+ All Categories
Home > Documents > philosophicalskepticism.orgphilosophicalskepticism.org/.../2014/06/Wittgenstein-an…  · Web...

philosophicalskepticism.orgphilosophicalskepticism.org/.../2014/06/Wittgenstein-an…  · Web...

Date post: 05-Feb-2018
Category:
Upload: buimien
View: 215 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend
48
WITTGENSTEIN AND PYRRHONISM: ON THE NATURE OF PHILOSOPHY 1 Plínio Junqueira Smith (Unifesp) Translated by Israel Vilas Bôas “Vision is the essential faculty and, once used, I shall cast it aside” – Clarice Lispector. 1. The systematic comparison between the philosophy of Wittgenstein and scepticism seems only to point out profound differences. It is known that Wittgenstein himself rejected scepticism explicitly during his whole life. As early as the Tagebücher from 14-16 (1.5.15), Wittgenstein formulates an objection, which will reappear in the Tractatus (6:51), according to which sceptical doubt is nonsensical (unsinnig), for it is intended to raise doubts about what cannot be said. And, in the end of his life, he condemns a universal scepticism, since doubt only makes sense if there are previous certainties: “If one tried to doubt everything, one would not get as far as doubting anything. The game of doubting itself presupposes certainty” (UG, 115). In these two objections, Wittgenstein insists in the idea that sceptical doubt is deprived of meaning 2 . The critique of a so-called “private language” could also be seen as a critique of scepticism, for the solipsist 1 This article was written to the colloquium “Scepticism: old and new”, held in Buenos Aires from June 25 th through the 27 th of 1992. Some changes were made after the colloquium. Originally published in Analytica, vol. 1, number 1, Rio de Janeiro: UFRJ, 1993, p. 153-186. 2 Strawson (1985) and Grayling (1985) drew inspiration from Wittgenstein, in particular from his Über Gewissheit, to reject scepticism.
Transcript
Page 1: philosophicalskepticism.orgphilosophicalskepticism.org/.../2014/06/Wittgenstein-an…  · Web viewWITTGENSTEIN AND PYRRHONISM: ... the word “pain” can only refer to my pain and

WITTGENSTEIN AND PYRRHONISM: ON THE NATURE OF

PHILOSOPHY1

Plínio Junqueira Smith (Unifesp)Translated by Israel Vilas Bôas

“Vision is the essential faculty and, once used, I shall cast it aside” – Clarice Lispector.

1. The systematic comparison between the philosophy of Wittgenstein and scepticism

seems only to point out profound differences. It is known that Wittgenstein himself rejected

scepticism explicitly during his whole life. As early as the Tagebücher from 14-16 (1.5.15),

Wittgenstein formulates an objection, which will reappear in the Tractatus (6:51), according

to which sceptical doubt is nonsensical (unsinnig), for it is intended to raise doubts about what

cannot be said. And, in the end of his life, he condemns a universal scepticism, since doubt

only makes sense if there are previous certainties: “If one tried to doubt everything, one

would not get as far as doubting anything. The game of doubting itself presupposes certainty”

(UG, 115). In these two objections, Wittgenstein insists in the idea that sceptical doubt is

deprived of meaning2.

The critique of a so-called “private language” could also be seen as a critique of

scepticism, for the solipsist position, which defends a “private language”, would be a

consequence of the sceptical objections to the realist position3. Scepticism would argue

towards showing that we could never know the internal states of other people: for example,

when I perceive something as red, I do not know if another person has the perception of green

or any other colour. Even saying that we believe that the other person perceives the same

colour I do, would be mistaken, because to speak of “belief”, it would be necessary that this

belief could be at least partially proved (or refuted) and that is impossible in the case of other

minds. And, finally, if the meaning of words consists in the reference to personal experiences

and if two people cannot have the same experience, then communicability is lost and I can

never attribute my internal states to other people: the word “pain” can only refer to my pain

1 This article was written to the colloquium “Scepticism: old and new”, held in Buenos Aires from June 25 th

through the 27th of 1992. Some changes were made after the colloquium. Originally published in Analytica, vol. 1, number 1, Rio de Janeiro: UFRJ, 1993, p. 153-186.2 Strawson (1985) and Grayling (1985) drew inspiration from Wittgenstein, in particular from his Über Gewissheit, to reject scepticism.3 Tugendhat (1979, p. 93-94) shows the role played by sceptical arguments in the internal dissolution of realism towards solipsism and, ultimately, in the abandonment of the language of "I". And Hacker (1990, p. 25-26) says that the presuppositions of metaphysical and linguistic theories of philosophers lead ineluctably to solipsism, being scepticism about other minds and about communication two necessary intermediate steps of this process.

Page 2: philosophicalskepticism.orgphilosophicalskepticism.org/.../2014/06/Wittgenstein-an…  · Web viewWITTGENSTEIN AND PYRRHONISM: ... the word “pain” can only refer to my pain and

and not to someone else’s. Once accepted these sceptical arguments, there would be no other

philosophical option than sustaining solipsism and a theory of private language. Now, if

Wittgenstein shows the absurd of the supposition of a private language (PI, 243-315), he

would equally show the absurd of the sceptical position, since this posture would lead us to

that supposition.

On the other hand, Kripke4 intended to see a new way of scepticism in Wittgenstein's

philosophy, which would bear strong similarity to Humean scepticism: Wittgenstein would

have had formulated a “sceptical doubt” to which he had given a “sceptical solution”, like

Hume did in the sections IV and V of his Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding.

Kripke’s interpretation hinges on the theme “rule-following”, of which the question of private

language would just be a particular case. Kripke expresses Wittgenstein’s argument in a

Humean form: from past cases, how can we know in the future that we are really following

the same rule? According to the “sceptical solution”, the correct understanding of a rule

would be shown by a behaviour that would be in accordance with the majority of the

linguistic community. But Baker and Hacker5 persuasively argue that the connection between

the rule and the act in conformity with it is an “internal relation”, that is, to understand a rule

is precisely to know which acts are in accordance with it. The “community view” would be, in

contrast, a way of associating empirically the rule to the acts conform to it and, thus, there

would be here only an “external relation”. It would be incorrect to attribute to Wittgenstein a

scepticism of Humean kind such as Kripke understands it.

Thus, at first sight nothing seems to indicate an approximation between Wittgenstein's

philosophy and scepticism and everything seems to point at the opposite direction.

Wittgenstein's reflexions on the meaning of a sceptical doubt, on the possibility of a private

language, and on what it is to follow a rule would culminate in the rejection of scepticism

rather than in its acceptance. Those who deny any kinship between scepticism and

Wittgenstein seem to be on the right track.

But it is necessary to notice that the scepticism to which Wittgenstein and his

commentators refer is the scepticism in its modern form, inaugurated by Descartes’s first

Meditation. The problematic of doubt and certainty, mainly as it is discussed in On Certainty

clearly has its origins in the Cartesian idea of a methodical, radical and universal doubt, as

well as in Berkeley's intention of denying the existence of the physical world6. No less

4 Kripke (1982), esp. pp. 60-69.5 Baker e Hacker (1984) especially the first essay.6 Kenny (1975) e Bouveresse (1987) recognise that Descartes is Wittgenstein's target, but is does not seem less correct to me that Berkeley is criticised as well.

Page 3: philosophicalskepticism.orgphilosophicalskepticism.org/.../2014/06/Wittgenstein-an…  · Web viewWITTGENSTEIN AND PYRRHONISM: ... the word “pain” can only refer to my pain and

modern is the question of solipsism, in which sceptical doubts lead us to a subject, the

Cartesian cogito or the Humean bundle of perceptions, which has access only to its own

representations7. Anyhow, it is with reference to modern philosophy that one has been

thinking the question of scepticism in Wittgenstein8.

If one wants to attribute a genuine meaning to this issue of the relationship between

Wittgenstein's philosophy and scepticism, one must introduce two modifications in the way it

is formulated. The first is to set aside the reference to this form of scepticism that is only a

methodological step of Cartesian dogmatism, as well as to the empirical and scientific twist

that Hume gives to it, and turn our attention to ancient Greek sceptics. The second is to set

aside temporarily this discussion by topics, and first tackle Wittgenstein's conception of

philosophy and the more general sense which he attributes to his own thinking. Only thus, one

will be able to discuss the purported scepticism of Wittgenstein with the necessary historical

and conceptual rigour.

My suggestion is that Wittgenstein's conception of philosophy has many similarities

with the Pyrrhonian conception9. To support this point, I shall expound briefly some aspects

of Wittgenstein's conception of philosophy, and then I will compare it with the one that

Sextus presents us. I do not intend to offer a new interpretation of the Wittgensteinian

conception of philosophy, but only to ordain what we already know with a view to a

determined purpose: to show the sceptical style in his conception.

2. Wittgenstein opposes roughly to his own conception of philosophy another one10,

which I will name traditional conception of philosophy. According to the traditional

conception, philosophy should deal with phenomena to see through them (“die Erscheinungen

durchschauen”; PI, 90) or with the things to see through them (“die Sache durchschauen”; PI,

92) reaching, thus, the essence of all things. By “essence of all things”, Wittgenstein refers to

something hidden behind things themselves and that an analysis of these would reveal. The

idea that the essence is hidden (“Das Wesen ist uns verborgen”) is a basic idea that

Wittgenstein attributes to traditional philosophy. Philosophy’s task would be to discover this

hidden essence by means of an analysis of the phenomena or of the things.

