat that context would evoke behavior different fromthat evoked following current looking and other environ-ment–sampling posturing of the body). That is, the envi-ronment that, if contacted, would evoke the currentvision differs from the environment that is contactedthrough current attending behaviors. In common par-

Page 20: On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts · On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts ... Interest in the behaviorological analysis of verbal behavior (Skinner, ) continues

Page 28 (issn 1536–6669) �ehaviorology �oday � Volume 7, Number 2, Fall 2004

lance, what one is now seeing is not what one would beseeing if one were alertly to look around and pay atten-tion to what currently is there.

That kind of on–going vision, or private seeing be-havior, which is discrepant with respect to the current en-vironment, may then, on the basis of that discrepancy,evoke the statement I ran yesterday. When such a past–tense verb form manifests, is little more than a de-scription of some current private behavior that is nowoccurring in the absence of most of its typical evocativethematic events. That is, in response to a current al-though isolated or fragmentary stimulus, one may re–seeor re–feel oneself running while, at the same time, react-ing to one’s currently non–running body as well as to anenvironment that does not currently evoke running.Casting the description of the visualized running in thepast tense is a response to that kind of incompatibility be-tween (a) one’s current visual awareness of the motivestate of one’s body relative to a running–compatible en-vironment and (b) other immediate attention–directedresponses to the motive state of one’s body in relation tothe current environment. That is, one is seeing oneselfrunning in an environment that would evoke running,but it is an environment that differs from the alternativeenvironment that is seen when one exhibits inspectionbehaviors pertinent to one’s immediate environment.

As described in common agential terms, if one snapsout of one’s reminiscence and pays attention to what iscurrently happening, the behavior being recalled wouldbe out of place in the immediate situation. Given thatthose classes of responding differ, the test for the currencyof the remembered behavior thereby fails, and the presenttense is not evoked when describing it. The person couldexplain what is happening by saying something like this:I have been experiencing a vision of myself running in a real-istic context. That vision has been evoked in a way that didnot anticipate (i.e., prompt) its contents. However, I havealso then contacted (a) the current state of my body and(b) the environment in which it currently exists, and, whenI did so, the inspection–induced vision my body was not run-ning in either a manner or context that comports with theinitial vision of myself running. Therefore, I am conditionedto regard the running in my initial kind of vision as havingoccurred previously, and I have been conditioned to describeany such running in the past tense. (If one remembers run-ning yesterday while running today, that situation wouldbe subject to the same kind of analysis, but the distinc-tions to which the analyst would have to respond wouldbe more subtle.)

Note, however, that the behavior of sensing the pastis happening in the present and is actually evoked by cur-rent (not past) events. The behaviors that are commonlyclassed as memories, recollections, or remembrances oc-cur exclusively as a function of current events (as do all

behavioral reactions). That is, everything behavioral hap-pens in the present, and we must account for our behav-ioral senses of both past and future in terms of presentevocative events. A sense of the reality of the past, by itsnature, is often said to be an abstraction that is derivedfrom past tacts, visions, and other nonverbal reactions,that have accumulated, but those are all behaviors, whichare processes, not entities, so they do not really ac-cumulate. They happen transiently and can have no sta-tus of endurance beyond their durations. Thus, memoriescannot be reiterations of stored behaviors.

When occurring initially, however, behavioral reac-tions to the environment, including tacts, result in con-sequences that physically change the body that hasmediated that behavior of contact—a kind of molecularscale change that renders that body more or less behavior-ally susceptible to such contacts11 on similar future occa-sions. On such future occasions of contact withenvironments that share stimulus elements with the pre-sent occasion, that kind of contact behavior, or a frag-mentary version of it, may be re–evoked. However, thatwill be happening in a future context that differs from thecurrent context. On such future occasions, it is that con-textual disparity, between currently re–evoked versions ofearlier contacts and on–going contacts of current events,that controls the casting of descriptions in the past tense.(Such evocations of specific tense forms, which dependcomparatively on the properties of behavior–controllingrelations, represent another large class of verbal behavior,called autoclitic verbal behavior, that will be discussed inthe next major section of this chapter.)

Thus, what is called a sense of the reality of the past isnecessarily always a current behavioral manifestation. Itcan be said that one behaves the reality of the past, butone must always be doing so in the present. Thus, thepast can have no essence beyond current behavior andhow it is being controlled. The so–called reality of thepast necessarily inheres only as an artifact of current be-havioral phenomena. Past is a current behavioral reactionto some currently encountered behavior–controlling rela-tions and to the relations among those relations.

Although, upon analysis, these controls may seemcomplex and subtle, the time–related verbal behaviorsthat denote the past tense are typically produced with anatural ease, largely because one comes so often undercontingencies to speak of the past that the necessary rela-tions are strongly conditioned and kept so. While an ac-counting for grammatical tenses as natural phenomenacan quickly become complex, the contingencies underwhich tense forms are produced are encountered fre-quently. Thus, within verbal communities, especiallythose in which verbal behavior is presumed to be themanifest will of a mystical self–agent, the intuitive gram-

Page 21: On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts · On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts ... Interest in the behaviorological analysis of verbal behavior (Skinner, ) continues

�ehaviorology �oday � Volume 7, Number 2, Fall 2004 (issn 1536–6669) Page 29

matical skills of the members quickly outstrip their ca-pacity to provide a rational account for those skills.

