+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Revisiting unitary psychosis, from nosotaxis to nosology

Revisiting unitary psychosis, from nosotaxis to nosology

Date post: 29-Jan-2017
Category:
Upload: domien
View: 219 times
Download: 3 times
Share this document with a friend
13
Vol. 35, No. 2, March-April 2012 101 Original artícle Salud Mental 2012;35:101-113 Revisiting unitary psychosis, from nosotaxis to nosology Carlos Rojas-Malpica, 1 Néstor de la Portilla-Geada, 1 Adele Mobilli-Rojas, 1 Danilo Martínez-Araujo 2 SUMMARY The concept of psychosis as known today comes from the late nine- teenth century, and was developed from ancient notions, such as in- sanity, alienation and dementia. Four dichotomies can be registered in the evolution of the concept: Psychosis vs. Neurosis, Unitary vs. Multiple, Functional vs. Organic, and Endogenous vs Exogenous. The purpose of this research is to rethink the issue of unitary psychosis from a new scientific and epistemological reading. Toward this objetive, the terms of nosotaxis, nosography and nosology are discussed, as well as the role of major classification systems of contemporary psychiatry. It also imposes a historical review of the concept from Aretaeus of Cappadocia to the present. Through a rigorous hermeneutic exercise, we discuss the problem of the positivist Kraepelinian conception of psychoses and its epistemological resolution through complex thinking theory, and chaos theory, with empirical reference to hallucinations and delusion as well as the biological basis of schizophrenia and bi- polar disorder, but emphasizing their common components. Essential to perform this exercise are theoretical developments from Bartolome Llopis and Henri Ey, enriched by the latest findings of neuroscience. It seems clear that mental illness is a loss of complexity, leaving little of the fresh and unexpected chaotic health behavior. While asserting the existence of a unitary psychosis is controversial with current available data, it is equally true that the assertion of a schizophrenia/bipolar disorder dichotomy is also difficult to sustain. However, the axial syn- drome common to all psychoses, Bartolomé Llopis´s brainchild, re- mains a fertile idea, as well as the concept of Henri Ey, to understand mental illness as a condition of loss of freedom. Key words: Unitary psicosis, hallucination, delusion, anankastic phenomena, nosology. RESUMEN El concepto de psicosis, tal como hoy se le conoce, viene del siglo XIX tardío, y fue elaborado a partir de nociones más antiguas, como insania, alienación y demencia. Se pueden registrar cuatro dicotomías en la evolución del concepto: psicosis vs. neurosis, unitaria vs. múltiple, funcional vs. orgánica y exógena vs. endógena. El propósito de la pre- sente investigación es replantear el tema de la psicosis única o unitaria desde una nueva lectura científica y epistemológica. Para ello se discu- ten los términos de nosotaxia, nosografía y nosología y el papel de los sistemas clasificatorios más importantes de la psiquiatría contemporá- nea. Se impone también una revisión histórica del concepto desde Are- teo de Capadocia hasta la actualidad. Por medio de un riguroso ejer- cicio hermenéutico, se discute el problema de la concepción positivista kraepeliniana de las psicosis y se plantea su superación epistemológi- ca desde el pensamiento complejo, la teoría de sistemas y la teoría del caos, tomando como referencia empírica las alucinaciones y el delirio, así como los fundamentos biológicos de la esquizofrenia y el trastor- no bipolar, pero haciendo énfasis en sus componentes comunes. Para realizar dicho ejercicio resultan fundamentales los desarrollos teóricos de Henri Ey y Bartolomé Llopis, enriquecidos por los más recientes hallazgos de las neurociencias. Parece evidente que en la enfermedad mental hay una pérdida de complejidad, quedando muy poco para lo fresco y caóticamente inesperado del comportamiento saludable. Aunque afirmar la existencia de una psicosis única resulta polémico con los datos disponibles en la actualidad, no es menos cierto que la afirmación categórica de una dicotomía esquizofrenia/trastorno bipo- lar también es difícil de sostener. Sin embargo, el síndrome axil común a todas las psicosis de Bartolomé Llopis, sigue siendo una idea fértil, como también la idea de Henri Ey de entender la enfermedad mental como una patología de la libertad. Palabras clave: Psicosis única, alucinación, delirio, fenómenos anancásticos, nosología. 1 Department of Mental Health, Faculty of Health Sciences, Universidad de Carabobo, Valencia, Venezuela. 2 Women’s Hospitalization Area, Dr. Carlos Arvelo” Military Hospital, Caracas, Venezuela. Correspondence: Dr. Carlos Rojas-Malpica, Departamento de Salud Mental, Facultad de Ciencias de la Salud, Universidad de Carabobo. Uslar 92-50, Urb. El Trigal centro, 2002-005, Valencia, Venezuela. E-mail: [email protected] Received: August 3rd, 2011. Accepted: October 28, 2011. EPISTEMOLOGICAL INTRODUCTION Nosological debate spans all the history of psychiatry and its offshoots. For the purposes of this article, we are more concerned with the concept of psychosis, and in particular, that of unitary psychosis. The concept of psychosis, as it is known today, comes from the late 19th century and was de- veloped from older ideas such as insanity, alienation and dementia. There are four distinct dichotomies in the evo- lution of this concept: psychosis vs. neurosis, unitary vs.
Transcript
Page 1: Revisiting unitary psychosis, from nosotaxis to nosology

Revisiting unitary psychosis, from nosotaxis to nosology

Vol. 35, No. 2, March-April 2012 101

Original artícle

Salud Mental 2012;35:101-113

Revisiting unitary psychosis,from nosotaxis to nosology

Carlos Rojas-Malpica,1 Néstor de la Portilla-Geada,1 Adele Mobilli-Rojas,1 Danilo Martínez-Araujo2

SUMMARY

The concept of psychosis as known today comes from the late nine-teenth century, and was developed from ancient notions, such as in-sanity, alienation and dementia. Four dichotomies can be registered in the evolution of the concept: Psychosis vs. Neurosis, Unitary vs. Multiple, Functional vs. Organic, and Endogenous vs Exogenous. The purpose of this research is to rethink the issue of unitary psychosis from a new scientific and epistemological reading. Toward this objetive, the terms of nosotaxis, nosography and nosology are discussed, as well as the role of major classification systems of contemporary psychiatry. It also imposes a historical review of the concept from Aretaeus of Cappadocia to the present. Through a rigorous hermeneutic exercise, we discuss the problem of the positivist Kraepelinian conception of psychoses and its epistemological resolution through complex thinking theory, and chaos theory, with empirical reference to hallucinations and delusion as well as the biological basis of schizophrenia and bi-polar disorder, but emphasizing their common components. Essential to perform this exercise are theoretical developments from Bartolome Llopis and Henri Ey, enriched by the latest findings of neuroscience. It seems clear that mental illness is a loss of complexity, leaving little of the fresh and unexpected chaotic health behavior. While asserting the existence of a unitary psychosis is controversial with current available data, it is equally true that the assertion of a schizophrenia/bipolar disorder dichotomy is also difficult to sustain. However, the axial syn-drome common to all psychoses, Bartolomé Llopis´s brainchild, re-mains a fertile idea, as well as the concept of Henri Ey, to understand mental illness as a condition of loss of freedom.

Key words: Unitary psicosis, hallucination, delusion, anankastic phenomena, nosology.

RESUMEN

El concepto de psicosis, tal como hoy se le conoce, viene del siglo XIX tardío, y fue elaborado a partir de nociones más antiguas, como insania, alienación y demencia. Se pueden registrar cuatro dicotomías en la evolución del concepto: psicosis vs. neurosis, unitaria vs. múltiple, funcional vs. orgánica y exógena vs. endógena. El propósito de la pre-sente investigación es replantear el tema de la psicosis única o unitaria desde una nueva lectura científica y epistemológica. Para ello se discu-ten los términos de nosotaxia, nosografía y nosología y el papel de los sistemas clasificatorios más importantes de la psiquiatría contemporá-nea. Se impone también una revisión histórica del concepto desde Are-teo de Capadocia hasta la actualidad. Por medio de un riguroso ejer-cicio hermenéutico, se discute el problema de la concepción positivista kraepeliniana de las psicosis y se plantea su superación epistemológi-ca desde el pensamiento complejo, la teoría de sistemas y la teoría del caos, tomando como referencia empírica las alucinaciones y el delirio, así como los fundamentos biológicos de la esquizofrenia y el trastor-no bipolar, pero haciendo énfasis en sus componentes comunes. Para realizar dicho ejercicio resultan fundamentales los desarrollos teóricos de Henri Ey y Bartolomé Llopis, enriquecidos por los más recientes hallazgos de las neurociencias. Parece evidente que en la enfermedad mental hay una pérdida de complejidad, quedando muy poco para lo fresco y caóticamente inesperado del comportamiento saludable. Aunque afirmar la existencia de una psicosis única resulta polémico con los datos disponibles en la actualidad, no es menos cierto que la afirmación categórica de una dicotomía esquizofrenia/trastorno bipo-lar también es difícil de sostener. Sin embargo, el síndrome axil común a todas las psicosis de Bartolomé Llopis, sigue siendo una idea fértil, como también la idea de Henri Ey de entender la enfermedad mental como una patología de la libertad.

Palabras clave: Psicosis única, alucinación, delirio, fenómenos anancásticos, nosología.

1 Department of Mental Health, Faculty of Health Sciences, Universidad de Carabobo, Valencia, Venezuela.2 Women’s Hospitalization Area, “Dr. Carlos Arvelo” Military Hospital, Caracas, Venezuela.

Correspondence: Dr. Carlos Rojas-Malpica, Departamento de Salud Mental, Facultad de Ciencias de la Salud, Universidad de Carabobo. Uslar 92-50, Urb. El Trigal centro, 2002-005, Valencia, Venezuela. E-mail: [email protected]

Received: August 3rd, 2011. Accepted: October 28, 2011.

