+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Quoted in Breazeale (1982) file · Web viewReinhold’s goal was to systemize Kant...

Quoted in Breazeale (1982) file · Web viewReinhold’s goal was to systemize Kant...

Date post: 31-Jan-2018
Category:
Upload: ngohuong
View: 215 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend
46
Philosophy of Mind in Nineteenth-Century Germany Barbara Gail Montero In Germany during the nineteenth century there was, as there is today, enormous interest in understanding the mind, its structure, its place in the world, and the possibility of a complete scientific account of human nature. Nineteenth-century Germany also witnessed a flowering of thought about the machinations of unconscious mental processes, thought which would go on to influence Sigmund Freud’s work at the turn of the twentieth century. And, as today, these ideas were discussed and debated among philosophers as well as natural scientists and educated members of the general public. In what follows, I focus on a small sampling of issues from nineteenth-century German philosophy and point out ways in which they resonate with various topics in contemporary philosophy of mind. For some this approach may prove to be a puzzle inside of a conundrum, however, I hope that for others it will bring out some interesting connections between then and now.
Transcript
Page 1: Quoted in Breazeale (1982) file · Web viewReinhold’s goal was to systemize Kant and antecedents to his view about consciousness are found in the . Critique of Pure Reason., for

Philosophy of Mind in Nineteenth-Century Germany

Barbara Gail Montero

In Germany during the nineteenth century there was, as there is today, enormous interest in

understanding the mind, its structure, its place in the world, and the possibility of a complete

scientific account of human nature. Nineteenth-century Germany also witnessed a flowering of

thought about the machinations of unconscious mental processes, thought which would go on to

influence Sigmund Freud’s work at the turn of the twentieth century. And, as today, these ideas

were discussed and debated among philosophers as well as natural scientists and educated

members of the general public. In what follows, I focus on a small sampling of issues from

nineteenth-century German philosophy and point out ways in which they resonate with various

topics in contemporary philosophy of mind. For some this approach may prove to be a puzzle

inside of a conundrum, however, I hope that for others it will bring out some interesting

connections between then and now.

1. The Reinhold-Fichte-Hegel Model of Consciousness

Although there were deep and virulent disagreements among the philosophers Karl Reinhold and

Johann Fichte about how to understand consciousness—Fichte (1930)1, for example, writing to

Reinhold in 1795, “I am a declared opponent of your system”—these and other philosophers at

the turn of the nineteenth century held a similar view about the basic structure of consciousness,

1 Quoted in Breazeale (1981). See also Breazeale (1982). Reinhold’s goal was to systemize Kant and antecedents to his view about consciousness are found in the Critique of Pure Reason.

Page 2: Quoted in Breazeale (1982) file · Web viewReinhold’s goal was to systemize Kant and antecedents to his view about consciousness are found in the . Critique of Pure Reason., for

a view about what all forms of consciousness share. This is the idea, roughly, that consciousness

involves awareness of an object, of the self, and of the self’s representation of the object.

Reinhold (1790, p. 167) referred to this as the “principle of consciousness,” which he stated as

follows: “in consciousness representation is distinguished through the subject from the subject

and object and related to both.”

Much of the interest in this principle at the time had to do with what Reinhold saw as its

primary value: that it would give philosophy its much-needed indubitable grounds, thus enabling

it to become a science—not an empirical science, but, even better, a science about which no

doubt remains. For the principle of consciousness, according to Reinhold, was a self-evident

principle from which all further philosophical claims could be derived. “Consciousness forces

everyone to agree,” Reinhold (1789, p. 200) claimed, “that to every representation there pertains

a representing subject and a represented object, both of which must be distinguished from the

representation to which they pertain.” Furthermore, such a self-evident, universally valid

proposition was needed, he argued, “or else philosophy as a science is impossible, and in that

case the bases for our ethical duties and rights—as well as these duties and rights themselves—

must remain forever undecided”.2

Whether the principle of consciousness did this work, however, was questioned by,

among others, the philosopher Gottlob Ernst Schulze. Schulze held that the principle, rather than

being self-evident, had the status of an empirical generalization, indeed, an empirical

generalization that was neither universally valid nor capable of grounding the rest of Reinhold’s

philosophy.3 But let me put aside the larger question of whether such a principle can serve as a

2 Quoted in Breazeale (1982).3 Breazeale (1982) explains that Fichte, persuaded by Schulze’s criticism, aimed to arrive at an even more basic principle from which the principle of consciousness follows, and what he proceeds to show in his Science of Knowledge is how the representational element of consciousness can be derived from the act of positing a subject and an object.

Page 3: Quoted in Breazeale (1982) file · Web viewReinhold’s goal was to systemize Kant and antecedents to his view about consciousness are found in the . Critique of Pure Reason., for

grounds for philosophy and focus on the truth the principle, on the question of whether

consciousness contains these elements, an idea that has striking similarities to the views of

certain contemporary theorists, such as Uriah Kriegel (2003, p. 104), who claims that “in your

auditory experience of [a] bagpipe you are aware primarily, or explicitly, of the bagpipe sound

[the object]; but you are also implicitly aware that this auditory experience of the bagpipe [your

representation of the bagpipe] is your experience[the self].”

Despite Schulze’s criticism, this model of consciousness maintained its hold in the

philosophical community in Germany into the nineteenth century and, as Michael Forster (1998,

p. 117) points out, Hegel typically proceeds on the assumption that consciousness does have this

threefold structure, with Hegel even at one point echoing Reinhold’s wording of his principle:

“[c]onsciousness simultaneously distinguishes itself from something, and at the same time

relates itself to it.” In the introduction to the Phenomenology of Spirit, however, Hegel does

submit the view to some scrutiny. “Consciousness,” Hegel (1807/1977, §85) states, “is, on the

one hand, consciousness of the object, and on the other, consciousness of itself; consciousness of

what for it is the True, and consciousness of its knowledge of the truth,” which seems to capture

at least the idea that in being conscious of an object (what for it is the True) we are also aware of

representing—not just representing but aware of representing—the object (that is, we are

conscious of our knowledge of the truth). Yet how does consciousness get to the object? Why

does it not just stop at the representation? Hegel anticipates these questions, telling us that

although it might seem “that consciousness cannot, as it were, get behind the object as it exists

for consciousness so as to examine what the object is in itself,” nonetheless “the distinction

between the in-it-self and knowledge [representation] is already present in the very fact that

consciousness knows an object at all;” that is, the very fact that we are representing an object,

Page 4: Quoted in Breazeale (1982) file · Web viewReinhold’s goal was to systemize Kant and antecedents to his view about consciousness are found in the . Critique of Pure Reason., for

Hegel seems to think, implies that there is an object—“something quite separate from us,” as he

puts it in Faith and Being (1907, p. 383)4—that we are representing.