The statement I will run tomorrow must also occurunder current stimulation. Future events, being virtual orpotential, are necessarily unreal and cannot function asevocative stimuli for current behaviors such as that state-ment. An assumption that a future event is controlling acurrent statement is classed as a teleological error. In gen-eral, during past behavioral episodes of operant condi-tioning, we have seen ourselves repeating behavior thathas been reinforced. In particular, in the past we have re-peated previous behaviors on later occasions when rein-forcement was possible or probable (occasions that weredefined by the presence of appropriately strengthenedevocative stimuli).

Given such a conditioning history featuring, for ex-ample, the reinforcement of running behavior, if cur-rently I contact events that, in the past, have preceded, byabout a day, the evocative stimuli for running—currentevents that, after about a day, have in the past led to thepresentation of stimuli that evoke running, I am condi-tioned to respond now to those current precursory cir-cumstances by saying something like Tomorrow, I’ll havean opportunity to run, and I will run. If I have not run re-cently, the evocative capacity of those current stimuli maybe further increased by the effects of deprivation.

If, instead of a history of reinforcement, one has hada history of aversive stimulation with respect to events nowencountered, a corresponding analysis of the controls ontense forms can be made with respect to avoidance andescape behaviors. Suppose that one contacts stimuli thatreliably have preceded a punished behavior. One may thendescribe those stimuli as threatening. In addition to evok-ing reviews of past sequences of behavior and its punish-ment, those currently encountered stimuli may alsoevoke a vision, or other kind of sensation, of one engag-ing in avoidance behavior that one has not yet exhibited.

The avoidance behavior may take a familiar formthat has never before been associated with this particularkind of aversive stimulation, or it may represent a newinstance of a familiar way of avoiding the impendingkind of aversive stimulation. The critical aspect is that theavoidance behavior featured in the current neural itera-tion is either a repeated version of a specific pattern ofbehavior that is occurring under a new aversive stimula-tion (new kind of threat; old means of avoidance) or anew combination of behaviors that are occurring under afamiliar kind of stimulation (familiar threat; new set ofavoidance behaviors).12 If one then comes under con-tingencies to describe the situation, the description willbe rendered in the future tense (e.g., Upon seeing that bullyapproaching, I am going to leave the area before he arrives).

Casting the verb in the future tense is a response tothe relation among some behavior–controlling relations.

In the above example, a current event reliably evokes anawareness and recognition of previous behavior alongwith its punishment. The current event, along with thisevoked neural behavior, may together also evoke a visionof one engaging in an alternative to the previously pun-ished behavior. The imagined episode is not an exactreiteration of a past episode (i.e., not an imagined copy ofsome previous behavior). That is, either the evocativestimuli or the combination of responses is new. Membersof a verbal community has been conditioned to describethe imagined manifestation of that different potential re-lation in situations of this kind as what one is going to do(i.e., in the future tense).

In any case, a predictive statement such as I will runtomorrow or I will say something nice does not imply amagical functional contact with a future event, but is in-stead actually a response to some current events. Neitherdoes it imply the reality of a knowledgeable self. Thegrammatical form of the verb in such a statement, whichis said to represent the future tense, has been conditionedon such occasions by the linguistic practices of one’s ver-bal community. The linguistic forms indicative of tensethen manifest automatically under control of some nuancesamong the controlling relations on some private neural be-haviors in the class to which people refer as one’s imaginings.

The imagined future episode may manifest in theelaborate detail of a daydream or it may recede to thelevel of a sketchy, fleeting, and fragmentary glimpse.Only temporal and associative factors pertaining to itscontrols discriminatively evoke the tense–indicativeforms. Thus, a person may describe a behavior in the fu-ture tense in the absence of a complete imagined versionof that behavior, because the future tense forms are con-trolled by non–thematic details of the imagined epi-sode—namely, by relations among the controllingrelations of its elements. When one says I will go to thestore, for the tense to be correctly rendered, one need notfirst imagine in detail a complete trip to the store. Thosetense forms need only be under control of relationsamong the controls on the elements of such an imaginedstory. Thus, the appropriate tense form can manifestquickly, and the imagined story per se need not actuallyunfold in detail for references to it to include forms thatdenote futurity.

Note that a sense of futurity inheres in current circum-stances. That sense of futurity manifests in the form of state-ments being cast in the future tense. However, futurity isalways a current behavioral product. Again, with respectto our futures, as with respect to our pasts, the reality ofpast and future can manifest only as current behavioralphenomena, with the critical distinction inhering in thenature of the controlling relations. We behave our senseof future as we behave our sense of past, with both occur-ring as aspects of our present behavior. The essence of the

Page 22: On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts · On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts ... Interest in the behaviorological analysis of verbal behavior (Skinner, ) continues

Page 30 (issn 1536–6669) �ehaviorology �oday � Volume 7, Number 2, Fall 2004

distinction between past, present, and future (includingtense–indicative constructions, and any other aspects ofour so–called sense of time) inheres in some different waysin which current behaviors are being controlled.13

Responding to Temporal RelationsSuppose that people are sensing their own behaviors.

Further suppose that those behaviors are occurring in acontext that does not share in defining the current ambi-ent environment. That is, such people are witnessingself–behavior that is occurring in reaction to virtual envi-ronments that differ from the environments that are re-vealed when “they start paying attention to what actuallysurrounds them.” In such cases, the behavior that theysense themselves exhibiting is virtual too. Neither the en-vironment nor the behavioral responses to it will passtests of reality.

