+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to...

Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to...

Date post: 14-Mar-2020
Category:
Upload: others
View: 3 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend
105
Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to the Concept of Religious Community in the Work of Ricœur, Levinas, and Marion Essay prepared under the direction of Joseph Britton (L’Institut Catholique de Paris) Submitted by Rebecca Norlander In partial fulfillment of The MA in French Cultural Studies Columbia University Programs in Paris September 2, 2002
Transcript
Page 1: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to the Concept of Religious Community in the Work of Ricœur, Levinas, and Marion

Essay prepared under the direction of Joseph Britton (L’Institut Catholique de Paris)

Submitted by Rebecca Norlander In partial fulfillment of

The MA in French Cultural Studies Columbia University Programs in Paris

September 2, 2002

Page 2: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

2

Table of Contents

Introduction—A Postmodern Assault? Establishing the Context..............................3

A. Selection of the Three Philosophers:

Paul Ricœur, Emmanuel Levinas, Jean-Luc Marion................................11

B. Identification of Four Recurrent Elements: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis..13

C. The Phenomenological Approach....................................................................19

I. Paul Ricœur..................................................................................................................27

I.A. Reclaiming Identity as Selfhood....................................................................28

I.B. The Constitutive Work of the Other...............................................................30

I.C. Development of a Phenomenological Hermeneutic.......................................32

I.D. Speech as Act: Interlocution and Narration...................................................38

II. Emmanuel Levinas.....................................................................................................45

II.A. “Defense of Subjectivity”.............................................................................47

II.B. The Levinasian Other: Face and Trace..........................................................50

II.C. The Saying and the Said................................................................................56

II.D. The Praxis of Ethical Relationships..............................................................59

III. Jean-Luc Marion.......................................................................................................61

III.A. The Subject as Recipient and Participant....................................................62

III.B. God as the Non-ontological Other: The Triumph of the Iconic Over the

Idolatrous.....................................................................................................63

III.C. Christ as the Word Incarnate........................................................................67

III.D. Eucharistic Participation..............................................................................70

Conclusion—The Emergence of a Theoretical Concept of Community.....................73 Works referenced.............................................................................................................83

Extended Bibliographies.................................................................................................90

Paul Ricœur...........................................................................................................91

Emmanuel Levinas................................................................................................96

Jean-Luc Marion..................................................................................................102

Page 3: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

3

Introduction: A Postmodern Assault? Establishing the Context

In his book Dieu Sans L’Etre,1 French philosopher and theologian Jean-Luc

Marion frees “God” from quotation marks. The traditional conceptual or ontological

notion Marion refers to as “God” is the symbol of the Divine limited to the vocabulary of

Being. He then distinguishes this “God” from G⊗d, his designation for the Divine

understood apart from the constraints of Heidegger’s onto-theological system in which

Being is conceived of in terms of contingent beings belonging to particular historical

context. According to traditional metaphysical philosophy, God has been conceived of as

“that which serves as the ground for being, as distinct from being but nonetheless trapped

in a metaphysical schema which is ‘bigger’ than God, a schema which is all-

encompassing, which employs God as part of dualistic formatting of experience.” 2

In the present age of “postmodern” assaults, God is rendered obsolete against the

backdrop of modern optimism and subsequent nihilism. Viewed through the lens of

philosophical movements such as existentialism, structuralism, and post-structuralism—

as they have evolved in twentieth-century France—God as a transcendent reality is

considered impossible and universal truth is deemed an obsolete construct given the

current trend of rejecting metanarratives. The question becomes: is it still possible to have

a meaningful discourse about God, and if so, how and where is that discourse enacted?

How does thought about God proceed in the wake of such an assault? 3

1 Jean-Luc Marion, Dieu sans l’être (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1991). / God Without Being, Trans Thomas A. Calson (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1991). 2 Anthony J. Godzieba, “Ontotheology to Excess: Imagining God Without Being” Theological Studies 1 (1995): 3. 3 This analysis of religious discourse and community will be limited to a consideration of God as understood in the Judeo-Christian tradition.

Page 4: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

4

While theology is a matter of faith, Heideggerian onto-theology necessarily results

in atheism because it endeavors to understand the Divine within Dasein4 and finds itself

unable to do so. Theology is based on faith, and the object of faith must remain

unrealized. “Being and God are not identical and I would never attempt to think of the

essence of God by means of Being. [. . .] Faith does not need the thought of Being. When

faith has recourse to this thought, it is no longer faith.” 5 The distinction between God

and Being inaugurated by Heidegger will be extended and developed by the philosophers

under consideration here—Paul Ricœur, Emmanuel Levinas, and Jean-Luc Marion. In

the Judeo-Christian tradition, God has been referred to as the Highest Being, the First

Cause, and the Causa Sui; however, in an attempt to respect that which transcends finite

human reason the pendulum has swung too far. A completely self-reliant God is

unrelated to us except for the fact that we know that God is the cause of God’s own

Being. We have reduced God to conceptual proofs, claiming either existence or non-

existence. God has been relegated to the status of just another object of finite human

understanding.

Unaided by the vocabulary of onto-theology and stripped of a metaphysical

foundation, what is it that allows us to continue a meaningful religious discourse? I aim

to show that the concept of community, which emerges through a rigorous

phenomenological approach, is one way discourse can proceed against a seemingly

hostile contemporary philosophical climate that otherwise appears to render action

4 Heidegger’s Sein, translated as Being, is not an essence that exists a-temporally but rather an event or process. If we could say that Being existed it would be relegated to the level of just another being, instead, Being is the mode of existence of beings and Dasein is the being through which Being comes to be known. Resisting attempts to objectivize or subjectivize it, Being functions as a verb and can move through language being reduced to it. [Martin Heidegger, Sein und Zeit, 17th ed (Tübingen: Max Niemeyer, 1993) / Being and Time, trans. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1962).]

Page 5: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

5

arbitrary. This notion of community will be based upon an extensive investigation of

four key elements—self, alterity, discourse, and praxis—and will draw upon the work of

the contemporary philosophers Paul Ricœur, Emmanuel Levinas, and Jean-Luc Marion.

Traditional theological systems have relied heavily on metaphysics in constituting

a view of the nature and attributes of God. This view, however, proves problematic, not

least of all due to the limitations it places on God. “The advent of something like ‘God’

in philosophy therefore arises less from God himself than from metaphysics, as destinal

figure of the thought of Being. ‘God’ is determined starting from and to the profit of that

of which metaphysics is capable, that which it can admit and support”. 6 Understood by

the Judeo-Christian tradition as Prime mover, Efficient Cause, or Necessary Being, the

idea of God is trapped within metaphysical7 constraints and is contingent upon the truth

of foundational metaphysical assumptions. Attempts to prove God’s existence are in and

of themselves negations of God’s true character. “The aim is no longer to compel belief

in God, a god whose existence must be proved is far from godly and any such attempts

lead to blasphemy.” 8 Herein lies the need for other approaches that aim to understand

God in non-metaphysical categories, such as the one proposed by Jean-Luc Marion. In

their search, philosophers and theologians alike have “generally exhibited tendencies

5 Heidegger as quoted in Marion, God Without Being, 61. 6 Marion, God Without Being, 34. 7 Metaphysics is a term that is frequently overgeneralized—without detailing the historical development of the term I believe it would be helpful to establish a working definition for this paper. Metaphysics, briefly, is a duality of being which is posited based on the distinction between being in general and prime Being, the latter of which is then taken to refer to “God” or the Divine as Ultimate Being. For an interesting discussion of metaphysics and the indebtedness of traditional theology to metaphysical philosophy, as well as a overview of Marion’s place and approach, see Scott David Foutz, “Postmetaphysic Theology, A Case Study: Jean-Luc Marion” Quodlibet Journal: 1 (1999). 8 Foutz 3.

Page 6: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

6

toward phenomenology and ethics as alternative paradigms,” 9 both of which will factor

into the subsequent analysis.

It is clear to anyone working on material from the second half of the twentieth

century that the term postmodern is frequently misused. Having been subjected to

academic carelessness and convenient appropriation, the word postmodern could

potentially refer to a whole host of ideas that may or may not be specifically implicated in

my work. From the outset I want state exactly why I have chosen to employ the term and

what I understand it to mean. Albeit nuanced and complex, postmodern remains the best

term to describe the philosophical backdrop for this study provided that a working

definition is established. 10

The word postmodernity is often used to describe the event of the postmodern.

Graham Ward distinguishes between postmodernism—a critical view of the philosophy

of modernity—and postmodernity—the word used to describe a cultural phenomenon in

developed nations during the seventies and eighties, a period concept. 11 The terms are

often treated as interchangeable, but the difference becomes crucial when examining

postmodern elements in contemporary society and thought even though the era known as

9 Foutz 2. 10 This paper does not purport to be a comprehensive examination of postmodern thought or postmodernity, simply a framework against which the rest of my work will be carried out. I am aware of the danger of allowing postmodernism to become a new sort of ground for theology, albeit an post-metaphysical “ground”—allowing my work to proceed in this fashion would be hypocritical. If postmodernity has overtaken or nullified modernity then it becomes preferable, however, this teleological preferencing of the new over the old, the current over the passé, is misleading and should be recognized as such. An anti-foundation is still a foundation. Following Drucilla Cornell, I use the word as an allegory to represent the limit to the principles of modernity. Postmodern represents the recognized failure of modern views—not their actual failing but the representation of their failure, hence the allegory. [Drucilla Cornell, The Philosophy of the Limit (New York: Routledge, Chapman, and Hill, Inc., 1992). See introduction: “What is postmodernity anyway?”] 11 Graham Ward, ed, The Postmodern God: A Theological Reader (Malden, Massachusetts: Blackwell Publishers Ltd, 1997). See Introduction.

Page 7: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

7

postmodernity may well be over. It is not my intention to set up a false dualism between

modernism and postmodernism; this would be misleading:

The bogus dichotomies of the absolute versus the relative, the universal versus the particular, the necessary versus the contingent, and the ahistorical versus the historical need to be recognized for what they are—namely conceptual constructs of a theoretical position-taking that are no longer compelling, options bereft of practical consequences for an understanding of ourselves and our world.12 Instead, I propose that recognizing the limits of traditional ways of thinking,

specifically metaphysical and onto-theological, and understanding the current

philosophical backdrop will aid in our exploration of alternative discourses being

developed. In the contemporary climate God is dead, as is value, absolute truth, and any

reading of reality that has been informed by religious faith. But suppose that Nietzsche,

in proclaiming God’s death, really only “killed” the idols of metaphysics. One of the

tenets of postmodernism under consideration here is the attempted overcoming of

metaphysics, defined as the correlation of being and reasoning. Thus, the recognition of

this idolatry creates a new space for thought about God outside the constraints of

ontology. Marion states that to

[r]each a nonidolatrous thought of God, which alone releases “God” from his quotation marks by disengaging his apprehension from the conditions posed by onto-theo-logy, one would have to manage to think God outside of metaphysics insofar as metaphysics infallibly leads, by way of blasphemy (proof) to the twilight of the idols (conceptual atheism). 13 This reading of Nietzsche’s infamous ‘God is dead’ allows an escape from

nihilism—were he just to state that God does not exist, Nietzsche would be making an

onto-theological claim, rather, by declaring God dead the foundation for metaphysics is

eliminated. However, this does not automatically grant us a liberated existence. “In

12 Calvin O.Schrag, The Self After Postmodernity (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1997), p.108. 13 Marion, God Without Being 37.

Page 8: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

8

dismantling the concept of God as a metaphysical aberration Nietzsche prepared the way

for a similar fate befalling the concept of man.” 14 The death of God establishes a new

secular religion but one without transcendence. This new world supposedly without

constraints soon imposes its own limitations. Without the duality meant to preserve both

humanity and God, there is no more exterior, everything is reduced to human terms.

Marion responds optimistically to this void because he sees it as a realm of

potentiality for thought about “God without Being” to advance. He states: “[. . .] the

collapse entails, even more essentially than a ruin, the clearing of a new space, free for an

eventual apprehension, other than idolatrous, of God.” 15 There is no foundation or origin

that cannot be traced back to man-made structures of reality. Meaning and truth are no

longer grounded on any given system of being or metaphysical essence, but must be

rethought in terms of intersubjectivity and as a product of textual perspective. Heidegger

and Nietzsche bring us to the same point—if theology is to continue to be possible then

language needs to surpass the constraints of metaphysics. Through the work of

Emmanuel Levinas we will consider the possibility to once again come into relationship

with the Other, while both preserving both self and maintaining the absolute alterity of

the Other. God, the infinite, the hidden, can only be encountered through participation or

experience, never constituted conceptually. While I do find this “clearing” of traditional

metaphysics a convincing and promising initiative,16 I want to avoid the tendency toward

postmodern kitsch—sympathizing with the “chirpy nihilists who blithely claim to be at

14 Schrag, The Self After Postmodernity, 2. 15 Ibid., 38. 16 See also David Detmer’s essay “Ricœur on atheism: a critique, ” Lewis Edwin Hahn, ed, The Philosophy of Paul Ricœur The Library of Living Philosophers. Vol. 22. (Chicago and La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1995), pp. 477-93.

Page 9: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

9

home in the wasteland” 17 The consideration of community will provide grounding,

preventing us from simply paying philosophical lip service to contemporary trends.

The point of origin for this work is the convergence of two of my recent

preoccupations: the so-called postmodern context and the apparently irreconcilable idea

of religious community. I consider myself the product of two very different and equally

influential cultures—the faith-based Protestant community in which I was raised and the

self-proclaimed atheistic relativism of current academia.18 This marked division set me

off searching for a path towards reconciliation between these two co-existing systems,

which led to each being broken down and then rebuilt taking into consideration the

influence of the other. Overall, contrary to initial skepticism, I have found this

deconstruction/reconstruction process extremely promising. Dismantling previous beliefs

in a search for Reality has quieted the angst. Instead of feeling pressured to justify my

notion of religious community for fear of its collapse, the idea of community as I

understand it now, having been influenced by contemporary philosophy, takes on a new

shape as a continually self-constituting space. Modernity, necessitating the justification

of religious thought, gives birth to postmodernity in which the nihilism of modern

atheism no longer makes sense. “Religion and philosophy are different, not as opposites

but as polar approaches to Transcendence.” 19 The move is made from a concept of God

to an experience of God, and what more plausible context for such an experience than a

community?

17 Jacques Taminiaux, “Philosophy of existence I: Heidegger,” G.H.R. Parkinson and S.G. Shanker, eds, Continental Philosophy in the 20th Century. Routledge History of Philosophy. Vol. 8. (New York: Routledge, 1994), p.143. 18 Incidentally, Ricœur experienced similar tension: “As for the unsettledness, I tend to relate it to the clash within me between my Protestant upbringing and my intellectual formation [. . .]” Paul Ricœur, “Intellectual Autobiography,” Hahn, 5.

Page 10: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

10

Speaking theoretically about community has emerged through my study of

postmodern philosophy as the best way to continue a discourse on faith, but it is not my

Archimidian point. I am working towards a concept, not from one. I refuse to approach

the ideas of Paul Ricœur, Emmanuel Levinas, and Jean-Luc Marion with a set definition

of what I understand community to be, thereby falling into the trap of looking for

elements in their work that correspond with my prefabricated definition. A top-down

approach would start with a definition of community and then proceed to highlight the

elements that matched the definition. My approach, however, will proceed from ground

level and work upwards, taking the predominant ideas in the works of each philosopher.

This will allow a shared space to emerge which I believe consists of the fundamental

elements that constitute that which I will then label a theoretical religious community.20

Methodologically speaking, I have chosen to treat each philosopher separately,

acknowledging the coherence of each system and its uniqueness in relation to the other

two, while still noting the “shared space”—i.e., the overlapping, inter-relatedness, and

progression of ideas. I use the word community only as the closest approximation for

what I see emerging and developing at the intersection points between the three, as well

as the “final product”, that is, what I believe becomes apparent when their respective

ideas are considered together. The space of overlap between Ricœur, Levinas, and

19 William Desmond, “Philosophies of Religion: Marcel, Jaspers, Levinas,” Parkinson and Shanker, 155. 20 The philosophers under consideration rarely employ the term “community” or discuss the idea in their works: this presents two possible problems that I want to address: first, perhaps I am manipulating the material and secondly, if the idea of community is as important as I have stated, is it not presumptuous to infer that Ricœur, Levinas, and Marion do not recognize its centrality and comment on it themselves. I counter these objections with the following remarks: the material is not being manipulated, merely selected, and I have indicated that my paper is not comprehensive but rather an examination of four recurring themes. I do consider the notion of community the way of rendering these themes intelligible and continuing a meaningful religious discourse. The relative silence of the three philosophers on the issue does not result from the fact that they have not considered this possibility so much as it is such an

Page 11: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

11

Marion will be subdivided into four major themes to be examined: the concept of

subjectivity or the self, the relationship with alterity, discourse, and praxis.

A. Selection of the Three Philosophers:

Paul Ricœur, Emmanuel Levinas, Jean-Luc Marion

Before explaining the four fundamental elements I have identified, a word on my

selection of philosophers. Believing that a religious discourse could be continued in the

context of postmodernism, though not without significant modification, I began to

consider material on hermeneutics and new ways of thinking and or speaking about God.

When I discovered phenomenology I found a vocabulary for describing the nature of

religious phenomena which I realized would be helpful were I to try to develop alternate

way of thinking about discourse. Ricœur, Levinas, and Marion soon surfaced as the most

recurrent names in contemporary French religious phenomenology, those whom I

consider the most pertinent to current philosophical debates about the nature of God and

whose ideas are conducive to religious thought (i.e. addressing questions concerning who

we are, how God is understood, how we interpret sacred texts, etc.). I am interested in

their ideas as works-in-progress. I will show how, when considered together, the ideas in

their works lend themselves to a concept of religious community that is in flux and self-

constituting, as well as the way that the works of each are developed and reworked by the

other two. It seems natural to consider Ricoeur, Levinas, and Marion together because of

underlying truth that it is implied and accepted tacitly. I am to show that the repeated themes have no sense understood apart from each other or apart from a space of enactment—it is this space I label community.

Page 12: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

12

the dialogue between the three men.21 I am also interested in these three scholars because

of their participation in their respective religious communities: Ricoeur belongs the

Protestant tradition, Levinas is Jewish, and Marion identifies himself as a Roman

Catholic. There is certain merit awarded their writing due to the correspondence between

belief and action. The fact that each belongs to a different religious tradition allows for a

broader investigation of the idea of community.

Once having selected three philosophers that continue the discourse in the context

of postmodernity, the question then becomes how this is carried out. What are the key

themes or focal points in their work? It is not always readily apparent how certain ideas

fit into the overall scheme—for instance, Ricœur does not develop his notion of

phenomenological hermeneutics necessarily for the purpose of biblical application,

however, that is one possibility.22 My goal is to take the key concepts and themes that

converge in the writings of Ricœur, Levinas, and Marion, and then see what emerges as

this so-called “shared space”. One major difficulty has been choosing material to

consider, and in no way does this study purport to be comprehensive. Each of the three

scholars has written extensively, and I will rely heavily on bibliographic material to direct

the reader for continued investigation of their ideas.23 This study should rightly be called

a comparison of texts, and rather than a study of the philosophers themselves or even of

their comparative ideas because those characterizations give a false impression of

21 e.g., Paul Ricœur, Autrement. Lecture d'Autrement qu'être ou au-delà de l'essence d'Emmanuel Levinas (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1997); Jean Luc Marion, Emmanuel Levinas: Autrement que savoir, (Paris: Éditions Osiris, 1988). 22 e. g., Weon Hyo Lee, Interpretation de la Bible selon la démarche de Paul Ricoeur, (Maitrise, L’Institut Catholique de Paris, 1994). 23 See extended bibliographies included for each philosopher

Page 13: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

13

comprehensiveness. I will be drawing primarily upon Ricœur’s Oneself as Another, 24

Levinas’s Totality and Infinity 25 and Otherwise than Being, 26 (alongside some discussion

of his “religious” texts Of God Who comes to Mind 27 and Difficult Freedom,28) and

Marion’s The Idol and Distance 29 and God Without Being.

B. Identification of Four Recurrent Elements: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis

The principle themes and key ideas are organized in four broad categories which

then, I will argue, lend themselves to the construction of a theoretical community. The

idea of community emerges because the elements cannot exist apart from each other

(they would not make sense), nor can they exist independently of the idea of community

(they would have no grounding). They are both contingent and causal, each element is

constituted by and necessitates the other elements. There is a constant referral of each

element back to the other three, creating a complex web as opposed to a pyramidal

progression.