What are we to say of the Reinhold-Fichte-Hegel (RFH) model of consciousness? Is

consciousness representational? And if it is, are we aware of it as such? Does consciousness

contain awareness of the self? Does it contain awareness of objects? These are, of course,

difficult and much debated questions, but let me touch on a few considerations. Of the three

elements, the idea that consciousness is representational in some sense or other was generally

taken as the linchpin of the view, with Fichte (1988, p. 71), for example, arguing that the

representational element of consciousness is derived from the act of positing a subject and an

object and at one point remarking that the idea that we could understand consciousness without

representation was “a piece of whimsy, a pipe dream, a nonthought.” Some contemporary

philosophers, however, such as John Searle (1983) and Amy Kind (2013), suggest that moods

like free-floating anxiety or general depression may be conscious, yet they do not represent

anything. 5 Of course, as those who hold representational accounts of consciousness do today,

someone who upholds the RFH model of consciousness might find representations lurking in

these darker moments—general depression is depression about everything, they might say. Still,

even if consciousness is representational, it is a further question whether we are conscious that

we are representing objects. Another contemporary philosopher, Joseph Levine (2006, p. 179),

seems to think we are not: “I am not in any way aware of any cognitive distance between me and

the scene in front of me; the fact that what I’m doing is representing the world is clearly not itself

part of the experience.” Hegel (1807/1977, §85), however, seems to think this distance is part of

4 Quoted in Forster (1998). Even assuming that a distinction between representation and object exists in the concept of object, whether all consciousness involves a distinction between representation and object still depends on whether all consciousness is consciousness of objects (for discussion, see Forster, 1998). 5 And some see consciousness as not representational at all. Such philosophers instead see consciousness as a relation between the self and objects that does not involve representations, in part, because they think it does not make sense to talk of perception as being either true or false. See Susanna Schellenberg’s (2010) discussion of the view she calls “austere relationalism.”

Page 5: Quoted in Breazeale (1982) file · Web viewReinhold’s goal was to systemize Kant and antecedents to his view about consciousness are found in the . Critique of Pure Reason., for

consciousness: “something is for it the in-itself [the scene]; and cognition, or the being of the

object for consciousness [my representing the scene], is, for it, another moment.”

One objection to the idea that consciousness contains an awareness of the self, an

objection that was voiced at the time and is heard today in connection with the concept of

“flow,” is based on the idea that sometimes we get “lost,” in thought, in sensation, or in action.6

When we are engrossed in a philosophical problem and making progress (which may happen

occasionally), are we not lost in thought? When we experience overwhelming pain, is it not true

that the only thing present to our minds is the pain? And, when all is going well, might not the

self disappear in running a marathon or dancing Swan Lake? Kreigel deals with such objections

by making the awareness of the self in conscious experience implicit rather than explicit. But I

wonder if one need even concede as much, for just what is it to get lost in movement? I believe

that a more accurate description of such situations is not that one gets lost, but rather that all

those uninvited worries about death, taxes and the like that have been crowding your mind

vanish. The self is there when movement flows and you feel lost; but it is just your better self.7

The idea that the self gets lost when thought flows may also be questioned. Does one

really loose the self, or do you experience yourself as focused on a particularly engaging topic?

Moreover, in as much as one does get “lost” in either thought or in skill, it seems that, again, one

might argue (contra the idea of phenomenal consciousness) that consciousness does as well, for

if there are times when you get lost, perhaps because you are working on automatic pilot, there is

no conscious at all.8 And although the case of the self getting lost in pain is a difficult one, it

6 James Messina (2011) points out that this objection was made by Johann Schwab, who, commenting on Reinhold’s principle of consciousness, asks, “Is there not a consciousness where we do not distinguish ourselves from the object; and is this not the case when we lose ourselves, as one says, in a sensation?” 7 Or rather, I would argue that when experts perform at their best, in general the self is not lost. See Montero (forthcoming), for discussion of this issue.8 For a neuroscientific approach to the question of whether a certain type of self-consciousness is necessarily part of consciousness experience, see Goldberg, Harel, and Malach (2006).

Page 6: Quoted in Breazeale (1982) file · Web viewReinhold’s goal was to systemize Kant and antecedents to his view about consciousness are found in the . Critique of Pure Reason., for

might be said that at least when pain is not overwhelming, one has a sense of an object (the

painful sensation in, say, your foot) and your awareness of such object (if only, you might think,

I could turn my awareness away from it).9 As for overwhelming pain, a defender of the RHF

model of consciousness might resort to making the awareness of the self implicit, however, there

is another line of defense: since, arguably, one can’t actually remember what goes on in extreme

pain, one might argue that one cannot know whether the self is present. Perhaps, a defender of

the RHF model of consciousness might say, in pain, one has the experience, I am in pain; yet one

forgets.10

A further consideration that is sometimes bandied about today in discussions of whether

consciousness is representational involves the neurological disorder “pain asymbolia,” whereby

one experiences pain but feels disconnected from it; individuals who have this condition may say

that they don’t mind the pain and even that it feels as if it is someone else’s pain. If we take these

statements at face value, what should they lead us to believe? Some think that pain asymbolia

illustrates that the experience of p need not involve an experience to the effect that I am

experiencing p. Yet one might say that pain asymbolia illustrates the relative forcefulness of the

“I” in ordinary pain experiences.11 Furthermore, one might find the self in the experience of

feeling as if someone else is in pain: It is I, who is aware of someone else’s pain.

As for the idea that in consciousness we are always aware of objects, this is refuted,

according to Schulze, by examples of deep reflection, wherein, according to Schulze, it is only

our ruminations that are present. But now we are entering the rocky terrain involving what is to

count as an object. Forster (1998, p. 188) suggests, in his defense of Hegel’s idea that all

9 This might not always be a helpful thought since it might be that that in some situations, focusing on pain, rather than distracting oneself from it, reduces it. See Johnston, Atlas, and Wager TD (2012).10 Another line of defense might even be that as there is no memory, there was no conscious experience.11 Of course, if we take what these individuals say at face value, this would still seem to counter the idea that it is analytic or necessary that conscious experience involves awareness of a subject.

Page 7: Quoted in Breazeale (1982) file · Web viewReinhold’s goal was to systemize Kant and antecedents to his view about consciousness are found in the . Critique of Pure Reason., for

consciousness involves thinking of something as objective, that “even if one is conscious only of

one’s own mental states, still one must think of them as objectively or really mental states.” In

short, the question of the validity of the RFH model of consciousness is very much an open one.

2. Hegel’s Dissolution of the Mind-Body Problem

Hegel, in overcoming mind-body dualism, had an explicit practical motivation: he felt

that his culture’s acceptance of dualism led to unhappiness; persuade people to think of mind and

body differently, and such unhappiness is eliminated. 12 And the way he aims to persuade

individuals to see the union in the disunion of mind and body is by helping them to understand

geist, or what is often translated as “spirit.” How successful are Hegel’s arguments against

dualism? And does the elimination of dualism help to alleviate unhappiness?