Let us further assume, in this case, that the virtualbehavior is occurring in a context that, relevant to realtime, places it in the past. People, in situations of thiskind, can normally specify whether such neural activityrepresents memory or imagination. Future events must beimagined necessarily, and consciousness of past eventsalso may be imagined (i.e., past events that have not ac-tually occurred). However, a current consciousness ofpast events may also represent reiterations of previous be-havior that actually occurred in the past.

We distinguish (a) the virtual behaviors that we re-gard respectively as representing actual past behavior and(b) imagined behavior when we tact the former as a mem-ory and the latter as a daydream. We seldom confound amemory and an episode of imagination. If one is askedwhether one is remembering a real party or merely imagin-ing an alternative to what actually occurred, in most casesa valid report is forthcoming with ease. At issue is thequestion of what enables peoples’ normally easy discrimi-native reactions to a memory and an imaginary recastingof history.

During a memory of a sequence of events, each neu-rally reviewed event evokes the next one without the ad-dition of new supplementary stimuli that add to, or enhance,either the behavior that is being recalled or the context inwhich it occurred. That is, for an accurate memory, noth-ing about the circumstances and the behavioral eventsthat occurred under those circumstances must changeduring the process of remembering.

However, the current environment differs from theenvironment in which the original behavior occurred, soone must sense again not only the original behavior butalso a functional equivalent of the behavior–controllingenvironment that produced it. That is, to remember is toengage again in some previous neural behavior. However,in an episode of memory, although those sensations(awareness, recognition, comprehension, etc.) must hap-

pen again as they happened before, this time they mustbe evocatively initiated by current events instead of theevents that evoked the original neural behavior (of con-sciousness). Thus, some aspect of the current environ-ment must initiate the review—perhaps an evocativeverbal prompt, or an encounter with other kinds ofstimuli in common with those that defined the previousepisode that is to be remembered.

If the privately reiterated behavior was strongly con-ditioned by consequences that ensued at the time of itsinitial occurrence, the current memory, once initiated,may chain in a self–sustaining manner. However, a weakmemory may have to be probed, but effective probes formemories do not add to, or subtract from, the context ofthe revisited episode. The conservative probes merelyfunction to narrow or confine the range of the con-stituent stimuli that will share in evoking the nextsequential moment of private reiteration.

For example, one may be having again a vision of aparty that one attended a few days earlier, but supposethat one is re–seeing aspects of that party that do not sa-liently feature all of the guests. If one is under currentcontingencies to identify each of the guests who attendedthat party, an appropriate probe may take the form of asimple instruction: Identify all persons who were in atten-dance. Functionally, such a instruction has the effect ofnarrowing the composite stimulus of a general partyscene to the human figures within it, and the subsequentparty scenes tend to feature the people who attended theparty in more salient ways that enable nominal tacts ofthose people. Importantly, such a probe, while exertingits focusing function with respect to a particular class ofstimulus elements, does not otherwise alter the overallstimulus array that is re–presenting as the memory.

To ask, simply, who was present avoids the presenta-tion of specific stimuli that may have strong capacities toevoke visions of certain people. For instance, the presen-tation of a probe such as Was George at that party? mayinadvertently prompt a George–seeing response that issufficiently strong to intrude into the on–going neuralreiteration. That is, one may then experience a George–seeing response in the context of the party when, in fact,George had not been in attendance. What are intendedas probes must be constructed conservatively lest theymiscarry by functioning as prompts—a point not lost ondevious inquisitors who may inject subtle prompting ele-ments into what are otherwise disguised as thematicallyneutral probes.

Imagination behavior pertaining to past events thathave never actually occurred must manifest as neural be-havior that could not have been strengthened by pastconsequences in the thematic context that is currently beingproduced, so sequential manifestation during imaginationis not facilitated by that kind of special strength. While

Page 23: On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts · On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts ... Interest in the behaviorological analysis of verbal behavior (Skinner, ) continues

�ehaviorology �oday � Volume 7, Number 2, Fall 2004 (issn 1536–6669) Page 31

the behavioral elements in the theme of the imaginedepisode produce reinforcing outcomes, the sequencing ofthose behaviors is new and is thus controlled differentlyfrom the sequencing in a memory.

Note that in a memory, a given neural behavioralevent tends to be followed by a specific subsequent eventon the basis of a microstructural susceptibility that wasestablished through consequation that occurred duringthe past behavioral episode that is now the theme of thememory. That is true of the control of each subsequentevent, so that the unfolding events in a memory share theunbroken sequential predetermination that we liken to apreexistent chain.

In contrast, during the imagined coalescence of somevirtual history, a given neural behavioral event is not al-ready linked to a specific next event by such thematic pre-conditioning. In an imagined historical episode, oneevent follows another on the basis of preconditioningthat was never constrained in a thematic way. That is, inan imagined historical episode, while that next event ispredetermined by past conditioning, that conditioninghistory may have occurred in thematic isolation from theconditioning that strengthened the other elements of theimagined sequence. Thus, during the imagination of afictitious past episode, neural behavioral elementsstrengthened during disparate historical episodes can fallinto place in the new sequence.