EPISTEMOLOGICAL INTRODUCTION

Nosological debate spans all the history of psychiatry and its offshoots. For the purposes of this article, we are more concerned with the concept of psychosis, and in particular,

that of unitary psychosis. The concept of psychosis, as it is known today, comes from the late 19th century and was de-veloped from older ideas such as insanity, alienation and dementia. There are four distinct dichotomies in the evo-lution of this concept: psychosis vs. neurosis, unitary vs.

Page 2: Revisiting unitary psychosis, from nosotaxis to nosology

Rojas-Malpica et al.

Vol. 35, No. 2, March-April 2012102

multiple, functional vs. organic and exogenous vs. endog-enous.1 The term “unitary psychosis” itself is derived from the German einheitpsychose. It is known in Spanish as both “psicosis única” and “psicosis unitaria.” The term has been used to mean several things: a) to refer to the idea that there is just one kind of psychosis, b) resulting from impairments to an invariable structure, and c) that clinical differences are pathoplastic effects of personal and environmental compo-nents.2 The debate on this issue is far from settled. For the Cambridge School, the concept of unitary psychosis refers to the collective denomination of a group of distinct doc-trinal positions, whose central idea is that there is only one form of psychosis, whose myriad clinical expressions can be explained by the action of endogenous and exogenous pathoplastic factors.3

Classificatory proposals, which have varied over time, such as the APA’s DSM and the WHO’s ICD, are designed to simplify and improve scientific communication, unify cri-teria, and shorten distances between the many theoretical positions. Such proposals receive strong criticism from dif-ferent points of view, resulting in the need to make multiple adjustments over the course of time. While they are taken as atheoretical models, they all retain some element from the botanical naturalist classifications of Linnaeus’s time. Clas-sifications must be understood as transitory models that express representations of clinical reality with virtues and defects, carrying the ideological and cultural markings of the spaces in which they are produced. So they are not to be seen as geologically consistent truths from which we might derive indisputable results. It is important this distinction be noted, given that (on behalf of these proposals) research of all kinds (clinical, epidemiological, biological, psycho-pharmacological, neurobiological, etc.) has been conducted, which tends to be presented as indisputable truth, ignoring the fact that their basis is epistemiologically lax.3,4 We must recall that the “disorders” described in the DSM are not nat-ural structures; nor are they discrete entities with no relation to other conditions. Rather, they are “groupings which are agreed upon based on algorithms, symptoms, and behaviors that disable the individual to a varying degree, and whose classification does not amount to an etiopathogenesis”. In addition, “not only are they compatible with the ideas that gave birth to the theory of unitary psychosis, but also they require these ideas be reestablished in many aspects (etiopathogenetic, clinical, therapeutic, and rehabilitational, among others)”.5 A more humble approach would be to ac-cept that there are no findings to be heralded as Truth, but only credible knowledge to be debated, as we see in the rest of the health sciences.

In light of this debate, it is appropriate that we revive three commonly used terms in medicine: nosography, noso-taxis and nosology. The common Greek origin of these terms is nosoç (nosos), which means disease. According to the Spanish Royal Academy Dictionary (translated to English)6

nosography is the part of nosology that deals with the clas-sification and description of diseases. However, it would be more accurate to say that nosography deals with description of disease, while nosotaxis deals with classification, although “nosotaxis” does not appear in the aforementioned diction-ary. In reality, all three activities are inseparable, as they all form part of a diagnosis (from the Greek diagnostikoç), while remembering that said concept has been expanded to multiaxial and idiographic diagnosis.7 When we speak of mental disease or disorder, we are conducting nosogra-phy, as it is necessary to describe the symptoms through which such disease manifests itself. Likewise, we are also conducting nosotaxis, in stressing that the central and com-mon point to these disturbances is the mental impairment by which they are classified. Furthermore, we must also conduct nosology, because everything will be accompanied by an effort to explain and/or understand the relationships between symptoms and the personal, biological, genetic, emotional, experiential, social and psychological substra-tum that make these symptoms possible. In this way, the most inclusive practice of all is nosology, through which the clinician seeks to grasp the logic inscribed in nature, which explains the disturbance or condition.8,9 But logic requires nuance. Contemporary scientific debate admits that not all processes can be understood through the mechanistic logic that drives the natural sciences, born and structured within the positivism of modern times, now criticized and ques-tioned by complexity theorists and systems theory.10,11 The innovation, as well as the difficulty, of complex thought, is that it does not aspire to eliminate contradiction, obscurity or uncertainty, but rather establishes these things as basic elements of the order/disorder of nature. We cannot ignore the chaos of madness (and nor can we assume they are syn-onymous). On this level of reflection, psychiatry must be heteroclite and heterological, that is, it must take its logical framework from both natural and spiritual sciences (het-erological), while also assuming that among its subjects of study (in this case, subjectivity and its processes of disease), at times cannot be understood when combined in adherence to common standards, and so expressed only through lan-guage and metaphor (heteroclite). To perform nosography, statistics and frequency analysis have often been used. In following research that is based on a supposedly “atheoreti-cal” model (as is the DSM), one runs the risk of defining the disease by its symptoms and the frequency with which they appear, and not by its structure. So we must advise that the most important thing is not necessarily that which is repeat-ed, but that which is indispensable for the support of the structure. In no way is a disease more completely described by referencing the frequency with which its symptoms ap-pear, as opposed to that which is essential to its process. It was toward this end that Karl Jaspers, making use of the phenomenological method, defined his general psychopathy. Therefore, mere symptomatological alliteration must not

Page 3: Revisiting unitary psychosis, from nosotaxis to nosology

Revisiting unitary psychosis, from nosotaxis to nosology

Vol. 35, No. 2, March-April 2012 103

be confused with phenomenology, as the latter seeks and proposes to arrive at the essential and/or structural which cannot be achieved through simple analysis of frequency. It is for this reason that the clinician must make use of herme-neutic rigor to interpret the symbolic processes and contents that structure the psyche, which cannot be understood by conventional readings.

Other terms which deserve attention from a nosologi-cal angle include that of “spectrum” and “comorbidity.” The former seems to derive from physics. When a beam of light is projected, one part can be seen as clearly illuminated, while another is faded, ending with darkness. This paral-lel with light would indicate that many nosological entities overlap along the edges, in many cases becoming indistin-guishable. An example of these blurry edges lies in the con-cept of borderline. Regardless of whatever truth there may be in these assessments, the real difficulty lies in the fact that most of the time the resemblance is in the clinical core and not in the periphery, as we will discuss later with regard to bipolar disorder and schizophrenia. In this regard, it is very likely that there is more overlapping between disease and health than there is between mental disorders themselves. So, the term “spectrum” can also be confusing, both for its intentions and for the reality it seeks to describe. The psy-choanalytic definition of spectrum, proposed by Tutte, is very interesting. He posited that “at one end are disorga-nized, invasive and paralyzing conditions, and at the other are conditions which are close to normalcy.” Between these ends there are all kinds of intermediary situations, condi-tions that produce effects of greater or lesser mental harm, including more or less mild states forming symptoms in the organization of neurosis, to that which is corresponds to veritable gaps in symbolization, which can lead to the psy-chic silence of psychosis.12

With regard to “comorbidity,” there are a few critical points to be made. When we treat a bipolar patient with a severe personality disorder and abuse of addictive drugs, must we consider this person to suffer from three or four “comorbid” pathologies? Or is it more accurate to consid-er that the entire condition comes from a common thread, which our nosotaxic parceling does not allow us to see? Can it be that the patients we so often see suffer from schizophre-nia, anxiety disorder, depression and obsessive compulsive disorder? Is the terrible anxiety suffered by our depressive patients “comorbid,” or is it as central as the deep sadness they experience? We will try to discuss these questions in more detail later in this article.

The need to measure, weigh, and quantify the “facts” of science, as well as the exclusion and confiscation of sub-jectivity have been imposed restrictively since the times of Auguste Comte.13 We can state that traditional scientific pos-itivism epistemologically governs the better part of biomed-ical research. However, thanks to psychoanalysis, phenom-enology, existential analytics, medical anthropology, and

other qualitative developments, we have managed to open a space for subjectivity in medical research, and (in particu-lar) in psychiatry. Thanks to this knowledge we have a her-meneutic tool that allows us to better penetrate psychotic existence, without which neither communicative efforts nor therapeutic relationships would be possible. Today, it is ac-cepted that the data from positivist research are useful in explaining many biological regularities. However, they are insufficient when used to analyze more complex phenom-ena, such as human behavior and its myriad determinations. This occurs because the linear mathematical systems lose their predictive capacity in the complex systems that require the logic established in Chaos Theory.14 According to Edgar Morin and his theory on complexity, the positivist method presents us with a reality that is cut into slices, which while producing knowledge, also produces ignorance. So, the alternative to the simplistic, reductionist and disjunctive thinking of positivism, must be complex thought.15

HISTORY Of THE CONCEPTOf UNITARY PSYCHOSIS

The notion of unitary psychosis began much earlier than the founding of psychiatry as a medical specialization, dating back to the 1st century in the work of Aretaeus. Bartolomé Llopis affirms that the Cappadocian suggested a fundamen-tal form of madness (melancholy) from which all other forms derived.16 The approach is complex. Let us follow an already fruitful path to understand this history.17 If we seek to define this concept in a simple way, we could say that he affirms that the different psychotic conditions represent no more than different levels of intensity of the same fundamental disorder. It was in the 18th century that Vincenzo Chiarugi (1759-1826) wrote, in 1793, his famous “Della pazzia.” It is important to note that the term “pazzia” is the equivalent to madness in English, and he used this word despite the fact that in Italian the word for insanity did exist.18 This Italian author, unjustly criticized by Pinel, proposed that “mad-ness” follows an evolution that spans from melancholy to mania, and from mania to dementia.