In the Encyclopaedia, Hegel (1830/1971, §389) tells us that “the soul is no separate

immaterial entity,” not because the soul or mind is material in the sense of solid, weighty matter,

but rather because matter is far less material than is often presumed. Once we realize this, Hegel

tells us, the question of mind-body dualism dissolves: “the question of the immateriality of the

soul has no interest, except where, on the one hand, matter is resolved as something true, and

mind conceived as a thing, on the other.” To accept this type of disunity, he argues, is a mistake,

for “in modern times, even the physicists have found matters grow thinner in their hands,” and

“they have come upon imponderable matters, like heat, light.” For Hegel, as matter thins, so

does the problem of the relation between mind and matter, for if matter is, as Hegel sees it, just

12 I say “explicit” here because although philosophers’ views on the mind-body problem today are often explicitly expressed as being motivated by purely theoretical concerns, grounded in logical argumentation, I think it is a reasonable guess that implicit motivations are at least sometimes at work as well.

Page 8: Quoted in Breazeale (1982) file · Web viewReinhold’s goal was to systemize Kant and antecedents to his view about consciousness are found in the . Critique of Pure Reason., for

as mysterious as mind, there is no question of either materialism or immaterialism. This is

Hegel’s dissolution of the mind-body problem.

In contrast, the Cartesian conception of matter, or body, which holds that body is

extension—extension in length, breadth, and depth—grounds the mind-body problem: if mind is

unextended and body is extended the distinction is plain, since something unextended cannot be

identical to something extended. Moreover, if causal interaction requires contact, causal

interaction between mind and body on the Cartesian picture is at best difficult to fathom. In

Hegel’s words, “the usual answer [as to how to understand the interdependence between mind

and body], perhaps, was to call it an incomprehensible mystery; and, indeed, if we take them to

be absolutely antithetical and absolutely independent, they are as impenetrable to each other as

one piece of matter to another, each being supposed to be found only in the pores of the other,

i.e. where the other is not.” But physics as Hegel saw it, and even more so today, fails to suggest

a conception of matter, wherein matter is diametrically opposed to mind.

For Hegel, the inaccuracy of the Cartesian conception of matter was apparent in such

physical phenomena as light and heat, which, in accord with the physics of his day, have, he

says, “lost the property (peculiar to matter) of gravity and, in a sense, even the capacity of

offering resistance.” And the more we learn about matter, the more “imponderable,” it becomes.

Noam Chomsky (1993, p. 41) puts it well: it is difficult to arrive at a “delimitation of ‘the

physical,’ that excludes Fregean ‘thoughts’ in principle, but includes mathematical objects that

‘push each other about,’ massless particles, curved space-time, infinite one-dimensional strings

in 10-dimensional space, and whatever will be contrived tomorrow.” Or as Bertrand Russell said

in 1927 (p. 104), “matter has become as ghostly as anything in a spiritualist’s séance.”

Page 9: Quoted in Breazeale (1982) file · Web viewReinhold’s goal was to systemize Kant and antecedents to his view about consciousness are found in the . Critique of Pure Reason., for

Like Russell and Chomsky, the thinning of matter allows Hegel to see mind, or “vital

spirit,” as sitting comfortably in the physicist’s world. Yet the distinction between mind and

matter, for Hegel, does not entirely disappear: these “imponderables,” he tells us, “which have

lost the property (peculiar to matter) of gravity and, in a sense, even the capacity of offering

resistance, have still, however, a sensible existence and outness of part to part; whereas the

‘vital’ matter, which may also be found enumerated among them, not merely lacks gravity, but

even every other aspect of existence which might lead us to treat it as material.” Nonetheless,

“vital matter,” on Hegel’s view, still is matter.13 And today, with the matter of physicists being

described in terms of equations and functions and, as such, no longer even having a sensible

existence and an “outness” of part to part, the mind-body problem dissipates almost entirely.

It should be clear that I am rather sympathetic to Hegel’s dissolution to the mind-body

problem. But let me look at a very different approach he takes to arguing against dualism: what

some commentators have seen as his argument for behaviorism. Hegel tells us in

Phenomenology of Sprit (1807/1977, §322) that “the true being of a person is that person’s deed”

and that “when a person’s performance and inner possibility, capacity or intention are contrasted,

it is the former alone which is to be regarded as their true actuality, even if he deceives himself

on the point, and, turning away from his action into himself fancies that in this inner self he is

something else than what he is in the deed.” The deed, he tells us, “is not merely a sign, but the

fact itself…and the individual human being is what the deed is.” And in the Encyclopaedia

(1830/1975, §140), referring favorably to the Gospels, in which it is written, “by their fruits ye

shall know them,” Hegel tells us , “a man is what he does.” Is Hegel, then, a behaviorist, holding

the view that mind isn’t distinct from body since it is no more than the movements of the body?

13 See Montero (1999, 2001, and 2005) for further discussion of how to understand the concept of matter in discussions of the mind-body problem.

Page 10: Quoted in Breazeale (1982) file · Web viewReinhold’s goal was to systemize Kant and antecedents to his view about consciousness are found in the . Critique of Pure Reason., for

I am not convinced that Hegel is presenting an argument for a metaphysical position,

which tells us what the mind is, rather than a normative one, which tells us how we ought to

judge others. Or at least, if Hegel is arguing for metaphysical behaviorism, he arrives at it by

means of normative considerations, considerations that have an echo in a strand of present-day

feminism. Hegel is bothered, and rightly so in my opinion, by people who brag about how great

they are or about how they could have done great things, when, in fact, their actions do not

reveal this. Similarly, Hegel is infuriated when others judge someone not by what the individual

has done, but by how the individual supposedly is inwardly, criticizing those who might discredit

someone’s apparently praiseworthy actions because they think that the inner motivation for such

actions was merely vanity or some other contemptible passion. He seems to think that, at least

for adults, what matters is what they do. And if so, though he does not speak of such cases

explicitly, Hegel would seem to think it similarly wrong to praise an adult for all his inner

genius, if such “genius,” has not produced any worthwhile actions, for, as researchers point out

today, such praise may very well be influenced by implicit biases, or stereotyping.14 Hegel, I

think, is right: in such situations, we should praise people according to what they do, rather than

how they supposedly are inside.

In fact, I think that Hegel might not go far enough in his advice, for he (1830/1975, §140)

seems to accept that “a sharp-eyed teacher may, from perceiving in a boy marked talents, express

the opinion that there is a Raphael or Mozart in him,” even if it is “the outcome [that] will then

teach to what extent such an opinion was grounded.” If our perceptions of others come with

implicit biases, as tests such as the implicit bias test seem to indicate, then even such an attitude

needs to be adopted with caution for it is most likely that certain groups of individuals will be

seen has having inner potential, and that perception, rather than having its accuracy tested by the

14 See Saul (2013) for discussion of implicit bias and women in philosophy.

Page 11: Quoted in Breazeale (1982) file · Web viewReinhold’s goal was to systemize Kant and antecedents to his view about consciousness are found in the . Critique of Pure Reason., for

pupil’s future actions, can in part determine them (those with Mozart inside of them will of

course be trained more rigorously than those without such perceived talent), which is great for

those who are seen as having potential, yet detrimental for those who are seen as lacking it.15