The person in whom both of these two classes of pri-vate neural behavior (memory and imagination) canmanifest can usually tell the difference, as they say. That is,the individual can usually respond discriminatively to thekind of control on the sequencing, tacting one as amemory and the other as a bout of imagination. Whensuch control is too weak and the discriminative respond-ing fails, a familiar self–probe may emerge: Did this reallyhappen, or am I just imagining it? On the other hand, de-scriptive features that cast the episode merely as belong-ing to the past are controlled by two factors: (a) by thepredetermined fix of the sequencing, and (b) by thematicor contextual clues.

Let us consider an example. When one imagines thatone is sailing aboard the ... Beagle with Charles Dar-win during the s, no matter how vivid and realisticthe unfolding scenes of that daydream, they were neveroriginally stimulated, even to the slightest degree, by di-rect energy inputs from that historical environment. Fur-thermore, when one imagines an alternative reality, thatdaydream is not occurring under strict stimulus controlof the current environment, and may be occurring in theabsence of any control by the current environment.

However, during some bouts of imagination, some ofthe imagined behavior may actually be occurring, as, forexample, when a person who is imagining being in battleexhibits some of the bodily motions that characterize

combat. Also, while the current environment would notprecisely evoke the behavior being imagined, some as-pects of the current environment may actually tend toevoke some of the behavioral elements of the imaginedactivity. For instance, the person who participates in animaginary battle may wield a real weapon of a kind thatsuits the theme, or an approximation of such a weapon.That is why an imagined episode often seems more vivid,and hence more reinforcing, when the person is in a set-ting in which such an imagined episode may actuallytend to occur.

For a person to distinguish between memory andimagination, the person must respond discriminatively tothe nature of the controlling relations in which that pri-vate neural behavior occurs. The neural behavioral eventsthat constitute a memory originally occurred under tightand precise control by an environment that, at that time,would have passed tests of reality. At that time, preciselinkages among the sequential elements of the originalneural behavior were conditioned. Later, on an occasionof the kind of private reiteration to which we refer as thememory of that episode, the order of the neural behavioralelements is predetermined through that conditioning,which occurred during the original episode, and theoriginal sequencing conservatively reoccurs. In contrast,the events in a bout of imagination feature private neuralbehavior the elements of which are coming together forthe first time. Each is some fragment from the person’sgeneral conditioning history, but the sequencing is new.

A verbal community imposes strong contingencies oneach member to respond discriminatively to the differencesin the controls on memory and imagination. However, anintuitive level of responding generally suffices, so althoughnearly everyone can exhibit that discrimination rather ac-curately, few people outside of behaviorological circleshave been conditioned to account for how it happens.

Unlike a remembered environment, the imagina-tively constructed environment, never having had to ex-ist in reality, is free to violate temporal constraints andthus may be interpreted as a past, present, or future set-ting. A daydream—whether a recasting of the past, indul-gence in an alternative present, or a virtual preview offuture events—rather than being teased into manifesta-tion with conservative probes (as may be necessary witha memory) can be prompted constructively as necessaryto maximize its reinforcing qualities.

The initially evoked scene of a daydream may be con-trived through prompting or may arise through naturallyencountered stimulation, and further evocative supple-mentation may not be necessary. That is, the subsequentepisode of daydreaming may then proceed through agenerally reinforcing chain of scenes in a relatively au-tomatic way that is sometimes described as free–flowingimagination. In that mode each scene is said to evoke the

Page 24: On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts · On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts ... Interest in the behaviorological analysis of verbal behavior (Skinner, ) continues

Page 32 (issn 1536–6669) �ehaviorology �oday � Volume 7, Number 2, Fall 2004

next scene. The kinds of thematic behavior that are fea-tured in a daydream are respectively well conditioned asa result of their respective histories of reinforcement, andtherefore they tend to be consciously reiterated in thedaydream. However, because the sequence is new, a newkind of environment would be required to produce it, soalong with the neural reiteration of the thematic behav-ior, the daydreamer must behave a kind of environmentthat would tend to produce it. In an imagined sequence,the environment–behavior function that characterizes re-ality works backwards in the sense that the emergence ofstrong behavior is evoking a neural iteration of the envi-ronment that in reality would control that behavior.

Note that in imagination, the conscious iteration isthe only real behavior that occurs to take the effect of anyoperant and respondent conditioning. That is, if, for ex-ample, reinforcement occurs, it pertains only to the on–going neural behavior of imagining. The imaginedthematic behavior per se never really occurs, so it is neverreally reinforced. Any reinforcement thus pertains to thebehavior of imagining, not to the thematic behavior thatis being imagined.

This distinction is important in the analysis of fanta-sies that feature thematic events the reality of whichwould probably be intolerable to the daydreamer. In thehistorical absence of a science by which to analyze the is-sue effectively, human culture has featured an ancient andreoccurring debate about whether antisocial fantasies arelikely to be “acted out.” For example, suppose that over along period a person is mercilessly tormented by anotherindividual. The tormented individual may often fantasizeabout revenge, perhaps by imagining scenes that featurethe persecutor being burned at the stake.

The imaginary immolation is entirely reinforcingsimply because only those thematic aspects of the neuralbehavior that are reinforced will survive. Whereas a realenvironment continues to impose its aversive stimulationas long as contact is maintained, any aversive aspects ofan imagined environment are subject to extinction andsuppression. In a fantasy the only real behavior is theneural behavior of imaging, and that neural behavior in-cludes both the thematic behavioral events and the envi-ronment that would be necessary to elicit and evokethose events.