7 8 I am aware of the existence of works that compare Wittgenstein and the Greek sceptics, but, amongst the main commentators of Wittgenstein's works, none takes into account the Greek scepticism.9 It is important to highlight that I only refer to the works of Wittgenstein after 1929, in particular to the Philosophical Investigations. Naturally, this suggestion does not apply to the Tractatus.10 Cf., regarding it, Moore (1959, p. 322)

Page 4: philosophicalskepticism.orgphilosophicalskepticism.org/.../2014/06/Wittgenstein-an…  · Web viewWITTGENSTEIN AND PYRRHONISM: ... the word “pain” can only refer to my pain and

To Wittgenstein, on contrast, philosophy does not deal with phenomena or things, but

with the “possibilities” of phenomena, i.e., with the “kind of statement that we make about

phenomena” (PI, 90). Philosophers take our ordinary claims about phenomena as raw material

of their philosophical reflexions. It is what Saint Augustine would have done when discussing

the nature of time and, hence, his considerations are grammatical: every philosophy is

involved with our way of making statements. As he says farther to his purported interlocutor,

“Your questions refer to words; so I have to talk about words” (PI, 120). Because traditional

philosophy confounds the semantic domain with the domain of things, it attributes to the latter

that which belongs to the former. “One predicates of the thing what lies in the method of

representing it” (PI, 104). But the correct understanding of language separates rigorously

these two domains and the philosopher will focus only on language. “Philosophical

investigations: conceptual investigations. The essential thing about metaphysics: it obliterates

the distinction between factual and conceptual investigations” (Z, 458). In other words,

traditional philosophy confounds logic and ontology, and Wittgenstein makes sure to separate

them carefully.

Once delimited the field of philosophy (language or discourse, whereas science would

deal with objective investigations), one sees that Wittgenstein opposes to the Erscheinungen

durchschauen another expression, viz., übersichtliche Darstellung (PI, 92). This

übersichtliche Darstellung is a description of the rules of our grammar, which allow us to

acknowledge what we already knew but had difficulty to see. Unlike the traditional

conception, Wittgenstein does not intend to go beyond things or phenomena to apprehend

some hidden essence. The essence, to Wittgenstein, is already visible on broad day light and,

through a sorting of grammatical facts, becomes clear. It is no longer about unveiling the “real

structure of the world”, but only about describing conceptual connexions. The essence, which

was conceived by philosophers as a hidden entity to be unveiled by an analysis, is now

interpreted by Wittgenstein as a mere grammatical rule of our language. If, to the traditional

conception, philosophy formulated ontological-epistemological questions, to Wittgenstein, all

questions are, in the end, semantic.

Wittgenstein characterises the propositions of traditional philosophy as scientific, as if

philosophy were a superscience, for it builds theories, formulates hypotheses, and explains the

world in the same way science does. But, to Wittgenstein, instead of these theories,

hypotheses, and explanations, philosophy should only make descriptions of the workings of

our language (PI, 109). No new thesis is proposed and, if it were the case to propose them,

there would never be a discussion about them, because everybody would agree about them

Page 5: philosophicalskepticism.orgphilosophicalskepticism.org/.../2014/06/Wittgenstein-an…  · Web viewWITTGENSTEIN AND PYRRHONISM: ... the word “pain” can only refer to my pain and

(PI, 128; BT. p.12). Thus, Wittgenstein does not sustain a philosophical opinion and cannot

even resort to any opinion that is not shared by his purported interlocutor, because, in this

case, they do not share the same language game that it is necessary to describe. “Of all the

topics that we have discussed, I do not have an opinion, and if I had one, I would immediately

disregard it in benefit of this debate for it would not be important to our discussion.”11. To

adopt an opinion is, to Wittgenstein, a way to be partial, as well as to sustain a creed, which is

contrary to philosophy: “Our only task is to be impartial, i.e., all we have to do is to point out

and dissolve the partialities of philosophy; we must not set up new parties – and creeds.” (BT,

p. 14).

Associated with this refusal to formulate philosophical theses or theories, one finds the

idea that, in philosophy, there is no argumentative method in the sense of articulating

premises and conclusions in order to establish the truth of the latter from the evidence of the

former. The argumentation employed by Wittgenstein aims at the dissolution of problems, by

resorting only to linguistic facts recognised by his interlocutor. “In philosophy, one does not

draw conclusions. ‘But it must be like this!’ is not a philosophical proposition. Philosophy

only states what everyone admits” (PI, 599).

It is important to notice that this ordaining is not the result of an empirical science, of

an investigation regarding facts, and that empirical knowledge of grammar is up to the

grammarian. Everything we want to know is already given from the beginning, and it is

enough to recall what we already know about our language. “The problems are solved, not by

giving new information, but by arranging what we have always known” (PI, 109).

One may explain in this way that, after saying that philosophy does not deal with

phenomena and things, Wittgenstein is then able say that philosophy of logic speaks of

propositions and of words in the common meaning of these terms, i.e., “we are talking about

the spatial and temporal phenomenon of language, not about some non-spatial, non-temporal

phantasm” (PI, 108). Not postulating hidden entities as an “essence”, Wittgenstein refers only

to what we refer in our “habitual” life, not only to real language, but also to ordinary objects

(PI, 106).

This positive objective, of description and understanding of what is already before our

eyes but we have difficulties in perceiving, acquires philosophical meaning from a negative

objective. The übersichtliche Darstellung does not have the goal of presenting a new doctrine

of essence of things, according to which the essence would be apparent in grammar and not

11 Quoted by Baker and Hacker (1984), p.8.

Page 6: philosophicalskepticism.orgphilosophicalskepticism.org/.../2014/06/Wittgenstein-an…  · Web viewWITTGENSTEIN AND PYRRHONISM: ... the word “pain” can only refer to my pain and

hidden behind things, but of eliminating philosophical confusions. The grammatical

consideration “sheds light on our problem by clearing misunderstandings away” (PI, 90).

It is in this sense that one must understand the statement, “the work of the philosopher

consists in assembling reminders for a particular purpose” (PI, 127; cf. BT, p.10). This

assemblage of reminders is nothing but the elucidation of the effective use of the words in our

common language. Further, Wittgenstein suggests that organizing our knowledge of the use of

language has a purpose, viz., to avoid theoretical confusions that arise when language spins in

the void, when it no longer works (PI, 132), when it “goes on holiday”. If, on one hand, it is

undeniable that one of Wittgenstein's goals is the description of grammatical rules (“Wir

wollen etwas verstehen, was schon offen vor unsern Augen liegt”; IF, 89), one the other, the

explication of the reason for which he wants to understand something points at a critical

design (“Denn das scheinen wir, in irgendeinem Sinne, nicht zu verstehen”; IF, 89), viz., to

undo the miscomprehension that philosophers have of the logic of ordinary language. “For the

clarity that we are aiming at is indeed complete clarity. But this simply means that the

philosophical problems should completely disappear” (PI, 133). This passage, albeit it

suggests a certain equivalence amongst clarification and elimination of incomprehension, also

points at a certain priority of the disappearance of philosophical problems in face of the task

of describing our grammar12.

Confined to the conceptual questions, philosophical investigations will not obtain a

new and deeper knowledge of things, but will make us recognise that the purported

philosophical knowledge is only a product of an inadequate use of language. It is precisely

because they destroy “houses of cards” that Wittgenstein judges important his considerations

(PI, 118). Shortly afterwards, he admits that “the results of philosophy are the uncovering of

one or another piece of plain nonsense and of bumps that the understanding has got by

running its head up against the limits of language. These bumps make us see the value of the

discovery” (PI, 119). In the Big Typescript, Wittgenstein formulates this idea in a more

incisive way: “All that philosophy can do is to destroy idols” (BT, p. 9). The conceptual

description, put in the place of traditional philosophical explanations, “gets its light, that is to

say its purpose, from the philosophical problems” (PI, 109). And Wittgenstein is emphatic

here: philosophical problems must “solved by means of an insight about the workings of our

language, and those workings must be recognised this way: in despite of an urge (entgegen

einem Trieb) to misunderstand them” (PI, 109; highlighted by Wittgenstein), Wittgenstein can 12 Cf. Hacker (1972), pp. 113-116. We disagree, hence, of those who see the therapy as a previous stage to prepare for a positive stage, as if the description of language were the main goal (e.g., Arregui (1984, pp. 161-168)) or even of those who see the process of clarification as an independent goal.

Page 7: philosophicalskepticism.orgphilosophicalskepticism.org/.../2014/06/Wittgenstein-an…  · Web viewWITTGENSTEIN AND PYRRHONISM: ... the word “pain” can only refer to my pain and

now give us a precise definition of what philosophy is: “Philosophy is a battle against the

bewitchment of our intelligence by means of language” (PI, 109)13.

When the nature of philosophy is defined this way, it is natural to characterise it as

therapeutic, as a philosophy whose objective is to heal the philosopher of the malady of which

his understanding is victim. “The philosopher’s treatment of a question is like the treatment of

an illness” (PI, 255). The metaphor of the bumps caused by the dashes of the understanding

against the limits of language (PI, 119) is in consonance with this characterisation: bumps

must be treated. At first, Wittgenstein thought there was only one therapeutic method (M, p.