24 Paul Ricœur, Soi-même comme un autre (L’ordre philosophique) (Paris: Seuil, 1990). / Oneself as Another. Trans. K. Blamey. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992). 25 Emmanuel Levinas, Totalité et Infini (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1961). / Totality and Infinity, Trans. A. Lingis (Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1969). 26 Emmanuel Levinas, Autrement qu'etre ou au-dela de l'essence (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1974). /Otherwise Than Being or Beyond Essence, Trans.A. Lingis (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1981). 27 Emmanuel Levinas, De Dieu qui vient à l’idée (Paris: Vrin, 1982). / Of God Who Comes to Mind, Trans. Bettina Bergo (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1998). 28 Emmanuel Levinas, Difficile Liberté: Essaies sur le judaisme (Paris: Albin Michel, 1963). / Difficult Freedom: Essays on Judaism. Trans. Sean Hand (Baltimore, MD: John Hopkins University Press, 1990). 29 Emmanuel Levinas, L’idole et la distance: Cinq etudes (Paris: Grasset, 1977). / The Idol and Distance, Trans. Thomas A. Carlson Perspectives in Continental Philosophy Ser. Vol. 17. Ed. John D. Caputo. (New York: Fordham University Press, 2001).

Page 14: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

14

The first of the four elements finding frequent consideration in the works of

Ricœur,30 Levinas, and Marion is the notion of the self and/or subjectivity. In the wake of

the postmodern assault on the self, what can be salvaged? A rethinking of the notion of

identity is in order following the emphasis on deconstructing the subject. The modern

vocabulary for describing identity is no longer applicable. Following Calvin Schrag, I

would argue that there is no longer a singular or easily distinguishable caricature of the

self, instead, multiple profiles exist and the way we acquire knowledge about this self is

through apprehension of a particular story.31

It is clear that the word ‘self’ will not do, because that is just the notion that the critique of metaphysics has most effectively delimited. The ‘self’ is something which we define in terms of its self-identity. Yet what seems to characterize ‘us’ above all is non-identity, difference, our power or, better, our vulnerability to spin off into the abyss. The self is precisely not that which breaks under the strain, gives way to the pull of the flux, which is constantly being divested of its illusions, tormented by the unconscious, constantly being tricked by its history and its language. If we have learned anything in the last one hundred years of European thought, it is that the self is anything but what it pretends to be. And even to speak, as does Ricœur, of a ‘wounded cogito’ is to employ a euphemism which tries to contain and minimize the damage. The ‘self’ is much more a place of disruption, irruption, solicitation. 32 Entering into postmodern thought calls for the reconstruction of the idea of

subjectivity and also that of interaction—as we will see, the notion of the self is never

constituted apart from considerations of what lies outside the self, be it human or divine.

At the end of our examination of the three scholars it will become apparent that the

context of community will allow us to rethink both of these aspects, first independently

and then in relation to each other. The origin of meaning is no longer considered to be

30 “The question of the subject appears in its right dimension as a thematic center” (referring to Ricœur’s Oneself As Another) Domenico Jervolino, “The Depth and Breadth of Paul Ricœur’s Philosophy,” Hahn. p.535. 31 Schrag, The Self After Postmodernity. 32 John Caputo, Demythologizing Heidegger. (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1993), p.18.

Page 15: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

15

the conscious reflecting subject but rather encounters that are mediated by culture. There

is a blatant rejection of the metaphysical desire for absolute transparence of the subject

and instead the self is understood contextually. The presence of a subject to itself is

indirect and mediated, contingent upon participation in the cultural realm.

The battered Cartesian cogito is reclaimed after having entered into a relationship

with the Other. Consideration of the self prefigures the other elements we will consider

(such as discourse and praxis) that hinge upon this re-articulated subjectivity:

In effect, the ‘question of the subject’ means that the subject is called into question. The subject called into question is the cogito at its broadest and most dynamic, a plural, finite subjectivity, actuating itself as striving and as a desire for being, which is not behind us or beneath us as some sort of metaphysical substratum, but is rather a task for our praxis and our hope for the future. Thus understood, the ‘question of the subject’ implies a relationship with its ‘other,’ i.e. with that which calls it into question and transforms its pure reflection, ever exposed to the risk of narcissism and metaphysical arrogance, into a questioning which generates ‘meaning’ in the course of its searching. 33 Ricœur articulates his idea of identity as a balance between subjectivism and

humanism; for Marion and Levinas the self is constituted by the call and response to the

Other.

The second of the four elements I identify as key themes in the work of Ricœur,

Levinas, and Marion is that of the relationship with alterity. I have chosen the word

alterity because it seems the most comprehensive—alterity is that which is completely

other, irreducible to the self, strange; including all possible variations of “otherness”.

The French distinction is helpful to bear in mind: otherness can either be l’autre (simply

the vague term for the other), l’Autre (a term often referring to the Divine Other) or

l’autrui (the specifically human other). This element first takes shape as the

33 Jervolino 536.

Page 16: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

16

phenomenological problem of solipsism—how do we know what exists apart from the

self? Heidegger grounds us as beings-in-the-world, in relation with others. Prior to

Heidegger, the nihilism of modern atheism left us without the capacity to relate to any

exterior or transcendence. God had always been understood ontologically, hence the

difficulty of finding a way to think of God that is outside the boundaries of ontology.

The enlightenment view that reason had usurped the place of religion rendered the

“real” world knowable. The world, no longer incomprehensible, ceased to be an-other

world. This allowed Nietzsche to proclaim the death of God and humanity God’s

assassins. A rethinking of alterity is in order, both as human and divine, in ways that do

not reduce either to an object of the subject’s experience or constitution. In this section

on alterity, all three philosophers will extend the ideas set out in the discussion on the

self. The dialectic between self and alterity is what constitutes identity in Ricœur’s work.

According to Levinas, the principal failure of Western philosophy has been its inability to

maintain the otherness of the other, continually dissolving it and absorbing it into the

realm of the Same, thus constituting a return to the self. Levinas has been called a

philosopher of alterity, constantly working to preserve otherness through a relationship he

calls the face-to-face.

The third element under consideration is discourse, understood here in the narrow

sense of that which is specifically linguistic, i.e., referring primarily to texts and

interpretation. “It is within this economy of discourse that the self is called into being,

and it is called into being as the who that is speaking and listening, writing, and reading,

discursing in a variety of situations and modalities of discourse.” 34 The self emerges

34 Schrag, The Self After Postmodernity, 17.

Page 17: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

17

from communicative practices, necessarily involving the Other, telling stories as a form

of self-constitution. “Language does not just reflect human being but actually makes

humans be, brings about human existence as communal understanding and self-

understanding.” 35 The role language plays should not be underestimated—how much of

what is “real” do we constitute in an effort to explain? The modern view of language was

that texts contained meaning that could be extracted using logical reasoning—the “truths”

of any text were independent of its context; they were thought to be pre-linguistic. The

idea that words correspond to an idea or an object is a tenet of modern thinking. All

meaning became contextualized and there was no longer any truth apart from what was

constituted within the system of signifier and signified.36 Linguistic signs relate

internally to the system, and placing a sign in a new context will alter its semantic value.

It is the overall language structure that makes possible the meaningfulness of any

particular word within that structure. We see again the interrelated nature of the four

elements: questions of discourse are inseparable from notions of subjectivity.

Structuralism characterized the subject as the intersection of linguistic, mythological or ideological forces which leave little space for individual agency and responsibility. Post-structuralist thinkers moved away from the rigid schemes and scientific claims of the structuralists, but maintained the view of the subject as an outdated humanist illusion to be demystified. Rather than the self-conscious, self-possessed source of insight and values, the subject was to be regarded as decentred and elusive, possibly no more than an effect of language or the residue of still-unliquidated and pernicious metaphysical thinking.37

The fourth element that surfaces frequently in the works at hand is what I will

broadly label praxis, though it takes on various forms. The word praxis was deliberately

35 Dermot Morgan, Introduction to Phenomenology (London: Routledge, 2000), p.270. 36 See the work of Swiss linguist Ferdinand De Saussure (1857-1913) 37 Colin Davis, Levinas: An Introduction (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1996), p.2

Page 18: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

18

selected, as the root of the word action, but also encompassing connotations such as

practice and performance. “The term praxis, which has been in the philosophical

vocabulary since the time of the Greeks, is particularly helpful for articulating the

communal character of human existence.” 38 Action has more of an individualistic sense

whereas praxis foreshadows the emergence of community. Praxis designates a sphere of

human action contrasted with theory.39

While the notion of discourse is often seen as emphasizing history and tradition

(i.e. the reason Biblical or Talmudic texts are seen as credible is because they have

withstood the test of time, the texts represent ideas that are grounded in a historical

tradition and this is what gives them weight), the notion of praxis is completely future-

oriented. It is a call to action. In this element we will see how each of the three

philosophers has a different “site” for this action. For Ricœur the action is speech,

reiterating his emphasis on language and interpretation; for Levinas it is the ethical

relationship; and for Marion it is the Eucharist, the meeting of immanence and

transcendence, that translates into a call to action.

The move is made from a concept of God to an experience of God. Having been

informed by the rethinking of the self, alterity, and discourse, praxis gives us a site or a

concrete space for action. “An account of the self in action is destined to gravitate into an

account of the self in community.” 40 It acts as cohesion and impetus, readily lending

itself to an understanding of postmodern community as a way to continue religious

thought and expression. “The world of action represents the highest sphere of human

38 Schrag, The Self After Postmodernity, 76. 39 The word praxis has Aristotelian roots but the definition has been modified in various ways since antiquity; for further development see Calvin Schrag, Communicative Praxis and the Space of Subjectivity (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1986), pp.18-20.

Page 19: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

19

engagement, especially when it emerges in join co-operative undertakings and in

discussion. It is only in the life of action, as opposed to the life of abstract thought, that

humans become fully authentic.”41 Without this fourth element we would stay in the

realm of theory, lacking the grounding that I believe is clearly demonstrated in the

philosophies of Ricœur, Levinas, and Marion.

C. The Phenomenological Approach

I have entitled my work “A Phenomenological Approach to the Concept of

Religious Community” for two primary reasons: 1) I see my own approach and

responsibility towards the material as phenomenological, involving a suspension of

personal beliefs and a description of the elements that surface; and 2) It is clear that each

of the three philosophers under consideration have a distinct relationship with

phenomenology and their work fits into the category of what can be called

phenomenological. Phenomenology provides an alternative way of understanding reality,

language, and human interaction. “It is with justifiable right that the phenomenologist

accuses empiricism of a naïveté regarding human experience.” 42 In order to eliminate

any ambiguity about the title of my thesis, I must specify that I am not considering each

of the three philosophers’ phenomenological approach to community, (i.e. three different

approaches toward the same end,) but rather the way their ideas (in the context of

phenomenological methodology) converge and the idea of community is that which

40 Schrag, The Self After Postmodernity, 76. 41 Hannah Arendt as quoted in Morgan 312. 42 Don Idhe, Hermeneutic Phenomenololgy The Philosophy of Paul Ricoeur (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1971), p.17.

Page 20: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

20

emerges. I believe phenomenology offers insights and presents a more apt vocabulary for

dealing with the possibility of contemporary religious discourse.

Broadly, phenomenology can be defined as the study dedicated to describing the

structures of experience as they present themselves to consciousness, or the study of the

structures of consciousness that enable consciousness to refer to objects outside itself.

“Phenomenology must carefully describe things as they appear to consciousness. In

other words, the way problems, things, and events are approached must involve taking

their manner of appearance to consciousness into consideration.” 43 Supposedly rejecting

the subject/object distinction, “[p]henomenology claimed instead to offer a holistic

approach to the relation between objectivity and consciousness” 44 The relationship with

the object takes places within the subject so that the “objective world” is really a

constituted object of subjectivity.

Phenomenology can be understood as both a method and a general movement.

While I acknowledge this dual purpose or definition, I am not studying the three

philosophers as phenomenologists, simply how they undertake a phenomenological

approach, and in some cases, how they find such an approach to be limited.

Phenomenology is a practice rather than a system, a different way of doing philosophy.

“…[P]henomenology’s first step is to seek to avoid all misconstructions and impositions

placed on experience in advance [. . .] Explanations are not to be imposed before the

phenomena have been understood from within.” 45 In Edmund Husserl, the founder of

contemporary phenomenology, we see foreshadowing of several of the elements found in

the subsequent work of Ricoeur, Levinas, and Marion, namely constitution of the self and

43 Ibid., 6. 44 Morgan 13.

Page 21: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

21

encounter with alterity. “Husserl came to believe that since the self-constitution of the

ego is the source of all constitution, then all phenomenology really coincided with the

phenomenology of the self-constitution of the ego. Connected with the focus on the ego

necessarily comes the problem of the experience of other egos, of alter egos, the

experience of the ‘foreign’, the ‘strange’, the ‘other’ (Fremderfahrung) in general.” 46

The phenomenological method as proposed by Husserl entails performing what he

calls the Epoche: when presuppositions are suspended or bracketed the pure phenomena

can surface. One of Husserl’s key words is ‘givenness’ (Gegebenheit), which expresses

his belief that all experience has a person, a ‘to whom’ it is directed. 47 We will take up

again the idea of givenness with Marion, whose constitution of the subject as recipient

underlies his philosophy of donation. The application of the phenomenological method

involves naming objects (also including concepts, not limited to material objects), noting

the relationships between these objects, and then describing processes48—the method I

am proposing in this study.

“…Paul Ricœur has justly remarked that phenomenology is the story of the

deviations from Husserl; the history of phenomenology is the history of Husserlian

heresies.” 49 The first of many dissenters was Martin Heidegger, whose ideas have had

substantial influence upon subsequent phenomenologists, including Ricœur, Levinas, and

Marion. His phenomenology was primarily an investigation of the meaning of Being and

its mode of presentation. Herein lies the major difference between Husserl and

45 Morgan 4. 46 Morgan 175. 47 Morgan 11. 48 James L. Cox, Expressing the Sacred: An Introduction to the Phenomenology of Religion (Harare, Zimbabwe: University of Zimbabwe, 1992).

Page 22: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

22

Heidegger: 50 “Husserlian phenomenology did not dispute the possibility of our gaining a

‘view from nowhere’, understood as the aperspectival, theoretical, ‘objective’

understanding of things.” 51 Heidegger abandoned ‘consciousness’ and ‘intentionality’

altogether in developing his notion of Being-in-the-world (In-der-Welt-sein),52 claiming

that “all description involves interpretation, indeed that description was only a derivative

form of interpretation. Husserl’s project of pure description, then, becomes impossible if

description is not situated inside a radically historicised hermeneutics.”53

Heidegger disagreed fundamentally with Husserl, believing it impossible to

reduce one’s understanding of the world into personal experience. For Heidegger, the

theoretical relation to the world is always derivative from a more immediate lived

experience. Against Husserl’s “pure” intentionality, Heidegger says that objects are

intended against a background and never purely given to us. He sees us as being thrown

into the world, which is actually a much deeper intentionality because it is based on

experience, instead of mere thought about objects.

Heidegger rejected traditional metaphysical approaches to the question of Being as having misunderstood the nature of beings by understanding them as ‘things’, as what is simply there, as occurrent, as ‘reality’, as present at hand. Traditional metaphysics, which thought is was simply describing things as they are, does not realise that it is constructed on the basis of a certain assumed attitude towards the world, which in fact is not fundamental, but belongs to a distorted way of experience due to the way humans are drawn into everyday existing.54

49 “Si bien que la phénomenologie au sens large est la somme de l’œuvre husserlienne et des hérésies issues de Husserl”—Paul Ricœur, A l’école de la phenomenologie. (Paris: Vrin, 1987): 9. As reprinted in Morgan 3. 50 Even though it has become more or less standard to oppose pure transcendental phenomenology to hermeneutic phenomenology (i.e., Husserl versus Heidegger), this dichotomy may be misleading and we should not overlook the possible hermeneutic quality of Husserl’s work. See John Caputo’s treatment in Radical Hermeneutics: Repetition, Deconstruction, and the Hermeneutic Project (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1987) Chap. 2 “Repetition and Constitution: Husserl’s Proto Hermeneutics.” 51 Morgan 12. 52 Ibid. 53 Ibid., 20. 54 Morgan 197.

Page 23: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

23

With Heidegger’s Sein und Zeit (1927) phenomenology took a decidedly

hermeneutical shift. The thread of hermeneutics, or interpretation of texts, runs through

the work of Ricœur, Levinas, and Marion. What does this shift entail?

Phenomenology became hermeneutical when it argued that every form of human awareness is interpretive, when it was not content to regard interpretation as just one specific form of awareness directed to one particular range of objects—for instance, texts. If all the intentions of our perception and imagination are already marked through and through by language, and moreover, the phenomenologist him- or herself can no longer claim an intuitive access to mental life, but is always interpreting it, then we are in hermeneutics.55

One possible objection to this emphasis on understanding and meaning as

functions of interpretation is the hermeneutical circle—the way we presume or

presuppose something in light of what we already know. Far from being a vicious circle,

“[f]or Heidegger this circle is not a contingent feature of understanding, but is essential to

human being as being-in-the-world.”56 Understanding is not simply sensory input, but

rather the way we relate, react, interpret, and express. This is the point of fusion between

phenomenology and hermeneutics: “Heidegger favors a new ‘fundamental ontology’, an

enquiry into the manner in which the structures of Being are revealed through the

structures of human existence, an enquiry, furthermore, which could only be carried out

through phenomenology, now transformed into hermeneutical phenomenology, since the

phenomena of existence always require interpretation, and hermeneutics is the art of

interpretation.” 57 This is one of the primary concepts that surfaces in Ricœur’s

philosophy, underlying what I see as the importance of the community as the space for

interpreting texts as meaningful.

55 Graeme Nicholson, “Hermeneutical Phenomenology,” (Encyclopedia of Phenomenology. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Pulblishers, 1997): 304. 56 Morgan 277.

Page 24: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

24

Some phenomenologists argue that a phenomenology of religion is an invalid

pursuit given the apparent contradiction in terms—phenomenology being the study of

what is immanent and religion the experience of the transcendent. There is also the

familiar charge that there is no religious reality other than the faith of the believer. How

does one address these claims? I believe that examining methods used by religious

phenomenologists can be helpful, understanding, however, that I am not purporting to do

a phenomenology of religion nor classify Ricoeur, Levinas, and Marion as religious

phenomenologists. In a broad sense, phenomenology is the study of phenomena, and

thus religious phenomenology the study of religious phenomena, with a specific method

of inquiry into religious expression and experience.58 The phenomenological approach is

descriptive and detailed, where reductionism is avoided and truth questions are bracketed

(so as not to trivialize the phenomena and ignore the complex nature of human

experience or impose false values), and the essence of phenomena explored. There is a

distinction to be made between the truth of religion and the truth about religion. The first

category of truth should be bracketed while the second lends itself to description, which

57 Ibid., 197 58 Here we might encounter the further objection against not only religious phenomena, but phenomena in general: if intentionality means that all mental acts have objects and that consciousness is consciousness of something, then are not phenomena also constituted by consciousness? Can the mind ever know anything outside itself? The idea that all mental acts have an object they are directed towards does not certify the existence of independent objects—that which is intended by consciousness is also constituted by it. Husserl’s Zu den Sachen selbst (“Back to the things themselves”) works against itself: “Phenomenology aims to study the encounters between consciousness and the world, but it also suggests that the world is only ever encountered as already constituted by and within consciousness. The encounter promised by intentionality may be precisely what the theory of intentionality precludes: consciousness can never meet anything truly alien to itself because the external world is a product of its own activity” (Davis 19). Stated otherwise, if the only foundation for knowledge is the existence of the ego or cogito (Descartes), then all paths leading to so-called other selves are problematic. This is also referred to as solipsism, the idea that other selves do not necessarily exist because they are always constituted. This criticism largely applies to the work of Husserl. Apodictic knowledge (that which is certain, beyond doubt) is unfounded because of the notion of intentionality. According to Husserl, he solves this problem with his notion of bracketing: apodictic certainty can be achieved if everything doubtable is bracketed. This bracketing includes the

Page 25: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

25

lies well inside the boundaries of a phenomenological project. Such an approach suits the

paradoxical nature of religion and religious inquiries: “Phenomenology accordingly is a

practice of making something manifest that is in one way already manifest, and yet that is

in another way still concealed, in need of further manifestation through a logos.” 59

Secondly, the question may be posed: in order to understand the notion of

religious community, why not take a theological approach, as opposed to an arguably

more difficult and ambiguous philosophical one? There are multiple responses but all

tied into the fundamental difference between the respective function of each discipline—

a phenomenological approach describes possibility whereas a theological one describes a

supposed actuality. Phenomenology is dedicated to precise description, never

justification. The question why, doubtless an integral part of examining the constitution

of any community, will not be directly addressed. I am not interested in peoples’

motivation for joining a particular community, or dealing with the differences between

specific instances of community. I aim to describe key elements, aided by the tools

provided by phenomenology, that can then be adapted to constitute particular instances of

community. “Theology, then, would always be particular and concrete—the theology of

this particular believing community. A phenomenology of religion, however, brackets

such participation and is able to range across religious communities.” 60 My aim here is

not a denial of participation but a temporary suspension of it in order to allow for the

openness to the idea of community on a theoretical level.

existence of both other selves and of an external world—in this way a transcendental Ego is revealed which remains the first apodictic truth upon which all others are based. 59 Nicholson 305. 60 Smith 27.