So it seems, then, that there is at least a normative component to Hegel’s view. But why

is it not also a metaphysical behaviorist view? Perhaps the above claim provides a clue, for

Hegel seems to think that there is something that the sharp-eyed teacher notices, that there is

some inner potential or talent. The ultimate judge of whether such talent exists, or how great it

is, he holds, is going to be seen, at least in the long-run, in behavior. Yet apart from the fact that

he says that the deed is not merely the sign of the mind, but the mind itself, he seems to accept

that we do have intentions, for if we didn’t, it wouldn’t be the case that, as he (1830/1975, §140)

says, “[occasionally] in individual cases …well-meant intentions are brought to nothing by

unfavorable outward circumstances.” And indeed, in such cases—for example, when a person

sets out to help a sick child, yet is struck with an illness himself and can no longer follow

through—we want to look to a person’s intentions rather than actions and praise those intentions

rather than seeing such a person as worthless because of his or her inaction. Of course, Hegel

would say, and probably rightly so, that we determine whether such intentions exist in the first

place by the actions they produce. But this does not mean that the inner intention does not exist

and, when illness strikes, it would not seem right to say that that person’s worth is the totality of

their deeds. Similar claims could be made for inner intelligence. Although in favorable

circumstances we ought to judge people’s smarts by what they do, in unfavorable circumstances,

such as extreme poverty, the wisest council would seem to be: make no judgment at all, or,

perhaps even better, assume Mozarts, Raphaels and Galileos exist in all. So although I think that

15 One might also wonder about the extent to which Mozart, himself, had “Mozart inside of him,” for it is well known that his father played a large role in guiding his musical development. See Rushton (2006).

Page 12: Quoted in Breazeale (1982) file · Web viewReinhold’s goal was to systemize Kant and antecedents to his view about consciousness are found in the . Critique of Pure Reason., for

Hegel’s dissolution of the mind-body problem based on the thinning of matter is persuasive, I am

not convinced that his behaviorist leanings should be understood as an argument for

metaphysical behaviorism.

This bring us to the question of whether overcoming mind-body dualism does the

practical work he thinks it does; that is, whether it promotes happiness. Whatever one may think

of the truth of Hegel’s metaphysical picture, his motivation is noble; who can cavil with wanting

to promote happiness? But does separating the mind from body lead to unhappiness? Perhaps it

does if dualism leads us to value individuals not for their bodily actions but for what goes on in

their minds; for such a picture, as Hegel (1807/1977, §322) suggests, may lead to thinking of

one’s actions as meaningless: “[w]ork and enjoyment…lose all universal content and

significance.”

Hegel, however, also thought that dualism was at the root, or at least a key component of

the Christian disparagement of the body. Dualism, he thought (§225), leads to embarrassment

about our natural bodily functions and to the view that “it is in them that the enemy reveals

himself in his characteristic shape.” I am not so sure. Specifically, I’m not sure if any

thoroughgoing materialist would or should feel any less shame than a dualists would at what we

now take to be shame worthy bodily functions. For example, materialist or dualist, one should

be ashamed of, say, pedophilic actions. If anything, it would seem that thinking of the body as

the not-self would make one less ashamed of its movements. It was, after all, a bodily urge, one

might say in explanation of purported shameful act, and thus not representative of who I really

am. Of course, if one accepts a religious doctrine that disparages the body, then that doctrine

might lead you to be at war with certain aspects of your bodily self. However, this would seem

to result entirely from the doctrine’s demotion of the body rather than its promotion of dualism.

Page 13: Quoted in Breazeale (1982) file · Web viewReinhold’s goal was to systemize Kant and antecedents to his view about consciousness are found in the . Critique of Pure Reason., for

Indeed, it might even be that, rather than mind-body dualism leading to desecrating the body, it

is the desecration of the body that makes one distance oneself from one’s body and thus lead to

mind-body dualism.

3. The Materialismusstreit

In September of 1854, twenty-three years after Hegel died, the prominent Göttingen physiologist

Rudolph Wagner presented a general lecture before the Association of German Scientists and

Physicians. In this lecture, he condemned the zoologist Karl Vogt’s materialistic stance on the

soul and the origin of human beings. The ensuing intellectual melee over the relative roles of

religion and science in our understanding of the world, what came to be known as the

materialismusstreit, or the controversy over materialism, touched virtually all aspects of German

society, affecting science, politics, religion, morality, education, even the food people chose to

eat, and in many ways prefigured the schism we find today at the root of some of our thorniest

political battles: abortion, gay marriage, cloning, and contraception.16Im Zentrum der

Kontroversen stand die Frage, ob die Ergebnisse der Naturwissenschaften mit dem Konzept einer

immateriellen , eines personalen und eines vereinbar sind.

Materialism had been gaining popularity among German academics through the views of

the philosopher Ludwig Feuerbach, who had studied with Hegel and, with the aim of, as he put

it, “plunging into the direct opposite,” also went on to study anatomy.17 However, the central

players in the materialismusstreit, which took place in the public eye, were scientists, such as

Vogt who, among other things, had a flair for rhetoric. In his Physiologische Briefe (Letters on

16Regarding the issue of diet, it was during the Materialismusstreit that, for example, the well-known pun, “Der mensch ist was er isst,” originated. 17 It is unlikely that Vogt had read Feuerbach’s works, for he had a strong aversion to philosophy, yet he was likely exposed to some of Feuerbach’s ideas second hand. See Gregory (1977).

Page 14: Quoted in Breazeale (1982) file · Web viewReinhold’s goal was to systemize Kant and antecedents to his view about consciousness are found in the . Critique of Pure Reason., for

Physiology), Vogt claimed that all mental processes, “are but functions of the brain substance or,

to express myself a bit crudely here, that thoughts stand in the same relation to the brain as gall

does to the liver or urine to the kidneys.” Though today many materialists hold precisely Vogt’s

view that mental processes are functions of the brain (though they would likely quibble with his

analogy seeing it as having too much in common with dualism, as it makes mental processes out

as something secreted by and thus separate from the functioning of the brain), at the time it was

considered scandalous and was the subject of much ridicule. Vogt, however, remained

undaunted, seeing his materialistic understanding of the mind as following directly from his

scientific investigations of the brain and his experiments on animals; “to assume a soul that

makes use of the brain as an instrument with which it can work as it pleases” Vogt said, “is pure

nonsense.”

Wagner, on the other hand, was inclined to think that Vogt’s materialism was actually

worse than pure nonsense, for as he saw it, it was dangerous nonsense.18 Though Wagner was

also a scientist, he held that there were certain limits to what science can and should

investigate.19 Not only was materialism not grounded in empirical evidence, according to

Wagner, but it also presented a serious threat to the moral and political order. There is no

reason, Wagner argued, why a religious conception of the origin of human life on earth and the

immortality of the soul cannot be upheld consistently with a scientific picture of the world. On

Wagner’s (1854) view, the realms of science and spirituality have nothing to say to one another:

“reason and belief are just as different from one another, … as the senses, as vision and

hearing”(pp. 18, 14f). To accept the picture Vogt paints of the natural world, Wagner said,

18 Many of the materialists also saw their opponents’ views as dangerous since they saw them as devaluing existence here on earth. 19 His scientific approach to materialism is illustrated by the fact that he tried to discredit Vogt’s thesis, unsuccessfully according to Vogt, by weighing brains, claiming that if the mind is purely material, more intelligent people should be endowed with heavier brains. See Vogt (1864).