Heinrich Neumann (1814-1884), who is considered by some to be the “father” of unitary psychosis, said in his Leh-rbuch der Psychiatrie, published in 1859: “There is one sole form of psychic impairment, we call it madness (das Irresein). Madness does not have different forms, but rather different stages, which are called: the delirious stage (der Wahnsinn), mental confusion (die Werwirtheit) and mental breakdown (der Biodsinn).”19

Georget EJ (1795-1828), one of the disciples of Esquirol, defined madness as “an idiopathic brain disorder, whose symptoms can vary greatly.” This definition appeared in “De la folie”, which was published in 1819, and translated by Heinroth to German just one year later.20 It had signifi-

Page 4: Revisiting unitary psychosis, from nosotaxis to nosology

Rojas-Malpica et al.

Vol. 35, No. 2, March-April 2012104

cant influence on psychiatrists such as Zeller, who was later a teacher to Griensinger and Neumann, the latter of whom became the most passionate defender of the paradigm of unitary psychosis in Germany. Hence the famous phrase at-tributed to this Berliner, that “mental diseases are diseases of the brain,” also attributed by some authors to Georget.21

Another francophone author, the Belgian Guislain J (1797-1860), believed that all mood disorders were a result of one morbid excitement of one’s sensitivities (feelings), which constitute the origin of all mental pathology. He greatly in-fluenced German psychiatry, which at the time was still governed by knowledge developed on the other side of the Rhine, although not long after this was to change radically.

It was through Albert Zeller (1804-1877), a teacher of Griesinger, that the concept of unitary psychosis became German. The consolidation of the idea of unitary psychosis was enshrined in a text by Griesinger W (1817-1868), written in 1845 when the author was just 28 years old, which quite soon became the most important psychiatry book of its time. The “Pathology and Therapy of Mental Diseases” would be translated to French in 1864, to English in 1867, and to Spanish by 1880, later seeing many subsequent releases in all these languages, evidence of its broad influence.22 There would be questioning of this hypothesis, one of the most im-portant being the concept of “paranoia,” a term which was proposed by Kahlbaum.

According to Lanteri-Laura, “until the middle of the 19th century, all the world followed the paradigm of abso-lute unitary psychosis, and the works of JP Falret and oth-ers were what opened the door to the idea of a plurality of mental conditions.”23

Also in France, and almost simultaneously, in 1854, two prominent “alienists” used the names “folie circulaire” (Fal-ret JP) and “folie à double forme” (Baillarger) to describe the entities which later would be detached from the root of unitary psychosis and Kraepelin would subsequently call “manic-depressive madness.” Later, the enormous in-fluence of the classificatory work of Emil Kraepelin was what finally buried (although not entirely, which we will discuss later) the old idea of unitary psychosis.24 However, it was also Kraepelin who in 1920 wrote: “No experienced diagnostician can deny that the cases in which it is impos-sible to make a clear decision are lamentably frequent.”24 It was words like these which brought Angst to affirm, per-haps somewhat boldly, that “it is very likely that Kraepelin would have changed his concept of this dichotomy had he lived longer.”25

Given these cases of difficult distinction, Eugen Bleuler spoke of “mixed psychoses” while Kurt Schneider used the term “cases in the middle.”26 Kretschmer even affirmed that “close to half of all psychotic patients suffer from mixed psychoses.”27 Schule showed the existence of cases that be-gin as manic-depressive, and end as schizophrenic, as well as the other way around.

In 1928, the Spanish psychiatrist Sanchís Banús high-lighted the conceptual difficulties in separating dementia praecox from manic-depressive psychosis. Five years later, the American psychiatrist Jakob Kasanin (1933) coined the term “schizoaffective psychosis” to refer to these cases of mixed symptoms, in what Alarcón called the first American contribution to psychiatric nosography.28

Without a doubt, in the Spanish-speaking world it was Barolomé Llópis who most distinguished himself in defend-ing the paradigm of unitary psychosis. He did so from the disadvantaged position he occupied due to his political con-victions in Spain during the 1940s. Based on his observations on the mental pathology of patients with pellagra, he devel-oped his theory on the axial syndrome common to all psychoses. His book continues to be, more than half a century later, an extraordinary example of psychopathological science, and so has been revived for new generations in a new release. Here we might recall Kuhn TS (1962), who has shown us the desti-ny of paradigms in the sciences, while Lanteri-Laura indicates that something always survives from the replaced paradigm.

Flor-Henry, in 1969, studying schizophreniform and af-fective cases in patients with epilepsy, found himself unable to differentiate clinically between the schizophrenic and manic-depressive cases, while also finding something very interesting: a greater incidence of epileptic foci in the domi-nant hemisphere in the first group, and in the non-dominant hemisphere in the second. This was confirmed by many au-thors, as Trimble points out.29

The paradigm of unitary psychosis, as we can see, re-emerges in the 21st century, and for many reasons. “Thus we return to the possibility (never fully abandoned) that the brain mechanisms underlying the occurrence of psychotic symptoms are shared, and that the value of the symptom-atology must be established based on the function of the pa-tient, not the condition,” as Baca affirms.30

We find authors such as Menniger, Ellenberger and Pruiser, who hypothesized that neuroses and psychoses are different stages of dyscontrol.31 On the other side of the world, in the Soviet Union, Gannushkin PB, one of the lead-ing figures of the so-called Moscow School of Psychiatry, in a classic monograph from 1931, affirmed that there was a continuum between neuroses, psychopathic personalities and psychoses.32

Hueso Holgado states: “These proposals are important in understanding how psychotic episodes can occur in peo-ple whose normal functioning is neurotic, or that of a per-sonality disorder, as I believe there is a continuum between the psychotic and neurotic.”33 Also Peralta et al.34 described psychoses as continual processes in a schizoaffective spec-trum. Or, is it possible to admit that a patient suffers from schizophrenia and bipolar disorder as comorbid entities?

For Villagrán, authors like Bonhoefer, Hoche, Kretschmer, Conrad, Ey, Menninger, Rennert, Janzarik, can be considered unitarists in one way or another. To this list we can add Ber-

Page 5: Revisiting unitary psychosis, from nosotaxis to nosology

Revisiting unitary psychosis, from nosotaxis to nosology

Vol. 35, No. 2, March-April 2012 105

rios, Timothy Crow and Robin Murray. The master of Bon-neval, Henri Ey, proposed that all mental disorders result from changes in the longitudinal axis (diachronic) or trans-versal axis (synchronic) of the structures of consciousness.35 Likewise, Timothy Crow as well as Murray and Duta36 af-firm on multiple occasions that there is a continuum in psy-choses, proposing that “we accept that the neo-Kraepelinian vision that schizophrenia and bipolar disorder are totally distinct entities is not supported by available scientific evi-dence.” To this we must add that spoken by Renato Alarcón: “It is, in reality, impressive that the dichotomy that underlies the apparent clinical separation between schizophrenia and bipolar disorder has survived almost a century.” Similarly, Murray and Duta go so far as to affirm that the history of psychiatry can be seen as the story of efforts made to over-come the notion of unitary psychosis. Other authors agree that the results of research conducted are inconsistent with the classification of psychoses, and in some cases, as with Craddock and Owen,37 they offer that current classifications inhibit both research and clinical practice. This statement coincides surprisingly with the words of Heinrich Neu-mann, written in 1854, more than a century and a half ago: “We cannot believe in the true progress of psychiatry be-fore making the decision to throw away all classifications.” In the field of psychology, the unitary theory has also had its distinguished followers, such as Hans Eysenck, of the Maudsley Hospital, and Gordon Claridge, from Oxford.38

However, Emil Kraepelin had a very interesting thought which deserves to be studied carefully. In their ex-tensive study on this author, Berríos and Hauser39 say that in his “Research Programme” from 1897, Kraepelin already proposed a plan for the classification of psychoses, which he developed from 1896 to 1898. Very soon he incorporates the problem of the evolution in the classification of psychoses, announcing that he had found a new way to study mental disease, describing early predictors of the clinical course. The Kantian category of time enters the door to psychiatry through the work of Kraepelin. Diagnosis was a way to un-derstand the connections between the clinical case and the underlying anatomical impairment. With his procedure, he wanted to link etiology, pathology and symptomatology. For Berríos and Hauser, contemporary psychiatry lives in a “Kraepelinian world”. The authors translate to English an extensive paragraph from his work, which reads as follows:

“¿... to what extent and with what clinical methods can we understand with the greatest clarity the manifestations of madness? The symptoms and signs that correspond to the base conditions are extraordinarily varied, which implies that the conditions preceding the process must have been complex. Even when external agents are clearly involved (for example, an injury to the head or intoxication)... there is a group of forces working in the mechanism: the nervous system of the affected individual, the deficit inherited from past generations, and their own personal history... these

prior conditions are especially important in considering the manifestations of the disorder that are not derived from ex-ternal injuries, but from the circumstances of the individual in question... it seems absurd to propose that syphilis causes patients to believe they are the proud owners of cars... and not that the general desires of people are reflected in these delusions... if these observations approach the truth, we will have to seek the key to understanding the clinical case pri-marily in the characteristics of the individual patients... be-cause their expectations play a defining role.”

The work of Berríos and Hauser, and the writings of Kraepelin, not only illustrate the depth of their thinking, but also give important epistemological clues for the clinical practice that they propose in their time. On the one hand, they want to integrate the personal history of the patient in the interpretation of the psychopathological phenomenon. This anthropological approach should not surprise us, com-ing from an author who was one of the first to conduct trans-cultural psychiatric studies. On the other hand, Krae-pelin does not seem to feel satisfied with the psychopatho-logical exploration techniques, as they do not allow him to articulate with the underlying condition. We believe that the study of the representations, with the most recent findings provided by neurophenomenology and the neurosciences, together with systems theory and in consideration of chaos, represents a good chance at transcending the epistemiologi-cal obstacles that hinder Kraepelinian research, as well as articulating the issue of the “underlying impairment” with clinical practice in treating disease and its pathoplastic ex-pression.40 We will touch on this in the next section.