Page 26: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

26

Phenomenology brings forward the what and how; it seeks to describe the key

elements and define the relationships at work. This approach highlights community, as

seen by the three contemporary philosophers I have selected, as essentially an

understanding of relationships, emerging from the four fundamental elements previously

described. Phenomenology is a way of grounding our theoretical community and we will

understand it as the doctrine of lived experience. The idea of community, I will argue, is

what emerges when a phenomenological approach is taken. A theological approach, on

the other hand, would presuppose this outcome. Theology can start from the notion of

community and then deconstruct it, top to bottom, while phenomenology works from the

ground up. Phenomenology presents the possibility of a “saturated” phenomenon (to use

Marion’s term), of a presence known solely through revelation, yet makes no actual

claims on such an occurrence. Theology, on the other hand, while it may to a certain

extent employ phenomenological methods, always refers to the relationship between faith

and a historical actuality. In dealing with phenomenology we are necessarily leaving

questions of faith on the periphery.

Page 27: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

27

I. PAUL RICŒUR61

An investigation of subjectivity is one of the focal points of Ricœur’s work,

especially in Oneself as Another, but as we will see it is inextricably linked to his

constitution of the other and his development of phenomenological hermeneutics. If there

are no longer any reference points outside subjectivity, as the postmodern argument goes,

the self is contingent upon textual meaning; hence the function of interpretation.

Ricœur’s approach to subjectivity is thoroughly phenomenological “in that it seeks to

clarify through reflective analysis that which is immediately and indubitably given to

consciousness: the fact of the subject’s own existence.”62

Oneself as Another is composed of studies which deal with the question ‘who’ in

relation to the problematic of the self. Briefly, Ricœur divides his work into the

following considerations: who is speaking? (philosophy of language), who is acting?

(philosophy of action), who is recounting about himself or herself? (question of personal

identity) and who is the moral subject of imputation? (the ethical and moral

determination of action). 63 The book includes nine studies exploring the various levels

of human action in three basic dimensions: linguistics, narration, and ethics. This is

Ricœur’s three-part formula—describe, narrate, prescribe—which he believes forms a

cohesive whole (i.e., there is no radical rupture between description and prescription,

between act and worth). The role of the self is paradoxical as both the foundation and the

end product—the concept of the self precedes our ability to describe, narrate, or

prescribe, yet it is also constituted in these three activities.

61 For extensive coverage of Ricœur’s life and work see the excellent biography by François Dosse: Paul Ricœur, Le sens d’une vie (Paris: Editions de la découverte, 1995). 789 p. 62 Madison 75. 63 Ibid., 16-18.

Page 28: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

28

I.A. Reclaiming Identity as Selfhood

Attempting to move beyond the objectivism/subjectivism debate, Ricœur,

drawing extensively on phenomenological thought, attempts to “ground” the idea of the

self in a post-metaphysical hermeneutic.

One of the core features of Ricœur’s hermeneutics has been his ongoing attempt to articulate a notion of ‘the subject’ which would be free from all forms of modern subjectivism. Unlike other forms of postmodern thought, hermeneutics has strenuously resisted the current, and very fashionable, anti-humanist calls for the abolition of ‘the subject’ (the ‘end of “man”’). The notion of the subject, hermeneutics insists, is not to be abandoned—but it must indeed be stripped of all its modernist, metaphysical accretions. This continued allegiance on the part of hermeneutics to the notion of the subject testifies to its rootedness in the phenomenological tradition inaugurated by Edmund Husserl. 64

It is evident that in Ricœur’s work the four elements I have outlined (self, alterity,

discourse, praxis) are all fluid categories. They flow in and out of each other and

considered separately each is hopelessly incomplete. For example, Ricœur writes that

“[t]he autonomy of the self will appear then to be tightly bound up with solicitude for

one’s neighbor and with justice for each individual.” 65 This phrase demonstrates the way

that the elements are intricately linked and interdependent—the self is itself constituted

and is an agent of constituting simultaneously. Ricœur’s hermeneutics deconstructs and

then reconstructs identity. It would be false to say that in this section I will only be

treating Ricœur’s view of the self—such a task is impossible. However, I will attempt to

isolate his remarks with the intended purpose of circling back around at the end to show

the interrelatedness of all four elements and thus the coherence of Ricœur’s philosophy as

it appears in Oneself as Another and other selected texts.

64 Madison 297. 65 Ricœur, Oneself as Another, 18.

Page 29: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

29

Ricœur begins Oneself as Another with a discussion of Cartesian and Nietzschean

philosophy, of the extremes between the “exalted subject” and the “humiliated subject” 66

and wonders what there is “left to say about this free-floating ‘I’” 67. He calls for a

complete rethinking of the self, one that takes philosophy beyond the alternatives of

cogito and anti-cogito.68 What Ricœur calls the ‘hermeneutics of the self’ is distinct from

traditional philosophies of the cogito—“To say self is not to say ‘I’. The ‘I’ is posited—

or deposed. The self is implied reflexively in the operations, the analysis of which

precedes the return toward the self.”69

Identity can be understood in two distinct ways, which Ricœur refers to as idem

identity and ipse identity. Idem is identity as sameness whereas ipse is identity as

selfhood.70 Idem identity is both quantitative and qualitative, yet does not provide an

answer to the crucial question “Who am I?” The answer is found in ipse-identity,

characterized by the awareness that preserving, strengthening, and revising our identity.71

In Oneself as Another, Ricœur declares his hypothesis—that the intervention of narrative

identity will eventually allow for the distinction between the two. This narration

intervenes “in the conceptual constitution of personal identity in the manner of a specific

mediator between the pole of character, where idem and ipse tend to coincide, and the

pole of self-maintenance, where selfhood frees itself from sameness.” 72 This notion of

selfhood will eventually serve as our base for understanding the concept of community

but not before the relation between self and alterity has been established. Without the

66 Ibid., 16. 67 Ibid., 6. 68 Ibid. 69 Ibid., 18. 70 Ibid., 16.

Page 30: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

30

work of “otherness” it would be possible (but erroneous) to exalt the self as an origin in

and of itself.

Ricœur again attacks the traditional grounding of the self in metaphysics by

emphasizing the constitutive importance of the other: “What Ricœur has worked to

articulate is a renewed, transformed and, above all, decentred notion of the subject, i.e.,

one which views subjectivity not as a metaphysical ‘origin’ of meaning but as the result

(‘effect’) of its transformative encounter with the ‘other’.” 73 Le us follow the natural

progression of Ricœur’s thought into a discussion of alterity.

I.B. The Constitutive Work of the Other

David Vessey looks at Ricœur’s Oneself as Another as contributing to our

understanding of alterity as intersubjectivity.74 How do we account for the centrality of

the work of otherness in constituting selfhood and what does Ricœur mean by the term

“otherness”? Ricœur calls alterity the site of the play between phenomenological and

ontological discourse.75 He states: “the main virtue of such a dialectic is that it keeps the

self from occupying the place of foundation. This prohibition is perfectly suited to the

ultimate structure of a self that will neither be exalted, as in the philosophies of the

cogito, nor be humiliated, as in the philosophies of the anti-cogito.” 76 It is important to

see otherness as fundamental in constituting the self, not something that embellishes or

enhances it at a later point, or simply that which prevents the phenomenological problem

71 David Vessey, “The Polysemy of Otherness: On Ricœur’s Oneself as Another” http://www.beloit.edu/philorel/faculty/davidvessey/DVRicoeur.html 72 Ricœur, Oneself as Another, 118-9. 73 Madison 314. 74 Vessey 1.

Page 31: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

31

of solipsism: “[. . .] otherness is not added on to selfhood from outside, as though to

prevent its solipsistic drift.” 77 Alterity occupies such an important place that the self is

incomprehensible without the Other:

the Other is not only the counterpart of the Same but belongs to the intimate constitution of its sense. Indeed, on the properly phenomenological level, the multiple ways in which the other than self affects the understanding of the self by itself marks precisely, the difference between the ego that posits itself and the self that recognizes itself only though these very affections.78 In our discussion of Emmanuel Levinas we will see the predominate way the

Other factors into (indeed, determines) his philosophy. Instead of distinguishing between

“self” and “I” (ipse/idem), Levinas sees ontology as lying within totality, and otherness

becomes the equivalent of radical exteriority. The Same signifies totalization and

separation, so the exteriority of the Other can no longer be expressed in language of

relation. The Other absolves itself from relation in the same movement by which the

Infinite draws from Totality. 79 Ricœur’s portrait of Levinas is much more despairing and

nihilistic than the one Levinas himself would sketch. He is critical of the Levinasian

Other, but how does Ricœur himself define the term? At the end of his discussion in

Oneself as Another, Ricœur remains vague when considering the possibility of a more

precise definition of who this “other” is:

Perhaps the philosopher as philosopher has to admit that one does not know and cannot say whether this Other, the source of the injunction, is another person whom I can look in the face or who can stare at me, or my ancestors for whom there is no representation, to so great an extent does my debt to them constitute

75 Levinas wants to be rid of the ontological discourse altogether as he defines it in sole pursuit of phenomenology as that which will allow the reconfiguration of traditional ways of doing philosophy 76 Ricœur,Oneself as Another, 318. 77Ibid., 317. 78 Ibid., 329. 79 Ricoeur’s critique of Levinas can be found in Oneself as Another 335-55.

Page 32: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

32

my very self, or God—living God, absent God—or an empty place. With this aporia of the Other, philosophical discourse comes to an end.80

Even with these acknowledged ambiguities in his work, Ricœur nonetheless

opens up a space for religious thought to proceed. The end of philosophical discourse as

it has been known in the past (i.e. founded on metaphysics) leaves Ricœur to establish a

new discourse, one developed phenomenologically, to get past the aporia. Philosophical

discourse is blocked but meaningful encounters with alterity can still take place given the

appropriate context—that of community.

I.C. Development of a Phenomenological Hermeneutic

Discourse is treated extensively in Ricœur’s philosophy and takes on various

shapes, however, I will limit my discussion here to his treatment of written discourse,

defined as text, and treat spoken discourse in the subsequent section on praxis. First will

be an inquiry into what Ricœur means by ‘text’ and an examination of Ricœurian

hermeneutics, (the art of interpretation,) culminating in his phenomenological

hermeneutics. Why Ricoeur’s emphasis on interpretation? The method of hermeneutics

implies going beyond the immanent context of a work to its reference, i.e., what it means.

It is also the culmination of the dialectics that have just been examined. Hermeneutics is

the site of interrelated problematics—the determination of selfhood by way of its contrast

with sameness, and the determination of selfhood by way of its dialectic with otherness.81

80 Ibid., 355. 81 Ibid., 297.

Page 33: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

33

The text can be considered the central object in Ricœur’s hermeneutics, defined

broadly as “any discourse fixed by writing” 82 It might seem that written discourse is

simply transcribed speech, or speech “once removed”, stripped of its immediacy.

But this definition does not mean that a text is nothing but a fixation of spoken words or of words that might as well have been spoken. The text stands in another relation to discourse than does the spoken word; writing is parallel to speech, but what characterizes it is its ability to preserve discourse and to turn it into an archive for both the individual and the common memory. 83 Thus both the spoken word and text have a function and significance, and both

will play an essential part in the development of the notion of community.

I have chosen to elaborate this point here because it strikes me as a way of

interpreting texts (the implications for specifically biblical texts are obvious) in a way

that does not lead to relativism or nihilism. In order to follow the development of

Ricœur’s hermeneutics, we must first examine the notion of the text.

Ricœur calls texts “the greatest enigma that the hermeneutic status of the

phenomenology of religion poses for us.” 84 Texts are products with particular cultural

origins and, most importantly, with implications for human relationships and actions.

Texts are not groundless or static, they are born and the birth and mediation of a text

takes place temporally within a community and has a direction or goal. If we were to

stay within the limits of a text then there would be no criteria for choosing among

conflicting interpretations, hence, the so-called postmodern relativism which pits various

understandings against each other by giving them all “equal” status. However, if texts

82 Paul Ricœur, Hermeneutics and the Human Sciences: Essays on Language, Action, and Interpretation (Ed. and trans. John B. Thompson. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; Paris: Editions de la Maison des Sciences de l’Homme, 1981), p.145. 83 Ibid.

Page 34: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

34

are understood culturally, and even more specifically as belonging to a community, then

they are grounded and take on a new level of significance. The text can be distanced from

its original context and emancipated from its author, thereby assuming a life of its own.

This autonomy frees the text (now “alive”) to be continually reinterpreted. In this sense

the text is living, being constantly re-actualized, re-interpreted, and re-contextualized. In

this process the reader, as part of a community, plays the central role, initiating an

appropriation of the text.

Inseparable from his discussion of texts is Ricœur’s notion of hermeneutics, the

way texts are understood. “[H]ermeneutics designates the art of textual interpretation, as

instanced in biblical exegesis and classical philology.” 85 Ricœur’s discussion of

discourse necessitates the first two elements considered, the self and alterity.

Subjectivity, as defined by Ricœur, is completely intertwined with his concept of text—

confronting a text is a form of self-understanding and self-transformation, hence its

pivotal place in Ricœur’s philosophy. Encountering a text is a challenge, representing

that which is “other”. We understand this new horizon by relating it to our own—

expanding and renewing ourselves through this contact with alterity by means of text.

Knowledge is not representation, as was the case in modernity, but transformation.

Ricœur believes that we are interpreting beings, incapable of existing without interpreting

signs. We interpret in a particular fashion based on the culture and tradition to which we

belong. This art of interpretation of texts is known as hermeneutics and is essential when

84 Dominique Janicaud, “The Theological Turn of French Phenomenology” Trans. Bernard George Prusak. Phenomenology and the “Theological” Turn: The French Debate. Perspectives in Continental Philosophy. Vol.15. Ed. John D. Caputo. (New York: Fordham University Press, 2000), p.132. 85 Madison 290.

Page 35: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

35

posing questions related to subjectivity . “Every hermeneutics […] is explicitly or

implicitly self-understanding.” 86

Ricœur moves from a concern with interpreting symbols and deciphering their

hidden meaning (due to the contingency of symbols on a particular cultural context) 87

toward a more linguistic and systematic approach that emphasizes written texts. His most

recent work culminates in the development of phenomenological hermeneutics, a term

with Heideggerian origin.

At this point we are confronted with the problematic hermeneutic circle: the

whole is interpreted in light of the various parts and vice versa. For instance, religions

founded on the word of God, the Logos, are not accessible apart from considering texts

thought to be holy, and those texts are considered holy based on their divine inspiration.

There is another circle present as well—that of the community acknowledging the

scriptures as its foundation and therefore preserving the holy as such. The relationship is

mutual—the Logos and confessing community each constitute and are constituted by the

other. What appears to be a “fusion of horizons” (to borrow a term from Hans Georg

Gadamer), however, is not a true fusion: we do not coincide with the ideas of another

person but rather discover their view. Their ideas are rendered intelligible and we

develop what Ricœur calls a “hermeneutical consciousness” 88 Our horizons are

constantly shifting based on encounters between self and other. Truth is dynamic rather

than static.

This [fusion of horizons] is a dialectical concept which results from the refection of two alternatives: objectivism, whereby the objectification of the other is

86 Paul Ricœur,The Conflict of Interpretations: Essays in Hermeneutics (Trans Don Ihde. Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1974), p.17. 87 Ibid., 317. 88 Ibid., 306.

Page 36: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

36

premised on the forgetting of oneself; and absolute knowledge, according to which universal history can be articulated within a single horizon. We exist neither in closed horizons, nor within an horizon that is unique. No horizon is closed, since it is possible to place oneself in another point of view and another culture [. . .] But no horizon is unique, since the tension between the other and oneself is unsurpassable.89 Here emerges Ricœurs most distinct contribution to the field of hermeneutics and

his expertise as a leading phenomenologist—what is called phenomenological

hermeneutics.

The question of method here is how is hermeneutics still a phenomenology. [Ricœur] says that hermeneutical phenomenology is a reflexive philosophy that remains within the fundamental inspiration of Husserl’s phenomenology. . . . Ricœur has rejected Husserl’s attempt to establish a self-foundational philosophy. He rejects a Cartesian--or Husserlian—attempt to found knowledge and the self on immediate and transparent consciousness. The most fundamental truth, the cogito, is as empty as it is certain. The self can only be understood by the ‘detour’ through works, actions, literature, and institutions. All self-understanding requires a hermeneutic of texts and text-like structures. 90

Why is a specifically phenomenological approach so important? Phenomenology

has evolved from considering language a superfluous layer imposed on “pure” lived

experiences towards a willingness to take into account the verbal expressions that have

given form to those experiences. The difficulty that Ricœur tries to address is the cultural

and historical element added onto the linguistic meditation. “Both phenomenology and

hermeneutics are committed to an understanding of the self and both are reflexive

methods that start in the middle of things, with both the world and our intersubjective

experiences as givens” 91

Ricœur, in his extensive and prolific career, shifts from a focus on Husserlian

phenomenology to a concern with symbols and language, which eventually develops into

89 Ricœur, Hermeneutics and the Human Sciences, 75. 90 Charles Reagan, “Paul Ricœur,” Encyclopedia of Phenomenology, 612. 91 Ibid.

Page 37: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

37

his notion of phenomenological hermeneutics, as a way of moving completely beyond

both objectivism and relativism. Humans by nature are relational beings (hence the fault

with a purely “objective” approach) yet philosophy without some sort of grounding

would be useless (thus the importance of phenomenology in Ricœur’s thought). Unlike

other forms of what could be considered postmodern thought, phenomenological

hermeneutics embraces the postmodern rejection of Enlightenment values but also seeks

to reconstruct those values in a way as to escape foundationalism without preaching

complete cultural, intellectual, or spiritual relativism.

For Ricœur, phenomenological hermeneutics is the explanation of symbolic

systems that bring humanity into contact with reality. At first glance the notion appears

to be contradictory—hermeneutics designates meditation or reflection while

phenomenology deals with immanence. Ricœur, however, does not see these two in

conflict. According to the method of phenomenology, that which eventually appears first

has to be discovered—involving a process. The task of “bracketing” is to make an object

or concept appear, and this task can be classified as hermeneutical.

Ricœur files complaint against structuralism, where the “individual capacity of

thinking and being creative tends to be denied in favour of the power of codes. To

understand man is to understand the structures that constitute his language, the networks

of myths and texts that constitute his culture, the social structures that constitute his

society.” 92 By rejecting this philosophy Ricœur reclaims the notion of man as subject.

Structuralist philosophy is simply “transcendentalism without a subject.” 93 Are not the

relations between humans and language and between language and the world more

92 Theodore Marius Van Leeuwen, The Surplus of Meaning: Ontology and Eschatology in the Philsophy of Paul Ricœur (Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1981) p.75.

Page 38: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

38

significant than the nature of the language structure itself? 94 Language is primarily

communication, a way of giving meaning to the world one inhabits. In place of this

structural approach, Ricœur posits a fundamentally phenomenological one, where the

immanence of language meets the transcendence of speech. “The presuppositions are

those of phenomenology: language expresses the meaning of the world and of being; the

subject is the bearer of this meaning. Man is the one who, by means of language, gives

sense to his world.” 95 96 Discourse is not a fixed and finite system but rather creation and

innovation. “Discourse is the event in which language takes on a temporal aspect.” 97

Language itself is an a-temporal possibility that becomes an actuality through discourse.

Community is the place where discourse finds expression.

I.D. Speech as Act: Interlocution and Narration

“La problemática del actuar humano, representa así un eje fundamental de su pensamiento. Cómo caracterizar al hombre que actúa, que decide, que toma iniciativas y se hace responsables de ellas? En dónde se enraiza esta capacidad que tiene el hombre de obrar libre y responsablemente? Qué es, en definitive, el actuar humano? Estas preguntas no cesan de acompañar la investigación de Ricoeur a lo largo de todo su obra.” 98

We see here how the elements are all interwoven—the event (praxis, acting out)

of discourse implies necessarily a self and an-other. In an anonymous a-temporal system

93 Ricœur, The Conflict of Interpretations: Essays in Hermeneutics, 53. 94 Van Leeuwen 76. 95 Ibid. 96 This is not to say that Ricœur offers a simple juxtaposition, “the openness of language to the lived world of experience to the closed state of the universe of signs in structural linguistics” (The Conflict of Interpretations 251). It is obviously through linguistics that the phenomenological-hermeneutic approach is possible. 97 Van Leeuwen 77. 98 “The problematic of human action represents a fundamental axis of Ricœur’s thought. How do we characterize the man who acts, who decides, who takes initiative and is responsible? And where does this capacity of man to act freely and responsibly take root? What is human action definitely? These questions do not cease to accompany Ricœur’s investigation throughout his work.” Eduardo Casarotti, “La

Page 39: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

39

the question ‘who is speaking?’ is irrelevant because language has no subject, there is no

“I” unless there is a discourse. 99 Ricœur distinguishes action from event--action is not

something that happens, but how we say what we do. Praxis, taking the form of speech,

is an event understood as the production of meaning. The fact that we say our actions

renders them meaningful. 100 Ricœur’s self is a self that speaks, and speech is the action

that renders the rest of human existence intelligible. In the consideration of speech

acts—broken down into the subcategories of interlocution and narration—we will see

how all the elements we have examined in Ricoeur’s philosophy are bound together. He

says that “[a]ction and agent belong to the same conceptual schema, containing notions

such as circumstances, intentions, motives, deliberations, voluntary or involuntary

motions, passiveness, constraints, intended or unintended results, and so on.” 101 His

theory of language denies the dichotomy present in structuralism between parole and

langue, speech acts and language as a system of signs. Speaking, as a creative act, is

simultaneously self-discovery and self-constitution. This act, however, is not creation ex

nihlo, it takes place against the background of language embedded in history. The self

enters into discourse by speaking, through narration. This translates into an action that

enters into time and space.