Page 15: Quoted in Breazeale (1982) file · Web viewReinhold’s goal was to systemize Kant and antecedents to his view about consciousness are found in the . Critique of Pure Reason., for

“would completely destroy the moral foundations of social order” and thus it is our “duty to the

nation” to reject it.20

The debate brought others into the fray and over the next two decades, the schism grew

ever more virulent and vitriolic. For example, the physiologist and physician Ludwig Büchner,

in his popular and provocative Force and Matter, argued that “atheism, or philosophical

Monism, alone leads to freedom, to intelligence, to progress, to due recognition of a man—in a

word, to Humanism.”21 And Andreas Wagner (no relation to Rudolf Wagner) defended the other

side, calling Vogt a conniving deceiver and arguing that the history of science provides no reason

to think that the posits of science and religion cannot be consistently upheld. Materialism, rather

than following from science, according to Andreas Wagner, “belongs to the diseased phenomena

of our time which have resulted from the displacement of the Christian standpoint and have

gripped all classes of civil society like an influenza.”22

Part of the interest in this debate, and no doubt part of the reason why it captivated the

public at large, has to do with the personalities involves. None of the central players were

overflowing with that virtue we call “modesty,” and all had consummate command of invectives.

However, there is quite a bit of philosophical interest as well; for there arose debates covering

questions about the existence of God, the nature of consciousness, the limits of scientific

knowledge, the respective roles and importance of sense experience and rational thought in our

understanding of the world, the reduction of chemistry, biology and physiology to physics, the

origin of morality, the existence of free will, and the epistemic status of faith. The sine qua non

of the materialist position, however, during this time was atheism; there is nothing beyond this

world, was the cry, and what science cannot capture, must be relegated to a figment of the

20 Wagner, R. (1854), op cit. 21 Buchner, L. (1855) Kraft und Stoff: empirschnaturphilosophische Studien (Frankfurt am Main: Meidinger). 22 Quoted in Gregory (1977, p.38).

Page 16: Quoted in Breazeale (1982) file · Web viewReinhold’s goal was to systemize Kant and antecedents to his view about consciousness are found in the . Critique of Pure Reason., for

imagination. “The world is not the realization of a unitary creative mind, but rather a complex of

things and fact,” Büchner said, and “we must recognize it as it is, not as we would like to

imagine it.”23 The loser on this picture, as we will see, was free will, yet consciousness, if not

the entire triad of mind, meaning, and morality, was seen as amenable to a complete scientific

explanation, and thus preserved, as materialists saw it.

Vogt, no doubt, thought that he was salvaging the mind, and in particular, consciousness,

by identifying mental processes with functions of the brain. Pointing to what we today call the

“explanatory gap” between mind and brain, his opponents ridiculed his approach. Their

criticism is brought out perhaps most acutely by the philosopher Hermann Lotze. Lotze wanted

to know how, on a materialistic picture of the universe according to which all of nature is

ultimately mechanical movements of extended substance, could consciousness exist? If the

workings of the brain are no different in essence from the workings of a spinning-jenny, he

asked, are we to then say that a spinning-jenny is conscious?

The physician Heinrich Czolbe, a lesser known, though in Lotze’s eyes more consistent

materialist, took Lotze’s comments to heart, leading him to diverge from the other materialists.

Czolbe admitted that Lotze had rightly identified an unbridgeable gap between a mechanical

description of consciousness and one’s own experience of consciousness and responded by

reducing human consciousness to fundamental consciousness in nature, propounding what might

be seen as panpsychism.24 To the question of whether a spinning-jenny is conscious, Czolbe now

had an answer: Yes, it is, but just a little. However, remaining committed to atheism, he denied

that consciousness implied or was in any way connected to a realm of reality beyond the scope of

science and empirical inquiry. Moreover, by similarly pushing morality and something he called

23 Bruchner, L. op cit. p. iv.24 This is similar to how various non-religious philosophers who accept the idea of an ineliminable explanatory gap between mind and brain, such as Thomas Nagel, David Chalmers, and Galen Strawson, respond to such a lacuna today.

Page 17: Quoted in Breazeale (1982) file · Web viewReinhold’s goal was to systemize Kant and antecedents to his view about consciousness are found in the . Critique of Pure Reason., for

“purpose” down to the level of fundamental physics, he sought to retain morality and purpose in

a world without God.

Though the materialists saw themselves as preserving consciousness, free will did not

fare as well. Büchner trumpeted the view that “not only what we are, but also what we do, want

sense, and think...depends on the same natural necessity as the entire construction of the

world.”25 And Vogt argued that physiological investigation shows us that “man, as well as

animal, is just a machine” and, with characteristic boldness, explained that because tampering

with the brain leads to changes in the mind, the proposition that we have free will is refuted.26

Perhaps the move here from premise to conclusion is rather quick, nonetheless, materialism and

freedom of the will do make unhappy bedfellows. Regardless of anything else one might say of

the ontological status of the mind, inasmuch as it interacts with matter in a deterministic way (for

example, inasmuch as brain damage deterministically leads to damaged mental processes) or

inasmuch as mental processes cause actions that occur on a deterministic plane (such as, the

movements of our bodies) it is hard to avoid the conclusion that the mind is determined.27

Yet, it is also difficult for materialists to maintain a coherent position on free will. Karl

Fischer (1853), a professor of philosophy at Erlangen, brought this out in his criticism of Vogt

and other materialists: how is it possible, he asked, to accept both, as the materialists seem to do,

that the mind is entirely material and that human beings are masters over their voluntary actions?

How is it possible to accept that humans are responsible yet lack freedom? Some of this

inconsistency can be straightened out. Vogt was a staunch supporter of freedom in the political

realm, especially regarding the separation of church and state, indeed, arguing that the very

existence of a religious institutions is necessarily an impediment to freedom. Such a call for 25 Büchner, op. cit. 236. 26 Vogt, op. cit.27 See Montero (2006) for discussion. Today we would want to say “in as much as it interacts in a deterministic or probabilistic way” and revise the conclusion accordingly.

Page 18: Quoted in Breazeale (1982) file · Web viewReinhold’s goal was to systemize Kant and antecedents to his view about consciousness are found in the . Critique of Pure Reason., for

political freedom can be seen as consistent with deterministic views about the mind and indeed is

analogous to the type of freedom present day “compatibilists” argue for in defining freedom as,

for example, freedom from external constraints. However, on Fischer’s side, it also seems that

some of the motivation for Vogt’s atheism evaporates once we accept determinism. According

to Vogt, “every church, without exception, is as such a restriction of the free development of the

human spirit, and because I desire a free development of the human spirit in all directions and

without limits, I want no restraint on this freedom, and therefore I want no church.”28 Vogt’s

motivation for the elimination of the church is grounded in his belief in the value of freedom, yet

how, asked Fischer, is this value consistent with Vogt’s determinism? For the materialists, the

existence of free will, as it defies any scientific law and was seen as inimical to a scientific

picture of the world, must be rejected. The opponents to materialism, however, saw the rejection

of free will as undermining moral values and, as they saw faith as a valid route to knowledge,

were able to hold on to it. This brings us to the relation between faith and science.