THE REPRESENTATIONS APPROACH

Reading a text from Michael Trimble,41 we come across this phrase from Lombroso: morbus totius substantiae, which could be translated as the total essence of the disease or as the disease is the essence of all. We mention this because when speaking of unitary psychosis, we are grasping for nothing less than the total essence of mental illness, which in Latin, Greek, German, Spanish and French can be written as: “totum essentiam mentis morbum”, “to su1nolo thç ousi1aç thç yucikh1ç asqe1neiaç”, “die gesamte Substanz der Geisteskrankheit“, “la esencia total de la enfermedad mental” and “le produit total de la maladie mentale”, respectively. Now, among the clinical entities of psychia-try, which of them contain the greatest amount of the sub-stance we are after? We believe there would be a consensus that schizophrenia and bipolar disorder best answer this question. Unitary and dichotomous classifications contain within their structure the greatest expression of the whole of mental illness. Following this inevitable circumlocution, we can add that for the ancient Greeks, the human body is apomimesis tou hólou, that is, a copy of everything, imitation of the universe, which is very much in keeping with the

Page 6: Revisiting unitary psychosis, from nosotaxis to nosology

Rojas-Malpica et al.

Vol. 35, No. 2, March-April 2012106

theoretical postulates of complexity and its hologramatic principle, which affirms that “not only is the part in every-thing, but also everything is in the part.” That being said, let us study “the parts” that contain the greatest amount of the whole that makes up the psychoses, which, in our opinion, together with autism and fear of death, are hallucinations and delirium.42,43

In traditional psychology, the concept of representation accepts a certain polysemy. It is thus that the apprehension of an immediately present object can be understood, as oc-curs in perception, but also the reproduction in the aware-ness of a past perception; likewise, the representation can be made to anticipate a future event, which brings it toward imagination.44 In some cases, there is a poietic representa-tion, through which reality is resemantized with novel subjective additions and, in intense contrast with that real-ity, there is the mineralized representation that character-izes hallucinations. For Wittgestein, the best representation must share a structural or logical form similar to reality, bringing it closer to the isomorphic conceptions whose best empirical expressions are found in mathematics and chem-istry. Ricoeur distinguishes between image and memory, for which he proposes an appropriate eidetic analysis.45 It is based on Husserl and his terms Vorstellung, Bild and Phantasie. Here, Vorstellung is equivalent to representation, Bild corresponds to the presentifications that describe some-thing indirectly, like sculptures and paintings; while when speaking of Phantasie one thinks of the angels and demons of legend, thereby tying the concept to fiction and beliefs. In any case, past events tend to become present as something already perceived or lived by the subject, or to the contrary, it is not recognized as one’s own. If hallucinations and de-lirium must be admitted as representations, then we must immediately point out a deficient piece of data regarding the majority of cognitive representations: they fail to adhere to what Kant refers to as triple subjective synthesis, consist-ing of traversing, joining and recognizing, which guarantees the cohesion and appropriation of what is perceived.46

Representing is not understanding, but it is a prior and important step toward understanding reality. In the process of understanding, the represented is assimilated and en-riched by consciousness, until it becomes part of the Ego. For Plato, ideas and things are not the same. Ideas belong to the reign of Being, while things have been created by a demiurge to the image and likeness of ideas. These kinds of considerations have given rise to a debate on the relation-ships between the concepts of eidólon, eikón and phantasia, that is, between the world of ideas and concepts, icons and the imagination, or fantasy. Although some debate whether representations were a subject of discussion in the world of the ancient Greeks, Foucault’s research seems to show that they were. In effect, when he examines the spiritual exercis-es recommended by the stoic emperor Marcus Aurelius, in his Meditations, he finds a recommendation “that the object

that we represent and capture in its objective reality, pass through description and definition, to the thread of suspi-cion, of the possible accusation, of the moral reproaches, of the intellectual relationships that dissipate illusions, etc.”47

To capture the objective contents of the representation, it will then be necessary to have a moment of both eidetic and onomastic meditation. In our words, we would say that the exercise recommended by Marcus Aurelius requires a lucid and self-critical awareness, not to be fooled by the first perceptive instant, and to examine the object until trans-forming the perception into an apperception, where the guarantee of having arrived at the truth is achieved when reflection drives and forms part of the Reason that presides over and organizes the world. To represent, then, is a mental activity that requires the integrity of the processes that make consciousness possible, which ought to be studied through the light of contemporary neuroscience.

For their part, Crick and Koch48 propose aspects of great relevance in understanding the so-called Neural Correlates of Consciousness. On the one hand, they are concerned with very quick reaction times, of an order that goes from mil-liseconds to a handful of seconds, in which there is only the possibility of already-developed behaviors, which the frontal area of the cortex seems, in large measure, to control, where some inputs from the sensory zones activate stereo-typical and unconscious responses, which for their speed do not require significant conscious elaborations. This in-dicates that a large part of the frontal activity runs and is dedicated to unconscious processes. On the other hand, they propose that the main function of the sensory cortex consists of constructing and utilizing detectors for specific traits or qualities, like those that are activated for orientation, move-ment, and facial recognition. In this way, we could affirm that most of the sensory and motor activities are already made and available throughout the cerebral cortex, by way of global prior representations.49 For Libet, nearly one half sec-ond must pass in order for a situation to be registered in the consciousness, so that we are we unaware of certain behav-iors, as the unconscious brain has carried them out.50 It is not necessary, for example, for an animal to explore between a wide variety of behavioral possibilities in order to know that there is a predator and that it is at risk. Instead, immediately the unconscious neural registries are consulted, leading to fight or flight behaviors. It is not only a matter of emotional or flight responses that are innate or learned, but also of neuronal groups of niches where unconscious behaviors are stored, which are very necessary for the preservation of the species and the perfection thereof among individuals. Crick and Koch speak even of an unconscious homunculus and of “zombie modes” that can be seen as cortical and structured unconscious reflections, such as rapid and stereotypical re-sponses. It is accurate to use the word zombie, a word of Haitian origin, which is used to refer both a person who is supposedly dead, but that has been revived by witchcraft,

Page 7: Revisiting unitary psychosis, from nosotaxis to nosology

Revisiting unitary psychosis, from nosotaxis to nosology

Vol. 35, No. 2, March-April 2012 107

as well as to designate an automated behavior in a subject with a certain level of alteration in consciousness, which at the same time appears void of voluntary initiative and vivid reflections in behavior. The zombie metaphor makes sense, because if, effectively, all behavior were not illuminated with the living light of consciousness, it would seem to be a kind of neuromotor robot. Consciousness is achieved much more slowly and with broader and less stereotypical sen-sory input, often configured in images, and it takes longer to decide between thoughts and appropriate responses that require complex processes. This process of conscious quali-fication of the different sensory nuances and its progressive complexity is a progressive trait, which, within phylogenetic evolution, leads up to the homo sapiens sapiens. Phylogenesis is characterized by increasing complexity, subjectivity and individuality. In fact, in the so-called half-conscious, driven by thalamocortical activation, when a task is performed that requires effort and attention, we find spontaneously co-ac-tivated neural structures that are coordinated in space and time, of the kind called prior global representations by Chan-geux, in such way that we can affirm that most sensory and motor activities are already made and available throughout the cerebral cortex. It must be admitted that there are visual, auditory, tactile, olfactory, motor, linguistic, mathematical, and aesthetic representations of different levels of complex-ity, which are constantly adjusted in the personal organiza-tion of the subject. Some are psychomotor and/or cognitive habits whose automation and availability save the subject some effort, allowing him energy for other realizations, while others require an autopoietic completion that implies contrasting prior representations to process novel behavior-al emergencies, which involve several levels of initial chaos, as well as new possibilities for organization of life and of the person. As such, we accept with other authors that percep-tion, hallucination, and delirium, as well as other cognitive and neuromotor activities, are representations, and that, as such, they cannot be considered as conceptually opposed categories, while they can be differentiated. But we also rec-ognize that all representations imply the joint activation of complex cortical connections related to thought, language, and imagination, and at a vertical and deeper level, of the regions that regulate and harbor needs, drives, and desires. Research by Kandel51,52 on memory and its neurobiological basis, refers to processes relating to ontogenesis. However, research on the human genome shows that there is a vast genetic heritage shared between the homo sapiens sapiens and other living beings. The effect on behavior of certain genotypic and phenotypic attributes is understood, as well as their relationships with neuroplasticity and the environ-ment, but we still know very little about the effect that the common heredity of our species can have on the symbolic products of the individual. The way we see it, Sarró’s ap-proach to the issue of delirium, which he considered to be expressive mythologems of the universal fears and desires of

the human race, which feed both delirium and myth, means they can also be considered to be archetypal representations whose neurobiological basis is only beginning to be un-derstood.31,32,53,54 Téllez-Carrasco says that the “archetypal” voice comes originally from Saint Augustine, who uses it in his work De Div Quest, and is an explanatory periphrasis of the Platonic eidos. Jung later used it in his famed theory of the collective unconscious. For Téllez-Carrasco, “archetypes would be symbols that shine through the same forms to re-veal the vitality in time and in space, and I suggest naming them with the neologism timofanías.”55

The hallucinatory phenomenon had been considered, since Esquirol, as a “perception without an object.” The def-inition had not been substantially modified until recently Alonso-Fernández questioned Esquirol’s idea in affirming that “the hallucination is anything but a perception with-out an object, because it is not a perception and it does have an object (...). Contrary to the activity of sensoperception, which comes from the outside to the inside, in its capacity as the centripetal mental function par excellence, the hallucina-tion is produced by objectivizing a mental image, provid-ing it with sensoriality, and then projecting it outward, in brief, an objectifying projection, in a distinctly centrifugal way.”56 In addition, today it is accepted that there are hal-lucinatory phenomena in healthy subjects, which are related to certain personality traits, including imagination.57 Like-wise, one aspect of the hallucinatory phenomenon has been brushed aside, that which was indicated by Falret JP, in La Salpêtrière, from 1864, where he states: “hallucinations of the insane refer only to one sense, to an object or an identi-cal series of objects. To the contrary, in dreams, fantastical perception of absent things cannot be predicted, they occur at random, with no discontinuity, and in the field of all the senses... hallucination, this perception without an object, or, if you prefer, this rumination of sensations...”58

That is to say, dreams present a subjective richness that is absent in the hallucinatory phenomenon, which consti-tutes a distinctive and fundamental piece of information in the semiology of both states. The phenomenology of hallu-cinations is best described as the rumination of sensations, as Falret so correctly calls it. We can conclude with Amaral, that hallucinations would be representations equipped with all the characteristics of normal perception, including the power of convincing us of the existence of the represented object,59 although it must be stressed that the most significant differences would be subjective richness, the greater level of complexity of conscious phenomena, and the sensation of the ego in control, all which characterize the representations of lucid consciousness.