First speech action: interlocution; defined as spoken language occurring between

two or more people. Ricœur describes the “complex situation of interlocution”:

Facing the speaker in the first person is a listener in the second person to whom the former addresses himself or herself—this fact belongs to the situation of interlocution. So, there is not illocution without allocution and, by implication,

constitucion narrativa de la identidad personal,” Filósofos de Hoy. http://fp.chasque.apc.org:8081/relacion/9905/filosofos_de_hoy.htm 99 Van Leeuwen 78. 100 Ted Klein, “The Idea of a Hermeneutical Ethics” Hahn, 351. 101 Ricœur, Oneself as Another, 51.

Page 40: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

40

without someone to whom the message addressed. The utterance that is reflected in the sense of the statement is therefore straightaway a bipolar phenomenon: it implies simultaneously an ‘I’: that speaks to a ‘you’ to whom the former addresses itself. ‘I affirm that’ equals ‘I declare to you that’; ‘I promise that’ equals ‘I promise you that.’ In short, utterance equals interlocution. 102

Language is made up of references, which are the bond between discourse and

world. The world, or site of praxis, is always topic or subject of discourse. Language

can be seen as the event while the speakers are the actors contained in a specific context.

Ricœur demonstrates the integration of interpretation into process of signification.

Presence of the other is required for interlocution and the whole process is thus placed in

a communicative setting. Language, orally in the form of speech, is the method of

communication—note the proximity of the words communication and community.

Language in the context of community functions as the link between human

understanding and reality. This is not to say that everything can be reduced to language,

nor does it negate the possibility of non-linguistic experience, it simply affirms the way

humans act and interact and thereby both constitute and understand reality. “There is no

world without a self who finds itself in it and acts in it; there is no self without a world

that is practicable in some fashion.” 103 The ideas are interdependent.

The second subset of spoken language we will examine is narration, because it is

within the framework of narrative theory that the selfhood/sameness and selfhood/other

dialectics reach their fullest development. Narration closes the gap between idem and

ipse identity. Ricœur places narration in between description and prescription as that

which connects them, serving as the link to that which is normative. 104

102 Ibid., 43-44. 103 Ibid., 58. 104 It could be argued that this with this normative element Ricœur strays from pure phenomenology’s emphasis on description

Page 41: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

41

[B]y placing narrative theory at the crossroads of the theory of action and moral theory, we have made narration serve as a natural transition between description and prescription [. . .] The actions refigured by narrative fictions are complex ones, rich in anticipations of an ethical nature. Telling a story, we observed, is deploying an imaginary pace for thought experiments in which moral judgment operates in hypothetical mode.” Selves in their complexity becomes woven together in a web of perspectives, the dissolution of self-identity gives way to a definition of the self as both receiver and giver of action. 105 What would the notion of praxis look like in Ricœur’s thought once it moved

from the hypothetical to the actual? His philosophy is vague but nonetheless has a distinct

orientation towards the future and possibility. Human existence is not limited to the

present actuality, there is a “ ‘surplus of being’ to human existence, and this surplus is

nothing other than possibility.” 106 As humans, we have the possibility, indeed capability,

(and Levinas will argue responsibility) to direct our own existence. Ricœur’s

hermeneutics is based on religious and biblical history; it is an exploration of capacities

“which make the human being a being of the future, namely the bearer of unfulfilled

promise.” 107

Ricœur sees the notion of praxis as key to his work in Oneself as Another, stating,

“one could say that these studies together have as their thematic unity human action and

that the notion of action acquires, over the course of the studies, an ever-increasing

extension and concreteness.”108 Here the discussion loops back around to recapture ideas

stated in the three previous sub-sections. The importance of speech acts has just been

demonstrated, and it is these speech acts that constitute agents of action and allow the

105 Ricœur, Oneself as Another, 170. 106 Kevin J. Vanhoozer, (Biblical Narrative in the Philosophy of Paul Ricœur: A Study in Hermeneutics and Theology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), p.7. 107 Ricœur, “Reply to Don Ihde.” Hahn, 73. 108 Ricœur, Oneself as Another 19.

Page 42: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

42

agent of action be designated as the one who is acting. “The questions ‘Who is

speaking?’ and ‘Who is acting’ appear to be closely interconnected.” 109

It is evident that Ricœur’s philosophy of narrative identity is contingent upon

individuals living in a community made up of interwoven stories.

We are subjects in others’ stories, others are subjects in our stories; others are authors of our stories, we are authors of others’ stories. Our narratives are essentially interwoven with other narratives. We are characters in other narratives [. . .] Through our discussions and interactions with others we facilitate the articulation and direction or their narratives, and they ours. All this to say that our identity is never simply our own. It is embedded with relations with others and we do not have ultimate control over the nature of these relationships much less the nature of our identity. 110

Long gone is the tradition of Enlightenment thinking affirming the capacity of

each individual to constitute identity given recourse to reason. While Ricœur’s

philosophy cannot properly be called post-metaphysical, he is nevertheless interested in

fundamentally re-thinking ontology. “Ricœur’s wager for meaningfulness is itself fully

warranted when it is extricated from all metaphysical contexts, as indeed it is when it is

grounded in the hermeneutical implications of human action and narrative discourse.” 111

112 The meaning of being is too often confused with meaning-as-being. Past ontologies

have lost the authority needed to act as a base for Ricœur’s hermeneutics, he sees the new

meaning of being (i.e. a new ontology) as “act and potentiality”.113 This rejection of

traditional ontologies is a thread running through the work of Ricœur, Levinas, and

Marion. Eventually we come to understand that it is praxis that allows us to interpret the

world as meaningful, and the origin of praxis is in a communally interpreted text.

109 Ibid., 17. 110 Vessey 1. 111 Schrag, The Self After Postmodernity, 88. 112 Ricœur himself resists applying the term post-metaphysical to his work, believing the terms “metaphysics” and “onto-theology” are too often treated as interchangeable terms.

Page 43: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

43

From Ricœur’s work that we have briefly examined here, we can ascertain his

relationship to the idea of religious community. His philosophy, while resting on the

notion of the solitary self, finds fullness in his hermeneutics of language and belief.

“Setting up a self through the mediation of the Scriptures and the application of oneself

of the multiple figures of naming God happens at the level of our most fundamental

capacity for action. It is the homo capax, capable man, who is interpellated and

restored.” 114 Essentially Ricœur’s philosophy is one calling for action, a praxis (practice)

that is rendered meaningful against the background of religious community.

Even as a self-proclaimed Protestant Ricœur’s position concerning personal faith

is difficult to determine from his work, and in no way does he claim to be a theologian.

“Though it is evident that Ricœur views himself in the vanguard of a renaissance of the

sacred, he is more concerned with elaborating the condition for the possibility of

revelation and redemption rather than with proclaiming their historical achievement. [. . .]

Ricœur is perhaps best viewed as an apologist for the intelligibility of the Christian

kerygma.” 115 In the introduction to Oneself as Another, Ricœur tells us about certain

final chapters that were part of the original series of lectures 116 (upon which the book was

based) but were not included in the final print version. The focus of these chapters was

Ricœur’s biblical hermeneutics. He chose to exclude them for several reasons (which

Ricœur himself calls “debatable and perhaps even regrettable”117), primarily because he

wanted to pursue “an autonomous, philosophical discourse” 118 and avoid the dogmatism

113 Ricœur, Oneself as Another. 20. 114 Ricœur, Hermeneutics and the Human Sciences, 146. 115 Vanhoozer 284. 116 Gifford Lectures, Edinburgh, 1986. 117 Oneself as Another 24. 118 Ibid.

Page 44: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

44

often associated with theological hermeneutics. In bracketing his personal convictions,

Ricoeur nevertheless acknowledges that this omission does not mean that he is

uninterested in the problematic of the self as it relates to biblical hermeneutics. Oneself

as Another is characteristic of Ricœur’s work at large: “It will be observed that this

asceticism of the argument, which marks, I believe, all my philosophical work, leads to a

type of philosophy from which the actual mention of God is absent and in which the

question of God, as a philosophical question, itself remains in a suspension that could be

called agnostic.” 119 120 The fact that he does not fully extend his thought to its

implications for religious concerns is both a strength and a shortcoming in Ricœur’s

work. Nevertheless, I believe that his philosophy tacitly necessitates the idea of religious

community as the space where the elements under consideration become thinkable and

take on shape. The self, possessing identity understood as ipse, having been constituted

by its encounter with alterity, interprets texts and gives meaning to the world by being

grounded temporally and culturally. The community is not an arbitrary grounding but the

space where the self interacts with and is constituted by these elements (the Other,

discourse, narration)—apart from an understanding of community these interactions

would remain senseless.

119 Ibid. 120 For consideration of Ricœur’s relation to Christianity in both his writings and his life see: Loretta Dornisch, Faith and Philosophy in the Writings of Paul Ricoeur (Problems in Contemporary Philosophy. Vol. 29. Lewiston, NY: The Edwin Mellen Press, 1990) Chap.2 “The Christian Context”; also Francois Dosse’s biography Paul Ricœur: Le sens d’une vie, ”Entre le philosophie et le religieux: ni confusion…” (653-664) and “Entre le philosophie et le religieux:…ni separation” (665-680).

Page 45: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

45

II. EMMANUEL LEVINAS

“I was strongly attracted to the prophetic fervor of Levinas, to his biblical call for justice, to this remarkable phenomenon of a philosopher-cum-prophet, of a distinctly prophetic voice, raised up among the postmoderns. Levinas seemed to me a kind of modern-day (or post-modern-day) Amos, albeit of a rather more Parisian sort.” 121 Emmanuel Levinas has had an enormous influence in contemporary French

philosophy and is credited with introducing phenomenology into France. He produced an

impressive body of work during his forty-year career, and the number of secondary

sources concerning his work is continually increasing 122 as a tribute to his impact. 123

Lithuanian by birth, in 1928 Levinas went to Freiburg to study phenomenology under

Husserl and later Heidegger and maintained precarious relationships with both men,

eventually distancing himself from Heidegger during WWII given the latter’s affiliation

with Nazism. In 1940 Levinas became prisoner of war and was sent to a forced labor

camp, while his parents, brothers, and many relatives were all killed in Nazi-related

genocide in the Ukraine.

During the fifties Levinas began to develop his philosophy of ethics arising in part

from what he considered the ethically neutral ontological tradition. His work was little

known prior to the publication of Totalité et Infini in 1961. The main thrust of the work is

the relationship between the self and Other, establishing Levinas as a phenomenologist of

alterity. In his 1974 publication Autrement qu’Etre Levinas elaborates these ideas and

121 Captuo, Demythologizing Heidegger, p3 122 See attached extended bibliography on Levinas 123 Surprisingly, given his impact upon continental philosophy, Levinas has not had as much influence in analytic circles as one might expect. This frequent omission is caused by several features of his writing: “Because of its dense style and apparent abandonment of rational argument and justification in favour of repetitive incantations and quasi-religious absolutist pronouncements, Levinas’s work is largely ignored among analytic philosophers. One is tempted to say that, rather than revealing things in the

Page 46: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

46

declares his intention to overcome ontology. Levinas has also written extensively on

Talmudic interpretation, however, he has been intentional about establishing himself as a

philosopher by using a separate publisher for his religious writings. Two of his so-called

religious works will appear in the following discussion—Of God Who Comes to Mind

and Difficult Freedom.

Levinas’s preoccupation with the possibility of an encounter with the Other is

evident throughout his work. Drawing extensively on the work of Heidegger, Levinas

immediately attempts to refute the charge that objects intended by the consciousness are

also constituted by it. According to Husserl, the object is always an intentional object,

because the mode of access to the object partially forms the object itself. Levinas would

say that intentionality does not entirely replicate that which is already possessed by

consciousness because consciousness is part of the world and the subject-object duality

denies the sovereignty or independence of either. Levinas’s definition of intentionality is

modified to include this idea of a process as continual interchange which he will define as

a relationship to alterity that denies the hegemony of the same. He charges Husserl with

a flawed understanding of consciousness, as revealed through phenomenological

reduction and appearing to stand apart from time and experience. Nevertheless, Levinas

comments, “Despite everything, what I am doing is phenomenology, even if there is no

reduction according to the rules set by Husserl, even if the whole Husserlian method is

not respected” 124

Given his discrepancies with Husserl, why does Levinas choose to employ the

phenomenological method and vocabulary? For Levinas, phenomenology triumphs over

phenomenological sense, Levinas’s thought appears to levitate above them, completely preoccupied with its own self-referential system.” Morgan 352.

Page 47: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

47

other philosophies because allows what is distinctly human to emerge. “Levinas credits

Husserl with reawakening philosophy to the possibility of being able to describe

concrete, lived human life, without reducing it to a series of inner psychic experiences (as

with the Cartesian way of viewing consciousness).” 125 Levinas follows Heidegger in

seeing the traditional concept of God as too dependant upon the realm of being, he is

interested in getting past God as an ontological characterization and phenomenology

allows such a pursuit. The notion of God runs through Levinas’s work but should not be

confused with the notion of the existence of God, which would remain entirely within the

category of metaphysics. “For Levinas, that which challenges the sphere of totality may

be understood as ‘transcendence’, the ‘other’, and ‘the infinite’; and Levinas may be seen

as trying to open up phenomenology to describe this transcendent dimension of human

experience.”126 Levinas begins from Heidegger’s existential philosophy of being-in-the-

world as opposed to Husserl’s transcendental idealism. Knowledge does not unfold in

isolation or neutrality but rather from an existential grounding in lived experience.

II.A. “Defense of Subjectivity”

In Totality and Infinity Levinas demonstrates the key role subjectivity plays in his

philosophy, it is fundamental to his subsequent development of alterity for which he is

best known and thus a logical place to begin the discussion. In the introduction, Levinas

states: “This book then does present itself as a defense of subjectivity, but it will

apprehend the subjectivity not at the level of its purely egoist protestation against infinity,

124 Levinas, Of God Who Comes to Mind, 140. 125 Morgan 328. 126 Morgan 329.

Page 48: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

48

nor in its anguish before death, but as founded in the idea of infinity.” 127 Subjectivity

understood in Levinas’s terms is not self-reflexive or egotistical. Infinity is the idea we

have of God, clearly distinguished from totality, which would be a misrepresentation. He

does not want to stay trapped in Descartes’ circle of immanence (the mind that locks

thought in itself), nor he does not want to deny integrity to the subject. He accomplishes

this task by grounding the idea of subjectivity in infinity. “Me voici” (here I am) is the

statement that precedes self-consciousness. “[H]ow does this pre-originary self express

itself? As someone, experienced as an Ego (Moi) but on a level prior to (i.e. beneath and

beyond) any awareness of itself as self and expressed only by articulating the total

exposure of the self-signifying sign to the Other in saying ‘me voici,’ that is ‘vois-moi

ici,’ ‘see me here,’ ‘here I am.’” 128

Can Levinas’s concept of the self and subjectivity be called post-metaphysical?

The Cartesian subject seizes itself as subject by reference to the non-self. Likewise, an

encounter with the infinite is utterly resistant to the solipsism of the transcendental Ego.

In this way Descartes discovers a relation with a total alterity irreducible to interiority and

his infinite God becomes the basis for the Other in Levinas’s thought. “I do not get an

answer to the question, Who am I? by regarding myself but by responding to somebody

and by distinguishing myself from the Other in responding to him. I do not proceed from

myself, but rather I return to myself by a retrograde movement that Levinas calls

recurrence.” 129

127 Levinas, Totality and Infinity, 26. 128 William J. Richardson, “The Irresponsible Subject,” Ethics as First Philosophy, ed. A. Peperzak. (New York: Routledge, 1995), p.129. 129 Bernhard Waldenfels, “Response and Responsibility in Levinas” Ethics as First Philosophy , ed. A. Peperzak, p.42

Page 49: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

49

If the relationship with alterity is constitutive of subjectivity, how is it conceived?

Levinas works to free subjectivity from ontological constraints, thus the title of his work

Otherwise than Being.

[S]ubjectivity is not ontologically elucidated by showing how the movement of Being issues in its constitution as an entity—or by showing how it constitutes itself as a term and a commencement by an ecstatic flight from Being. Levinas opposes the ontological philosophy which accounts for subjectivity as a locus or moment engendered by the inner movement of Being for its own exhibition. He intends to show subjectivity as the locus where alterity makes contact, a locus finally created by this movement of alterity. As support of alterity, subjectivity’s final meaning is not to be a subsistent entity or moment of Being. 130

To what extent can Levinas’ idea of self be linked to his Jewish roots? There

appears to be a certain privileged sense of having been chosen, which then gives action

meaning (this idea will be developed in the next section as it relates to human interaction,

i.e., self and other in a reciprocal relationship). Levinas’ writing focuses on the

correlative themes of freedom and responsibility—starting with the individual but

necessarily implicating a relationship with the Other.

The self is unique and free, asserting its freedom to answer the call that appoints it

as unique: “[. . .] someone constitutes him- or herself as ‘subject’ by assuming

responsibility, by being responsible.” 131 Responsibility is the consummation of the self

and a prerequisite for freedom, yet paradoxically the self is contingent upon both

responsibility and freedom simultaneously. “The coinciding of freedom and

responsibility constitutes the I.” 132 The awareness of responsibility is a necessity for the

existence of freedom, which then becomes a limitless freedom grounded in the idea of

130 Levinas, Otherwise than Being, xxii. 131 Waldenfels 40. 132 Levinas, Totality and Infinity, 271.

Page 50: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

50

infinity. The base for a Jewish concept of community is the individual, responsible to

God and Other, possessing infinite freedom within this responsibility.

The discussion of alterity is so central to Levinas’s philosophy that it becomes

impossible to delve too deeply into a discussion of the self without implying something

about the relationship to the Other. Levinas interprets subjectivity as subjection to the

other, not as a concept that exists independently. “The other means that which cannot be

objectified, the sphere of subjectivity, although not understood in the spirit of mastery,

but rather as founded on openness to the other.” 133 The self is understood as constituted

by alterity, therefore we will move to a discussion of the second element.

II.B. The Levinasian Other: Face and Trace

Levinas indicts totalistic thinking for having reduced alterity to something

provisionally separate from the Same or the self but ultimately reconcilable with it.

Systems of power, rooted in totality, have served the ontological domination of history by

labeling certain ideas as “true” based on how well they can be situated within an already

familiar system of references. “Totalité et infini proposes a revolution, not only in

phenomenology, but with regard the entire history of European philosophy. [. . . ]

Western thought and practice are ruled by a desire for totalization; an attempt is made to

reduce the universe to an originary and ultimate unity by way of panoramic overviews

and dialectical syntheses.” 134

According to Levinas, ontological thinking is actually atheistic at its core—by

denying the existence of anything outside itself there is no room for transcendence and

133 Morgan 342. 134 Peperzak, “Emmanuel Levinas,” Encyclopedia of Phenomenology, p. 414.

Page 51: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

51

theology finds itself in the place of having to justify its position through philosophical

discourse. It becomes a pawn of the rational reasoning that claims absolute authority

over meaning and significance. However, Levinas does not advocate mysticism or a

simple naïve faith, he sees these as reaffirming the ontological view by placing God once

again within the category of being. “God is an object of knowledge revealed to the

subject, experienced as a presence. The alleged transcendence of God thereby turns out

to be a kind of immanence: God is ultimately understood as part of our own world.” 135

What exactly is meant by the term Other in the Levinasian sense? In this

subsection we will look at the way the Other refers to a person, another human, (le

prochain, neighbor, autrui) then to God (the Infinite or Divine).

The other is not merely an alter-ego, not an object to be categorized and made a

part of my world. Levinas strives to preserve the Other: once familiar, the Other has lost

its distinguishing quality, that of strangeness. The danger for Levinas lies in transforming

the Other into a reflection of the Same and violating its alterity—i.e., allowing the Other

to become an object of knowledge or experience. How then does Levinas discuss the

Other without familiarizing it and thus robbing it of its otherness? In phenomenological

terms, traditional philosophy has imposed concepts and systems of constraint upon the

other, Levinas even accuses Husserl of supressing the “otherness” of phenomena.

“Emmanuel Levinas’s phenomenology is closely attentive to the way in which other

human beings inhabit the horizons of my experience and present themselves as a demand

to me, a call on me to get outside the sphere of my own preoccupations.” 136 For Levinas,

the Other lies absolutely beyond comprehension and should be preserved in all its

135 Davis 96. 136 Morgan 5.

Page 52: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

52

irreducible strangeness. The otherness of the Other is manifested in the face of another

human. We belong to communities that function according to reciprocal needs, but in

order for the concept of community to exist we first have to escape the horizon of the

personal ego. Consideration for the other is not about subjective needs and desires—the

face of the Other (i.e. the other facing me) interrupts and brings people into ethical

relationships.