More so than today, the debate over materialism focused on questions about the limits of

science and the role of religion in our understanding of the world. The materialists saw no need

for positing a world beyond that which is accessible to our senses, and where our senses leave

off, reason, they held, fills in. Even more, at times they professed the view that science has

definitely shown that there is no world beyond our senses. Vogt supported his position primarily

by pointing out what he saw were the untoward consequences of rejecting it: a devaluation of life

here on earth and the maintenance of a political order that depends on the coercive force of the

church. The church for him was the primary impediment to human freedom, which (his denial of

free will notwithstanding) he saw as necessary for underpinning morality, as necessary for

underpinning our ability to freely choose the right action.

28 Quoted in Gregory (1977), p. 193, from the stenographic report by Willheim Vogt, Carl Vogt, p. 66, n. 1

Page 19: Quoted in Breazeale (1982) file · Web viewReinhold’s goal was to systemize Kant and antecedents to his view about consciousness are found in the . Critique of Pure Reason., for

Büchner, though he presented similar reasons to reject the idea of suprasensual

knowledge, was also fond of another argument for the idea that there is no world beyond that

which we come to know through sense experience. His reasoning seems to be that because we

are “only a product of this world and of nature itself,” our experience of the world, “must mirror

and repeat the laws of nature.”29 Critics again pointed to what they saw as inconsistencies in this

picture, arguing that although the materialists call for social action and for individuals to right the

wrongs of society, their view leaves no room for right and wrong. Frederick Gregory, in his

delightful overview of nineteenth century German materialism, notes that this inconsistency was

perhaps brought out best Mathilde Reichardt in her letter to another of the central proponents of

materialism at the time, the physician Jacob Moleschott: “Sin [you claim] lies in that which is

unnatural—but where is there unnaturalness in a world in which each effect corresponds with

strict logical consequence to an endless series of causes, all of which themselves are based on a

natural necessity?”30

Rudolph Wagner (1854), who saw religious belief as a “new organ of the mind,” argued

for the view that faith and science must be kept as two distinct means of knowledge; where the

one treads, the other must not go. And like the materialists, Wagner’s arguments were based

primarily on the need to avoid the disastrous consequences of rejecting such a view. The natural

sciences, he agreed with the materialists, do not suggest an immaterial individual soul, and this is

why we need another form of knowledge, for the existence of an immaterial soul is indispensible

to the existence of morality (1854, p. 21). Lotze (1852) saw this as “a queer sort of double-entry

booking,” and “an unworthy fragmentation of our mental powers” (p. 36). And so the debate

went on.

29 Quoted in Gregory (1977), p. 113.30 Quoted in Gregory (1977), p. 48.

Page 20: Quoted in Breazeale (1982) file · Web viewReinhold’s goal was to systemize Kant and antecedents to his view about consciousness are found in the . Critique of Pure Reason., for

Though Friedrich Lange in his 1865 History of Materialism considered the

Materialismusstreit settled, looking back it seems an open question as to which side won. Lange

gives the anti-materialists the upper hand. Summing up Lange’s conclusion, Bertrand Russell, in

his 1925 introduction to the book, puts it like this: “there is no good reason to suppose

materialism metaphysically true; it is a point of view which has hitherto proved useful in

research, and is likely to continue useful wherever new scientific laws are being discovered, but

which may well not cover the whole field, and cannot be regarded as definitely true without a

wholly unwarranted dogmatism.” (Lange 1950, p. xix). All three of the prominent materialists

lost their jobs. And in 1872, the physiologist Emil Du Bois-Reymond took himself to be

speaking for the scientific community when he said that there is a fundamental limit to what

science can tell us about the world, proclaiming, Ignoramus et ignorabimus (we do not know and

we will never know). 31

The contemporary German philosopher, Michael Heidelberger (2007), however, suggests

a way in which the materialists were ultimately victorious. Despite what he sees as their

excesses, he thinks that it is fortunate that their criticism of Wagner’s double-entry bookkeeping

prevailed since it led to what he sees as the general positive attitude toward natural science in

Germany. “If the materialists had not won this battle,” as Heidelberger sees it, “the dispute over

the role of Darwinism in German secondary education that took place towards the end of the

nineteenth century…would not have ended as it did,” adding that “American ‘creationism’ is not

taken seriously by anyone—across all circles, and entirely independently of political creed or

ideology.”

31 The Mathematician David Hilbert later expressed his disagreement: “In opposition to the foolish ignorabimus our slogan shall be: ‘We must know — we will know!' [Wir müssen wissen — wir werden wissen!]” This was in 1930. In 1931, however, Gödel proved his famous incompleteness theorem, which might be interpreted as showing that Hilbert’s goal is impossible.

Page 21: Quoted in Breazeale (1982) file · Web viewReinhold’s goal was to systemize Kant and antecedents to his view about consciousness are found in the . Critique of Pure Reason., for

We are now quite a distance from what many today think of as standard philosophy of

mind, which sees itself as prescinded from religion and politics. Yet, perhaps one lesson we can

learn from the Materialismusstreit is that such issues are not always easy to pull apart.

4. Eduard von Hartmann's Theory of the Unconscious

Towards the end of the nineteenth century, the German novelist Friedrich von Spielhagen

captured the intellectual milieu, in describing a Berlin salon as fixated on two topics: Richard

Wagner’s opera Tristan und Isolde, which was thought to probe the depths of the unconscious,

and Eduard von Hartmann’s book, Philosophy of the Unconscious, which was thought to explain

it. Though discussions of Tristan und Isolde might be overheard today in cafes near Lincoln

Center after the curtain goes down, von Hartmann’s book has long faded from the limelight.

However, it was certainly in the limelight in the 1870’s. Friedrich Nietzsche (1872, p. 262), with

characteristic irony, put it this way: “In the entire world one does not speak of the unconscious

since, according to its essence, it is unknown; only in Berlin does one speak of and know

something about it, and explain to us what actually sets it apart.”32 What, then, was all the

brouhaha about?

It is of course not true that in the nineteenth century it was only in Berlin that theories of

the unconscious were being discussed in the salons in Germany; and it is also not true that it was

only von Hartmann’s work that provoked such discussions. For example, before von

Hartmann’s book came out, the zoologist polymath Carl Gustav Carus had been lecturing on the

unconscious in Dresden, taking the unconscious as the foundation of his theory of the mind.

“The key to understanding the conscious life of the soul lies in the realm of the unconscious,”

32Quoted in Nicholls and Liebscher, (2010) Thinking the Unconscious, (Cambridge University Press), p. 1.