322), but then he recognised the existence of various ways of conducting this treatment:

“There is not a philosophical method, though there are indeed methods, like different

therapies” (PI, 133)14.

The idea that the method is the essential in philosophy makes it so that the latter turns

into “a matter of skill” (M, p. 322). The idea of a “skill” comes here in opposition to the idea

of “profundity” present in traditional philosophy. The reflexions from this philosophy have a

general meaning, which consists in the discovery of the hidden essence of phenomena or of

things and of the foundation of the sciences (PI, 89). Philosophical profundity can be

characterised as a (supposed) contemplation of the “ideal” that hides itself in reality (PI, 101).

However, it is an illusion, because the profundity is but a grammar Witz, and the whole

question is to know why do we experience the feeling of profundity when we are confronted

with philosophical problems (PI, 111). What characteristics, by its time, does the

Wittgensteinian skill have?

This skill is, as all the others, “very difficult to acquire”. In order to do that, says

Wittgenstein, it is not enough to attend classes, but discussion is indispensable. As the

physician, the philosopher must learn a technique, he must acquire an ability to heal; and, as

the physician must diagnose the true cause, and prescribe the appropriate medicine,

Wittgenstein must investigate which grammar mistake is in the origin of a determined

philosophical illusion, as well as the way to make the philosopher abandon his particular way

of speaking15. In the Big Typescript, Wittgenstein speaks of a capacity to philosophy and,

right after it, tackles the problem of teaching philosophy. Here, “the capacity for philosophy 13 The Big Typescript defined philosophy in the following way: “Philosophising is: rejecting false arguments” (BT, p. 6). Because the descriptions of our language's grammar acquire signification only from philosophical problems, the discussion upon the possible systematicity of this description, independently of the therapeutic finality, appears to us as a discussion outside Wittgenstein's mind (as Backer and Hacker (1980, pp. 290-293) and Strawson (1985, pp. 14-21) do).14 Hacker (1972, pp. 139-144) describes some of these causes of philosophical diseases and, in (1990, pp. 89-92), draws some comparisons with psychoanalytical theory, as the Big typescript (BT, p. 7) had already suggested.

Page 8: philosophicalskepticism.orgphilosophicalskepticism.org/.../2014/06/Wittgenstein-an…  · Web viewWITTGENSTEIN AND PYRRHONISM: ... the word “pain” can only refer to my pain and

consists in the ability to receive a strong and lasting impression from a grammatical fact” (BT,

p. 15)16. Not only the memories of our uses of the words will not be allowed to leave anything

out, under the charge of there remaining the feeling that something is wrong (M, p. 323), but

also their ordering and reordering will be necessary until we find a determined order that will

allow us to shun away a philosophical illusion (If, 132). On the other hand, the description of

our language is not only made of remembrances, and Wittgenstein allows himself to resort to

apparently absurd possible uses to illuminate certain “regions” of language that, otherwise,

could remain obscure. “Our method is not merely to enumerate actual usages of words, but

rather deliberately to invent new ones, some of them because of their absurd appearance”

(BB, p. 28; cf. PI, 122, 130). Wittgenstein demands yet another philosophical ability, viz., to

learn how to express precisely that which the philosopher would like to say. “One of the most

important tasks is to express all false thought processes so true to character that the reader

says, “Yes, that’s exactly the way I meant it”. ... Indeed, we can only prove that someone

made a mistake if he (really) acknowledges this expression as the correct expression of his

feeling” (BB, p.28; cf. IF, 122, 130).

Of what does the philosopher suffer, after all? Of what kind are the philosophical

problems that cause intellectual wounds, and must be dissolved? Philosophical questions have

origin in “a vague mental uneasiness” (M. p. 323, emphasis added). “Philosophical errors or

‘troubles in our thought’ were due false analogies suggested by our actual use of expressions”

(M, p.257, emphasis added; cf. too pp. 318-319 e 323-324). “The problems arising through a

misinterpretation of our forms of language have the character of depth. They are deep

disquietudes (tiefe Beunruhigungen)” (PI, 111; the second highlight is mine). “A simile that

has been absorbed into the forms of our language produces a false appearance, and this

disquiets us (der beunruhigt uns) (IF, 112; emphasis added; cf. IF, 125; cf. also BT, pp, 6, 9-

11, 14, 19). In the Blue Book, when rejecting the idea that an ideal language should be

produced to improve ordinary language, Wittgenstein attributes a new function to the

construction of ideal languages. “Whenever we make up 'ideal languages' it is not in order to

replace our ordinary language by them; but just to remove some trouble caused in someone's

mind by thinking that he has got hold of the exact use of a common word” (BB, p. 28;

emphasis added). A little before, Wittgenstein referred to the philosophical question “what

15 One must highlight, however, that the sort of thinking demanded by philosophical activity is "very different from what is required in the sciences" (M. p. 322). We have already observed that philosophy has a very different procedure from science; here, nothing is hidden, no new fact must be discovered and no theory (or hypothesis) is formulated.16 The text presents the following manuscript variation: "A talent for philosophy consists in the receptiveness to receive a strong and lasting impression from a grammatical fact".

Page 9: philosophicalskepticism.orgphilosophicalskepticism.org/.../2014/06/Wittgenstein-an…  · Web viewWITTGENSTEIN AND PYRRHONISM: ... the word “pain” can only refer to my pain and

is...?” as “an utterance of unclarity, of mental discomfort” (BB, p.26; emphasis added; cf. BB,

p.1 e p.59). This discomfort would be comparable with the mental discomfort children

experience when they ask “why?”.

What causes this disturbance? What philosophical form adopts this mental

discomfort? “A philosophical problem has the form: 'I don’t know my way about' (ich kenne

mich nicht aus)” (PI, 123). This disorientation can only relate to a disorientation in language,

in the grammatical rules (PI, 203), and, as a disease, generates a sensation of malaise. In those

passages of the Blue Book that deal with Saint Augustine's reflexions upon time (BB, p. 26),

Wittgenstein talks about a contradiction amongst different uses of the word “measure”. In the

paragraph 125 of the PI, Wittgenstein talks about a mathematical contradiction that generates

the mental discomfort. It is here, hence, that there is the origin of the philosophical problem

taken in its generality: “The civil status of a contradiction, or its status in civil life: there is the

philosophical problem. (PI, 125). How does one interpret this passage?17

The Blue Book gives us the first indications to think the mechanism that leads us from

contradiction to discomfort: the philosopher “sees a law in the way a word is used, and, trying

to apply this law consistently, comes up against cases where it leads to paradoxical results”

(BB, p. 27). The PI describes this mechanism in a different way: “The fundamental fact here

is that we lay down rules, a technique, for a game, and that then when we follow the rules,

things do not turn out as we had assumed. That we are therefore as it were entangled in our

own rules” (PI, 125). Different rules can work well until a new and unusual situation causes

two of them to come into disagreement, producing a contradiction that can generate a

philosophical problem. If we treat mathematically, e.g., a mathematical contradiction, no

philosophical disturbance will arise, for it is up to the mathematician to solve that conflict

manifested by two mathematical rules. But if we attribute a philosophical status to the

mathematical contradiction, then it will be inevitable the rise of a philosophical problem.

Transgressing the conceptual domain, to enter the objective domain, the philosopher will seek

outside the mathematics the solution to an eminently mathematical problem, when he should

only search um a conceptual description the origin of that contradiction. “This entanglement

in our rules is what we want to understand (i.e. übersehen)” (PI, 125; cf. PI, 89)18.

17 Fann (1975, pp. 72-73) cites a long passage of Hertz about the contradiction that closely resembles Wittgenstein's texts regarding this theme (Hertz, The principles of Mechanics, New York, Dover Publications, 1956, pp. 7-9).18 This, we see once again that the positive part submits itself to the negative: the description only focalises the contradiction manifested by the rules.

Page 10: philosophicalskepticism.orgphilosophicalskepticism.org/.../2014/06/Wittgenstein-an…  · Web viewWITTGENSTEIN AND PYRRHONISM: ... the word “pain” can only refer to my pain and

That is why, according to Wittgenstein, of the two ways to cure these disturbances –

either answering the philosophical question or showing that the particular question is not

permitted (M, p. 323) -, only the latter is satisfactory. As long as the philosopher seeks after

epistemological or ontological solutions to semantic problems, his disturbances will not cease

to exist. The Blue Book illustrates this point: “Very often, the way the discussion of such a

puzzle runs is this: First, the question is asked, “What is time?”. This question makes it appear

that what we want is a definition. We mistakenly think that a definition is what will remove

the trouble (as in certain states of indigestion we feel a kind of hunger, which cannot be

removed by eating). The question is then answered by a wrong definition; say, “Time is the

motion of the celestial bodies”. The next step is to see that this definition is unsatisfactory.

But this only means that we do not use the word “time” synonymously with “motion of the

celestial bodies”. However, in saying that the first definition is wrong, we are now tempted to

think that we must replace it by a different one, the correct one” (BB, 27). But there is no

correct definition of time and the solution to the problem must come from somewhere else.

Wittgenstein compares this situation to that one wherein we have a hair on our tongue, but

cannot get hold of it, and cannot get rid of it (BT, p. 6).