Levinas acknowledges that there is a desire for the otherness of the other, yet as

such this desire can never be satisfied because once otherness is possessed it is lost.

Something must first present this otherness to consciousness in order to prevent it from

being assimilated and reduced to the Same. Levinas localizes the appearance of this

otherness in the face-to-face situation. The face of the Other resists my power to

assimilate the Other into my knowledge and realm of experience. This encounter with

the Other through the face-to-face is also the birthplace of responsibility and ethics. The

possibility of an encounter with Other (which exists prior to our recognition of it) puts

my power and freedom into question and makes me responsible.

Perhaps here we find something particularly Jewish about Levinas’s thinking—he

interprets the meaning of each and every experience in light of the ethical relation

between people, in appealing to our personal responsibility in which each individual is

unique and chosen. The Divine is manifested through my neighbor.137 Levinas prefers le

prochain to the more abstract Autrui—the neighbor is close, a real person in my

proximity rather than a philosophical abstraction.138 The idea of freedom being subject

137 Levinas, Difficult Freedom, 159. 138 Anthony F. Beavers, “Emmanuel Levinas and the Prophetic Voice of Postmodernity,” http://cedar.evansville.edu/~tb2/trip/prophet.htm

Page 53: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

53

to the exteriority of the Other, our neighbor, is a main idea of Hebraic tradition; moral

freedom must be constantly oriented by exteriority of other.

Levinas says that language is the way we coexist with the other while keeping

otherness intact. I make my world available in words to the other as the expression of a

desire that transcends myself. “To speak, at the same time as knowing the Other, is

making oneself known to him. The Other is not only known, he is greeted [salué]. He is

not only named, but also invoked. To put it in grammatical terms, the Other does not

appear in the nominative, but in the vocative.” 139 This is an important distinction for

Levinas: I can either appropriate the Other or through language give myself to the Other.

The manifestation of the face (a living presence or expression) is discourse,140 and

“[Discourse] is the production of meaning” 141 The revealer and the revealed coincide in

the face and discourse is how we relate to that which transcends us. The Other remains

absolute in the discursive relation, not reduced to the realm of the same.

In Levinas’s philosophy the face of the other is the origin of language and

meaning. The other is presented through the act of speaking: me voici (here I am). This

statement foreshadows our discussion of discourse in Levinas, and then reciprocally the

notion of praxis—the response to the face is morality, responsibility is necessitated by the

call. “The face is present in its refusal to be contained. In this sense it cannot be

comprehended, that is, encompassed. It is neither seen nor touched—for in visual or

tactile sensation the identity of the I envelops the alterity of the object, which becomes

precisely a content.” 142

139 Levinas, Difficult Freedom, 7. 140 Levinas, Totality and Infinity, 66. 141 Ibid. 142 Ibid. 194.

Page 54: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

54

Responsibility is a form of recognition and also constitutive of subjectivity, it is

the way one expresses oneself to the other. This notion is incomprehensible without the

face as the expression and experience of alterity. Levinas’s “…ethical philosophy of

responsibility grounded in phenomenology of the face (or quasi-phenomenology: for a

face is not so much a mode of appearing of the other as a ‘trace’ where alterity

passes)…” 143 In his discussion of the trace Levinas passes from an understanding of

alterity as another person to alterity as God, the Divine, to which he gives the name illeity

(illeité).

The trace is the most complete and accurate way the divine can be comprehended.

Levinas uses the word illeity to express the remote otherness of God—the logical

question that follows is: How do we speak of illeity without reducing God to our own

familiar, ontologically-bound terms? Of God who Comes to Mind sets out as an

investigation into understanding “God” as a meaningful word. God is not an essence,

substance, or Being, (each of these terms belongs to the obsolete vocabulary of ontology),

rather God is that which is radically exterior. Levinas is not willing to speak of God in

terms of negative theology because even that would permit the indirect characterization

of what God is and thereby falls short due to its dependence on the language of

immanence and ontology. God is transcendence encountered at core of subjectivity,

recognized by the trace.

The trace is what we know of God, that which God leaves behind in the world. It

is not a sign pointing to a signified or a remainder of that which was originally present

and is now gone. Levinas distinguishes between the terms a-Dieu, dieu, and adieu. He

143 Levinas, Otherwise than Being, xxi.

Page 55: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

55

uses the term “a-Dieu” where the “a” suggests a movement, instead of dieu to avoid

implication that God can be considered a noun referring to a substance with separate

existence. The adieu suggests a farewell to God as ontological category; God as area of

sense not commanded by consciousness.144 It is important to note that “autrement

qu’être” (otherwise than being)—the title of Levinas’s text—is not equal to être

autrement (being otherwise). This distinction is crucial if the danger of turning the other-

than-Being into simply another Being (albeit a different one) is to be avoided.

The Other as Divine and Infinite is transcendent, interrupting the ego.

Transcendence is not that which transports us to another place or time but rather a

commandment: transcend yourselves and remain in the here and now. The community is

the place where we have transcendent encounters with the Other—where alterity in both

the human and divine sense is preserved and we are called to be responsible. Levinas’s

philosophy is a phenomenology (or transphenomenology) of the modes in which the

Other is revealed; in some ways his thinking passes the limits of phenomenology—

alterity cannot be conceived of either as a phenomenon or as a being. Levinas’s move

beyond ontology is evident--the contact between the Ego and the Other is

incomprehensible within an ontological framework. Levinas is critical of Heidegger’s

phenomenology because he believes it still brings the Other back into Dasein.145 146

144 Davis 98. 145 Ibid. 146 One possible critique of Levinas is that he tries to develop non-ontological language to express the beyond of Being but uses the very same language to overcome it

Page 56: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

56

II.C. The Saying and the Said

I have divided the section on discourse as it appears in Levinas’s work into two

parts—primarily his distinction between the Saying and the Said, with some analysis of

his treatment of texts and Talmudic writings in particular.

In Otherwise than Being, Levinas distinguishes between le Dire (the Saying) and

le Dit (the Said). He accuses traditional philosophy of only being concerned with the

Said, without recognizing the underlying significance of the Saying. When philosophers

concentrate only on what is said they overlook the essential exposure to the Other—

without this exposure meaning would not exist. Every utterance is a situation or structure

or event which includes an exposure to the Other as a speaker or receiver of discourse.

The Saying does not equal that which is said but refers to the action of giving myself to

another in discourse, of interacting with the Other. Language, far from being a mere

representation of reality, is a way of presenting myself to the Other. While the Said is the

birthplace of ontology, the Saying is the place where proximity to the Other is at last

conceivable, the place of ethics and responsibility. It is where that which escapes Being,

(i.e., the Infinite) can be sought.

For Levinas the Saying and the Said are two aspects of language which bear their

own distinct meanings. It is easier to analyze the Said because it is an intentional

communication, whereas the Saying is more elusive. In short, the Said can be seen as the

traditional philosophical discourse that overlooks the encounter with the Other, (i.e., the

event of language, the Saying). Levinas is very aware of the difficulty of trying to make

the Saying an object of philosophical discourse or enquiry because the attempt alone

suffices to bring the Saying into the realm of the Said and thereby strip it of its essential

Page 57: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

57

quality, that which is Other about it. The problems are parallel: the Other is in danger of

becoming an alter ego the same way that the Saying is in danger of being reduced to the

Said. “The movement back toward Saying is the phenomenological reduction in which

the indescribable is described” 147 Who does the Saying? It is a self, pre-original,

irreducible point of reference, a self not yet conscious of itself.

The reduction to Saying leads back to something pre-original, pre-phenomenological, before the constitution of the Ego and the birth of consciousness [. . .] The subject, for Levinas, is not the humanist or existentialist originator of its own actions and meanings, but neither is it the structuralist or post-structuralist battleground of structures and ideologies. Prior to consciousness, hence also prior to choice, commitment, activity or passivity, the subject is exposed to the Other, capable of speaking and responding to the discourse of others. Most importantly, the ethical nature of this exposure is brought out by the verbal link between the ability to respond and responsibility: ‘saying is to be responsible for others [dire, c’est répondre d’autrui]. 148

Also included in this section on discourse is Levinas’s writings about text, in

particular his Talmudic interpretations. The Talmud, as a text and as a prophetic book, is

of utmost significance for Levinas—a source of inspiration and a possible explanation for

human discontent with discursive reasoning. The appeal to prophetic inspiration

demonstrates that the Saying is greater than being and transcends it; the Infinite is that

which directs all thoughts and all words toward meaning.

The community is the space of the Saying, not the already established Said but the

place of living discourse which plays a fundamental part in his philosophy, as was the

case with Ricœur.

Levinas sees no contradiction between respecting the authority of a particular text

and simultaneously allowing for the uniqueness of each individual interpretation, given

the inexhaustible meaning of the Talmud and the possibility of revelation informing and

147 Levinas, Otherwise than Being, 53.

Page 58: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

58

modifying interpretation. The reader solicits the text with current interests in mind, and

is reciprocally solicited by the text to an exploration of meaning. The biblical and

talmudic texts invite the reader to explore context of quotation in light of the

particularities of the current discussion. Following Ricœur, Levinas draws on Gadamer’s

hermeneutics: the act of reading brings about a fusion of horizons and is rooted in

tradition. In this way interpretation is saved from arbitrariness, subjectivism, and

“hermeneutic nihilism” 149 Levinas’s talmudic readings leave space for innovation—the

reader plays active role but not exclusive role in the production of meaning.

Discourse in the form of prayer occupies an important place in Levinas’s talmudic

writings. The idea of prayer, as grounded in a community, highlights a different aspect of

discourse—having its origin in the ‘here below’, prayer moves beyond language,

transcending it:

In [prayer] the individual renews his links—through the number, or minyan—with the community of Israel dispersed throughout space and time, and through this unity he renews his links with the highest Unity. His presence and participation in the office, for which the prayer of an isolated person is often merely a consolation, the act of embracing such ancient expressions, such primordial thoughts, all those verbal gestures in a language that thousands of years of history have not destroyed—all this makes one conscious of the presence, permanence and eternity of Israel. 150 Levinas’s writings on prayer are rooted in the idea of community: “whatever the

ultimate meaning of prayer, whatever its heights or depths, it is collective prayer, familiar

to us all, that opens up this ultimate meaning to the daring tenderness of the few” 151

Essentially for Levinas it is God, by means of a community and through the method of

prayer, that allows for meaningful experience. For Levinas, one of the definitions of

148 Ibid., 47. 149 Davis 115. 150 Levinas, Difficult Freedom, 270.

Page 59: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

59

community is Israel; however, he is clear in his stipulation that Israel is not a substitute

for an experience but rather the context for the fulfillment of one. “Through Him it is

possible to have an elementary, massive and incomparable experience, one we must

cultivate in this way: the experience of the reunion of Israel. It does not, for all that,

represent a necessary collectivist substitute in the absence of any transcendent

nourishment.” 152

II.D. The Praxis of Ethical Relationships

The notion of praxis in Levinas’s work takes the shape of ethics. Ethics here

designates something other than the conventional or ontological definition. The exposure

to the Other, effected in the Saying, provides the core of Levinas’s ethics and

distinguishes it from traditional systems. We are in a world and community face-to-face

with others, responsible both to and for others. This responsibility is a prior condition to

the constitution of the self because who I am is defined and realized by coming into

contact with the Other. Otherness prevents totalizing conclusions and allows for a

meaningful communal relationship between self and other. Traditional ethical systems

are rooted in egoism but Levinas argues (and here diverges from conventional

definitions) that responsibility to the Other is actually the fundamental structure

underlying ethics. In this way, ethics precedes metaphysics. All social interaction

necessarily takes place within the sphere of the other. Therefore, ethics in the Levinasian

sense is an inescapable part of being human.

151 Ibid. 152 Ibid.

Page 60: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

60

What Levinas calls “L’ethique” (the ethical) does not mean ethics as norms for

behavior, rather, it is understood as “a domain from which nothing human can be

excluded,” 153 it is the space for consideration of identity and relation to the world.

Levinas frequently declares that he never wrote an ethics—not as doctrine about moral

principles, norms, obligations, or interdictions that rule human behavior. Ethics here

signifies the place where the ethical and theoretical cannot be opposed or even

distinguished, where opposition between “is” and “ought” is neither possible nor valid.

Morality is not simply a branch of philosophy but that which could be called a first

philosophy 154 because of its emphasis on the primacy of relationships. First philosophy

is the irreducible structure on which the rest of Levinas’s philosophy rests. He starts not

from the ego or cogito (as would a traditional metaphysics-based ethics), but with the

‘face-to-face’, a confrontation of two selves, confrontation that is both descriptive and

normative and the condition upon which subjectivity develops.155

153 Davis 3. 154 See Adriaan T. Pepperzak, Ethics as First Philosophy- a compilation of papers given at the International Levinas Conference “Ethics as First Philosophy? The significance of Emmanuel Levinas for Philosophy, Literature and Religion” at Loyola University Chicago, May 20-23 1993. 155 Here lies another possible critique of Levinas: the ethical dimension is supposedly where the descriptive and prescriptive meet, but this is ambiguous, and perhaps deliberately so. He is not always clear how, when, or why the move is made from “is” to “ought”.

Page 61: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

61

III. JEAN-LUC MARION

In his 1977 work L’idole et la distance Marion understands the “death of God” to

mean the death of the metaphysical concept of God. He undoes traditional Nietzschean

pessimism by arguing that perhaps the seeming failure of God (a God that is eventually

“killed” by modern humankind) is really proof of God’s loyal omnipresence. Marion

understands the true presence of God to be a function of distance, thus, if we have

“killed” God we have killed only what was nearby, that which was understood

ontologically, a function of the category of being. He goes further to say that not only is

God understood as a function of distance, but that even questions of presence or absence

fall into the category of that which needs to be deconstructed—namely, all concepts and

language that we have employed to render “God” understandable or accessible. Concepts

or definitions arising out of metaphysics are inherently flawed because they impose limits

on the limitless—God by definition exceeds every description we can invent. Marion

sees this failure as promising, opening up new space for a new theology of “God without

being”. Respect of distance and the refusal to reduce God to our concepts of Being allow

for true thought and language about that which has been in the past unthinkable and

ineffable. The key text for this section will be Marion’s God Without Being in which he

elaborates the discussion begun in Idol and Distance—he attempts to escape the limits

imposed by thinking in terms of being by understanding history as phenomenologically

signaling God’s presence in contrasting ways: the idolatrous versus the iconic.

Page 62: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

62

III.A. The Subject as Recipient and Participant

In a way that is reminiscent of Levinas’s philsophy of the Self and Other,

Marion’s subject only becomes such to the extent that he/she is subjected to the otherness

of another person—the subject is called into selfhood. Marion repeats Levinas’s

phenomenological grounding of subjectivity, which is a sense-bestowal from the exterior,

from an encounter with the Other. Marion refers to this sense-bestowal as the claim,

stating:

The claim calls me. I have not even been able to say, before the claim has already hailed me, and therefore has taken and comprehended me, because it has summoned and named me as a me. Indeed, what can I answer to a claim, if not ‘me voici! Speak!’ such that I no longer have to speak (myself) in the name of I?? The claim alone first speaks and therefore exempts me from the I and establishes me as a me. 156

This “naming” of the self is constitutive. It is Marion’s way of bypassing the

problem of the Ego and developing a sense of identity that does not have subjective

origins but is instead constructed in response to the claim. Why is the notion of the self a

key concept in Marion’s phenomenology? While he spends less time on the issue than

either Ricœur or Levinas, the self is one of the basic elements necessary for Marion to

develop the idea of donation (givenness): essentially the “me” becomes the recipient

when in relationship with God as Giver.

Marion’s subject provides the base for the other elements we will consider. They

are all contingent upon understanding the self as having been constituted by the claim.

From the idea of subjectivity we will proceed to formulate a concept of God as the non-

ontological Other (how does the subject conceive of the Divine in a way that avoids

idolatry); the self as the recipient of the saturated phenomenon (known only through

Page 63: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

63

revelation, i.e., revealed to the subject); and finally the self as participant in the Eucharist.

Marion’s philosophy culminates in this idea of participation—each individual partakes of

the body and blood of Christ and in that sense expresses and confirms their individual

faith, yet the Eucharist is simultaneously a communal activity where selves enter into

community with one another. These various functions and roles of the self will be

examined in more depth in the following subsections.

III.B. God as the Non-ontological Other: The Triumph of the Iconic Over the Idolatrous

For Marion alterity clearly refers to G⊗d—as contrasted with Ricœur’s ambiguity

and Levinas’s Other as both human neighbor and Infinite God—a continuous search for

alternate ways of speaking about the Divine, an attempt to be free of the quotation marks

by understanding “God” outside ontology.

As a well-known contemporary phenomenologist, Jean-Luc Marion initially

adopts the phenomenology of Heidegger, believing him to be the first to disassociate God

and Being, yet there is still a fundamental difference between Heidegger’s Being and

Marion’s G⊗d. This difference relates to the difference between a being and Being

(Daesin) as conceived by Heidegger—a being is something we can possess while Being

is elusive, avoiding description and explanation. The continual forgetting of this

difference has led to linking the two, to describing Being in terms of a being, to

constructing a metaphysics or ontology. These systems provide beings with a foundation

that eventually results in a highest Being which is its own cause (i.e., Descartes’ Causa

Sui). According to Marion, it is imperative that the distance be maintained between

156 Jean-Luc Marion, Reduction and Givenness: Investigations of Husserl, Heidegger, and Phenomenology. Trans. Thomas A. Carlson. (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1998) p.198.

Page 64: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

64

being and Being, and criticizes Heidegger for relegating God to a place within the system

that articulates this difference. For Marion, Heidegger’s injustice lies in the way he

reduces or neutralizes God instead of placing God completely apart from ontological

systems. In this, Marion considers Levinas a strong ally, for as we have seen Levinas is

preoccupied with maintaining the radical alterity of God which he terms illeity.

One of Marion’s major contributions has been his phenomenological discussion

of the idol and icon; it is this distinction that gives us access to that which is completely

other. It is helpful to preface the discussion with a clarification: the idol and icon are not

two different types of being. The same thing can be either one or the other at different

moments, because “[t]he idol and icon determine two manners of beings for being, not

two classes of beings.” 157 The comparative phenomenology of the idol and icon

concerns modes of apprehension and reception of the divine in visibility.

Marion states that “the conceptual idol has a site, metaphysics; a function, the

theology in onto-theology; and a definition, causa sui.” 158 The idol is the result of

human projection. Finding its origin in our human subjectivity, the idol represents our

expectations frozen into an image that simply reflects us back to ourselves. “The decisive

moment in the erection of an idol stems not from its fabrication, but from its investment

as gazeable, as that which will fill a gaze.” 159 The intention of the glance does not permit

itself to be transcended, thus neither the intention nor the glance itself are able to go past

the visible, they are fixed and reflected back to the gazing self. “The idol thus acts as a

mirror, not as a portrait: a mirror that reflects the gaze’s image, or more exactly, the

157 Marion, God Without Being, 9. 158 Ibid., 36. 159 Ibid., 10.

Page 65: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

65

image of its aim and the scope of that aim.” 160 However, the mirror remains invisible, so

the viewer has the illusion of seeing something divine when gazing at the idol. The

divine is enclosed and trapped in the human glance. “What renders the idol problematic

does not stem from a failure (e.g. that it offers only an ‘illusion’) but, on the contrary,

from the conditions of its validity—its radical immanence to the one who experiences it,

and experiences it, rightly so, as impassable.” 161 Measures used to gauge concepts

supposedly representing God are simply products of human thought. Idols are

conceptual—“When a philosophical thought expresses a concept of what it then names

“God”, this concept functions exactly as an idol.” 162 According to Marion, modernity’s

concept of God has developed in this idolatrous manner and has thus silenced God and

left humanity with the false conviction of having ‘killed’ God.

Marion’s phenomenology of the icon gives us access to the divine due to its origin

beyond subjectivity. The icon is not produced by the human glance as is the idol, the

icon summons the viewer’s glance. “The icon does not result from a vision but provokes

one.”163 With the icon the invisible is made visible because the glance and its intentions

are no longer frozen; they transcend the icon and find no rest, the glance can only focus

on infinity. “…the icon opens in a face that gazes at our gaze in order to summon them to

its depth” 164 This idea has biblical reinforcement: Paul’s letter to the Colossians refers to

Christ as “the icon of the invisible God” 165

160 Ibid., 12. 161 Ibid,. 28. 162 Ibid., 16. 163 Ibid., 17. 164 Ibid, 19. 165 Colossians 1:15

Page 66: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

66

God cannot enter our thoughts without saturating them, exceeding them, entering

into our thought “only in obliging it to criticize itself.” 166 The only scriptural idea that

serves as both name and intention is Agape, “God is Agape”.167 God as Love is not

fulfilled by being conceptualized and does not allow the idolatrous gaze: “For Love does

not present itself as an object to be admired and contemplated in and of itself, but rather

directs the recipient’s gaze to the Giver and Subject of that Love. Love does not pretend

to comprehend or embody the invisible but instead gives itself over in order that the

intention of the Giver might be encountered by the recipient.” 168 169

This notion of givenness that we touched upon in the intro becomes a central idea

in Marion’s philosophy. “For what is peculiar to love consists in the fact that it gives

itself. Now, to give itself, the gift does not require that an interlocutor receive it, or that

an abode accommodate it, or that a condition assure it or confirm it.” 170 This is how God

moves out of the constraints of idolatry—the fact that no one can impose any conditions.