Page 22: Quoted in Breazeale (1982) file · Web viewReinhold’s goal was to systemize Kant and antecedents to his view about consciousness are found in the . Critique of Pure Reason., for

Carus argued in his 1846 book, Psyche: On the Developmental History of the Soul, a book about

which von Hartmann commented was written with “senile long-windedness and verbosity.”33

However, it was von Hartmann’s perhaps also longwinded, near 1200 page tome that galvanized

the German public, going through nine editions between 1868 and 1884, and through its indirect

influence likely played a role in inspiring Freud’s theories about the unconscious, such as those

that appeared in 1900 in Interpretation of Dreams.

What was von Hartmann’s theory of the unconscious? What were so many chattering

about in the salons and smoke-filled cafes in Berlin in the 1870s? This is not at all an easy

question to answer, as von Hartmann acknowledges in an anonymously published criticism of his

own book wherein he faults the author for failing to define the central topic of inquiry.34

Nonetheless, let me attempt to highlight some of what I see as philosophically interesting about

his idea of the unconscious as well as his method for investigating it.35

Having completed his secondary education in 1858, the same year Büchner’s Force and

Matter was published, von Hartmann began developing his views on the unconscious at the

height of the Materialismusstreit, and his methodology, he claims, is thoroughly in line with

materialistic principles (an indication that, in the short run the victors of the Materialismusstreit

was at least seen by some as the materialists). As von Hartmann’s book’s subtitle, “Speculative

Results According to the Inductive Method of Physical Science,” indicates, he took the proper

method for philosophy to be empirical, to observe the world through our senses and to provide

the best possible explanation of such data. “[A] scientific hypothesis” he (1893b, p. 167) tells us,

“should never extend farther than the need of explanation requires.” Conclusions, as such, cannot

33 Quoted in Nicholls and Liebscher (2010) p. 15734 “Das Unbewusste vom Standpunkt der Physiologie und Descendenztheorie,” which along with other work, was added as a third volume to the tenth edition to Philosophie des Unbewussten. 35 This, however, might not line up with what people were talking about in the cafes, for the book, beside addressing the metaphysical nature of consciousness, has chapters on such things as sexual love, ambition, lust of power, vanity, domestic felicity, dreams and so forth.

Page 23: Quoted in Breazeale (1982) file · Web viewReinhold’s goal was to systemize Kant and antecedents to his view about consciousness are found in the . Critique of Pure Reason., for

be known with certainty, but, he thought, when reasoned through carefully, the precepts of his

book should be held with the same level of credence as any good scientific theory.

So far so good, however, what many later commentators took to be peculiar about his

project is just how far beyond the empirical he ultimately ventured.36 Quoting Arthur

Schopenhauer, von Hartmann (1893a, p. 57) says, “the materialists endeavor to show that all,

even mental phenomena, are physical: and rightly; only they do not see that, on the other hand,

everything physical is at the same time metaphysical.” And go beyond the physical—for this is

the intended sense of “metaphysical”—he does.

Von Hartmann, whose book was published ten years after Darwin’s Origin of the

Species, was, like Darwin, concerned with the appearance of teleology in the natural world.

How could instinctive behavior, reflex responses, and the body’s ability to repair itself be

purposive, yet not consciously so? What explains, von Hartmann (p. 79) wanted to know,

“purposive action without consciousness of the purpose.” Von Hartmann thought that Darwin

explained the transmission of traits, but not their existence in the first place (a view, as Sebastian

Gardner (2010) points out, that seems to imply his rejection of the theory of random mutation)

and the best way, he thought, to explain this was to invoke a metaphysical purposive

unconscious. Even in explaining intentional action, he thought, we need to posit some type of

unconscious purpose, for as he (p. 77) saw it, a decision to lift your finger depends on minute

muscular movements about which you are unaware, and in order to explain the purposiveness of

the intentional action, these minute musical movements must be purposive as well: “from the

necessity of a voluntary impulse at the point “P” it follows that the conscious will to lift the

finger produces an unconscious will to excite point “P.” In this way, conscious intention reduces

36 For example, Lange op cit. Von Hartman does draw a line, though, at least here: “The question might here be raised whether the atoms have a consciousness. However, I think that the data are all too lacking or any decision to be come to thereupon.” Vol 2, p. 183

Page 24: Quoted in Breazeale (1982) file · Web viewReinhold’s goal was to systemize Kant and antecedents to his view about consciousness are found in the . Critique of Pure Reason., for

to mechanical movements, which themselves reduce to something mental; “matter itself” von

Hartmann (1893b, p. 86) held, “is in essence nothing else whatever but unconscious mind.” We

are already a long way from the materialism of Vogt and Büchner and Moleschott. However,

Hartmann takes us even further.

From the “impossibility of a mechanical, material solution [to the problem of

purposiveness in nature] it follows that the intermediate link must be of a spiritual nature,” he

(1893a, p. 77) tells us. And the spiritual nature, according to von Hartmann, involves a synthesis

of Schopenhauerian blind impulse and Hegelian reason; beyond our world, according to von

Hartmann (1893c, p. 145), lies a unity of Will and Idea: “Will and Idea conceived in

metaphysical essential unity, actually suffice for the explanation of the phenomena presented to

us in the known world, they form the apex of the pyramid of inductive knowledge.”

And now we take the final plunge, for von Hartmann holds that “the Unconscious Will

and the Unconscious Idea coalesced to form the one universal spiritual world-essence,” yet

ultimately, because of the preponderance of pain over pleasure in the world, the existence of the

world is not a good thing. Making Schopenhauer seem veritably cheerful in comparison, von

Hartmann tells us (p. 125), “we have seen that in the existing world everything is arranged in the

wisest and best manner, and that it may be looked upon as the best of all possible worlds, but that

nevertheless it is thoroughly wretched, and worse than none at all.” Thus, humankind’s ultimate

purpose is to come to this realization, which will bring about the end of the world. As Sebastian

Gardner puts it, on von Hartmann’s view, “[t]he world is thus only a device for cancelling the

original synthesis of Will and Idea,” only a device for cancelling itself.

Lest I end on a pessimistic note, let me conclude with a comment from C. K. Ogen’s

1931 preface to von Hartmann’s book (p. xiii). This comment, I think, also sums up what is

Page 25: Quoted in Breazeale (1982) file · Web viewReinhold’s goal was to systemize Kant and antecedents to his view about consciousness are found in the . Critique of Pure Reason., for

most valuable about the work of the other philosophers I have addressed herein. If nothing else,

Ogen points out, we must admire von Hartman for “focusing the attention of the world on an

idea.”37

References

Breazeale, D. (1981). “Fichte's ‘Aenesidemus’ Review and the Transformation of German Idealism,” The Review of Metaphysics, Vol. 34 (3), pp. 545-568.

Breazeale, D. (1982). “Between Kant and Fichte: Karl Leonhard Reinhold's ‘Elementary Philosophy,’” The Review of Metaphysics, Vol. 35 (4), pp. 785-821.

Chomsky, N. (1993). Language and Thought. Wakefield: Moyer Bell.