From England, Hughlings Jackson began to propose a Darwinian reading of the phenomenon of delirium: “the disease only causes the physical condition for the negative element of the mental condition; the positive element, that is, delirium, obviously an elaborate delirium, as absurd as

Page 8: Revisiting unitary psychosis, from nosotaxis to nosology

Rojas-Malpica et al.

Vol. 35, No. 2, March-April 2012108

it may be, means activity of the healthy available nervous system, it means evolution moving toward what remains intact of the highest cerebral centers.”60 Later, in the times of the great clinical structures, the neo-Jacksonian theory pro-posed by Henri Ey only considered psychotic or delirious hallucinations to be true hallucinations, which constitute a free and positive aspect, a product of a global destructuring of the activities of the neo-cortex, which has as a negative trait the loss of the ability to distinguish between reality and the interior fantasy that makes hallucination possible. In this way, for Ey it is not a matter of simple cortical irritation, nor of the projection of a repressed affection in the unconscious, but one of a very complex alteration that severely impacts the subject and restricts his/her freedom.

The topic of delirium has been subject to many different reflections. We know that the term was coined by Chiarugi in 1795, defining it as a disturbance in the ability to judge or as a feverless fantasy with no alteration in consciousness. A formal description of delirium is later developed by Jaspers, in 1913, who in addition to indicating the impossible content of delirium, insists on its character of absolute evidence and its incorrigibility by way of logical argument or experience.61 Other authors have insisted on the primary or derived char-acter of the delirious experience, from which comes the de-scription of the delirious occurrence or feeling, delirious cog-nition, and delirious perception. The problem of the genesis and understanding of delirium is also debated, referring to the possibility of understanding delirium based on a specific experience that changes radically throughout the life of the subject, or if to the contrary, it is a matter of a primary expe-rience, not derived from any other, which would allow us to speak of primary and secondary delirium. Another debate on the problem of delirium consists of understanding it as a separate entity, with clearly defined compartments within mental activity, or if, to the contrary, these boundaries are blurred with passions, fantasies and beliefs. Clearambault insisted on the automatic character of the delirious phenom-enon. In obsessive disorders, the patient is besieged by in-trusive thoughts which are perceived as having come from outside the desire and intention of the Ego, but in so-called psychic hallucinations, there is a true xenopathic emanci-pation, by which thoughts become foreign, strange, inter-vened, imposed, intercepted, published, stolen, divulged; the boundaries of the Ego are confused and mental activity seems to come from another place; there is no clear separa-tion between what comes from outside by way of the senses, and what is developed within, in one’s personal privacy. In Clérambault’s mental automatism syndrome, there is a true amalgamation between delirium and the hallucinatory phe-nomenon. Acoustic-verbal hallucinations, such as impera-tive phonemes, talking voices, enigmatic words and hearing one’s thoughts, become structured as a whole in delirium, until being broken down in the final stages of schizophrenic disorder.62 Amaral performs an interesting exercise63 in es-

tablishing the debate between delirious perception and ap-perception. But the perspectives of Castilla del Pino and of Dörr Zegers must also be highlighted, who used very differ-ent methodological means to arrive at similar conclusions on the function of delirium. The former proposes that de-lirium would have an orthopedic function for a starved and ill-structured Ego, while the latter, wanting to see beyond the disease, considers that delirium can be another human possibility through which a person transforms an unbear-able existence into a different less painful reality.64

In our case, we are interested in studying the phenome-non by which delirium comes to install itself at the center of the life of the patient, as a mineralized representation of the world of himself, until structuring most of his behavior and his life, which we propose be called anankastic representa-tions, clarifying that this concerns a separate approach that in no way seeks to diminish or discount different possible approaches to this phenomenon. Diachronic study of the topic shows that said anankastic representation comes from a series of prior phenomena, such as Griesinger’s pre-de-lirium, the primary experience of Moreau de Tours, or Con-rad’s trema, until the delirium constitutes a unitary world in the conscious mind.64,65 To understand the phenomenon, it seems to us that Llopis’ idea is fundamental, regarding the fact that nature does not have different laws for producing similar phenomena, in such way that the delirium and the hallucinations that are observed in different clinical entities, must obey one pathogenetic mechanism, and so, “thought disorders and perception disorders are not, in reality, quali-tatively different, but just means of expressing the different levels of intensity of a disorder.”

Thanks to brain research techniques like fMRI and SPECT imaging, electronic microscopes, histochemistry, etc., the neurobiological basis of hallucinations is better un-derstood. A decrease in the activity of the left dorsolateral prefrontal cortex, together with the activation of some areas of the sensory cortex, seem to be the most notable traits of this process. In any case, what must be stressed is that what is activated in the hallucinatory phenomenon is a sensory network carrying a threatening signal to the patient, which is only possible because it has left his/her control. Every-thing points to this being a matter of representations that are presentified before a conscious mind that does not recognize them as its own, because they have evaded the coinciding detection mechanism for afferent and re-entrant signals that support conscious perception, according to the findings of neuroscientists. This is a critical finding for this debate, and so neurophysiology must take on the issue of representa-tions, the storing of information, engrams, and the recogni-tion of the constitutive memories of the individual.66

Processes of simulation and supervision intervene in the many states of consciousness that allow global access to the past, present and future. The subject is not only receiv-ing stimuli from their environment, to which they respond

Page 9: Revisiting unitary psychosis, from nosotaxis to nosology

Revisiting unitary psychosis, from nosotaxis to nosology

Vol. 35, No. 2, March-April 2012 109

from their brain with the innate patterns encoded in their genome, but they are also an agent that makes new reali-ties and behaviors. They are a poietic and autopoietic fac-tor. And for that reason they have dignity. In the dialogue regarding genetic traits, environment and the constitution of the epigenetic, consciousness and neuroplasticity are fun-damental.67 In order for everything to work harmoniously, a balance of activity is needed between the sensory and primary motor cortex and the association areas scattered throughout the cerebral cortex which, it would seem, are organized from the prefrontal cortex. The constructs con-tained in prior representations must be reviewed at every chance and undergo some circumstantial adjustment or pro-found transformation, as the case may be. This is a process of metacognition through which the mind examines its own contents, in a similar way to that recommended by Mar-cus Aurelius in his exercises from the 2nd century. When a pathological situation alters this process, the constructs can become raw material for hallucinations and delirium. The autopoiesis is interrupted and the mental dynamic is trapped by anankastic representations. Crick’s zombies, the prior representations of Changeux, or Téllez’s timofanías, now independent from the Ego, imposed automatically on a conscious mind that cannot differentiate them from reality, thus constitute a symptomatic expression of what we have called mental illness, anánkẽ.68

Authors that study the relationships between chaos and health propose, contrary to prevalent thinking, that health has a high level of uncertainty, in the same way that a lack of variability and physiological and behavioral chaos leads to a mineralization of the possibilities of existence, just as occurs in most mental disorders. As such, new therapeutic strategies must not regularize the behavior of the patient on the level of his anánkẽ, but rather increase his repertoire of lost complexity, transforming psychiatry into a true science of liberty, as Henri Ey once proposed.69

THE bIOLOGICAL fUNDAMENTSOf THE PROPOSAL

The Kraepelinian desire to link symptoms to the “underlying disorder” is ongoing. Today it has been suggested that the correlation between biological variables with psychological dysfunctions, as well as the existence of basic units in psy-chopathology in so far as common nuclei between different disorders that show different clinical manifestations, seems to be more appropriate for classification in psychiatry. How-ever, we must not forget that the history of the patient and their cultural experiences have a fundamental pathoplastic value, as Kraepelin himself acknowledged. From the neuro-biological point of view, it is well established that the there are signs of alterations in the metabolism of the neurotrans-mitters that are not specific to any disorder, which rather are

related to psychopathological dimensions of certain speci-ficity. In this same way, functional psychopharmacology is in line with the approach of said dysfunctions, and inevita-bly will lead to the use of combinations of useful drugs in different disorders.70

While nosography still holds a place of privilege in psy-chiatry, it is itself a guide that can become complicated. The syndromic organization of current psychopathology has been shown to have faults. It is believed that a functional organization in this area could be more appropriately used as a reference framework for research in biological psychia-try, with proposals for a two-tiered diagnostic system. On the first tier we would find the nosological diagnosis, while the second would include a detailed description of the psy-chological and biological components of the dysfunction, together offering a way to deal with what has become a problem in the area of psychiatry, which has been called, rather ironically, nosologomania.71 These criteria support our proposition regarding the need to read the findings of psychopathological and clinical research from a new episte-miological point of view.