In a passage of the PI, Wittgenstein says, “A main cause of philosophical disease – a

one-sided diet: one nourishes one’s thinking with only one kind of example” (PI, 593). To

avoid these diseases, hence, it is fit to prescribe a multisided diet; thence the idea of

multiplying the examples of language games, of providing the conditions to the execution of

an analysis that deals with the problem from various angles, without ever intending to a

systematisation (cf. PI, 130-31). The Blue Book did not say something much different (p. 28),

when it recommended counteracting the false analogies with descriptions and inventions of

uses of words, for the false analogies imposed a single meaning to different uses of a

determined word19.

Another one of these methods is substituting a form of expression for other, in order to

make the misunderstanding disappear. This substitution method can be called an “analysis”,

for it often resembles a decomposition (PI, 90). But, in contrast with Tractatus, there is not a

perfect decomposed form of an expression, not is there a complete logical analysis to unveil

the determinate meaning of a proposition of common language (PI, 91). The analysis

Wittgenstein intends to perform now only aims at avoiding misunderstandings and, hence, the

language games he invents to that end must be interpreted only as objects of comparison that

19 Hottois (1976, pp. 141-154) elaborates the idea of an opposition between good and bad images. The “language games” would be good analogies, which would fight the bad analogies that generate philosophical problems.

Page 11: philosophicalskepticism.orgphilosophicalskepticism.org/.../2014/06/Wittgenstein-an…  · Web viewWITTGENSTEIN AND PYRRHONISM: ... the word “pain” can only refer to my pain and

illuminate our language, and not as revealers of a hidden meaning, but present, in all correctly

constructed propositions (PI, 130). The analytical method acquires, thus, a new meaning in

the later thought of Wittgenstein.

Roughly, one can say that, by pointing to an original contradiction in our rules and to

different uses of words, Wittgenstein intends to dissolve the philosophical problems. Thus, to

perform the linguistic therapy is to make the ways of language known again to philosophers,

to orient them in grammar rules and, by this means, to eliminate the contradictions that

produce their disquietudes. By detecting the origin of the problem and the conflict of rules

upon which the misunderstandings lie, we will quit putting philosophical questions to

ourselves, and, in this sense, we will quit philosophising in the traditional sense.

The disappearance of the disturbance that afflicted the philosopher follows the

abandonment of traditional philosophising. No longer confused or seduced by language, the

philosopher quits running his head up against the limits of language. Wittgenstein expresses

this point in a very famous metaphor, “What is your aim in philosophy? – To shew the fly the

way out of the fly-bottle” (PI, 309). The Notes for Lectures confirm the idea that this

metaphor expresses the disquietude of the philosopher and shows that to leave the fly-bottle is

to reach tranquillity: “The solipsist flutters and flutters in the flyglass, strikes against the

walls, flutters further. How can he be brought to rest (zur Ruhe zu bringen)?” (NL, p. 300)20.

Other passages also refer to tranquillity as the end pursued by philosophy, “The real discovery

is the one that makes me capable of stopping doing philosophy when I want to. – The one that

gives philosophy peace (zur Ruhe bringt), so that it is no longer tormented by questions which

bring itself in question. – Instead, we now demonstrate a method, by examples; and the series

of examples can be broken off. – Problems are solved (difficulties eliminated), not a single

problem” (PI, 133; the first highlight is mine; cf. BT, p. 19). “Disquiet in philosophy (Die

Unruhe in der Philosophie) might be said to arise from looking at philosophy wrongly...

Instead of the turbulent conjectures and explanations (turbulenten Mutmassungen und

Erklärungen), we want to establish the quiet weighing of linguistic facts (ruhige Erwägung

sprachlicher Tatsachen setzen,)” (Z, 447, emphasis added; cf. BT, p. 20)21. It becomes

undeniable therefore that tranquillity is the ultimate goal of the therapy, that it plays a central

role in Wittgenstein’s conception of philosophy. If we describe language, it is to eliminate the

philosophical illusions and if we eliminate the philosophical illusions, it is to alleviate the

20 Quoted by Tugendhat (1979), p. 92.21 Compare these passages with the manuscript variation of the BT, p. 15, quoted in the footnote 16 above.

Page 12: philosophicalskepticism.orgphilosophicalskepticism.org/.../2014/06/Wittgenstein-an…  · Web viewWITTGENSTEIN AND PYRRHONISM: ... the word “pain” can only refer to my pain and

mind22 of its discomfort or to remove its disturbance and reach tranquillity. Thus, intellectual

tranquillity is the supreme purpose of Wittgenstein’s philosophy, and it is what explains the

objectives subordinate to it that otherwise could seem gratuitous23.

This psychological aspect, so to speak, of therapy has its counterpart in a linguistic

aspect. The first and more evident is that we “bring words back from their metaphysical to

their everyday use” (PI, 116)24. On the other hand, by helping the philosopher to escape this

from the metaphysical use of the terms, “clear up the ground of language on which they (the

houses of cards) stand” (PI, 118). It is effectively about a liberation, for we were imprisoned

in a metaphysical language, which constrains and bothers us. Wittgenstein employs a

metaphor to express the difficulty of making language come back to work normally, “the

choice of our words is so important, because the point is to hit the physiognomy of the matter

exactly; because only the thought that is precisely targeted can lead the right way. The

railway carriage must be placed on the tracks exactly, so that it can keep on rolling as it is

supposed to” (BT, p. 6). This precision consists in the adequate choice of words to express

what the philosopher would like to say, so that he recognises himself in the formulation

proposed by the “therapist”.

Even the mathematician, e.g., is tempted to make (nonmathematical) affirmations

upon the objectivity and the reality of mathematical facts (der mathematischen Tatsachen);

these affirmations do not properly constitute a philosophy, but are rather its raw material, i.e.,

they must be treated by philosophy (PI, 254). When we encounter contradictions, we will seek

to clarify the grammatical rules that give rise to these contradictions so that science can solve

them in its own domain. Scientific investigations will be, thus, free of philosophical

confusions, of distortions that result from a necessarily partial philosophical perspective.

Since philosophy is “before all new discoveries and inventions” (PI, 126; BT, p. 13), one can

sustain that one of its functions is to disentangle sciences from the false problems risen by

22 By employing the word "mind”, we do not attribute any "mentalism" to Wittgenstein's philosophy. The use of this word is authorised by the philosopher himself (e.g., BB, p. 28 and M, p. 323, quoted above). On the other hand, Wittgenstein is not a behaviourist (cf., e.g., Tugendhat (1979, pp. 120ff.) e Hacker (1990, pp. 224-253)).23 Backer e Hacker (1980, “The Nature of Philosophy, p. 259-293) have not mentioned even a single time the tranquillity as the final goal of Wittgensteinian therapy. Arregui (1984, p. 157ff.) says that tranquillity is Wittgenstein's purpose, but does seem to distinguish it from the Übersicht. However, the repeated use of the word “Zweck” (for ex., PI, 109, 127, 132) allows one to talk about clarity as a means to tranquillity. For that reason, we agree with Hottois (1976, p. 164), affirming that the ultimate goal of the übersichthiche Darstellung is to arrive at a state of tranquillity.24 By criticising the idea of a private language, Wittgenstein assumes one must only use words as they are normally used, "If we are using the word 'to know' as it is normally used (and how else are we to use it?)" (PI, 246).

Page 13: philosophicalskepticism.orgphilosophicalskepticism.org/.../2014/06/Wittgenstein-an…  · Web viewWITTGENSTEIN AND PYRRHONISM: ... the word “pain” can only refer to my pain and

philosophers and, sometimes, by scientists themselves when they step aside from their

scientific work.

The return to the common use of words does not mean a blind adherence to the

conceptions of the common person, nor a prejudice against speculation. Wittgenstein, on one

hand, acknowledges the value of philosophical illusions: they are not mere mistakes, but

answer to basic errors that allow us to reflect upon our language; the importance of

philosophical problems is as great as that of our own language (PI, 111; cf. BT, p.8). And, on

the other hand, he does not aim at rejecting the modifications of our language, but, on the

contrary, conceive it as essentially mutable (albeit its structure changes in an extremely slow

rhythm; cf. IF, 18 and UG, 95-99). To his mind, however, it is not up to the philosopher to

promote the reform and improvement of language: “Such a reform for particular practical

purposes, an improvement in our terminology designed to prevent misunderstandings in

practice, is perfectly possible. But these are not the cases we have to do with. The confusions

which occupy us arise when language is like an engine idling (leerläuft), not when it is doing

work” (PI, 132). One of the meanings of the famous affirmation that “philosophy leaves

everything as it is” (PI, 124) is precisely that common language must not be altered by

philosophy, but only described when misunderstandings arise.

Giving up the great theoretical and systematic constructions, philosophy will

constitute itself in a practice, i.e., in the activity of reminding or producing possible uses of

words to perform the therapy25. We imagine other language games as object of comparison to

illuminate our language game (PI, 130). If language is like a city (PI, 18), the philosophical

observations that Wittgenstein makes regarding it are like sketches of a landscape (PI, pref.),

accentuating some of its aspects, or walls surrounding its limits, so that philosophers do not

contravene them (BT, p. 16). In the same way medicine is an activity, so is Wittgenstein's

linguistic therapy, “philosophy unravels the knots in our thinking; hence its result must be

simple, but its activity as complicated as the knots it unravels” (BT, p. 14; emphasis added). It

is precisely because philosophy is an activity that Wittgenstein will demand, as we have seen

above, a technical capacity from the philosopher. A method to cure the dogmatists and

metaphysicians of the disease is a way of conducting an investigation, a particular way of

exerting this therapeutic activity.