If the imaginatively constructed environment were tobe replaced with its real and behaviorally unsanitizedcounterpart, the fantasizing person would probably be re-pelled by the spectacle of a person really burning to deathwhile tied to a post. That is because the real environmentwould inclusively be imposing a wide variety of aversivestimuli that could not be subtracted directly from the realenvironment by operant extinction or suppression. To rida real immolation of its intrinsic aversive features, nor-

mally one must avoid contact with it, either by departingthe scene or preventing the whole episode before it begins.

In a real immolation, a piece of sizzling flesh meltingaway in the flames is generating the energy that triggersthe spectator’s consciousness of the event. That energycontinues to impinge on the spectator regardless of theaversive nature of its behavioral effects on that spectator.In contrast, during a fantasized episode, the cor-responding environmental events are being generated be-haviorally and are therefore under the operant control oftheir own aversive effects. In a fantasized version, if apiece of sizzling flesh melting away in the flames is aver-sive, the behaviors of consciousness that are generatingthat aversive aspect of the overall spectacle are suppressed,and that feature is thus behaviorally subtracted from theon–going scene (all of which is occurring only in the sensethat it is being behaved in response to energy that is cir-culating internally rather than impinging from without).

A daydream is susceptible to continual self–prompt-ing, which typically occurs in ways that maximize the re-inforcing thematic and contextual effects. That occurs asthematic aspects of an on–going daydream evoke briefthoughts about potentially reinforcing thematic varia-tions any of which may initiate a new chain of day-dreaming along the contextual and thematic path of thatvariation. On the other hand, in accurate remembering,one is under contingencies to reproduce an unchangedversion of some private neural behavior that has alreadyoccurred. If one is privately to behave again as one hasbehaved previously, then the stimulus controls on the pri-vately reiterated version of that behavior must conserva-tively re–present as a functional equivalent of the controlsthat prevailed in the original episode.

Accurate memories are important to a verbal commu-nity, so its members are taught how to engage in the kindsof self–probing practices that are least likely to alter thecontent of the reiterations that they share in evoking. Forexample, a person who is challenged to recall the mode oftransportation that that person used to get from town to town may find that the response is not forthcoming.One approach is to follow a self–instruction to describethe contingencies under which the trip was undertaken,if that is possible. If the reason for the trip can be reiter-ated, then the selected mode of travel would probably havebeen the one that best afforded the kind of travel–relatedexperiences that comport with that contingency. Such asequence of thinking may share in strengthening the cur-rent identification of the travel mode that was used.

Suppose, on the other hand, that one were first to se-lect arbitrarily any travel mode that would have beenavailable to a traveler at that time (for example, a bus)and then ask, “Might I have taken the bus?” The promi-nent manifestation of the term bus may evoke memoriesof past bus trips that could then be mistakenly associated

Page 25: On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts · On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts ... Interest in the behaviorological analysis of verbal behavior (Skinner, ) continues

�ehaviorology �oday � Volume 7, Number 2, Fall 2004 (issn 1536–6669) Page 33

with the trip in question. If one actually made the trip bycanal barge under contingencies to scout for scenes thatcould serve as the subjects of landscape paintings, thenthe advantage of the non–committal probe for the travelmode, based on a review of the contingencies underwhich the trip was undertaken, becomes obvious.

Thus, in a sophisticated verbal community, eachmember may be taught to probe with a thematically neu-tral self–question whenever the person is challenged torecall the details of an event. That kind of question is de-void of intrinsic qualities that may directly evoke detailsthat could then be reported as invalid memories aboutthat particular journey. In the legal sub–community, ac-curate recall is especially important. In a courtroom, anattorney’s question, posed to his or her own witness, thatexplicitly suggests a particular potential answer tends toevoke an objection from opposing counsel on thegrounds that that attorney is “leading the witness.”

Note the differences in the controls on memory andimagination. Both classes represent currently evoked be-haviors, but in the case of memory, the contextual con-trols remain functionally similar to those that prevailedduring the original episode, so that one behaves now, ina private neural way, as one behaved previously in thatsame private neural way. One cannot behave again if onedid not previously behave that way in the first place.Thus, one cannot remember (i.e. cannot re–behave) a be-havioral event that one did not originally behave (i.e., anevent of which one was not initially conscious, as they say)However, in the case of original imagination, the controlson the private neural behavior do not functionally matchthe controls that prevailed during a prior episode.

Note that the behavioral reiteration that we call amemory consists of private neural behaviors. Note also, thatthe behavior that is now reoccurring as a memory is a re-occurrence of some behavior that originally occurred as theprivate neural behaviors of consciousness. That is, the behav-iors that reoccur in a memory, consist only of repetitionsof the original behaviors of consciousness, not repetitionsof any other kinds of behaviors of which the person mayhave been conscious. It is only the behaviors of con-sciousness that repeat during a bout of remembering.

For example, suppose that one is recalling one’s flip-ping the light switch that turned off the ceiling light asone was leaving a room on a particular occasion. The be-havior being recalled is the muscle–driven flipping of theswitch, but the behavioral mode in which that memorymanifests consists only of private neural behavior, and,furthermore, it is a reiteration of what originally was onlyprivate neural behavior. The behavior of recall manifestsin, and pertains only to, behaviors in the class called con-sciousness. If, during the original behavioral episode, themotor behavior of reaching toward the light switch andflipping it did not evoke concurrent behaviors of con-

sciousness (i.e., awareness, recognition, comprehension,etc.), then later memory of that switch flip will be impos-sible, because that memory would have to occur as a reit-eration of original private neural behavior that had notoccurred in the first place.