Reason is not capable of disclosing religion because it is an idol; only revelation (i.e. self-

giving) can be classified as an icon. For us as humans its necessary first to be in order to

then act, speak, or love. But we should not reduce God to our categories of being or

impose our determinations. For God the opposite is true—God is love before being,

constituting a “radical reversal of the relations between being and loving” 171 compared

with what we know from our human experience. Marion encourages us to think God

outside the concept of Sein, in the horizon of God’s own self-revelation as Agape.

166 Marion, God Without Being, 19. 167 1 John 4:8 168 Foutz 5. 169 Marion has been criticized for ignoring the possibility that love itself could become an idol. 170 Marion, God Without Being, 47 171 Ibid., xx.

Page 67: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

67

As much as Marion draws on phenomenology in order to articulate the idol/icon

distinction, he also recognizes potential shortcomings in its applicability. God’s face

could never appear within the horizon of phenomenology because God cannot be reduced

to the perception of the ego or constituted by the I. 172 “God would fail to apear as a

phenomenon precisely because he exceeds the limits of a horizon and refuses to be

reduced to the ego’s constituting glance.”173 In this rejection of Husserlian

phenomenology Marion proposes another possibility, that of an unconditional and

irreducible phenomenon that reverses the reduction by surpassing it. “The religious

phenomenon is an impossible phenomenon, for Marion, not because it fails to measure up

to the ‘criteria of phenomenality,’ but because it overwhelms those conditions—it

exceeds them, bedazzles them, saturates them with a donation which far exceeds the

intention.” 174 This is what Marion refers to as the saturated phenomenon, God giving

himself in Christ.

III.C. Christ as the Word Incarnate

G⊗d, liberated from onto-theological conceptions, is at the origin of meaningful

religious discourse according to Marion. God is the source—discourse does not have

human origins but is dependent upon God’s self-revelation. Christ calls himself the

Word, the Logos, and he abolishes the gap between speaker and sign. Christ says

Himself and thereby transgresses language. “The Word says [himself] absolutely though

172 Gregory Bruce Smith, Nietzsche, Heidegger, and the Transition to Postmodernity (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996) p.20. 173 Ibid. 174 Ibid.

Page 68: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

68

unspeakably, unless he is only absolved from unspeakableness in traversing it by a

perfect incarnation.” 175

The Word/Logos is the Said of the Father. 176 The Word is the discourse that

changes humanity definitively: “Only the Said that lets itself be said by the Father can

assure the pertinence of our logos concerning him.” 177 We must let the Word speak, to

and about G⊗d. The theologian should abandon “discourse and every linguistic initiative

to the Word, in order to let himself be said by the Word, as the Word lets himself be said

by the Father [. . .] Our language will be able to speak of G⊗d only to the degree that

G⊗d, in his Word, will speak our language and teach us in the end to speak it as he

speaks it.”178 179 Marion sees this distinction as the fundamental difference concerning

Christianity:

That which theology has to say, that which distinguishes its voice from among the other voices of the world is the fact that Christ alone abolishes the distance between speaker and speech, between sign and referent. For just as Christ speaks the Word of God, he himself is the Word, and thus speaks himself. This is the power and promise of the Christian theology: Christ speaks himself, the Word. Thus any legitimate Christian theology must be conceived as a logos of the Logos, a word of the Word, rather than proposing its own logos about the Logos or allowing its own logos to precede the Logos. 180

As we have seen, with the icon the invisible is made visible, but this move from idol to

icon necessitates our thinking in terms of donation. Why is this concept so important in

175 Marion, God Without Being, 141. 176 In this Marion’s thinking differs from that of Levinas; the Said no longer has a negative connotation but instead refers to what the Father has spoken, i.e. Christ as Word. Given this distinction, one must be cautious about the danger of viewing Marion’s thinking as “completing” that of Levinas the way some view Christianity to be the “fulfillment” of Judaism. Rather, the dialogue between the two must be thought of as a valid expression of two different faith systems, both valuable and complete yet with acknowledged differences. 177 Ibid., 143. 178 Ibid., 144. 179 An interesting consideration here would be Marion’s emphasis on silence as a valid and appropriate discourse—paradoxical because at first it appears to be the absence of discourse. An interesting topic for further study would be Marion’s place in the tradition of negative theology.

Page 69: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

69

the philosophy of Marion? In an essay entitled “Sketch of a phenomenological concept of

gift,” 181 Marion elaborates on the centrality of understanding givenness (donation).

Primacy is given to the notion of the gift because Marion sees the revelation is

“saturated” meaning—a phenomenon must be able to give itself and the only way for this

to occur is through the gift, (as the trait of every phenomenon revealing itself).

Evidently, in order to understand the role of revelation, central to Marion’s thinking, this

notion of the gift must be closely examined.

The gift understood in metaphysical terms is flawed according to Marion: the

giver, as the active efficient cause, gives the gift to a passive recipient. In this sense,

givenness is bound by a link of reciprocity--gratuity on the part of the giver implies that

the giver needs to make restitution. The giver as the efficient cause produces a material

cause (the gift) and the end result is a final cause, understood either as the benefit of the

receiver or the glory of the giver. This definition of givenness is clearly paradoxical—

Marion follows Jacques Derrida182 in his analysis of the gift. First, for the gift to remain a

gift and not become a system of exchange, there must be no reciprocity, no debt is

incurred, no contract entered. As soon as the gift-giver and gift-recipient are bound by

reciprocity, true donation (givenness) disappears. The gift is only beneficial if the

recipient does not immediately interpret it as something to be returned—this is the idea of

pure gratuity. The recipient is not ungrateful, rather, a true gift surpasses consciousness

so that it remains “unknown”. The disappearance of the recipient also implies that the

180 Foutz 6. 181 Westphal, Merold, ed, Postmodern Philosophy and Christian Thought (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1999) pp.122-143. 182 See “On the Gift: A Discussion Between Jacques Derrida and Jean-Luc Marion,” Moderated by Richard Kearny, God, the Gift, and Postmodernism , ed. John Caputo and Michael Scanlon (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1999) pp.54-78.

Page 70: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

70

giver must be unaware of the gift being given. Consciousness of the gift signifies self-

recognition and approval on the part of the giver, a certain “narcissistic gratitude”. The

difficulties here are readily apparent: if in losing the gift I re-find myself then we are back

to a system of exchange. The loss becomes gain because the self weighs more that the

gift given, therefore infinitely more is gained in the giving of the gift. Hence givenness

only becomes possible once separated from metaphysics. It is this understanding of

givenness that allows a discourse to emerge—it is God giving us the Word and enabling

us to speak.

III.D. Eucharistic Participation

Discourse becomes meaningful insofar as people in the community participate in

the transcendent. The Eucharist, which is the meeting point of immanence and

transcendence and central to Marion’s thought, necessitates a community. It is a ritual

practiced with other people in the presence of God, it is also a ritual done in the presence

of a community and in communion with God. Love can only be known through praxis—

in loving and being loved. It belongs to the realm of personal relationships, love is

dependent upon performance to be realized.

As was demonstrated in the previous section, “other hermeneutics fixate on

meanings within the text, [while] theology and Christian readers desire the advent of the

referent himself.” 183 We are unable to understand the text apart from the help of the

Word—we must go beyond the text to the Word and let Christ as Logos reveal Himself

and inform our reading of texts. But how does this occur? Marion answers: through

183 Foutz 6.

Page 71: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

71

participation. Marion’s philosophy is essentially one of action in the form of

participation in the Eucharist.

To illustrate this point Marion uses the example of Jesus appearing to the two men

on the road to Emmaus—the risen Christ does not disclose his identity until the three

participate in the Eucharist. “[T]hey said to one another, ‘did not our hearts burn within

us, when he was speaking along the way, when he opened to us the text of the

Scriptures?” 184 The importance of the Eucharist in Marion’s philosophy is evident.

Scripture, as the Word of God, is understood through the Word (Logos), that is, Christ. It

is this “self-referentiality” (the Logos making the Word comprehensible) that allows us to

interpret the text and find it meaningful. “The Eucharist accomplishes, as its central

moment, the hermeneutic. It alone allows the text to pass to its referent, recognized as

the nontextual Word of the words.” 185

The third and fourth elements under consideration (discourse and praxis) are

inextricably linked: interpretation and meaning are impossible without acknowledging

the site of action. We join with Christ, the referent, as we participate in communion.

“The Eucharist alone completes the hermeneutic; the hermeneutic culminates in the

Eucharist; the one assures the other its condition of possibility: the intervention in person

of the referent of the text as center of its meaning, of the Word, outside of the words.” 186

Again we see circular reasoning, not vicious or redundant but rather where each part aids

in our understanding and considered together they form an intelligible, comprehensible

whole. “The circle is closed: the hermeneutic presupposes that the disciples occupy the

184 Luke 24:32 185 Marion,God Without Being, 149. 186 Ibid., 151.

Page 72: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

72

eucharistic site of the Word, but their hermeneutic, in return, passes through every text

and all speech, toward, again, the absolute referent.” 187

Marion clearly affirms the necessity of a community as the only possible context

for joining together the various elements we have considered.

Finally the community: it hears the text, verbally passes through it in the direction of the referent Word, because the carnal Word comes to the community, and the community into him. The community therefore interprets the text in view of its referent only to the strict degree that it lets itself be called together and assimilated, hence converted and interpreted by the Word, sacramentally and therefore actually acting in the community. 188

His emphasis on community refers directly back to Scripture and our responsibility as

participants:

Marion places the locus of communal identity in participation of the Eucharist [. . .] this basis of identity is much more meaningful and nearer (if not identical) to the outward criteria of communal identity suggested by Christ himself in Scripture. Thus Marion grounds his understanding of the community on a very sure foundation, a foundation which both Christ and Scripture demand of the individual. It is clear that these two witnesses place upon the individual a responsibility to participate in the Eucharist with the understanding that it is done so in order to partake and encounter the Living Christ. 189

Essentially, praxis for Marion takes the form of faith, belief as the culmination or

fulfillment of discourse. Faith is an end in itself. “Faith neither speaks nor states; it

believes, and has no other end than to believe.” 190 We end our discussion of Jean-Luc

Marion with a clear organization of the four elements: bringing the individual into

relationship with the Other, (G⊗d,) by way of the Word, (Christ,) at the site of

Eucharistic practice.

187 Ibid., 152. 188 Ibid. 189 Foutz 8. 190 Ibid., 183.

Page 73: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

73

CONCLUSION

“In order for love to be able to penetrate the World, which is Redemption, in order for Time to move to Eternity, Love must not remain at the state of individual enterprise, it must become the work of community, the time of a community. One must be able to say, from now on, ‘We’. 191

This final section will be an examination of why the four elements identified in

the work of each philosopher not only allow the idea of religious community to emerge,

but actually necessitate such a move.

At first glance, the idea of limiting subjectivity of interpretation within a

community seems natural, given that the Biblical and Talmudic texts originated in a

community and have been preserved in the same fashion. Indeed it would be ridiculous

to assert that religious thinking can take place completely independently of a community.

Despite many variations of both Christianity and Judaism that currently exist, at the core

they are all the result of centuries of interpretation compounded and modified. All

theologies that develop do so with the influence of a particular religious community.

Thus the idea of community makes sense historically, but is it still relevant today? This

exploration of religious community takes into consideration the analysis of the four

elements as the shaping force behind contemporary Judeo-Christian thought.

The word community as I have understood it is admittedly ambiguous, and

necessarily so. Rather than oversimplify, I have chosen to risk being too vague in order

to preserve the complexities of what I understand a possible present-day religious

community to be. It appears that a community preferences the “we” over the “other”—

exactly the kind of thinking Levinas works to eliminate. There are many paradoxes to be

examined here, as well as the complexities that arise from working with a notion with

Page 74: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

74

such a loose definition.192 I want to establish broad ideas based on the four fundamental

elements which could then later be adapted and applied to specific instances of religious

community, be they Protestant, Jewish, Roman Catholic or otherwise.

Far from identifying a religious community with a homogenous group, (a

“community” defined as consensus would be both threatening and entirely unworthy of

philosophical consideration), there is obviously a precarious balance to be found here.

On the one hand, community is a shared understanding between a group, and on the other

it is a place fueled by difference. Calvin Schrag defines community as “principally a

creative and self-affirming modality of being-with-others in society, as contrasted with

conformism and mere conventionalism as a self-effacing modality of being-with” 193

There is clearly an element of transcendence at play here: the dialectic between self and

community is something that continually constitutes itself and at the same time belongs

to a tradition antedating the point of origin of the self. Similarly, Drucilla Cornell,

representing the view of Hegel, writes that

[t]he community is not an external force that coerces the previously isolated individuals; rather, the community is internal to the individuals themselves, their own interrelatedness, which makes them who they are. Recognition (Anerkennen) is achieved between individuals when they understand community as their internal interrelatedness, “the we that is I and the I that is we.” 194 Once again the focus is on the double identity of a community, as each individual

remaining distinct but at the same time bound to and defined by the other members of the

community.

191 Levinas, Difficult Freedom, 193. 192 One such paradox that arises in Ricœur’s thinking is the paradox of belonging to a community. It is not possible to arrive in nothingness—in this sense one is always fundamentally a part of a community antedating its particular members. It is also the case, however, that the members create the community, it is an entity in continual flux. 193 Schrag, The Self After Postmodernity, 91.

Page 75: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

75

We can now define community broadly as the site where humanity is brought into

relationship—the place where the self encounters the immediate other and the ultimate

Other. Following Heidegger’s emphasis on the complex web of human relations and the

impossibility of “pure” intentionality, we are always part of a community—albeit vague

and nondescript—i.e. interacting with other human beings. Theoretically the concept of

community appears to be a given, now we will try to narrow down our understanding

given the four elements under consideration and their significance in determining a

religious community.

Why is the idea of community that which emerges? What basis do I have for

making this claim? I believe it is what makes the elements we have considered

intelligible; without the context of community there would be no practical working space

for their actualization and they would remain purely theoretical. Community brings the

ideas of the self, other, discourse, and praxis into a working relationship; tacitly

grounding the work of Ricœur, Levinas, and Marion even when not explicitly stated.

We will begin the synthesis with the first element—the self:

Although agreeing with the postmodernists in their assaults on both the classical substance-theory of the self and the modern epistemological or foundationalist construal of self as transparent mind, the principal argument is that a jettisoning of the self understood in these senses does not entail a jettisoning of every sense of self. In the aftermath of the deconstruction of traditional metaphysics and epistemology, a new self emerges, like the phoenix arising from its ashes—a praxis-oriented self, defined by its communicative practices, oriented toward an understanding of itself in its discourse, its action, its being with others, and its experience of transcendence. 195 Obviously the basic unit comprising any group of people is the individual. There

is a distinction to be made between a group of people and a community. Why does

194 Cornell 43. 195 Schrag, The Self After Postmodernity 121.

Page 76: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

76

community emerge from a study of the four recurrent themes, as opposed to just a group

of people identified by their pursuit of similar interests? What is the fundamental

difference between a group and a community, and specifically a religious community?

Once a self becomes part of a group identity is lost. The goal of a group is to dissolve

personal identity, to forgo individuality for the sake of the group. Community, on the

other hand, is a cohesive whole comprised of individuals whose individuality is

heightened and fulfilled given their relationship with other people. The self in

community has been constituted by the presence of others and thus remains paradoxically

intact. The self is not sacrificed for the sake of a community, but has necessarily been re-

examined in light of the contemporary philosophical and religious context.

The self according to Ricœur, Levinas, and Marion is not understandable apart

from the work of the other. Modernity, with its brazen proclamation of the capacity of

the individual mind is gone and has been replaced by an emphasis on selfhood as

constituted in relationship. According to this latter way of thinking, there is a dialectic at

work that is only fully developed in the context of community. “Community is

constitutive of selfhood. It fleshes out the portrait of the self by engendering a shift of

focus from the self as present to itself to the self as present to, for, and with the other.” 196

We see the interplay between the self and community, each constitutes and is constituted

by the other. Who we are cannot be discovered or defined except in a community where

people confront each other. We are born into a world that is already constituted by

language and community and who we are is both determined by and a reflection of that

community. The community in which one finds oneself cannot be reduced to history,

196 Ibid., 78.

Page 77: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

77

culture, or religious practices (though these may occupy significant roles)—the self is

discovered as a result of confrontation and has no meaning except in context of

community. Levinas’s concept of the “face-to-face” is a dialectical confrontation that

grounds communication between others and oneself without reducing or absorbing either

to the other. The Other that is essential in constituting our selfhood can also refer to the

Divine. There is movement in two directions: a community is both a group of selves who

are personally and individually communing with God and thereby joined in mind and

spirit, and at the same time a gathering of people in communion with one another who

then address God.

The notion of discourse, the third element present in the works we have examined

by Ricœur, Levinas, and Marion, is also a fundamental part of distinguishing between a

group and a community. A group, while often seeking to adopt particular discourse, is

not defined by such. The community, on the other hand, is both embedded in a particular

discursive history and tradition, and continually shaping its own space through discourse.

Discourse, as we have seen, can be understood in various ways: communication,

texts, interpretation, meaning, prayer, etc. Discourse is what happens between people, or

between people and God (i.e. between the self and the human other or between the self

and the Divine Other). The self needs a way to relate to exteriority, discourse allows for

this communication because it is reflexive. Discourse asks how we find meaning.

Interpretation is community based, never carried out in isolation. Meaning lies in the

synthesis of individual and communal formation:

Facts thus become defined as facts only against the backdrop of communalized interpretive practices. But such is also the case with respect to values. Values, like facts, do not fall fully clothed, fixed and finished, from some celestial abode. Values become values only when they are taken as being valuable within the

Page 78: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

78

concrete context of everyday life. Like facts, values are constituted and defined against a backdrop of communalized interpretive practices. 197

There are no facts without interpretation because a fact becomes a fact only when it

becomes relevant. Interpretation is the work of a community. Here we return to

Gadamer’s fusion of horizons—contact between the text backed by the author’s intent

and the reader coming from a particular context allows for meaning.

Action, or praxis, also occurs in various forms, all obviously tied to the idea of

community as a space that is continually evolving. It is in flux, adapting and shifting

because the individuals who comprise it are also changing. Modernity was uneasy with

change, postmodern thought welcomes it. Truth is dynamic, not static, and it is worked

out communicatively.

Ricoeur’s notion of action relies heavily on his understanding of discourse,

emphasizing the way in which we ‘say’ our actions and interpret their meaning. “To

evoke the reason for an action is to try to place the action in a broader context, generally

one composed of rules of interpretation and of norms of execution, which are assumed to

be shared by the agent and the community.” 198 Actions, as well as the motivation for

those actions, do not necessarily have inherent worth, they become significant due to

their place in a community. In order to be intelligible, both discourse and action require

the history of discursive and institutional practices in addition to the current context.

Religious phenomenon such as those we have discussed, are not isolated phenomenon.

Religious community provides both historical perspective and constitutive capability,

rendering action, thought, and interaction meaningful. In a community the people are

players and participants, not part of a rigid pre-existing system. Communities are

197 Schrag Communicative Praxis and the Space of Subjectivity, 93.

Page 79: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

79

constructed by the recognition of historical and cultural components that have played a

part in the members’ self-constitution, but they also highlight the ethical feature of self-

actualization; i.e., the capacity to create and the responsibility that determines our

relationship with alterity.

The self that is called into being through discourse and action is at the same time called into being within a community. This was already announced in the recurring references to communicative praxis as an amalgam of discourse and action, supplying the textured space for the self-implicature of the human subject in its manifold concretions.199

Were we to push this study past the theoretical level there would be numerous

paths to follow—such as the move toward grounding the theoretical in particular

instances of community. (“Jewish universalism has always revealed itself in

particularism.” 200) The work of Ricoeur, Levinas, and Marion has shown that

community is what saves us from arbitrariness, however, we are still left with only a

vague idea of why one might choose a particular community over another. For instance,

Levinas discusses Judaism as a community in various senses of the word, yet there exist

many different Jewish communities to which one could belong and the issue of why one

and not another is never addressed. In essence, we are saved from relativism within a

community, but not saved from the relativity of communities. It can be inferred from the

silence on this issue that personal tradition plays a role for each of the three—Levinas

remains grounded in Jewish tradition and part of a Jewish community because that is

what he knows and by which he has been constituted. Essentially participation in a

community is motivated by personal choice.

198 Ricœur, Oneself as Another, 64. 199 Levinas, Totality and Infinity, 77. 200 Ibid., 164.

Page 80: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

80

This work has been defined as phenomenological in nature. How has this

approach been useful, and what are the potential shortcomings in the application of the

phenomenological method? I believe that phenomenology, at its core, is conducive to the

idea of religious community: “Husserl recognized the intersubjective communal

grounding of the knowing activity and focused more on the ethical dimensions of this

intersubjectivity, how the ‘I’ stands in the ‘we’.” 201 However, Ricœur, Levinas, and

Marion have been charged with the distortion of phenomenology and accused of using it

improperly.