According to Wittgenstein, of the traces of the traditional way of philosophising, only

a few remain valid (to be of general character, to be fundamental both to ordinary life and to

the sciences, and to be independent of the results of science; cf. M, p. 323) and, in its place, 25 The idea that philosophy is a practice was already present since Tractatus (4.112).

Page 14: philosophicalskepticism.orgphilosophicalskepticism.org/.../2014/06/Wittgenstein-an…  · Web viewWITTGENSTEIN AND PYRRHONISM: ... the word “pain” can only refer to my pain and

we have only a new discipline that is no more than an heiress of what we call traditional

philosophy (BB, p. 28).

But it is certain that philosophy has no end, since language will continue to suggest

false analogies, and certain people will be propense to be seduced by them26. Thus, new

problems will arise and new philosophical theories will be proposed, making necessary new

therapies. Besides, the dissolution of philosophical problems is always through the

“transversal streets”, never through the “main road” (Z, 447), i.e., the therapy solves particular

problems and repels punctual difficulties, but not a single problem (PI, 133). Thus, therapeutic

philosophy demands an unceasing work: “but in that case we never get to the end of our

work! – Of course not, for it has no end” (Z, 447)27.

3. This conception of philosophy has nothing to do with the so-called Cartesian

scepticism of the first Meditation, which aims at destroying every belief to rebuild sciences

from new and solid foundations, and, at first, neither it resembles Humean scepticism, which

results from an empirical science, whose purpose is to discover the principles of human mind.

In Wittgenstein, a universal doubt is not possible, nor is philosophy an empirical science.

However, the conception of philosophy presented by Sextus Empiricus reveals itself very

close of the Wittgenstein's conception exposed above. A comparison between them presents a

series of affinities, to the point that we can characterise Wittgenstein's conception as a

sceptical conception28.

In the first place, Wittgenstein holds that the task of philosophy is eminently critical

and negative. We have seen that philosophy was defined as a battle against the bewitchment

of our intelligence by means of language, only destroying “houses of cards”, i.e.,

metaphysical thoughts. By refusing to construct arguments to arrive at conclusions, it did not

formulate theses, only combated, with the means of language itself, those theses proposed by

philosophers. This first idea is the one that says philosophy must become a therapy. The

26 Grammatical problems, according to Big Typescript, are profoundly rooted in our own grammar, associating themselves to the most ancient habits of thought. Because we had, and still have, the tendency to think like this is the reason language became as it is, in a manner that the liberation of the seduction of language involves an effort against our instinct, as a natural thought (cf. PI, 109). And that would explain the observation that philosophy, since Plato, does not tire of coming back to the same problems, for the basic structure of language is essentially still the same (BT, pp, 14-16).27 Hottois (1976, p. 165) intends that complete clarity produces a definitive state of serenity. With this, Wittgenstein would reintroduce a theoretical connotation in his philosophy, as well as a utopic ideal. But what seems definitive to us is only the tranquillity regarding a solved particular problem. Other philosophical problems threat the tranquillity that, from this point of view, is momentary.28 I obviously do not intend to deplete this comparison here. Danilo Marcondes (NP) tackle this problem, approximating, to my mind correctly, Wittgenstein and Sextus.

Page 15: philosophicalskepticism.orgphilosophicalskepticism.org/.../2014/06/Wittgenstein-an…  · Web viewWITTGENSTEIN AND PYRRHONISM: ... the word “pain” can only refer to my pain and

speculations about "the structure of the real" must cede their places to the descriptions of

language, and we acknowledge that, in the origin of philosophical questions, lies a problem to

be solved.

Sextus Empiricus would certainly subscribe to this characterisation of philosophy29. In

contrast to the dogmatists, who formulate a positive thesis about the possibility of knowledge

of the “real”, and to the Academicians, who formulate a negative one, the Pyrrhonian

investigations do not result in any knowledge, whether positive or negative (PH 1.1-3). There

would be, then, according to Sextus Empiricus, three species of philosophy: the dogmatic, the

academic, and the sceptical (PH 1.4), in which the specificity of the latter would consist in its

abstention from the formulation of any philosophical thesis. The sceptic does not hold any

dogma, if by “dogma” we understand, “to assent to some unclear object of investigation in the

sciences; for Pyrrhonists do not assent to anything unclear” (PH 1.13).

If in dogmatic and academic philosophies, arguments sustained theses about the

supposed “real world”; in Pyrrhonism, they assume a very different function. If we understand

"argument" as a discourse that articulates premises and conclusions with the purpose of

establishing theses about reality, then there is no sceptical argument, only dogmatic

arguments that come into conflict with one another, annulling themselves mutually, and

producing suspension of judgement. With respect to argumentation understood in this sense,

what is proper to the Pyrrhonist is not in the formulation of any particular argument, but in the

disposition or organisation of the arguments. The Pyrrhonist ascertains the conflict, the

diaphonía, of opinions and points at the impossibility of finding a criterion that can solve it.

Incapable of pronouncing himself about the existence of the real, due to the equipotence of

the various discourses elaborated by philosophers, the Pyrrhonist is led to suspend judgement.

Dogmatism is seen as a species of disease, which consists in self-love (PH 1.90), in

the conceit and rashness of the philosophers (PH 3.280), and must be cured by Pyrrhonist.

Sextus Empiricus also employs a medical metaphor to explain the way by which the

Pyrrhonist treats the dogmatist’s posture: just as the physician applies stronger medicine to the

most severe diseases, the Pyrrhonist employs stronger or weaker arguments conform to the

intensity of the dogmatist’s disease (PH 3.280). Everything that is constructed of "positive",

for both Wittgenstein and Sextus, assumes philosophical relevance from that destructive

intention. In effect, the Pyrrhonist conceives his arguments as an aperient drug that, by

expelling the contrary argument, is expelled with it (PH 2.188). In the same way, for

29 Except, as we will see ahead, from the idea that the philosophical problems are dissolved. This idea is not in Pyrrhonian thought.

Page 16: philosophicalskepticism.orgphilosophicalskepticism.org/.../2014/06/Wittgenstein-an…  · Web viewWITTGENSTEIN AND PYRRHONISM: ... the word “pain” can only refer to my pain and

Wittgenstein, the description of language is distinguished from the grammarian’s work

precisely because it serves to eliminate the philosophical confusion. It is noteworthy that the

Tractatus (6.54) employed the same metaphor that Sextus did (M 8.481) to characterise the

philosophical work as a necessary step to be subsequently abandoned: after we use the ladder

to climb the wall, we knock it over.

We have already seen Wittgenstein's particular way of understanding the philosophical

therapy, and it remains to see Sextus’s way of conceiving it. A brief exposition of the

Pyrrhonian therapy already points at other similarities amongst both philosophers. In the

origin of philosophising is a disquietude or disturbance, and therapy must supress this

disquietude, conducing the philosopher to calmness and tranquillity (ataraxía) in relation to

philosophical questions, by means of an opposition of arguments. At first, the Pyrrhonist has

hoped to find, in the possession of truth, the end of his philosophical problems. The

observation of contradictions in things, and the aporia in relation to which alternative he

should accept, had disturbed the Pyrrhonist – before he became a Pyrrhonist. The

investigation of the true and false in things seemed, at first, the solution to his disturbance

and, hence, the Pyrrhonist – before he became a Pyrrhonist – dedicated himself to this

investigation (PH 1.12). But from this investigation has not resulted the possession of truth,

but the suspension of judgment (due to the equipotence of arguments). It occurred then, as if

by chance, that to the suspension of judgment followed the desired tranquillity of the soul

(dianóia) with respect to preventable issues (PH 1.28-29) Based on the repeated experience of

the suspension followed by tranquillity, the Pyrrhonist has gradually abandoned the search for

truth and replacing it with the pursuit of the suspension of judgment. The goal remained the

same, the hope to achieve tranquillity, but the means to achieve it have changed in the course

of his investigations.

With respect to this point, one has observed some similarities between Wittgenstein

and Sextus. Therapy, to both of them, aims at restoring the lost tranquility in front of a

philosophical problem that disturbs us. The cause of this disturbance is identified as being a

contradiction and, of the two possible solutions – either reply to the philosophical question or

abandon it –, only the latter propitiates tranquility, whilst the first only perpetuates the initial

disquietude. It occurs, hence, a shift in the philosophy’s task, since truth ceases to be the

horizon to steer its reflexions. Philosophy becomes a means to achieve, so to speak, a

philosophical tranquility.

In both thoughts, moreover, one tries to curb the partiality of dogmatic philosophy by

calling attention to other aspects involved in the question. Philosophy must be impartial. In

Page 17: philosophicalskepticism.orgphilosophicalskepticism.org/.../2014/06/Wittgenstein-an…  · Web viewWITTGENSTEIN AND PYRRHONISM: ... the word “pain” can only refer to my pain and

Wittgenstein's case, that is done by counteracting (cf. BB, p. 28) the false analogies with

descriptions and inventions of uses of words or attending to the diverse uses that a word has,

without tying oneself to a single one nor imposing it to all uses of that expression; and, in

Sextus’s case, by opposing negative arguments to positive ones. Pyrrhonism’s most

characteristic feature is the opposition of arguments to arguments in order to produce a state

of mind wherein one does not affirm nor denies any thesis that postulates the reality of things

(PH 1.8). The method seeks after the frontal collision of two opposing tendencies that annul

each other. The characterisation of the dogmatist as a lover of himself (philautós) –, i.e., as he

who prefers his own opinions and elects himself as criterion to solve the conflict of opinions –

corresponds to this denounce of his partiality in the consideration of the arguments and

opinions involved in an issue.