New systems have been proposed for grouping the different psychiatric disorders, based on aspects such as the presence of common genetic findings, the existence of similar biomarkers, comorbidity, and response to the same family of medications. Taking into account these proposals, it is clear that schizophrenics share more dimensions with bipolar disorder than with other mood disorders.72 More recent psychopharmacological research offers evidence that drugs originally proposed for treatment of schizophrenia, such as olanzapine and quetiapine, are not prescribed for so-called drug-resistant depression.73,74 In the same way, other medications initially used for epilepsy are now indicated as mood stabilizers.75,76 Likewise, the so-called “Attenuated Psychotic Symptoms Syndrome,” which is proposed for the new DSM-V, seems to respond better to preventive treat-ment with SSRIs than with antipsychotics.4 This all points toward a common pathogenetic mechanism that places the separate entities of the nosotaxis in doubt.

A strong and significant overlap has been found in bio-markers such as the slow tracking eye movement, sensory openness (P40), prepulse inhibition, the reduction of P300 and a neural synchronization defect both in schizophrenia and in bipolar disorder.77,78,79,80 Although Del-Ben, Rufino Armanda, Brandão Fragata et al.81 have used instruments allowing them to hone the ability of the clinician to make differential diagnoses in the first psychotic episodes, their efficacy is clearer in episodes induced by drug abuse. It is possible that with their instruments one can better distin-guish between the different etiologies in the severe stages of the disorder, but without a doubt, a very similar response has been activated in all cases. Similarly, Mauricio Kunz, Keila Maria Ceresér, Goi Pedro Domingues et al.,82 find biologi-cal data on inflammatory and immunological activity that

Page 10: Revisiting unitary psychosis, from nosotaxis to nosology

Rojas-Malpica et al.

Vol. 35, No. 2, March-April 2012110

seems to differ between schizophrenics and those suffering from bipolar disorder, which could indicate a rather severe expansion of the underlying impairment, which regardless can exist in both cases, and so can result in false negatives.

Different structures have been indicated, sharing com-mon aspects, both for schizophrenia and for bipolar disor-der, especially the tonsil, the hippocampus, and above all the prefrontal dorsolateral cortex, the supraorbital cortex, and the anterior cingulate cortex.83 In these structures, alterations have been described, such as differences in blood flow,84 hippocampal dysfunction that produces an impairment in declarative memory with hypoactivity of the dorsolateral prefrontal cortex and variable dysregulation of the anterior cingulate cortex, as well as the prefrontal cortex, which ex-plains the alterations in abstract thinking, mental flexibility, and the initiation of an activity, as well as a dysfunction in the ventrolateral cortex.85 In both entities a decrease has been noted in the cerebral volume, with diminished gray matter, evidenced in observable changed in imaging studies such as nuclear magnetic resonance and FMR.86-93

Epidemiological and biological evidence, both of schizophrenia and bipolar disorder, indicates more coinci-dence than difference. It has already been shown that there is evidence of common basic neurobiological processes for both disorders, but equally important is the evidence that indicates a common genetic susceptibility, which would explain the alterations in neurodevelopment and brain my-elination, as well as those observed in brain functions such as sensory discrimination and visuospatial orientation.94

Likewise, recent epidemiological studies also highlight common components, making it ever more evident that the diagnostic division between schizophrenia and bipo-lar disorder is unable to define different etiological and/or pathophysiological entities. Large epidemiological studies, as well as recent genetic studies, reinforce the strong con-nection between these disorders.95,96

In studies conducted with bipolar subjects that had psy-chotic symptoms, a relationship to the genome was suggested in the 8p and 13q chromosomes, which have been implicated in prior research both on schizophrenia and bipolar disor-der. In other association studies for bipolar subjects with psy-chotic symptoms and subtypes such as bipolar patients with psychotic symptoms incongruent with mood have shown weak positive results for several potential dysbindin genes, DAOA/G30, DISC-1 and neuregulin. This is consistent with the hypothesis that subphenotypes of bipolar psychotic pa-tients can represent a clinical manifestation of genes overlap-ping between schizophrenia and mood disorders.97

Specific common genes, or loci, have been implicated in both disorders. The evidence suggests an overlap in the genetic susceptibility between traditional systems of classi-fication that dychotomize psychotic disorders into schizo-phrenia and bipolar disorder. The most notable findings are the genes DAOA (G72), DISC1 and NRG1. Identifica-

tion of genes that make individuals susceptible to psycho-sis will surely have a large impact on our understanding of pathophysiology, leading to changes in classifications and clinical practice.98 More recently, studies have compared the risk variant to the gene ZNF804A, rs1344706, finding it able to invoke susceptibility for both disorders, where homozy-gous subjects showed a reduction in the cortical gray matter in the superior temporal gyrus and in the anterior and pos-terior cingulate cortex.99

In a large study involving some 36,000 subjects with schizophrenia and 40,500 with bipolar disorder, it was found that immediate family members (parents, siblings and offspring) of both groups had an increased risk for both conditions. If a patient suffered from schizophrenia, his/her siblings were nine times more likely to suffer bipolar disor-der and four times more likely to suffer schizophrenia. Half siblings with the same mother were 3.6 times more likely to suffer schizophrenia if their half sibling had schizophrenia, and 4.5 times more likely to suffer bipolar disorder. Half siblings with the same father were 2.7 times more likely for schizophrenia and 2.4 times more likely for bipolar disor-der. Adopted children with a biological father with either of the disorders had a significant risk for the other disorder. This leads to the conclusion that both shared and unshared environmental factors contribute to risk, but to a lesser ex-tent than genetic predisposition.100

In an extensive association study conducted by the In-ternational Schizophrenia Consortium, the genomes of 3,322 Europeans was compared to 3,587 control subjects, showing the extent to which common genetic variations underlie the risk of suffering schizophrenia. They found the major his-tocompatibility complex on chromosome 6, as well as chro-mosome 4 related to cognition and 11 related to perception, indicating that there is genetic evidence for a polygenetic component for the risk of suffering schizophrenia, which in-volves thousands of common alleles of very little effect. This component also contributes to the risk of suffering bipolar disorder, but not for other non-psychiatric disorders.101

All these findings lead us to consider that the relation-ship between schizophrenia and bipolar disorder could be described either as two pathologies that present a high level of overlap, or as a continuum that presents one common nu-cleus of genetic, neurochemical, and structural susceptibil-ity.102 Some authors103 suggest that as a model of the relation-ship between schizophrenia and bipolar disorder, extended endophenotypes should be established, which, based on a common genotype, would share one neuroanatomy, one physiopathology and certain cognitive impairments that would present a particular clinical manifestation. Other authors104 have come to suggest that the current model of schizophrenia includes multiple phenotypically juxtaposed syndromes and that, as such, the unitary concept of schizo-phrenia may have come to an end, meaning we must con-figure the known facts on genomic, environmental, endo-

Page 11: Revisiting unitary psychosis, from nosotaxis to nosology

Revisiting unitary psychosis, from nosotaxis to nosology

Vol. 35, No. 2, March-April 2012 111

phenomic and phenotypic dimensions to identify groups of etiopathologically significant and empirically demonstrable entities. It can be concluded that the findings described on the relationship between schizophrenia and bipolar disor-der constitute a challenge for the conception that they are unrelated diagnostic entities. These disorders represent a continuum of deficits in neurodevelopment influences both genetically and environmentally, more than etiologically separate entities.105 Major clinical syndromes, in part for the severity and for the predominant pattern of abnormal brain development, result in functional deficits, modified in turn by other genetic and environmental factors.106,107

Current classifications are based on symptoms and ig-nore etiology. It is said that these classifications have a high level of reliability, an uncertain validity, and a variable util-ity. Biological criteria must be established for the current diagnostic entities. The biological variables and the endo-phenotypes established could validate the diagnostic enti-ties following quantitative and qualitative methods. There is no doubt that contemporary neurosciences are close to bringing clinical practice to identify the “underlying impair-ment,” as Kraepelin desired. But psychiatry does not read symptoms as they do in neurology, a more topographical and synchronic discipline, where the relationships are clear-ly established between injury, symptom and sign. Access to the experiential world of the patient requires, in addition to an understanding of his/her body, a diachronic exercise that reveals the meanings and their value in the subjectivity of the patient. In summation, it is a matter of a hermeneutic with a higher level of complexity.

fINAL REfLECTIONS

Affirming the existence of a “unitary psychosis” would be a controversial act given the clinical and neurobiological data we have reviewed. However, the proposal of Llopis regard-ing the axial syndrome common to all psychoses (in plural, and so multiple), seems to us an idea that sheds a lot of light on the phenomenon, and one that is not theoretically exhausted. In the same way, it seems difficult to construct clinical structures as separate entities by virtue of recent research. At best, the solution would be to do more nosology and less nosotaxis.

The historical approaches toward unitary psychosis indicated by Berríos have in common their basis on a natu-ralist focus on the phenomenon, inherent to the positivism so present in the sciences, even today. From this perspec-tive, everything points to an enormous symptomatological, biological and even therapeutic overlap between schizo-phrenia and bipolar disorder. However, another episte-miological possibility is opened by way of systems theory, chaos theory, and complex thought. This is how we want to suggest the possibility of a new reading of psychopatho-logical phenomena, as a tension between the stochastic and

the anankastic, which underlies many biological and social happenings. Both in health and in disease, many processes coexist, which are inherently linked to life. Apostosis must occur, while neuroplasticity and neurogenesis must occur at the same time. Using complex thought, it is easier to under-stand and accept the dynamics of programmed regularities and emerging chaos.