An interesting book has appeared recently entitled Phenomenology and the

“Theological Turn” 202 following the debate over Dominique Janicaud’s 1991 article, “Le

tournant théologique de la phénomenologie française.” The book includes responses by

Marion and Ricœur, among others, on the possibility of religion as a philosophical rather

than a theological project. “Janicaud inverts the scenario of Plato’s Apology: he indicts

Lévinas et al. for corrupting the future of French philosophy by introducing into

phenomenology a god—the biblical God—who does not belong there.” 203 Janicaud

offers his own interpretation: there has been a rupture between the phenomenology of

Husserl and Heidegger and that of contemporary phenomenologists who now consider

religion a suitable subject for inquiry. He states that “Emmanuel Levinas’s Totality and

Infinity is the first major work of French philosophy in which this theological turn is not

only discernible, but explicitly taken up within a phenomenological inspiration.” 204 It is

201 Morgan 61. 202 Dominique Janicaud, “The Theological Turn of French Phenomenology,” Trans. Bernard George Prusak, Phenomenology and the “Theological” Turn: The French Debate, Perspectives in Continental Philosophy, Vol.15, ed. John D. Caputo. (New York: Fordham University Press, 2000). 203 Janicaud 4. 204 Ibid. 36.

Page 81: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

81

an opening to the invisible, to the Other that thwarts the project of immanence. I would

argue against Janicaud, as do Marion and Ricœur, that there is a doubly-directed

movement here. Indeed, French phenomenology has become more theological in nature,

but so has theology become more phenomenological. A more thorough and complex

understanding of both of these systems will result in each informing the other. Herein lies

what may perhaps be considered the strongest objection to my work: in exchanging the

ontological vocabulary for the phenomenological one in order to explore different ways

of speaking about the Divine, it is still ontology that dictates what can and cannot be said.

While it is clear that modern and/or metaphysical thinking (insofar as the two can be

equated) errs in its idolatrous conception of God identified with Being, so also the

attempt to think of God “beyond” the ontological difference is to perpetuate the

metaphysical system of thought. Ontology still determines the character of that which is

thinkable.205

As a concluding remark I acknowledge the shortcomings of a work such as the

one attempted here. Out of respect to the current philosophical setting, postmodern in its

refusal of preferring any one particular understanding, I believe that various approaches

are useful only insofar as they prevent the movement toward totalization—i.e. taking one

approach and mistaking it for the approach. I do not see postmodern thought as

weakening or even negating truth claims, but rather grounding them by acknowledging

the complexity of any given project at hand—in this case a phenomenological approach

to the possibility of continuing religious discourse is only valid insofar as one recognizes

205 See Anthony J. Godzieba, “Ontotheology to Excess: Imagining God Without Being” Theological Studies 1 (1995): 3-20.

Page 82: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

82

its shortcomings. By acknowledging the possibility of polyvalent truth one can be even

more certain of what one believes, because shortcomings are taken into consideration as

valid and valuable instead of glossed over in an attempt to make them disappear. I have

chosen a philosophical approach because I believe it has particular merits, however, I

recognize that there are other ways of speaking about the Divine.

The self in community is historically embedded but has resources for

transcending historical specifics by being situated within communicative praxis and

existing with others. The Enlightenment preoccupation with individuality undermined

any understanding of humans as fundamentally social and communal creatures,

embedded in a particular cultural history, and often shaped by religious values and

beliefs. The idea of community re-emerges here, against the backdrop of postmodernity,

having been informed by the philosophical context but not entirely determined by it. We

are both individual and communitarian; contact with others is constitutive of selfhood,

such as in Levinas’s face-to-face. God (or G⊗d) is radically other, otherwise than being,

known by the trace and experienced in community. It is against this space, constituted by

our participation, that a meaningful discourse is initiated and sustained.

Page 83: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

83

Works Referenced Albano, Peter Joseph. Freedom, Truth and Hope: The Relationship of Philosophy and

Religion in the Thought of Paul Ricœur. Landam, MD: University Press of America, 1987.

Beavers, Anthony F. “Emmanuel Levinas and the Prophetic Voice of Postmodernity.” http://cedar.evansville.edu/~tb2/trip/prophet.htm Caputo, John. “Apostles of the Impossible: Derrida and Marion.” Caputo and Scanlon.

185-122. ---., ed. Deconstruction in a Nutshell: A Conversation with Jacques Derrida. New York:

Fordham University Press, 1997. ---. Demythologizing Heidegger. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1993. ---. The Mystical Element in Heidegger’s Thought. New York: Fordham University

Press, 1986. ---. The Prayers and Tears of Jacques Derrida: Religion without Religion.

Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1997. ---. Radical Hermeneutics: Repetition, Deconstruction, and the Hermeneutic Project.

Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1987. ---., and Michael J. Scanlon, eds. God, the Gift, and Postmodernism. Bloomington:

Indiana University Press, 1999. Casarotti, Eduardo. “La constitucion narrativa de la identidad personal.” Filósofos de

Hoy. http://fp.chasque.apc.org:8081/relacion/9905/filosofos_de_hoy.htm Chalier, Catherine. Levinas: Utopie de l’humain. Paris: Editions Albin Michel, 1993. Cobb-Stevens, Richard. “The beginnings of phenomenology: Husserl and his

predecessors.” Parkinson and Shanker. 5-37. Cohen, Richard A., ed. Face to Face with Levinas. Albany, NY: State University of New

York Press, Albany, 1986. Cornell, Drucilla. The Philosophy of the Limit. New York: Routledge, Chapman, and

Hill, Inc., 1992. Courtine, Jean-François, ed. Phénomenologie et théologie. Paris: Criterion, 1992.

Page 84: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

84

Cox, James L. Expressing the Sacred: An Introduction to the Phenomenology of

Religion. Harare, Zimbabwe: University of Zimbabwe, 1992. Critchley, Simon and Timothy Mooney. “Deconstruction and Derrida.” Parkinson and

Shanker. 441-73. Davis, Colin. Levinas: An Introduction. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press,

1996. De Vries, Hent. “Adieu à dieu, a-Dieu.” Ethics as First Philosophy. Ed. A. Peperzak.

211-20. Desmond, William. “Philosophies of Religion: Marcel, Jaspers, Levinas.” Parkinson and

Shanker. 131-74. Detmer, David. “Ricœur on Atheism: A Critique.” Hahn. 477-93. Docherty, Thomas. “Postmodernist Theory: Lyotard, Baudrillard and Others.”

Parkinson and Shanker. 474-505. Dornisch, Loretta. Faith and Philosophy in the Writings of Paul Ricoeur. Problems in

Contemporary Philosophy. Vol. 29. Lewiston, NY: The Edwin Mellen Press, 1990.

Dosse, François. Paul Ricœur: Le sens d’une vie. Paris: Editions de la découverte, 1997. Drabinski, John E. "Sense and Icon: The Problem of Sinngebung in Levinas and Marion. Philosophy Today 42 (Supp) (1998): 47-58. Encyclopedia of Phenomenology. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer Academic

Publishers, 1997. Erickson, Millard J. Postmodernizing the Faith. Grand Rapids, MI: Baker Books, 1998. Foutz, Scott David. "Postmetaphysic Theology--A Case Study: Jean-Luc Marion."

Quodlibet: Online Journal of Christian Theology and Philosophy 1.3 (1999). http://www.quodlibet.net/marion.shtml.

Gibbs, Robert. “Emmanuel Levinas (1906-1995).” Ward. 45-51. Godzieba, Anthony J. “Ontotheology to Excess: Imagining God Without Being.”

Theological Studies 1 (1995): 3-20. Hahn, Lewis Edwin, ed. The Philosophy of Paul Ricœur. The Library of Living

Philosophers. Vol. 22. Chicago and La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1995.

Page 85: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

85

Heidegger, Martin. Sein und Zeit. 17th ed. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer, 1993. / Being and

Time. Trans. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1962.

Hopkins, Burt C. Intentionality in Husserl and Heidegger: The Problem of the Original

Method and Phenomenon of Phenomenology. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1993.

Ihde, Don. Hermeneutic Phenomenololgy: The Philosophy of Paul Ricoeur. Evanston,

IL: Northwestern University Press, 1971. ---. “Paul Ricœur’s Place in the Hermeneutic Tradition.” Hahn. 59-70. Janicaud, Dominique. “The Theological Turn of French Phenomenology.” Trans.

Bernard George Prusak. Phenomenology and the “Theological” Turn: The French Debate. Perspectives in Continental Philosophy. Vol.15. Ed. John D. Caputo. New York: Fordham University Press, 2000.

Jervolino, Domenico. “The Depth and Breadth of Paul Ricœur’s Philosophy.” Hahn.

533-43. Kemp, Peter. “Ethics and Narrativity.” Hahn. 371-94. ---. “Toward a Narrative Ethics: A Bridge between ethics and the narrative reflection of

Ricœur.” Kemp and Rasmussen. 65-87. Klein, Ted. “The Idea of a Hermeneutical Ethics.” Hahn. 349-66. Kovacs, George. The Question of God in Heidegger’s Phenomenology. Evanston, IL:

Northwestern University Press, 1990. Lacoste, Jean-Yves. “Penser à Dieu en l’aimant: philosophie et théologie de Jean-Luc

Marion.” Archives de philosophie 50 (1987): 245-70.

Lee, Weon Hyo. Interpretation de la Bible selon la démarche de Paul Ricœur. Memoire de Maitrise à L’Institut Catolique de Paris, 1994.

Levinas, Emmanuel. Autrement qu'etre ou au-dela de l'essence. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1974. /Otherwise Than Being or Beyond Essence. Trans.A. Lingis. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1981.

---. De Dieu qui vient à l’idée. Paris: Vrin, 1982. / Of God Who Comes to Mind Trans. Bettina Bergo. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1998.

Page 86: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

86

---. Difficile Liberté: Essaies sur le judaisme. Paris: Albin Michel, 1963. / Difficult Freedom: Essays on Judaism. Trans. Sean Hand. Baltimore, MD: John Hopkins University Press, 1990. ---. Totalité et Infini. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1961. / Totality and Infinity. Trans. A. Lingis. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1969. Lingis, Alphonso. Phenomenological Explanations. Dordrecht, The Netherlands:

Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 1986. Madison, G.B. “Hermeneutics: Gadamer and Ricœur.” Parkinson and Shanker. 290-

349. ---. “Ricœur and the Hermeneutics of the Subject.” Hahn. 75-92. Marion, Jean-Luc. Dieu sans l’être. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France (PUF), 1991.

/ God Without Being. Trans Thomas A. Calson. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1991.

----."In the Name: How to Avoid Speaking of ‘Negative Theology.’" Trans. Jeffery L. Kosky. Caputo and Scanlon. 20-41.

---. “Metaphysics and Phenomenology: A Summary for Theologians.” Ward. 279-98. ---. Réduction et donation: Recherches sur Husserl, Heiddegger, et la phénoménologie.

Paris: PUF, 1989. / Reduction and Givenness: Investigations of Husserl, Heidegger, and Phenomenology. Trans. Thomas A. Carlson. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1998.

---. Etant donné : essai d'une phénoménologie de la donation. Collection «Épiméthée».

Paris : PUF, 1998. / English translation by Jeffrey L. Kosky forthcoming. ---. L’idole et la distance: Cinq etudes. Paris: Grasset, 1977. / The Idol and Distance.

Trans. Thomas A. Carlson. Perspectives in Continental Philosophy Ser. Vol. 17. Ed. John D. Caputo. New York: Fordham University Press, 2001.

---. “Le phenomène saturé.” Phénomenologie et théologie. Courtine. 79-128. / "The

Saturated Phenomenon." Trans. Thomas A. Carlson. Philosophy Today 40 (1996): 103-124.

---. “Sketch of a Phenomenological Concept of Gift.” Trans. John Conley and Danielle

Poe. Westphal. 122-43. ---. "Le sujet en dernier appel." Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale (1991): 77-95. /

"The Final Appeal of the Subject." Trans. Simon Critchley. Deconstructive Subjectivities. Eds. Simon Critchley and Peter Dews. Albany: SUNY Press, 1996. 85-104.

Page 87: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

87

Mongin, Oliver. Paul Ricœur. Paris: Editions de Seuil, 1994. Morgan, Dermot. Introduction to Phenomenology. London: Routledge, 2000. Nicholson, Graeme. “Hermeneutical Phenomenology.” Encyclopedia of

Phenomenology. 304-7. “On the Gift: A Discussion Between Jacques Derrida and Jean-Luc Marion.” Moderated

by Richard Kearny. Caputo and Scanlon. 54-78. Parkinson G.H.R. and S.G. Shanker, eds. Continental Philosophy in the 20th Century.

Routledge History of Philosophy. Vol. 8. New York: Routledge, 1994. Peperzak, Adriaan T., ed. Ethics as First Philosophy. New York: Routledge, 1995. ---. “Emmanuel Levinas.” Encyclopedia of Phenomenology. 412-15. Reagan, Charles E. “Paul Ricœur.” Encyclopedia of Phenomenology. 610-14. ---. “Words and Deeds: The Semantics of Action.” Hahn. 331-45. Richardson, William J. “The Irresponsible Subject.” Ethics as First Philosophy. Ed. A.

Peperzak. 123-31. Ricœur, Paul. Autrement. Lecture d'Autrement qu'être ou au-delà de l'essence d'Emmanuel Levinas. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1997. --- Le conflit des interprétations. Essais d'herméneutique. (L'Ordre philosophique) Paris: Seuil, 1969. /The Conflict of Interpretations: Essays in Hermeneutics. Trans Don Ihde. Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1974. ---. “Experience et langage dans le discours religieux.” Courtine. 15-40. ---. Hermeneutics and the Human Sciences: Essays on Language, Action, and

Interpretation. Ed. and Trans. John B. Thompson. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; Paris: Editions de la Maison des Sciences de l’Homme, 1981. (Comprised primarily of previously published texts)

---. “Intellectual Autobiography.” Hahn. 1-54. ---. “The Human Being as the Subject Matter of Philosophy.” Kemp and Rasmussen.

89-101. (Originally presented at the World Congress of Philosophy, Brighton, 89-102. August 1988).

---. “Reply to G.B. Madison.” Hahn. 93-5.

Page 88: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

88

---. “Reply to Don Ihde.” Hahn. 71-4. ---. Soi-même comme un autre (L’ordre philosophique). Paris: Seuil, 1990. / Oneself as

Another. Trans. K. Blamey. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992. Rockmore, Tom. Heidegger and French Philosophy. New York: Routledge, 1995. Schmidt, Lars-Henrik, ed. Paul Ricœur: In the Conflict of Interpretations. Aarhus,

Denmark: Aarhus Universitetsforlag, 1996. Schrag, Calvin O. The Self After Postmodernity. New Haven: Yale University Press,

1997.

---. Communicative Praxis and the Space of Subjectivity. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1986.

Silverman, Hugh J. “French Structuralism and After: de Saussure, Lévi-Strauss, Barthes,

Lacan, Foucault.” Parkinson and Shanker. 390-408. Smith, Gregory Bruce. Nietzsche, Heidegger, and the Transition to Postmodernity.

Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996. Steeves, H. Peter. Founding Community: A Phenomenological-Ethical Inquiry.

Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1998. Stewart, David. “Ricœur on Religious Language.” Hahn. 423-41. Taminiaux, Jacques. “Philosophy of Existence I: Heidegger.” Parkinson and Shanker.

38-73. Van Leeuwen, Theodore Marius. The Surplus of Meaning: Ontology and Eschatology in

the Philsophy of Paul Ricœur. Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1981. Vanhoozer, Kevin J. Biblical Narrative in the Philosophy of Paul Ricœur: A Study in

Hermeneutics and Theology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990. Vansina, Frans D. Paul Ricoeur, Bibliography 1935-2000. Louvain, Belgium: Leuven

University Press, 2000. Vessey, David. “The Polysemy of Otherness: On Ricœur’s Oneself as Another.”

http://www.beloit.edu/philorel/faculty/davidvessey/DVRicoeur.html Vogel, Arthur A. “Catching up with Jean-Luc Marion.” Anglican Theological Review 82

(2000): 803-811.

Page 89: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

89

Waldenfels, Bernhard. “Response and Responsibility in Levinas.” Ethics as First Philosophy . Ed. A. Peperzak. 39-52.

Ward, Graham, ed. The Postmodern God: A Theological Reader. Malden, MA:

Blackwell Publishers Ltd., 1997. Ward, Graham. “The Theological Project of Jean-Luc Marion.” Post-Secular

Philosophy. Ed. Phillip Blond. London: Routledge, 1998. 67-106. Westphal, Merold, ed. Postmodern Philosophy and Christian Thought. Bloomington,

IN: Indiana University Press, 1999. Wyschogrod, Edith. Emmanuel Levinas: The Problem of Ethical Metaphysics. The

Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1974.

Page 90: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

90

The following extended bibliographies (including books, articles, and secondary sources) of Paul Ricœur, Emmanuel Levinas, and Jean-Luc Marion include only those sources that have not been previous cited in the section entitled Works Referenced. They are organized alphabetically according to each philosopher. The extended bibliographies are not meant to be comprehensive lists but rather groups of specifically selected entries that will aid the reader in a continued exploration of themes or ideas presented in the preceding study. The limited nature of this study, as an MA thesis, prevented me from consulting the following works, however, out of fairness to Ricœur, Levinas, and Marion, I include these references as an indication of the depth of their work. The sheer volume of secondary sources (which has also been drastically edited here) is a testimony to the central place occupied by these three thinkers in contemporary philosophical and religious thought.

Page 91: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

91

Extended Bibliography—Paul Ricœur [For a comprehensive bibliography refer to Frans D. Vansina’s Paul Ricœur, Bibliography 1935-2000, (Louvain, Belgium: Leuven University Press, 2000.)] Books by Paul Ricœur The Contribution of French Historiography to the Theory of History. (The Zaharoff Lecture for 1978-1979). Oxford: Clarendon Press (New York: Oxford University Press), 1980. La critique et la convinction. Entretiens avec François Azouvi et Marc de Launay. Paris: Calmann-Lévy, 1995. De l'interprétation. Essai sur Freud (L'Ordre philosophique). Paris: Seuil, 1965. Essays on Biblical Interpretation. Ed. Lewis Mudge. Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1980. Histoire et vérité (Esprit). Paris: Seuil, 1955. / History and Truth. Trans. Ch. A. Kelbley. Northwestern University Studies in Phenomenology and Existential Philosophy. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1965. Interpretation Theory: Discourse and the Surplus of Meaning. Preface T. Klein. Fort Worth: Texas Christian University Press, 1976. Le Juste. Paris: Editions Esprit, 1995. Lectures on Ideology and Utopia. Ed. George H. Taylor. New York: Columbia University Press, 1986. Le Mal: Un défi à la philosophie et à la théologie. Genève: Labor et Fides, 1986. La métaphore vive (L'Ordre philosophique). Paris: Seuil, 1975. / The Rule of Metaphor. Multi-Disciplinary Studies in the Creation of Meaning in Language. Trans R. Czerny with K. McLaughlin and J. Costello. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1978. Philosophie de la volonté Tome I. Le volontaire et l'involontaire (Philosophie de l'esprit). Paris: Aubier, 1950. / Freedom and Nature: The Voluntary and the Involuntary. Trans. E.V. Kohák. Northwestern University Studies in Phenomenology and Existential Philosophy. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1966. Philosophie de la volonté. Tome II. Finitude et Culpabilité. L'homme faillable (Philosophie de l'esprit). Paris: Aubier, 1960. / Fallible Man. Trans. Ch.A. Kelbley. Chicago: Henry Regnery, 1965. Philosophie de la volonté Tome III. Finitude et Culpabilité. La symbolique du mal (Philosophie de l'esprit). Paris: Aubier, 1960. / The Symbolism of Evil. Trans. E. Buchanan. Religious Perspectives. Vol 17. New York: Harper and Row, 1967. The Philosophy of Paul Ricœur. An Anthology of His Work. Ed. and Preface C. Reagan and D. Stewart. Boston: Beacon Press, 1978. Réflexion faite. Autobiographie intellectuelle. Paris: Editions Esprit, 1995.