This therapy demands from he who exerts it, whether in Wittgensteinian or Sextian

form, a certain ability or capacity. I have described briefly the technique demanded from one

who intends to dissolve the philosophical problems (to perceive grammatical facts, to know to

ordain linguistic observations, to invent possible uses and to apprehend and express what the

other wants to say). Will there be something in Sextus that corresponds to this ability of the

philosopher? It is the very definition of scepticism and sceptic that gives us the answer. Being

Pyrrhonism defined as a capacity (dúnamis) of opposing arguments and arguments (PH 1.8),

the Pyrrhonist will be precisely the one who participates in this capacity (PH 1.11). Whilst the

philosopher has the capacity of producing arguments and theses with respect to a supposed

real, the sceptic has the ability to organise them with the purpose of annulling them mutually

and reaching the suspension of judgement. The modes of Aenesidemus and Agrippa, e.g., can

be seen as techniques of neutralisation of dogmatism. Besides, Sextus affirms the sceptics are

“men of talent” (PH 1.12) who have been troubled by the contradictions of opinions and who

contrived tranquillity by means of suspension of judgement; it is required, thus, to become a

sceptic, some talent to acquire and exert this technique.

The idea that the sceptic possesses a particular ability is consistent with the idea that

there is no sceptical argument in that sense of argument I defined above, which is to be

conclusive with respect to the reality of things, for the Pyrrhonist does not propose an

argument that convinces the philosopher that he is wrong, but he proposes mainly a technique

to achieve tranquillity, a path by which the philosopher can get rid of the problems that

torment him. To the extent in which the conflict presents opinions and arguments of both

sides and with equal persuasive force, the Pyrrhonist may intend his reflexions to be the most

rational and rigorous result that is within our reach.

Page 18: philosophicalskepticism.orgphilosophicalskepticism.org/.../2014/06/Wittgenstein-an…  · Web viewWITTGENSTEIN AND PYRRHONISM: ... the word “pain” can only refer to my pain and

In Wittgenstein's conception, philosophy is not a theory or a contemplation of truth,

but a practice, an activity of eliminating confusions and philosophical problems. The same

can be said of Sextus Empiricus: Pyrrhonism also received the name of “zetetic”, from its

activity of investigating and enquiring (apò energeía tês katà tò zetãn kaí sképtesthai) (PH

1.7). Furthermore, the idea that Pyrrhonism is a practice is entailed in the definition of sceptic

as someone who possesses a determined technical capacity.

Not only to Wittgenstein, but also to Sextus, philosophy is nothing but this therapeutic

activity. Albeit both of them recognise a scientific dimension and propose, each in their own

way, a conception of science, the scientific activity is beyond the attributions of the

philosopher qua philosopher. Science deals with phenomena, with facts; philosophy deals

with the discourse about phenomenon, with concepts, and with language. The therapy is done

exclusively in the discursive domain: “The sceptic, being a lover of mankind, wishes to cure

by discourse (iásthai lógoi), according to his capacity (dúnamin), the conceit, and rashness of

the Dogmatists” (PH 3.280, emphasis added). This aspect of Sextian philosophy becomes

clear when one pays attention to the domain of suspension of judgement. This cannot be about

phenomena, for they impose themselves to us, forcing us to an involuntary assent (PH 1.13

and 19); thus, one can only exert it upon the discourse that postulates the reality or unreality

of phenomena. Wittgenstein also affirms to be language the instrument to cure the disease of

the understanding: “Philosophy is a battle against the bewitchment of our intelligence by

means of language” (PI, 109, emphasis added). The critical project is limited to fight

dogmatism by means of discourse without resorting to science or phenomena.

With respect to this last point, one can make another approximation between

Wittgenstein and Sextus. To Wittgenstein, the logical analysis does not furnish the hidden

meaning of our language, as if the meaning needed to be unburied by an analysis of our

language; ordinary language is perfectly in order, even if there are (or precisely because there

are) indeterminations of meaning. Sextus, by his turn, condemned the philosophers’ attempt at

finding, by means of an "analogy", a deeper grammar that would serve as criterion to

distinguish good from evil Greek (M 1.41ff). To Sextus, the criterion of correct or incorrect

use of words shall not be owed to a special art that discovers a deep meaning of the word, but

only to its real and non-technical use (M.1.152-153 and 176ff). Common use is the criterion

of what belongs and does not belong to the language of a certain community. The meaning of

discourse is in the surface.

Another important idea of Wittgenstein that finds clear resonances in Pyrrhonism is

that we must speak like everybody, i.e., that we must employ words with the meaning they

Page 19: philosophicalskepticism.orgphilosophicalskepticism.org/.../2014/06/Wittgenstein-an…  · Web viewWITTGENSTEIN AND PYRRHONISM: ... the word “pain” can only refer to my pain and

habitually have. According to Wittgenstein, the philosopher use common expressions to build,

based on them, philosophical propositions (PI, 90), which is condemnable, but it is not

condemnable the use of common propositions in appropriated circumstances. And the use of

ordinary language does not entail the adoption of any philosophical thesis, for it is beneath

any dispute between realists and idealists (cf. BB, p. 48). The Pyrrhonist, by his turn,

acknowledges that he can say, when he is chilled, that he is chilled (PH 1.13). He can say the

phenomenon without being thereby postulating its reality. All sceptical formulae used to

indicate the suspension of judgement (PH 1.187-209) only express the phenomenon or the

personal experience30 of the Pyrrhonian and do not indicate any form of dogmatism. However,

the Pyrrhonist does not accept the discourse that attributes or rejects reality to phenomena,

i.e., that discourse that, differentiating itself from the habitual discourse of men, intends to

establish dogmas about what is real and what is not. Both allow themselves to use the

common discourse without any ontological commitment and reject the philosophical

discourse that intends to establish truths about the real. From this point of view, the similarity

between the two thinkers could not be greater.

It shall not follow from there, to the Pyrrhonist, as to Wittgenstein, that common use is

untouchable. Both conceive meanings as a human convention. Wittgenstein warns, in the Blue

Book, us so that we do “not forget that a word has not got a meaning given to it, as it were, by

a power independent of us... A word has the meaning someone has given to it” (BB, p. 28).

Likewise, Sextus says that language is conventional (M 1.37-38; 142ff). Therefore, nothing

prevents that one gives new meaning to words, or even that one invents new words, and both

conceive an evolution in language and a refinement of our vocabulary. To Wittgenstein, this

reform of language must be done in conformity with practical purposes to avoid

misunderstandings in the practical use of language (PI, 132)31. And Sextus, criticising the

dogmatists about their incapacity to distinguish ambiguities, says the same thing, “for, if an

ambiguity is a word or phrase having two or more meanings, and if words have meaning by

convention, then those ambiguities that are worth resolving – i.e., such as occur in some

practical situation – will be resolved, not by the dogmatist but by the people practised in each

particular art, who themselves have the experience of how they have created the conventional

usage of the terms to denote the things signified” (PH 2.256)32. This passage of Sextus is very

30 31 However, Wittgenstein himself coined expressions of strict philosophical use, such as "rule", "language-game", "form of life" etc.32 Sextus had already said the same thing regarding sophisms: the observation of practical life is capable of solving sophisms, but the philosopher is not (PH 2.254).

Page 20: philosophicalskepticism.orgphilosophicalskepticism.org/.../2014/06/Wittgenstein-an…  · Web viewWITTGENSTEIN AND PYRRHONISM: ... the word “pain” can only refer to my pain and

significative, since it also attributes to those who deal with empirical and practical questions

the responsibility of avoiding the ambiguities of language that arise from the equivocalness of

words. And even in the common course of life, when it is useful to draw a distinction to avoid

an ambiguity, people do not hesitate in drawing it. “Thus, it is the experience of what is useful

in each particular case that propitiates the distinction of ambiguities” (PH 2.258). On the other

hand, the ambiguities that dogmatists try to solve are not involved in the practical experiences

of life. Of these considerations by Sextus about ambiguity, one can say that the philosopher

tries in vain to solve ambiguities that escape to practical life, whilst common people and

artisans overcome their difficulties from experience. The invention of new terms, to avoid the

ambiguities of the old ones, is due to the necessity of distinguishing in the practical domain

what was not distinguished before, being this um of the modes by which language seems, in

the Pyrrhonist's eyes, to evolve.

Another similarity is that the new task of philosophy is endless. In the case of

Wittgenstein, both the functioning of language and his method of dealing with philosophical

issues led to the conception of an infinite task for philosophy. In the case of Sextus, one also

conceives the idea of a constant rebirth of dogmatism, and, as the investigation about truth has

not reached any definitive result, it remains open the possibility of one discovering the truth.