Although from a mechanical and determinist point of view, there are strong reasons to think that human be-havior is overdetermined by cerebral biological conditions, we cannot deny the processes which lead to the forming of self-consciousness and that occur in the connection between the sociodependent internal circuits and the so-called “exo-brain,” represented in the myriad symbols that circulate in our culture and that allow us to “conceive” objects, unlike signs and signals, which only announce them. This is rel-evant, because Bartra believes that there is found the seed of our own free will, which he believes to have a miniscule representation in the entirety of our behavior.108 So, it bears mention the importance of the hermeneutic effort in inter-preting this symbolic world, and its value for the under-standing of the psychotic existence. Although the so-called “free will” has a quantitatively miniscule share of overall behavior, its specific weight in the organization of subjectiv-ity is enormous and fundamental. In some way we could see it as the apex of the processes of autopoiesis that lead to the expression of subjectivity, arrested by the anankastic impositions of the psychotic process.

We believe that in the psychotic structure of world, men-tal life is anchored to some anachronic place of the physis, from which it is anankastically regulated and subjected to a progressive sclerosis that suspends the autopoietic systems. It is a process where the many expressions of the entropic (en-ergy seeking to organize itself) end up absorbed by a mineral-izing structure, leaving very little for the fresh and chaotically unexpected of healthy behavior. It is evident that in mental illness there is a loss of complexity. As such, nineteenth cen-tury positivism must be transcended if the search for mental health seeks to arrive at a restitution of subjectivity with all its richness. An understanding of these phenomena will result in new therapeutic practices, both psychosocial and biological, and psychiatry will come closer to the concept of the science of liberty, as Henri Ey once proposed.

REfERENCES

1. Berríos G. Historical aspects of psychoses: 19th Century issues. Br Med Toro 1987;43(3):484-488.

2. Berríos G. Unitary psychosis in English speaking psychiatry: A concep-tual history. En: Fur und wider die einhetspsychose. Mund C, Saβ H (eds). Gerog theme Verlag. New York: Stuttgart; 1992.

3. Berríos G. The notion of unitary psychosis: a conceptual history. History Psychiatry 1994;5(17):13-36.

4. Hueso-Holgado H. Riesgo del síndrome de síntomas psicóticos atenua-dos en DSM-V. Norte Salud Mental 2011;IX(39):19-26.

Page 12: Revisiting unitary psychosis, from nosotaxis to nosology

Rojas-Malpica et al.

Vol. 35, No. 2, March-April 2012112

5. Santo-Domingo J. La psicosis única en la actualidad: de H. Ey y B. Llopis a la ICD-10 y la DSM-IV. Arch Neurobiol 1998;61(3):175-186.

6. Real Academia Española. Diccionario de la Lengua Española (DRAE). Madrid: Espasa Calpe; 2001.

7. Mezzich J, Berganza C, Ruiperez M. Culture in DSM-IV, ICD-10, and Evolving Diagnostic System. Psychiatric Clinics North America 2001;24(3):407-419.

8. Laín E. La medicina hipocrática. Madrid: Ediciones de la Revista de Oc-cidente; 1984.

9. Moya J. Psicosis única y trastornos del lenguaje. Rev Asoc Esp Neurop-siq 1998;XVIII(66):219-234.

10. Morin E. El pensamiento complejo. Barcelona: Editorial Gedisa, SA; 2003. 11. Letelier J. Los derroteros científicos De Francisco Varela. Biol Res

2001;34(2):7-13. 12. Tutte J. ¿Es posible una psiquiatría dinámica? Aportes desde el psicoa-

nálisis. Rev Psiquiatr Urug 2010;74(2):139-158. 13. Comte AU. Discurso sobre el espíritu positivo. Editorial Aguilar: Buenos

Aires; 1975. 14. Romanelli L. Teoría del caos en los sistemas biológicos. Rev Argent Car-

diol 2006;74:478-482. 15. Morin E. La epistemología de la complejidad. CNRS, París, Fuente:

Gazeta de Antropología Nº 20, 2004 Texto 20-02. http://www.ugr.es/~pwlac/G20_02Edgar_Morin.html, available at: www.pensamiento-complejo.com.ar

16. Llopis B. La psicosis única, escritos escogidos. Fundación Archivos de Neurobiología. Madrid: Editorial Triacastella; 2003.

17. De la Portilla Geada N. Psicosis única en la actualidad. Salud Mental 2010;33(2):107-109.

18. Huertas R. Nosografía y antinosografía en la psiquiatría del siglo XIX: En torno a la psicosis única. Rev Asoc Esp Neuropsiquiatr 1999;XIX(69):63-76.

19. Benitez I. La evolución del concepto de hebefrenia (primera parte). Alc-meon.1992;2(2):182–205. Available at:: http://www.scielo.org.mx/scielo Org/php/reflinks.php

20. Zilboorg GG. Historia de la psicología médica. Buenos Aires: Librería Hachette SA; 1945.

21. Villagrán J. Psicosis: Análisis histórico y conceptual. Revista Gallega Psi-quiatría Neurociencias 1997;1:9-25.

22. De la Portilla N. Reseña histórica de las traducciones en psiquiatría. Va-lencia, Venezuela: Ediciones de la Universidad de Carabobo; 2003.

23. Lanteri-Laura G. Ensayo sobre los paradigmas de la psiquiatría moder-na. Madrid: Editorial Triacastela; 2000.

24. Kraepelin E. Die erscheinungs formen des irresseins. Z Gesamte Neurol 1920;62:1-29.

25. Angst J. Psychiatric diagnosis: the weak component of modern research. World Psychiatry 2007;6(2):94-95.

26. Arenas A, Rogelis A. Revisión de la historia del trastorno esquizo-afec-tivo y su relación con los rasgos de personalidad. Universitas Médica 2006;47(2):47-56.

27. Kretschmer E. Gedankenüber die fortentwicklung der psychiatrischen systematik bemerkungen zu vorrstehender abhandlung. Z Gesamte Neurol Psychiatr 1919;48:317-371.

28. Alarcón R. When the paradigms languish. World Psychiatry 2007;6(2):97-98. 29. Trimble MR. The psychoses of epilepsy. New York: Raven Press; 1991. 30. Baca B. Lo psicótico. Historia conceptual de las psicosis. En: Trastornos

psicóticos (ed). Barcelona, España: Ars Médica; 2007. 31. Meninger K, Ellenberger H, Pruyser P, Mayman M. The unitary concept

of mental illness. Bull Menninger Clin 1958;22:4-12. 32. Lavretsky H. The Russian concept of schizophrenia. A review of the lite-

rature. Schizophr Bull 1998;24(4):537-557. 33. Hueso Holgado H. Psicosis histéricas o trastorno disociativo psicóti-

co. El problema de la nosología psiquiátrica. Academia Biomedicina Digital. 2008:34(1-8). Available at: http://dialnet.unirioja.es/servlet/articulo?codigo=2877424. Access date: August 13, 2011.

34. Peralta V, Basterra V, Zandio M, Cuesta M. Psicosis cicloide; etiopato-genia, características clínicas y nosología. Ediciones 1: Aula Médica Psi-quiatría; Mexico: Grupo Aula Medica; 2008.

35. Crow TJ. A continuun of Psychosis, one human gen, and not much else-the case for homogeneity. Schizoprh Res 1995;(2):135-145.

36. Murray R, Dutta R. The right answer for the wrong rehaznos. World Psychiatry 2007;6(2):93-94.

37. Craddock N, Owen M. Rethinking Psicosis: the disadvantages of a dicotomus classification now outweigh the advantages. World Psychiatry 2007;6(2):84-91.

38. Claridge G. Lecture of the Annual Conference in Cardiff. Psychologists 2006;19(11):656-658.

39. Berríos G, Hawser R. The early development of Kraepelin’s ideas in clas-sification: a conceptual history. Psychological Medicine 1998;18:813-821.

40. Rojas-Malpica C. Las alucinaciones y el delirio como representaciones anancásticas. Salud Mental 2010;33:379-387.

41. Trimble MI. The soul in the brain; the cerebral basis of language, art, and belief. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press; 2007.

42. Rojas-Malpica C. El enfermo mental ante la muerte; Estudios clínicos de antropología psiquiátrica. Valencia, Venezuela: Ediciones del Rectora-do; Universidad de Carabobo; 2002.

43. Marina JA. Anatomía del miedo. Barcelona, España; Editorial Anagrama SA; 2007.

44. Ferrater-Mora J. Diccionario de filosofía. Barcelona, España: Ariel; 2004. 45. Aristegui-Urkia I. La intencionalidad en la representación mental: Esbozo

de dos modelos. Citado 2008 feb. 08. Available at: http://www.sc.ehu.es/yfwtahum/web/N.4/8.%20Aristegi.pdf. Access date: February 8, 2008.

46. Ricoeur P. La memoria, la historia, el olvido. Buenos Aires: Fondo de Cultura Económica; 2000.

47. Foucault M. La hermenéutica del sujeto. Madrid: Akal SA; 2005. 48. Crick F, Koch C. A framework for consciousness. Nature Neuroscience

2003:6(2):119-126. 49. Changeux JP. El hombre de verdad. México DF: Fondo de Cultura Eco-

nómica; 2005. 50. Libet B. Mind time; The temporal factor in consciousness. Harvard: Har-

vard University Press; 2004. 51. Kandel E. A new intellectual framework for psychiatry. Am J Psychiatry

1998;155:457-469. 52. Kandel E. Biology and the future of psychoanalysis: A new intellectual

framework revisited. Am J Psychiatry 1999;156:505-524. 53. Soto-Sedek JM. Consideraciones en torno al delirio y otras psicosis. Ca-

racas: Fundación Editorial el Perro y la Rana; 2007. 54. Sarró R. Análisis temático de los delirios endógenos. Rev Psiquiatr Psicol

Med Eur Am Lat 1987;18(2):65-79. 55. Téllez-Carrasco P. Las timofanías, arquetipos de la vitalidad. Revista

Psiquiatría Psicología Médica Europa América Latina 1979;14(3):197. 56. Alonso-Fernández F. La objetivación alucinatoria: una alternativa entre

la vulnerabilidad psicopatológica y la estética comunicativa. Psicopato-logía 2006;26(3-4):69-103.