Absent an evocation of that kind of neural behaviorof consciousness during the initial episode, a reiterationof it cannot later reoccur. Thus, behaviors that originallyoccur under direct stimulus control cannot be recalled,because the kind of behavior that would have to repeatdoes not happen in the first place.

Note, however, that daydreaming and other kinds ofimaginings can, in theory, be recalled, because they origi-nally manifest in the neural behavioral mode that is nec-essary for recall to pertain. However, the neuralmicro–structuring that was established (i.e., conditioned)during the original bout of imagination is, of course, sub-ject to the kind of on–going natural degradation that isresponsible for forgetting. Thus, the thematic content ofeither a bout of imagination or an environment–inducedbout of consciousness can be rendered progressivelyunrememberable (i.e., unreviewable) as a result of theforgetting process. However, the thematic content of aninteraction with a real environment that fails to evoke theconcurrent neural behaviors of consciousness cannot laterbe reviewed in the memory mode because no capacity isbeing established to support that later kind of neural re–behaving (as in the previous light switch example).

A person distinguishes between the memory andimagination classes of private neural behavior on the ba-sis of differences in the controlling relations on some cur-rent private neural activity. The distinction per se thusinvolves some further behavior that does not alwaysemerge, thus leading, perhaps, to the familiar self–probe“Am I remembering or imagining this episode?”

Imagined behavior can be interpreted as an alterna-tive past, present, or future. The designation of tense thatemerges under the control of an on–going episode ofimagination can be evoked by either of two classes ofevents, or both.

The first is contextual and pertains to the temporalimplications of the thematic content. If the activity per-tains to events that are correlated with points on a timeline, then the daydream can be classified temporally. Forexample, virtual characters that are dressed in the clothingof earlier times and who work with old–fashioned toolsevoke a designation of past. If the imagined events rely onthe solutions of problems that are as yet unsolved, thatcircumstance evokes designations of future. Absent suchcontextual clues, the time frame may remain ambiguous.

The second class of controls on temporal designa-tions pertains to the contingencies under which the epi-sode of imagination is occurring. For instance, if one isunder an explicit contingency to imagine what daily life

Page 26: On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts · On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts ... Interest in the behaviorological analysis of verbal behavior (Skinner, ) continues

Page 34 (issn 1536–6669) �ehaviorology �oday � Volume 7, Number 2, Fall 2004

will be like years in the future, the ensuing bout ofimagination would involve temporal specifications thatcan denote futurity in exclusive response to the kind ofcontingency under which that bout of imagination wasinitiated. For instance, an imagined scene that includes acommon wall calendar in some detail would feature a cal-endar that is labeled with a future year. The verbs in ver-bal descriptions of the scenes being imagined would berendered in tense forms that indicate futurity.

Responding to The Nature ofthe Controls on a Tact

If the utterance of a tact is impending because of con-tact with its evocative stimuli, the vocalizer may also be ina position to respond to the number, strength, and otherproperties of those stimuli as well as merely exhibiting thedescriptive tact that they tend to evoke. For example,suppose that a potential verbalizer is in visual contactwith a bird flying overhead. The bird can present as avariety of different bird–related stimuli, but those stimu-lus elements, which collectively define that particularbird, become respectively salient in a differential waydepending on the duration, viewing angle, and other cir-cumstances of their presentation to that vocalizer.

Suppose that the bird zips past so rapidly that the ver-balizer hardly catches a glimpse of it. Only a very few ofits properties exert stimulus control over the vocalizer’sverbal behavior. If those are properties that, in the past,have been associated with ravens, they may evoke the rawtact raven. However, that set of behavior–controllingstimuli is also small, and some of those properties mayalso have been present during past contacts with otherkinds of birds. These historical facts too are aspects of thisbehavior–controlling situation, and they too may affectthe verbal utterance. The verbalizer is likely to say It couldhave been a raven. The term raven is a composite tact ofthe few properties of the bird that shared in exertingfunctional control during the brief fly–by. The term couldis controlled both by the paucity of the evidence and bythe previous appearances of at least some of those samecharacteristics in other species of birds.

Suppose, on the other hand, that the same bird hadsoared slowly past the verbalizer. Assume that it had re-mained in view for an extended interval with favorablelighting while wheeling so as to present different viewingangles. In that case, several additional properties of thebird would be likely to gain stimulus control over thespeaker’s verbal behavior, and those well presented prop-erties would tend to establish their respective conditionedevocative functions to a greater extent. In that case, thetact raven could again be evoked under that broadenedstimulus control, but the vocalizer is also in a position torespond to the relatively large number of bird–relatedproperties that are sharing in the control of that tact plus

the circumstances of their near optimal presentation. Inthat case, the verbalizer may say I’m sure that that was araven. The sure is a response to the richness of the evidence,including its variety as well as the special circumstancesthat insured the behavior–controlling effectiveness of itselemental presentations.14

In the past, when a speaker said either It could be araven or I’m sure that it is a raven, it has often been as-serted that the verbalizer is responding to the probabilitythat the primary tact raven is valid. However, the vocal-izer in such cases did not contact a “probability” in thesense of an environmental entity. Instead, the vocalizercontacted sets of stimuli, each of some relative salience,the elements of which were presented in ways that differ-entially exploited their respective conditioned evocativecapacities. The class of responses that are evoked by thosekinds of features of the situation are related to the pri-mary tact insofar as such responses are evoked by certainqualities of the controls on the primary tact. When avocalizer says It could have been a raven, a mediator tendsto respond with less raven–related behavior than whenthe vocalizer says I’m sure that it was a raven.