Thus, each new proposed argument is a threat to the Pyrrhonian position and must be

investigated, whether to re-establish the equipotence of arguments or to recognise that the

"truth" has finally been reached. Either way, both "condemn" themselves, by the own internal

logic of their reflexions, to a permanent critical task.

A basic idea, therefore, animates both Wittgenstein's and Sextus' thought: that life

goes on just fine without the dogmatic philosophy. To Wittgenstein, as we have seen,

common sense is neither realist nor idealist, being beneath these philosophical disputes (BB,

p. 48). Thus, when we employ affirmative proposition current in our common language, we

are not committing ourselves philosophically to any theory, but only living our lives and

using language as a useful tool to them. Dogmatism is like a pair of glasses upon our noses,

and it distorts our view of things; it is so close that it seldom occurs to us to take them off (PI,

103). However, it is only when we remove the dogmatic lenses that we can see things as they

are. Sextus thinks, “it is enough to live by experience and without opinions, in accordance

with the common observations and preconceptions” (PH, 2.246). The propositions in which

the Pyrrhonist employs the verb "to be" do not express the acceptance of a dogma, for the

verb "to be" must be read as indicating what appears to the sceptic, thus the suspension of

judgement is integrally preserved (PH 1.135). By renouncing to philosophise in its traditional

Page 21: philosophicalskepticism.orgphilosophicalskepticism.org/.../2014/06/Wittgenstein-an…  · Web viewWITTGENSTEIN AND PYRRHONISM: ... the word “pain” can only refer to my pain and

moulds, the Pyrrhonist returns to common sense and live his life as an ordinary man, albeit

without the dogmatic beliefs of the latter. The Pyrrhonist, in effect, does not attack common

life and even speaks on its side, since he refutes those who have risen up against common

judgement (M 8.156-158). To both, we can make affirmations following the common use of

language, adopting the common way of seeing the world, without, however, making of this

conception a philosophical theory. In other words, if, on one hand, there is a continuity

between the dogmatism of both common person and philosopher, on the other hand, Sextus

and Wittgenstein defend common life (or sense) against the philosophical criticisms and

expurgate what they contain of dogmatism.

So many and so important similarities seem to justify the characterization of

Wittgenstein's conception of philosophy as Pyrrhonian. A negative and therapeutic

philosophy, whose purpose is tranquillity, which demands a determined technical capacity

from he who practises it, which deals only with discourse, rejecting the philosophical and

accepting the common without any ontological commitment, and conceived as an endless

attitude. This more general conception of philosophy is shared by Wittgenstein and the

Pyrrhonists.

4. To the conclusion that the conception of philosophy by Wittgenstein is Pyrrhonian,

however, is possible to oppose some objections. One could say that, if the general conception

does not differentiate one thinker from the other, in its details we find noteworthy differences.

The way by which we achieve tranquillity in each philosophy has little in common,

employing analyses and argumentations of very different nature. If the landscape is the same,

the path shall be different.

Naturally, in a therapy, the diagnosis plays a foundational role, for it is in function of

it that we determine the medicine to be ministered. Sextus identifies in self-love, in rashness

and in conceit the major defects that lead a man who is willing to philosophise to dogmatism.

Here it is the root of all their evils: by not examining an issue from every possible angle, by

not reflecting maturely about every argument involved in a determined problem and by

preferring his personal opinions, without taking in due considerations the ones of others, a

man naturally incurs in an arrogant and precipitated dogmatism. Wittgenstein’s diagnosis is

different: a thinker becomes a dogmatist less for his psychological characteristics than for a

dynamic proper to language. It seduces him and bewitches his understanding; incapable of

resisting this temptation, the philosopher experiments a sensation of deepness and starts to

reflect upon the “structure of the world”, when the cause of his reflexion is actually a

Page 22: philosophicalskepticism.orgphilosophicalskepticism.org/.../2014/06/Wittgenstein-an…  · Web viewWITTGENSTEIN AND PYRRHONISM: ... the word “pain” can only refer to my pain and

contradiction of the rules of language that moves away the common use of words. Thence the

importance that Wittgenstein attributes to philosophy, for the philosopher is not only "hasty",

but also the one who experiments and denounces basic contradictions of language in his

theories. It is when language goes on holiday that one is tempted to philosophise.

Of these different diagnoses, result different therapies. The Pyrrhonist's activity is to

show to the dogmatist the various opinions sustained with respect to a questions, the equal

force of the arguments employed by different philosophical schools and the impossibility of

discovering a neutral criterion to decide the controversy. The activity of the Wittgensteinian

philosopher will be very different: it is necessary to do, from remembrances of common use

of words, a punctilious description of the workings of our ordinary language, inventing, if

necessary, language games to illuminate our grammar, so that the philosopher can recover

from his illness. The great novelty of Wittgenstein's style of philosophising is tied, thus, to his

particular way of proposing a philosophical therapy.

What is the scope of these objections to the previous suggestion that the conception of

Wittgenstein's philosophy is a Pyrrhonian conception? One could say that the differences,

albeit can serve to deny the character strictly Pyrrhonian of Wittgenstein’s thought, point to

what could be a contribution to the history of scepticism: Wittgenstein would turn much more

acute the conscience that it is in discourse that lies the origin of dogmatism. If this idea was

already present in Sextus, it was not present the idea that it is due to a malfunction of

language (to a contradiction between its rules) that arise the problems posited by

philosophers. The specific analysis of various processes involved in the functioning of our

language and of how words end up losing meaning and “idling” would significantly advance

the comprehension of the illusions that lurk dogmatism.

To the extent that the Pyrrhonist is that who has the ability to oppose argument to

argument in any way at all (PH 1.8) to reach tranquillity of the soul by means of suspension

of judgement, one could think that Wittgenstein offers a new way of reaching tranquillity.

(Let us remember that Wittgenstein admits the possibility of various therapies). In addition to

the modes of Aenesidemus or Agrippa and all the opposition of particular arguments in the

various branches of knowledge, the sceptic would now have at his disposal a new and

powerful mean by which we could learn or acquire that technical ability to become sceptical:

by identifying the false analogies that produce philosophical illusions and describing the good

functioning of language so that he would see that the use proposed by philosophers does not

make sense or, if it does, it is only a new way of speaking that does not have epistemological

or ontological implications, as dogmatism would like it had. To identify false analogies that

Page 23: philosophicalskepticism.orgphilosophicalskepticism.org/.../2014/06/Wittgenstein-an…  · Web viewWITTGENSTEIN AND PYRRHONISM: ... the word “pain” can only refer to my pain and

are in the foundation of philosophical illusion, to recognise where our grammatical rules enter

in conflict, to apprehend exactly that the philosopher wants to say, to describe correctly a part

of our habitual language, and to invent different language games, but useful to therapeutic

purposes, would be tasks that would demand an refined discernment and that would have an

enormous persuasive efficacy. Wittgenstein would promote, thus, a species of renovation of

the Pyrrhonian tradition, in a very original sense.

Apparently stronger objections, however, could be formulated. The difference of

method between Sextus and Wittgenstein would point to a deeper and more decisive

difference to our question, viz. that the Pyrrhonian sceptic remains stuck in the field of

traditional philosophy, whilst Wittgenstein would have emancipated from it. One would show

that of two ways. On one hand, the sceptic would share a presupposition with philosophers:

“that we possess knowledge of our own subjective experience, that we know with absolute

certainty how things are with us, has been the common ground of agreement between sceptics

and their opponents ever since philosophical debates about the extent and possibility of

human knowledge began”33. The idea that phenomena are not open to investigation, that they

are azétetoi would not result from their inevitable character, as Pyrrhonists claim. To

Wittgenstein, the exclusion of doubt is rooted in grammar and not in the nature of that which

is right; for example, nothing is considered as doubt about our internal states: it is senseless to

say, “I may be in pain or I may not, I am not sure”34. Thus, the sceptic would remain stuck to

the traditional conception of philosophy, for he would attribute the impossibility of doubting

to an intrinsic propriety of phenomenon, when, in fact, the absence of sense of this doubt lies

in our language. On the other hand, the method of Wittgenstein, instead of opposing argument

to argument, assuming a philosophical presupposition, has the goal of identifying this

presupposition and extirpate it: “it seems to have been an almost instinctive maxim of his that

where philosophical debate has polarized between a pair of alternatives that seem exhaustive,

the appropriate method to follow is not just to examine the conflicting arguments on each side

and then opt for the seemingly stronger ones. Rather we should find out what was agreed by

all participants in the centuries-old debate and reject that”35.

The force of this objection lies in the attribution to Pyrrhonists of a common

presupposition with the dogmatists; the opposition of arguments and acceptance of

phenomena would show the presence of the sceptic in the traditional territory of philosophy.

33 Hacker (1990), p. 63.34 Cf. Hacker (1990), pp. 58-5935 Hacker (1990), p. 63.

Page 24: philosophicalskepticism.orgphilosophicalskepticism.org/.../2014/06/Wittgenstein-an…  · Web viewWITTGENSTEIN AND PYRRHONISM: ... the word “pain” can only refer to my pain and

But it is precisely in this attribution that the objection is wrong, for the sceptical only makes

use of dogmatic arguments to reject them, as an aperient drug that is expelled along with the

substances present in the body, without ever compromising to them (PH 2.188). On the other

hand, the common presupposition that the sceptics would share with dogmatists would be that

we cannot doubt the ideas in our minds or the immediate data of our consciousness. Now, this

formulation is strictly modern and cannot be imputed to Greek Pyrrhonists. However, it is true

that the sceptic does not attribute to grammar the exclusion of doubt about phenomena, but

here we go back to the different already mentioned in the previous objection, and that I do not

hesitate to recognise: the Pyrrhonian and Wittgensteinian way of fighting dogmatism are very

different.