57. López A, Paíno M, Martínez P, Inda M et al. Alucinaciones en pobla-ción normal. Influencia de la imaginación y la personalidad. Psicothema 1996;8(2):269-278.

58. Lanteri-Laura. Las alucinaciones. México DF: Fondo de Cultura Econó-mica; 1994.

59. Amaral M. Alucinações: a origem e o fim de um falso paradoxo. J Bras Psi-quiatr 2007;56(4):296-300. Serial on the Internet. Available at: http://www.scielo.br/scielo.php. Access date: April 1, 2010.

60. Berríos G, Fuentenebro de Diego F. Delirio; Historia. Clínica. Metateoría. Madrid: Trotta SA; 1996.

61. Dörr O. Psiquiatría antropológica. Santiago de Chile: Universitaria; 1997. 62. De Clérambault GG. Automatismo mental. Buenos Aires: Polemos; 2004. 63. Amaral M. Alucinações: a origem e o fim de um falso paradoxo. J Bras

Psiquiatr 2007;56(4):296-300. 64. Castilla del Pino C. El delirio, un error necesario. Oviedo: Nobel, SA; 1998. 65. Conrad K. La esquizofrenia incipiente. Madrid: Fundación Archivos de

Neurobiología; 1997. 66. Díaz J. Persona, mente y memoria. Salud Mental 2009;32(6):513-526. 67. González Valenzuela J. Genoma humano y dignidad humana. Barcelo-

na: Anthropos; 2005.

Page 13: Revisiting unitary psychosis, from nosotaxis to nosology

Revisiting unitary psychosis, from nosotaxis to nosology

Vol. 35, No. 2, March-April 2012 113

68. Rojas Malpica C, Gómez-Jarabo G, Villaseñor S. La enfermedad mental como anánkẽ. Inv Salud 2004;6(3):159-164.

69. Ey H, Brisset B. Tratado de psiquiatría. Barcelona: Toray-Masson; 1969. 70. Andrews G et al. Consistency of diagnostic thresholds in DSM-V. Aust

N Z J Psychiatry 2010;44(4):309-313. 71. Van Praag HM. Two-tier diagnosis in psychiatry. Psychiatry Res

1990;34(1):1-11. 72. Andrews G. 164th Annual meeting. Honolulu, Hi: American Psychiatric

Association; 2011. 73. Shelton RC, Williamson DJ, Corya SA, Sanger TM et al. Olanzapi-

ne/fluoxetine combination for treatment-resistant depression: a con-trolled study of SSRI and nortriptyline resistance. J Clin Psychiatry 2005;66(10):1289-1297.

74. Bauer M, El-Khalili N, Datto C, Szamosi J et al. A pooled analysis of two randomised, placebo-controlled studies of extended release quetiapine fumarate adjunctive to antidepressant therapy in patients with major depressive disorder. J Affect Disord 2010;127(1-3):19-30.

75. American Psychiatric Association. Practice guideline for the treatment of patients with bipolar disorder (revision). Am J Psychiatry 2002;159(4 supl.):1-50.

76. Smith LA, Cornelius V, Warnock A, Bell A et al. Effectiveness of mood stabilizers and antipsychotics in the maintenance phase of bipolar disor-der: a systematic review of randomized controlled trials. Bipolar Disord 2007;9(4):394-412.

77. Hong LE, Mitchell BD, Avila MT, Adami H et al. Familial aggregation of eye-tracking endophenotypes in families of schizophrenic patients. Arch Gen Psychiatry 2006;63(3):259-264.

78. Sánchez-Morla E, García-Jiménez M, Barabash A, Martínez-Vizcaí-no V et al. P50 sensory gating deficit is a common marker of vulne-rability to bipolar disorder and schizophrenia. Acta Psychiatr Scand 2008;117(4):313-318.

79. Swerdlow NR, Light GA, Cadenhead KS, Sprock J et al. Startle gating deficits in a large cohort of patients with schizophrenia: relationship to medications, symptoms, neurocognition, and level of function. Arch Gen Psychiatry 2006;63(12):1325-1335.

80. Bramon E, McDonald C, Croft R, Landau S et al. Is the P300 wave an endophenotype for schizophrenia? A meta-analysis and a family study. Neuroimage 20051;27(4):960-968.

81. Del-Ben C, Rufino C, Teixeira B, Azevedo-Marques J et al. Diagnóstico diferencial de primeiro episódio psicótico: importância da abordagem otimizada nas emergências psiquiátricas. Rev Bras Psiquiatr [periódi-co na Internet]. Available at: http://www.scielo.br/scielo.php. Access date: April 8, 2011.

82. Kunz M, Ceresér K, Goi P, Fries G et al. Serum levels of IL-6, IL-10 and TNF-α in patients with bipolar disorder and schizophrenia: differences in pro- and anti-inflammatory balance. Rev Bras Psiquiatr (periódico na Internet]. Available at: http://www.scielo.br/scielo.php. Access date: April 8, 2011.

83. Schloesser R, Huang J, Klein P, Manji H. Cellular plasticity cascades in the pathophysiology and treatment of bipolar disorder. Neuropsycho-pharmacology 2008;33(1):110-133.

84. Schultz S, O’Leary D, Boles Ponto L, Arndt S et al. Age and regional cere-bral blood flow in schizophrenia: age effects in anteriorcingulate, frontal and parietal cortex. J Neuropsychiatry Clin Neurosci 2002;14(1):19-24.

85. Eisenberg D, Berman K. Executive function, neural circuitry, and genetic mechanisms in schizophrenia. Neuropsychopharmacology 2010;35(1): 258-277.

86. Thompson P, Vidal C, Giedd J, Gochman P et al. Mapping adolescent brain change reveals dynamic wave of accelerated gray matter loss in very ear-ly-onset schizophrenia. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 2001;98(20):11650-11655.

87. Drevets W, Price J, Simpson J, Todd R et al. Subgenual prefrontal cortex abnormalities in mood disorders. Nature 1997;386(6627):824-827.

88. Altshuler L, Bookheimer S, Proenza M, Townsend J et al. Increased amygdala activation during mania: a functional magnetic resonance imaging study. Am J Psychiatry 2005;162:1211-1213.

89. Weinberger D, McClure R. Neurotoxicity, neuroplasticity, and magnetic resonance imaging morphometry: what is happening in the schizophre-nic brain? Arch Gen Psychiatry 2002;59(6):553-558.

90. Connor C, Guo Y, Akbarian S. Cingulate white matter neurons in schizo-phrenia and bipolar disorder. Biol Psychiatry 2009;66(5):486-93.

91. Drevets W, Savaz J. The subgenual anterior cingulate cortex in mood disorders. CNS Spectr 2006:13:8.

92. McDonald C, Bullmore E, Sham P, Chitnis X et al. Regional volume de-viations of brain structure in schizophrenia and psychotic bipolar disor-der: computational morphometry study. Br J Psychiatry 2005;186:369-377.

93. Arnone D et al. Magnetic resonance imaging studies in bipolar disorder and schizophrenia: meta-analysis. Br J Psychiatry 2009;195:194-201.

94. Ellison-Wright I, Bullmore E. Anatomy of bipolar disorder and schizo-phrenia: a meta-analysis. Schizophr Res 2010;117(1):1-12.

95. Maier W, Zobel A, Wagner M. Schizophrenia and bipolar disorder: diffe-rences and overlaps. Curr Opin Psychiatry 2006;19(2):165-170.

96. Gottesman I. Complications to the complex inheritance of schizophre-nia. Clin Genet 1994;46(1):116-123.

97. Tsuang M, Lyons M, Faraone S. Heterogeneity of schizophrenia. Con-ceptual models and analytic strategies. Br J Psychiatry 1990;156:17-26.

98. Goes F, Sanders L, Potash J. Putative psychosis genes in the prefrontal cortex: combined analysis of gene expression microarrays. Curr Psychia-try Rep 2008;10(2):178-189.

99. Craddock N, O’Donovan M, Owen M. The genetics of schizophrenia and bipolar disorder: dissecting psychosis. J Med Genet 2005;42:193-204.

100. Voineskos A, Lerch J, Felsky D, Tiwari A et al. The ZNF804A gene: Cha-racterization of a novel neural risk mechanism for the major psychoses. Neuropsychopharmacology 2011 (en prensa).

101. Lichtenstein P, Yip B, Björk C, Pawitan Y et al. Common genetic deter-minants of schizophrenia and bipolar disorder in Swedish families: a population-based study. Lancet 2009;373:234-239.

102. Purcell S, Wray N, Stone J, Visscher P et al. Common polygenic varia-tion contributes to risk of schizophrenia and bipolar disorder. Nature 2009;460:748-752.

103. Craddock N, O’Donovan M, Owen M. Psychosis genetics: modeling the relationship between schizophrenia, bipolar disorder, and mixed (or “schizoaffective”) psychoses. Schizophr Bull 2009;35(3):482-490.

104. Prasad K, Keshavan M. Structural cerebral variations as useful endophe-notypes in schizophrenia: do they help construct “extended endopheno-types”? Schizophr Bull 2008;34(4):774-790.

105. McHugh PR, Slavney PR. Methods of reasoning in psychopathology: conflict and resolution Compr Psychiatry 1982;23(3):197-215.

106. Keshavan S, Nasrallah H, Tandon R. Schizophrenia, “Just the Facts” 6. Moving ahead with the schizophrenia concept: from the elephant to the mouse. Schiz Research 2011;127:3-13.

107. Owen M, O’Donovan M, Thapar A, Craddock N. Neurodevelopmental hypothesis of schizophrenia. Br J Psychiatry 2011;198:173-175.

108. Bartra R. Antropología del cerebro: Determinismo y libre albedrío. Salud Mental 2011;34(1):1-9.

Declaration of conflict of interests: None


Recommended