Consider that relation refers to two variables, one ofwhich exhibits change that bears an orderly correspon-dence to on–going changes in the other variable. Whileeither of the two variables acting independently canevoke verbal responses, so can the relation between them.Note that a verbal response to a behavior–controlling re-lation occurs as a response to two on–going classes ofchange, one occurring among some independent (in thiscase, environmental) variables and the other among somedependent (in this case, behavioral) variables. That is,changes in the contacted environment correspond in anorderly way to changes in a behavioral variable. That is,the order in the behavioral change is defined by the na-ture of the on–going environmental change.

Those two kinds of on–going changes are all that isavailable to be contacted (we do not really contact a rela-tion or a correspondence), and although that is all thatcan be contacted, such a pair of changes, with one reflect-ing the other in some orderly way, collectively evoke theinferential tact relation, which chains to the subsequentverbal behaviors that we call its comprehension. Such anextended tact reifies certain aspects of what, fundamen-tally, are processes. The compound adjective behavior–controlling, which modifies relation, is evoked by theorderly reflection of environmental change in the corre-sponding change to the behavioral variable.

Many such responses to aspects of the controls onother verbal behaviors manifest, not as tacts, but as awide variety of other linguistic nuances. Such subtle re-sponses to the properties of the controls on other verbalbehaviors are so important that they command their ownmajor classification of verbal behavior. The next main

Page 27: On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts · On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts ... Interest in the behaviorological analysis of verbal behavior (Skinner, ) continues

�ehaviorology �oday � Volume 7, Number 2, Fall 2004 (issn 1536–6669) Page 35

section of this chapter is devoted to that special class,which is called autoclitic verbal behavior.

[Part continues in the next issue.—Ed.]�

Footnotes1 Note that we do not speak technically of this condition-

ing history in terms of the child having learned thesethings. That is because there is no agential child thatpresumably inhabits the body as an agent who,through its own initiatives or allowances, learns whatto do. There is only a body to be operantly condi-tioned, and that conditioning occurs automatically asa result of external events. People do not learn (be-cause the people–agents that would have to do it, donot exist). Instead, conditioning happens to bodies.When such conditioning has happened to the bodyof a person, that person then has an altered bodystructure that, thereafter, responds differently to itsenvironment. Persons who believe superstitiously inautonomous self–spirits that control behavior theninterpret those changes in behavior as evidence ofchanges in the putative will of the responsible agent,who is then said to have learned. The behaviorologicaldefinition of the verb to learn is merely to exhibitchange in behavior in the presence of a given stimulus asa result of an appropriate history of conditioning.

2 The relation between the textual stimulus and the vocalproduction of the word “house” is traditionally saidto represent a “point–to–point” correspondence, butthe correspondence is more accurately described by“range–to–range.” The smallest functional incrementof the textual stimulus is a whole letter, which pre-sents as a far broader range than a mere point. Like-wise, during the vocal pronunciation of the word, itis not possible to specify a single instant of soundproduction that corresponds exclusively to any onepoint in a printed letter of the text version. That is,the vocal sounding that is controlled by a single let-ter, consists of a broader range of sound than a singlepoint of sound (whatever that would mean). At best,a range of sound production corresponds to a letter,or letter combination, within the printed word. Con-sider, for instance, the control exerted on a reader’svocal behavior by the printed letters …ough… in theprinted word thought.

3 In everyday agential language, it could be said that thechild must already have learned the spoken name fora house or the written label for a house (i.e., the childmust know what that word means when spoken orwritten). Note, however, in the previous sentence,that substantial conceptual errors are implicit in eachof the four terms child (as an agent), learned, know,

and means. This illustrates what is wrong when com-mon language descriptions of even simple behavioralevents are left unchallenged.

4 If a box dumper in the aircraft were able to dump thedisks in such a way that they would flutter to theground in an array determined by how they had beendumped, that skilled disk dumper could then insureany desired ground pattern of white dots by dumpingthe disks in a particular manner. For example, thatdisk dumper could dump a box of disks in a way thatwould predictably result in the word cow beingspelled in a sequence of dot patterns that respectivelysuggest the letters c, o, and w. In that case, the readerwould be responding to verbal stimuli that had beenproduced by an author who had a curious way ofwriting text.