One could insist in the objection and say that, to Wittgenstein, dogmatic theses and

arguments lack meaning, and, hence, a method of opposition of arguments would be equally

meaningless, which would show that the only alternative to whom wishes to do a therapy

would be to reject the implicit presuppositions of the debate. But, on one hand, this method

would not distinguish Wittgenstein from the philosophers who intended to shift the

philosophical scenery (think, for example, of Berkeley and his critique of materialism; of

Kant and his "Copernican Revolution"; or of Bergson and his considerations upon space and

time); and, on the other, Pyrrhonism had also said to be incompatible the dogmatic notions

(cf., for example, PH 3.2-5, to the case of God or PH 3.13, to the concept of "cause"). The

way by which the Pyrrhonist fights dogmatism generally admits of two levels: firstly, one

questions our ability to conceive the dogmatic discourse, conflicting the various definitions of

the investigated terms and, secondly, one opposes different arguments invoked in favour of

the sustained dogmatic positions. Everything happens as if Wittgenstein, considering decisive

the first level – which questions the meaning of philosophical discourse –, ended up

suppressing the second, since, strictly speaking, it lacks sense. That does not prevent the

sceptic to be capable of conceiving, in an ample sense of the term, that which the dogmatist

says (PH 2.1-12). Likewise, Wittgenstein is capable of apprehending what the philosopher

would like to say, but cannot say. Thus, the opposition of arguments makes sense to the exact

extent in which one can conceive, lacto sense, that which the dogmatist says. Only a theory

that postulated what really is the meaning of words could criticise the sceptic this way, but

evidently, as it is known, it is not Wittgenstein's position: the idea that use is meaning does

not constitute a theory of language.

This objection can receive a final form that seems convincing to me, viz. that the

Pyrrhonian way of fighting dogmatism does not go so far as to dissolve the philosophical

Page 25: philosophicalskepticism.orgphilosophicalskepticism.org/.../2014/06/Wittgenstein-an…  · Web viewWITTGENSTEIN AND PYRRHONISM: ... the word “pain” can only refer to my pain and

question, as Wittgenstein does, and, hence, at least logically, the possibility of discovering the

truth remains open to the Pyrrhonist. Thus, the interminable therapy to which they condemn

has a different meaning, for, whilst one still thinks it is possible, albeit highly improbable, to

reach the truth, the other has his investigation, so to speak, closed to the truth. It is impossible

not to recognise that, in Sextus, there is no mention of a dissolution of philosophical

problems, and that the questioning of the meaning of philosophical discourse always gives

way to the opposition of arguments. It must be recognised that the difference in the manner of

conducting the therapy involves this second difference, that the Wittgensteinian therapy

dissolves philosophical problems, whilst after the Pyrrhonian critical they would remain

significative. If, to modern taste, Wittgenstein is more radical, to Pyrrhonian taste, the

dissolution of the problem and the consideration of the question of truth as over can have the

flavour of a negative dogmatism of academician sort.

Another objection may come precisely from those who, having this Pyrrhonian taste,

believe there is a form of dogmatism of language in Wittgenstein's philosophy. These people

would see a superiority in Pyrrhonism, for the conflict of philosophies, and the polemical

character amongst them, are not a theoretical construction of the Pyrrhonist, but a fact of the

history of philosophy recognised by dogmatists independently from their particular belief.

Wittgenstein, in contrast, would have elaborated a dogmatic conception of nature of

philosophy and philosophical discourse and, based on it, he arrives at a position apparently

similar to that of Pyrrhonists. Thus, there would be a species of unconfessed dogmatism in

this philosophy of language36.

One could retort to this objection in the following way: not only the conflict of

philosophies is a fact of history, but also it is a fact the philosophers often complain about the

imprecision, and about the difficulties that common language presents to metaphysical

speculation. Hence, they elaborate a technical vocabulary, refining common words or

inventing new words one supposes better express the reached truths. Anyway, it is frequent

amongst philosophers the establishment of a linguistic domain whose meaning amply differs

from the meaning that words have in their ordinary use. If (as the Pyrrhonian sceptic) we

place ourselves in the field of the pre-philosophical not knowing with the purpose of

identifying which is the discourse that reflects reality, then we can ask ourselves, from

common language, for the precise meaning of each philosophical discourse. In the very

attempt to clarify the meaning of philosophical discourse, we recognise it does not have any

36 To formulate this objection, I inspired myself on the pages 7-9 of Porchat's article "Scepticism and Argumentation".

Page 26: philosophicalskepticism.orgphilosophicalskepticism.org/.../2014/06/Wittgenstein-an…  · Web viewWITTGENSTEIN AND PYRRHONISM: ... the word “pain” can only refer to my pain and

meaning. Thus, one could say that Wittgenstein's therapy starts from other fact of history of

philosophy, not constituting itself from a dogmatic conception of the nature of philosophy.

Wittgenstein and Sextus Empiricus, therefore, set forth on from different facts of philosophy,

without postulating an arbitrary beginning, and tread on different paths, albeit parallel, so that

it fits to say that it is about two related conceptions of philosophy.

One could also object that the reach of the differences pointed above is ampler than it

seems at first and that this new therapeutic method proposed by Wittgenstein leads, in contrast

with what is suggested here, to a thought very different from Pyrrhonism when effectively

applied to particular philosophical problems. This is indeed a question that remains open, and

only the study of particular therapies may confirm, or not, Wittgenstein's fidelity to the way

by which he conceived philosophy. But whatever it is the result of such investigation, it shall

not diminish in any way the similarities with respect to the conception of the nature of

philosophy, and that is all I intended to have shown here.

Page 27: philosophicalskepticism.orgphilosophicalskepticism.org/.../2014/06/Wittgenstein-an…  · Web viewWITTGENSTEIN AND PYRRHONISM: ... the word “pain” can only refer to my pain and

REFERENCES

WITTGENSTEIN, L.:

(TLP) Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, Suhrkamp, Frankfurt a.M., 1984.

(IF) Philosophische Untersuchungen in Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, Suhrkamp, Frankfurt a.M.,

1984.

(Z) Zettel in Über Gewissheit, Suhrkamp, Frankfurt a.M., 1984.

(UG) Über Gewissheit, Suhrkamp, Frankfurt a.M., 1984.

(BB) Blue Book, Blackwell, Oxford, 1958.

(BT) The Big Typescript, German–English Scholars’ Edition, edited and translated by C. Grant

Luckhardt and Maximilian A. E. Aue, Blackwell, Oxford, 2005.

(M) Wittgenstein’s Lectures in 1930-33 in Moore, Philosophical Papers, George Allen and Unwin Ltd.,

London; Humanities Press inc., New York, 1959.

OTHERS

ARREGUI, J.V., (1984) Acción y Sentido en Wittgenstein, Ed. Universidad de Navarra, Pamplona,

Spain.

BAKER, G.P. and Hacker, P.M.S., (1980), Wittgenstein, Meaning and Understanding, Basil Blackwell,

Oxford.

BAKER, G.P. and Hacker, P.M.S., (1984), Scepticism, Rules and Language, Blackwell, Oxford.

BOUVERESSE, J., (1987) Le Mythe de l’intériorité, Les Éditions de Minuit, Paris.

BURNYEAT, M. (1982), “Idealism and Greek Philosophy: What Descartes saw and Berkeley missed”,

in The Philosophical Review, XCI, nº 1, jan.

FANN, K.T., (1975) La Concepción de Filosofia de Ludwig Wittgenstein, Técnis, Madrid.

FOGELIN, R.J., (1976) Wittgenstein, Routledge and Kegan Paul, London.

HACKER, P.M.S., (1972) Insight and Illusion, At the Clarendon Press, Oxford.

HACKER, P.M.S., (1990) Wittgenstein: Meaning and Mind, Basil Blackwell, Oxford.

HOTTOIS, G., (1976) La Philosophie du Langage de Ludwig Wittgenstein, Editions de L’Université de

Bruxelles, Belgium.

HUME, D., (1975) Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, Blackwell, Oxford.

KRIPKE, S.A., (1982) On Rules and Private Language, Blackwell, Oxford.

MALCOM, N., (1988) “Wittgenstein’s ‘Scepticism’ in On certainty” in Inquiry, vol. 31, nº 3, Sep /

1988, Norwegian University Press.

MARCONDES DE SOUZA FILHO, D. (NP), Finding One’s Way About” (draft).

PORCHAT, O., (2007) “Ceticismo e Argumentação” in Rumo ao Ceticismo. São Paulo: UNESP.

SHIBLES, W., (1969) Wittgenstein, Linguagem e Filosofia, Ed. Cultrix/EDUSP, São Paulo.

STRAWSON, P.F, (1985) Skepticism and Naturalism: some varieties, Columbia University Press, New

York.

TUGENDHAT, E., (1979) Selbstbewusstsein und Selbstbestimmung, Suhrkamp. Frankfurt a.M.,


Recommended