Carus, C. G. (1864), Psyche: Zur Entwicklungsegeschichte der Seele (Pforzheim “ Glammer und Hoffmann).

Reinhold, K. L. (1790). Beyträge zur Berichtigung bisheriger Misverständnisse der Philosophen. Jena.

Fichte, J. G. (1930). Briefwechsel: Kritische Gesamtausgabe, ed. Schulze, 2nd Edition. Leipzig: Haessel.

Fichte, J. G. (1988). “Review of Aenesidemus,” in Fichte: Early Philosophical Writings, ed. Breazeale. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

Fischer, K. (1853), Die Unwahrheit des Sensualismus mit besonderer Rüchsicht auf die Schriften von Feuerbach, Vogt, und Moleschott bewiesen. Erlangen.

Forster, M. N. (1998). Hegel’s Idea of a Phenomenology of Spirit. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Gardner, S. (2010). “Eduard von Hartmann’s Philosophy of the Unconscious,” in Thinking the Unconscious: Nineteenth-Century German Thought, eds. Nicholls & Liebscher. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press.

Goldberg, I. I., Harel, M., and Malach, R. (2006). “When the Brain Loses Its Self: Prefrontal Inactivation during Sensorimotor Processing,” Neuron, Vol. 50 (2), pp. 329-339.

37 In von Hartman, E. (1972) Philosophy of the Unconscious; Speculative Results according to the Inductive Method of Physical Science, one volume edition (Westport, Connecticut: Greenwood Press Publishers) p. xiii

Page 26: Quoted in Breazeale (1982) file · Web viewReinhold’s goal was to systemize Kant and antecedents to his view about consciousness are found in the . Critique of Pure Reason., for

Gregory, F. (1977). Scientific Materialism in Nineteenth Century Germany. Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel Publishing Company.

Hegel, G. W. F. (1807/1977). Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. Miller. New York: Oxford University Press.

Hegel, G. W. F. (1830/1971). Hegel’s Philosophy of Mind: Being Part Three of the Encyclopaedia of Philosophical Sciences, trans. Wallace. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Hegel, G. W. F. (1830/1975). Hegel’s Logic: Being Part One of the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences, trans. Wallace. New York: Oxford University Press.

Hegel, G. W. F. (1907). Theologische Jugendschriften, ed. H. Nohl. Tubingen: J.C.B. Mohr.

Heidelberger, M. (2007). “Freedom and Science! The Presumptuous Metaphysics of Free Will Disdainers,” in Psychology’s Territories: Historical and Contemporary Perspectives from Different Disciplines, eds. Ash & Sturm. Mahwah, New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Inc. Publishers.

Johnston N. E., Atlas L. Y., and Wager T.D. (2012). “Opposing Effects of Expectancy and Somatic Focus on Pain” PLoS ONE, Vol. 7 (6): e38854. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0038854.

Kind, A. (2013). “The Case Against Representationalism about Mods,” in Current Controversies in Philosophy of Mind.

Kriegel, U. (2003). “Consciousness as Intransitive Self-Consciousness: Two Views and an Argument,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 33 (1), pp. 103-132.

Lange, F. A. (1950). The History of Materialism and Criticism of its Present Importance, trans. Thomas. London: Degan Paul, Trench, Trubner and Co. (Originally published in three volumes from 1877–1881.)

Levine, J. (2006). “Conscious Awareness and (Self-)Representation,” in Self-Representational Approaches to Consciousness, eds. Kriegel and Williford. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Lotze, R. H. (1852). “Medicinische Psychologie oder Physiologie der Seele,” (Leipzig: Weidmann).

Messina, J. (2011). “Answering Aenesidemus: Schulze’s Attack on Reinholdian Representationalism and Its Importance for Fichte,” Journal of the History of Philosophy, Vol. 49 (3), pp. 339-369.

Montero, B. (1999). “The Body Problem,” Noûs, Vol. 33 (2), pp. 183-200.

Montero, B. (2005). “What is the Physical?” The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind, Eds. Beckermann, McLaughlin & Walter. New York: Oxford University Press.

Page 27: Quoted in Breazeale (1982) file · Web viewReinhold’s goal was to systemize Kant and antecedents to his view about consciousness are found in the . Critique of Pure Reason., for

Montero, B. (2006). “What Does the Conservation of Energy Have to Do with Physicalism?” Dialectica 60:4 (2006), pp. 383–396.

Montero, B. (forthcoming). The Myth of ‘Just do It’: Thought and Effort in Expert Action. XX, Oxford University Press.

Nicholls and Liebscher, (2010) Thinking the Unconscious, (Cambridge University Press), p. 1.

Friedrich Nietzsche (1872-1874), Nachgelassene Fragmente, Sommer , Werke: Kritische Gesamtausgabe, part 3, vol. IV, ed. Giorgio Colli and Mazzino Montinari (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1978).

Reinhold, K. L. (1789). Versuch einer neuen Theorie des menschlichen Vorstellungsvermögens.

Rushton, J. (2006). Mozart. New York: Oxford University Press.

Russell, B. (1927/1961). An Outline of Philosophy. London: George Allen and Unwin.

Saul, J. (2013). "Implicit Bias, Stereotype Threat and Women in Philosophy,” in Women in Philosophy: What Needs to Change?, eds. Hutchison & Jenkins. New York: Oxford University Press.

Schellenberg, S. (2010). “The Particularity and Phenomenology of Perceptual Experience,” Philosophical Studies, Vol. 149, pp. 19-48.

Searle, J. R. (1983). Intentionality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Vogt, C. (1864). Lectures on Man: His place in Creation, and in the History of the Earth, edited by James Hunt (London: Longman, Green, Longman and, Roberts, Paternoster Row), lecture three.

von Hartmann, E. (1893a). Philosophy of the Unconscious; Speculative Results According to the Inductive Method of Physical Science, Volume 1, trans. by Coupland. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Tubner, & Co. Ltd.

von Hartmann, E. (1893b). Philosophy of the Unconscious; Speculative Results According to the Inductive Method of Physical Science, Volume 2, trans. by Coupland. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Tubner, & Co. Ltd.

von Hartmann, E. (1893c). Philosophy of the Unconscious; Speculative Results According to the Inductive Method of Physical Science, Volume 3, trans. by Coupland. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Tubner, & Co. Ltd.

von Hartman, E. (1972). Philosophy of the Unconscious; Speculative Results according to the Inductive Method of Physical Science, one volume edition (Westport, Connecticut: Greenwood Press Publishers) .

Page 28: Quoted in Breazeale (1982) file · Web viewReinhold’s goal was to systemize Kant and antecedents to his view about consciousness are found in the . Critique of Pure Reason., for

Wagner, R. (1854), Ueber Wissen und Glauben mit besonderer Beziehung zur Zukunft der Seelen. Fortsetzung der Betrachtungen über "Menschenschöpfung und Seelensubstanz.” (Göttingen: Wigand). First published in the Augsburg Allgemeine Zeitung on January 1, 1852. (pp. 18, 14f).


Recommended