5 A sound being heard is a behavioral response. Such a be-havior can occur directly—for example, in the senseof privately hearing a word that is being read silently.Light waves from the printed text enter the eyes andare transformed into corresponding neural impulsesthat are transmitted to the neural body parts thathave the capacity to behave the corresponding sound.The private audition occurs under direct stimuluscontrol of the visually appreciated text in the absenceof any sound waves that would typically evoke thathearing response. That is, upon contacting theprinted word book, the reader privately hears thesound of that word even though the reader’s vocalsystem has not produced the corresponding soundwaves in the ambient air. The behavior of hearing theword book can also occur indirectly when such a vo-calization does occur—that is, when the vocalmusculature responds to the printed text by produc-ing some corresponding sound waves in the ambientair. Those waves then travel outside the body fromthe mouth to the ears, where they stimulate the auralsystem of the body. That aural system converts thesound waves into electro–chemical neural impulsesthat are transmitted to the neural body parts thathave the capacity to behave the corresponding sound,whereupon the behavior of audition occurs. It maythen be said, incorrectly, that “the person hears his orher own voice saying book.” However, the natural oc-currence of that audition–type of behaving is a partof the behavior that defines the concept of person inthe first place. The person does not exist indepen-dently apart from the behaviors that define it. Thehearing behavior is a part of the person.

6 The basis of such a statement is that no one seems ableto exhibit both kinds of behavior at the same time,which increasingly implies that the same body part isexclusively required for each kind of behavior. Just asa person’s right hand cannot concurrently scratch the

Page 28: On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts · On Verbal Behavior: The Second of Four Parts ... Interest in the behaviorological analysis of verbal behavior (Skinner, ) continues

Page 36 (issn 1536–6669) �ehaviorology �oday � Volume 7, Number 2, Fall 2004

top of that person’s head and rub that person’s stom-ach, some neural body parts cannot concurrently ex-hibit two distinct kinds of private neural behavior,and no program of behavioral conditioning can makethat happen.

7 This subclass of intraverbal behavior has been called duplicbehavior, a term derived from the verb duplicate.

8 This subclass of intraverbal behavior has been calledcodic, a term derived from the noun code.

9 The term repertoire does not refer to the contents of anarchival mental storage facility for behaviors, but tothe neural capacities to reproduce them upon occa-sions of appropriate environmental stimulation. Ev-ery response is produced anew, and is never an oldone retrieved from mental storage in mystical ar-chives. Conditioning does not put behaviors in stor-age; it produces the microstructures that representthe capacity to behave in a certain way, given thenecessary stimulation. Upon the arrival at such a spe-cific structure of such a specific transmission of en-ergy, the incipient stage of a particular behavioralresponse is automatically initiated.

10 Recall that the bodily structure develops in response toits genetic code and may do so with a structure thatis already capable of specific respondent reactions tospecific environmental stimuli. In contrast, behavioralconditioning is a subsequent process of restructuringthe body, which capacitates new kinds of environ-ment–behavior relations. Whether capacitatedthrough (a) genetics, (b) respondent conditioning, or(c) operant conditioning, all behavior manifests as adependent variable in structure–to–structure func-tional relations (structure of environment to structureof behaving body). Respondent–operant distinctionsare based on when and how bodily structures becomeconfigured for their functional participation in suchenvironment–behavior relations. Manifestations ofsuch relations require that the behavioral variable betriggered by energy that may impinge from without(e.g., light, sound, or energy imparted by impingingprojectiles). The energy that triggers behavior mayalso be released from storage within the body (aswhen a person’s hand moves back and forth in con-tact with a stationary surface thus making possiblethe person’s feeling behavior.

11 Note that the term contact really refers to a behavioralreaction. Contacts with… manifest as behavioral reac-tions to…. As will be further explored in the nextchapter, the reality of the environment, as deter-mined by our contacts with it, is an inference (i.e., asubsequent kind of behavioral reaction) that is basedon prior behavioral reactions that presumably wereevoked by an environment. Thus, our own behavior is

as close as we ever get to the reality of what we call“our environments.”

12 Recall that, if the current neural behavior is entirely arestimulated rendition of a prior one, it is called amemory and described using indicators of the past tense.If, on the other hand, it features a composite of be-haviors from different earlier episodes that have neveroccurred together, all evoked by a current event that, inthe past, has preceded punitive stimulation, one de-scribes the avoidance behavior as impending insofaras it is cast in the future tense. The forms that indicatefuturity are thus controlled antecedently by a currentevent that restimulates neural reiterations of past be-havioral reactions that originally occurred as parts ofdifferent episodes. An example is when, in response toa current event, one imagines one taking some com-posite action the elements of which have, in the past,occurred on different occasions. “Different past occa-sions” are discriminatively distinguished as differenton the basis of how elements of current neural behav-iors (called recollections) are being controlled.

13 One is confined within the prison of one’s own behav-ior and serves a life sentences exclusively in the func-tional present.

14 Note that, as functional accounts for such nuances ofverbal behavior accumulate, the apparent need for ex-planatory reliance on a body–managing self–spirit isproportionally diminished. That is, the self–agent re-treats with the advance of functional accountings.Thus, the relative certainty reflected in this vocalizer’sstatement does not reflect the increasing resolve of acomprehending self–agent. Instead, the inclusion ofthe phrase I am sure that… is merely a functional re-sponse that is determined (evoked) by special proper-ties of the set of stimuli that evoke the raw tactraven—namely, the large number of its stimulus ele-ments, the quality of their presentations, and theirendowments of evocative strength from their previ-ous respective episodes of operant conditioning.

References

Fraley, L.E. (2004). On verbal behavior: The first of fourparts. Behaviorology Today, 7 (1), 10–20.

Skinner, B.F. (). Verbal Behavior. New York: Apple-ton–Century–Crofts. Reprinted, , Cambridge,: The B.F. Skinner Foundation.�


Recommended