Page 92: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

92

Temps et récit. Tome I (L'Ordre philosophique). Paris: Seuil, 1983. / Time and Narrative. Vol. 1. Trans. K. McLaughlin and D. Pellauer. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984. Temps et récit. Tome II. La configuration dans le récit de fiction (L'Ordre philosophique). Paris: Seuil, 1984. / Time and Narrative. Vol 2. Trans. K. McLaughlin and D. Pellauer. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1985. Temps et récit. Tome III. Temps raconté. (L'Ordre philosophique). Paris: Seuil, 1985. / Time and Narrative. Vol 3. Trans. K. McLaughlin and D. Pellauer. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988. Articles and Essays by Paul Ricœur “Biblical Hermeneutics.” Semeia. An Experimental Journal for Biblical Criticism 4 (1975): 27-148. “The Bible and the Imagination.” The Bible as a Document of the University. Ed. Hans Dieter Betz. Chico, CA: Scholars Press, 1981. 49-75. “Christianity and the Meaning of History. Progress, Ambiguity, Hope.” The Journal of Religion 22.4 (1952): 242-53. “Civilisation universelle et cultures nationales.” Esprit 29.10 (1961): 439-53. /

“History and Hermeneutics.” The Journal of Philosophy 73 (1976): 683-95. “D’un Testament à l’autre: essai d’hermeneutique biblique.” La mémoire et le temps,

Mélanges offerts à Pierre Bonnard. Genève: Labor et Fides, 1991. 299-309. “Emmanuel Levinas, penseur du témoignage.” Répondre d’autrui. Emmanuel Levinas (Langages). Textes réunis par J.-C. Aeschliman. Neuchâtel: La Baconnière 1989. 17-40. “Faith and Action: A Christian Point of View. A Christian must rely on his Jewish

memory [expansion of a paper delivered at a conference on “Perspectives on the Good Society.” Chicago 1963].” Criterion 2.3 (1963): 10-15.

“Faith and Culture.” The Student World. World’s Student Christian Federation (The

Greatness and Misery of the Intellectual). 50.3 (1957): 246-51. “French Protestantism Today.” The Christian Century 72 (1955): 1236-38. “Individu et identité personelle.” Sur l’individu (Colloque de Royaumont sur

‘L’individu.’ 1985). Paris: Seuil, 1987. 54-72. “Imagination in Discourse and in Action.” The Human Being in Action. Ed. A.T.

Tymieniecka. London: D. Reidel, 1978. 3-22.

Page 93: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

93

“The Language of Faith.” Union Seminary Quarterly Review 28.3 (1973): 213-24. “Life: A Story in Search of a Narrator.” Facts and Values. Philosophical Reflections from

Western and Non-Western Perspectives. Martinus Nijhoff Philosophy Library. Vol. 19. Ed. M.C. Doeser and J. N. Kraaj. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff, 1986. 121-132.

“The Model of the Text: Meaningful Action Considered as a Text.” Social Research 38.3

(1971): 529-562. “New Developments in Phenomenology in France: The Phenomenology of Language.”

Social Research 34.1 (1967): 1-30. “Nommer Dieu.” Études théologiques et religieuses 52.4 (1977): 489-508. “On Interpretation,” Philosophy in France Today. Ed. Alan Montefiore. Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press, 1983. 175-97. “Philosophical Hermeneutics and Theological Hermeneutics.” Studies in Religion.

Sciences Religieuses 5.1 (1975-6): 14-33. “Philosophy and Religious Language.” Journal of Religion 54 (1974): 71-85. “The Problem of the Foundation of Moral Philosophy.” Philosophy Today 22 (1978):

175-92. “Religion, Atheism, and Faith [Bampton Lectures in America, delivered at Columbia

University, 1966].” The Religious Significance of Atheism. Edited by A. MacIntyre, Ch. Alasdair and P. Ricœur. New York-London: Columbia University Press, 1969. 58-98.

“Self as Ipse.” Freedom and Interpretation, The Oxford Amnesty Lectures, 1992. Ed.

Barbara Johnson. New York: Basic Books, 1993. “The Task of Hermeneutics [lecture given Princeton Theological Seminary, 1973].”

Philosophy Today 17.2-4 (1973): 112-28. “Toward a Hermeneutic of the Idea of Revelation.” Harvard Theological Review 70.1-2

(1977): 1-37. “Verité et mensonge.” Esprit 19.12 (1951): 753-78. Select Secondary sources Barral, Mary Rose. “Paul Ricœur: The Resurrection as Hope and Freedom.” Philosophy

Page 94: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

94

Today 29 (1985). Bourgeois, Patrick L. Extension of Ricœur’s Hermeneutic. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1975. Dornisch, Loretta. “Symbolic Systems and the Interpretation of Scripture: An Introduction to the Work of Paul Ricœur.” Semeia 4 (1975): 1-19. Esprit, spécial Paul Ricœur, juillet-âout 1988. Gisel P. “Paul Ricœur: Discourse between Speech and Language.” Philosophy Today 21

(1977) (Supp): 446-56. Ihde, D. Hermeneutic Phenomenology: The Philosophy of Paul Ricœur. Evanston, IL:

Northwestern University Press, 1971. Joy, M. “Derrida and Ricœur. A Case of Mistaken Identity (and Difference).” Journal of

Religion 68.4 (1988): 504-26. Lowe, Walter James. Mystery and the Unconscious: A Study in the Thought of Paul

Ricœur. ATLA Monography Ser. Vol. 9. Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow Press, 1977. Mongin, Olivier. Paul Ricœur (Les Contemporains). Paris: Seuil, 1994. Pellauer, David. “Paul Ricœur on the Specificity of Religious Language.” Journal of

Religion 61 (1981): 264-84. Reagan, Charles E., ed. Studies in the Philosophy of Paul Ricœur. Columbus: Ohio

University Press, 1979. ---. “The Self as Another.” Philosophy Today 37.1 (1993): 3-22. Schwartz, Sanford. “Hermeneutics and the Productive Imagination: Paul Ricœur in the

1970s.” Journal of Religion (1983): 290-300. Streib H. Hermeneutics of Metaphor, Symbol, and Narrative in Faith Development

Theory. Bern-Frankfut: Verlag Peter Lang, 1991. Van den Hengel, John W. The Home of Meaning: The Hermeneutics of the Subject of

Paul Ricœur. Washington: University Press of America, 1982. ---. “Faith and Ideology in the Philosophy of Paul Ricœur.” Eglise et théologie 14 (1983): 63-89. Wells, Harold. “Theology and Christian Philosophy: Their Relation in the Thought of

Page 95: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

95

Paul Ricœur.” Studies in Religion /Sciences Religieuses 5 (1975): 45-56.

Page 96: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

96

Extended Bibliography-Emmanuel Levinas [For more comprehensive references see the online bibliography of Levinas’s works in English compiled by Peter Atterton at http://home.pacbell.net/atterton/levinas/ Also see the standard bibliography of studies both by and on Levinas:, Roger Burggraeve Emmanuel Levinas. Une bibliographie primaire et secondaire (1929-1989), (Leuven, Peeters, 1990.)

Books by Emmanuel Levinas L’Au-delà du verset: Lectures et discours tamudiques. Paris: Minuit, 1982. / Beyond the Verse: Talmudic Readings and Lectures. Trans. Gary D. Mole. London: Athlone Press, and Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1994. Collected Philosophical Papers. Trans. A. Lingis. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1987. De L'existence a l'existant. Paris: Editions de la Revue Fontaine, 1978. / Existence and Existents. Trans. A. Lingis. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1978. Emmanuel Levinas: Basic Philosophical Writings. Ed. A. Peperzak, S. Critchley and R. Bernasconi. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1996. En découvrant l’existence avec Husserl et Heidegger. Paris: Vrin, 1949, 1967. / Discovering Existence with Husserl. Trans. and Ed. Richard A. Cohen and Michael B. Smith. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1998. Ethique et infini. Paris: Librairie Arthème Fayard and Radio France, 1982. / Ethics and Infinity. Trans. Richard A. Cohen. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1985. Hors Sujet. Montpellier: Fata Morgana, 1987. / Outside the Subject. Trans. Michael B. Smith. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1993. Quatre Lectures Talmudiques. Paris: Minuit, 1968. / Nine Talmudic Readings. Trans. Annette Aronowicz. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1990. Le temps et l’autre. Montpellier: Fata Morgana, 1982. / Time and the Other. Trans. Richard Cohen. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1987. Transcendence et intelligibilité. Geneva: Labor et Fides, 1984. / Alterity and Transcendence. Trans. Michael B. Smith. London: Athlone Press, and New York: Columbia University Press, 1999.

Articles and Essays by Emmanuel Levinas “Au-dela de l'essence.” Revue de Metaphysique et de Morale 75 (1970): 265-83. “Le langage et l'immanance.” Bulletin de la Societe Francaise de Philosophie 59 (1965): 25-6. “Le mot je, le mot tu, le mot Dieu.” Le Monde, 19-20 Mar. 1978: 2. “Religion et idee de l'infini.” Le Monde dimanche, 5 Sept. 1982: XI.

Page 97: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

97

“La theorie de l'intuition dans la phenomenologie de Husserl.” Paris: Alcan, 1930. / “The Theory of Intuition in Husserl's Phenomenology.” Trans. A.Orianne. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1973. “Wholly Otherwise.” Trans. Simon Critchley. Rereading Levinas. Ed. R. Bernasconi and S. Critchley. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1991. 3-10.

Select Secondary Sources Atterton, Peter. "Levinas and the Language of Peace: A Response to Derrida." Philosophy Today 36.1 (1992): 59-70. Avram, Wes. "On the Priority of `Ethics' in the Work of Levinas." Journal of Religious Ethics 24.2 (1996): 261-85. Baird, Marie L. "Revisioning Christian Theology in Light of Emmanuel Levinas's Ethics of Responsibility." Journal of Ecumenical Studies 36.3/4 (1999): 340-52. Bauman, Zygmunt. "The World Inhospitable to Levinas." Philosophy Today 43.2 (1999): 151-67. Beavers, Anthony F. Levinas beyond the Horizons of Cartesianism: An Inquiry into the Metaphyiscs of Morals. New York: Peter Lang, 1995. Bergo, Bettina. "The God of Abraham and the God of the Philosophers: A Reading of Emmanuel Levinas's 'Dieu et la Philosophie'." Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal 16 (1993): 113-64. Bernasconi, Robert. "Deconstruction and the Possibility of Ethics." Deconstruction and Philosophy: The Texts of Jacques Derrida. Ed. John Sallis. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987. 122-39. ---. "Levinas: An English Bibliography." Bernasconi and Wood. 181-88. ---. "Levinas and Derrida: The Question of the Closure of Metaphysics." Face to Face with Levinas. Ed. Richard A. Cohen. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1986. 181-202. ---, and David Wood, eds. The Provocation of Levinas: Rethinking the Other. London: Routledge, 1988. ---, and Simon Critchley, eds. Re-Reading Levinas. Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 1991. ---. "Rereading 'Totality and Infinity'." The Question of the Other: Essays in Contemporary Continental Philosophy. Ed. Arleen B. Dallery and Charles Scott. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1989. 23-34. ---. "The Trace of Levinas in Derrida." Derrida and Difference. Ed. David Wood and Robert Bernasconi. Coventry, England: Parousia Press, 1986. 17-44. Blond, Phillip. "Emmanuel Levinas: God and Phenomenology." Post-secular Philosophy. London: Routlege, 1998. 195-228.

Page 98: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

98

Blum, Roland Paul. "Emmanuel Levinas' Theory of Commitment." Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 44 (1983): 145-68. Boothroyd, David. "Responding to Levinas." The Provocation of Levinas: Rethinking the Other. Bernasconi and Wood. 15-31. Bouckaert, Luk. "Ontology and Ethics: Reflections on Levinas' Critique of Heidegger." International Philosophical Quarterly 10 (1970): 402-19. Brody, D. H. "Emmanuel Levinas: The Logic of Ethical Ambiguity in Otherwise Than Being or beyond Essence." Research in Phenomenology 25 (1995): 177-203. Brown, David. Continental Philosophy and Modern Theology. Oxford: Blackwell, 1987. Burke, John Patrick. "The Ethical Significance of the Face." ACPA Proceedings 56 (1982): 194-206. Casey, Edward. "Levinas on Memory and the Trace." The Collegium Phaenomenologicum: The First Ten Years. Ed. John Sallis. Boston: Klewer Academic Publishers, 1988. 241-55. Ciaramelli, Fabio. "Levinas's Ethical Discourse between Individuation and Universality." Re-Reading Levinas. Bernasconi and Critchley. 83-105. Cohen, Richard A. "Emmanuel Levinas: Happiness is a Sensational Time." Philosophy Today 25 (1981): 196-203. Critchley, Simon. The Ethics of Deconstruction: Derrida and Levinas. Cambridge: Blackwell, 1992. Dallery, Arleen and Charles E. Scott, eds. The Question of the Other: Essays in Contemporary Continental Philosophy. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1989. Derrida, Jacques. Adieu: To Emmanuel Levinas. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1999. ---. "Violence and Metaphysics." Writing and Difference. Trans. Alan Bass. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1978. 79-193. Durie, Robin. "Indication and the Awakening of Subjectivity." Ethics and the Subject. Ed. Karl Simms. Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1997. 43-52. Durie, Robin. "Speaking of Time... Husserl and Levinas on the Saying of Time." Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 30.1 (1999): 35-8. Dussel, Enrique. " 'Sensibility' and 'Otherness' in Emmanuel Levinas." Philosophy Today 43.2 (1999): 126-34. Ehman, Robert R. "Emmanuel Levinas: The Phenomenon of the Other." Man and World 8 (1975): 141-45. Hand, Sean., ed. The Levinas Reader. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1989. Hendley, Steven. "From Communicative Action to the Face of the Other: Habermas and Levinas on the Foundations of Moral Theory." Philosophy Today 40 (1996): 504. Kaplan, Laura Duhan. "Encountering the Face of God: A Levinasian Exploration of Theistic Existentialism." Philosophy in the Contemporary World 5.1 (1998): 20-4.

Page 99: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

99

Kelbley, Charles A. "An Introduction to Emmanuel Levinas." Thought: Fordham University Quarterly 5 (1974): 81-6. Keyes, C. D. "An Evaluation of Levinas' Critique of Heidegger." Research in Phenomenology 2 (1972): 121-42. Kosky, Jeffrey L. "After the Death of God." Journal of Religious Ethics 24.2 (1996): 235-60. Lawton, Philip. "Levinas' Notion of the 'There Is'." Philosophy Today 20 (1976): 67-76. Lee, Jung H. "Neither Totality nor Infinity: Suffering the Other." Journal of Religion 79 (1999): 250-79. Libertson, J. "Levinas and Husserl: Sensation and Intentionality." Tijdschrift voor Filosofie 41 (1979): 485-502. Lichtigfeld, Adolph. "On Infinity and Totality in Hegel and Levinas." South African Journal of Philosophy 2 (1983): 31-3. Lyotard, Jean-Francois. "Levinas' Logic." Face to Face with Levinas. Cohen. 117-58. McDonald, Dana-Noelle. "Moving beyond the Face through Eros: Levinas and Irigaray's Treatment of the Women as an Alterity." Philosophy Today 42 (Supp) (1998): 71-5. Meskin, Jacob. "From Phenomenology to Liberation: The Displacement of History and Theology in Levinas's Totality and Infinity." Philosophy and Theology 4 (1989): 119-44. Min, Anselm Kyongsuk. "Toward a Dialectic of Totality and Infinity: Reflections on Emmanuel Levinas." Journal of Religion 78 (1998): 571-92. Peperzak, Adrian, ed. Ethics as First Philosophy. New York, Routledge, 1995. ---. "Emmanuel Levinas: Jewish Experience and Philosophy." Philosophy Today 27 (1983): 297-306. ---. "From Intentionality to Responsibility: On Levinas' Philosophy of Language." The Question of the Other: Essays in Contemporary Continental Philosophy. Ed. Arleen Dallery and Charles Scott. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1989. 3-22. ---. "The One for the Other: The Philosophy of Emmanuel Levinas." Man and World (1991): 427-59. ---. "Phenomenology--Ontology--Metaphyiscs: Levinas' Perspective on Husserl and Heidegger." Man and World 16 (1983):113-27. ---. To the Other: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Emmanuel Levinas. West Lafayette, Indiana: Purdue University Press, 1993. ---. "Judaism and Philosophy in Levinas." International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 40.3 (1996): 125-146. ---. "Illeity According to Levinas." Philosophy Today 42 (Supp) (1998): 41-6. ---. "Levinas' Method." Research in Phenomenology 28 (1998): 110-25.

Page 100: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

100

Purcell, Michael. "Leashing God with Levinas: Tracing a Trinity with Levinas." Heythrop Journal: A Quarterly Review of Philosophy and Theology 40.3 (1999): 301-18. Rapaport, Herman. "Face to Face with Ricoeur and Levinas." Meanings in Texts and Actions. Ed. David E. Klemm. Charlottesville, VA: University Press of Virginia, 1993. Tallon, Andrew. "Emmanuel Levinas and the Problem of Ethical Metaphysics." Philosophy Today 20 (1976): 53-66. Vasey, Craig R. "Emmanuel Levinas: From Intentionality to Proximity." Philosophy Today 25 (1981): 178-95. Walsh, Robert D. "Levinas and Responsibility in the Ethical Philosophy of Emmanuel Levinas. " Proceedings of the Catholic Philosophical Association 62 (1988): 95- 105. Ward, Graham. "The Revelation of the Holy Other as the Wholly Other: Between Barth's Theology of the Word and Levinas's Philosophy of Saying." Modern Theology 9.2 (1993): 159-80. Werhane, Patricia H. "Community and Individuality." New Literary History: A Journal of Theory and Interpretation 27.1 (1996): 15-24. Westphal, Merold. "Levinas and the Immediacy of the Face." Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers 10.4 (1993): 486-502. ---. "Levinas, Kierkegaard, and the Theological Task." Modern Theology 8.3 (1992):

241-61. Woods, Tim. "The Ethical Subject: The Philosophy of Emmanuel Levinas." Ethics and the Subject. Ed. Karl Simms. Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1997. 53-60. Wyschogrod, Edith. "Derrida, Levinas and Violence." Derrida and Deconstruction. Ed. Hugh J. Silverman. New York: Routledge, 1989. 182-200. ---. "Emmanuel Levinas and the Problem of Religious Language." The Thomist: A Speculative Quarterly Review 36 (1972): 1-38. ---. "Exemplary Individuals: Towards a Phenomenological Ethics." Philosophy and Theology 1 (1986): 9-31. ---. "Interview with Emmanuel Levinas: December 31, 1982." Philosophy and Theology 4 (1989): 105-18. Ziarek, Krysztof. "Semantics of Proximity: Language and the Other in the Philosophy of Emmanuel Levinas." Research in Phenomenology 19 (1989): 213-47.

Page 101: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

101

Extended bibliography--Jean-Luc Marion (See also Jean-Luc Marion: Online Resources; compiled by James K.A. Smith, Department of Philosophy, Loyola Marymount University, Los Angeles, CA. http://bellarmine.lmu.edu/jkasmith/marion.htm) Books by Jean-Luc Marion Avec ou sans Dieu? L’avenir des valeurs chrétiennes. Paris: Beauchesne, 1970. La croisée du visible. Paris: La Différence, 1991. / English translation by James K.A.

Smith forthcoming from Stanford University Press. De surcroît. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France (PUF), 2000. Études sur Lévinas et la phénoménologie: Positivité et transcendance. Collection

«Épiméthée». Paris: PUF, 2000. Phénoménologie et métaphysique. Ed. G. Planty-Bonjour. Paris: PUF, 1984. /

Phenomenology and Metaphysics. Trans. Thomas A. Carlson. Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1998.

Prolégomènes à la charité. Paris: La Différence, 1986. / English translation forthcoming

from Fordham University Press. Questions cartésiennes: Méthode et métaphysique. Paris: PUF, 1991. / Cartesian

Questions. Trans. Jeffery L. Kosky, John Cottingham, and Stephan Voss. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1999.

Questions cartésiennes II: Sur l’ego et sur Dieu. Paris: PUF, 1996. Reduction et donation: recherches sur Husserl, Heidegger et la phénomenologie. Paris:

PUF, 1989. Sur la théologie blanche de Descartes: Analogie, creation des verités éternelles, fondement. Paris: PUF, 1981. Sur le prisme métaphysique de Descartes. Paris: PUF, 1986. / On Descartes’ Metaphysical Prism. Trans. Jeffery L. Kosky. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1999. Sur l’ontologie grise de Descartes: Science cartesienne et savoir aristotelicien dans les

Regulae. Paris: Vrin, 1975.

Page 102: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

102

Articles and Essays by Jean-Luc Marion "A Dieu, rien d’impossible." Revue de Métaphysique et de morale 5 (1989): 43-58. "L’ambivalence de la métaphysique cartésienne."Etudes Philosophique 4 (1976): 443-60. "Amour de Dieu, amour des hommes." Résurrection 34 (1970): 89-96. "L’angoisse et l’ennui: pour interpreter ‘was ist metaphysik?’" Archives de Philosophie 43 (1980): 121-46. "'Christian Philosophy': Hermeneutic or Heuristic?" The Question of Christian

Philosophy Today. Ed. Francis J. Ambrosio. New York: Fordham University Press, 1999. 247-264.

"Christian Philosophy and Charity." Trans. Mark Sebanc. Communio 19 (1992): 465-73. "Comment Heidegger permet-il de refaire de l'histoire de la philosophie?" Martin

Heidegger. Ed. Michel Haar. Paris: L'Herne, 1983. "La conversion de la volonte selon ‘l’action.’" Revue Philosophique de la France et de

l’Etranger 177 (1987): 33-46. "De la ‘mort de dieu’ aux noms divins: l’itineraire théologique de la métaphysique." Laval Théologique et Philosophique 41 (1985): 25-42. "Descartes et l’onto-théologie." Bulletin de la Societe Francaise de Philosophie 76 (1982): 117-58. / "Descartes and Onto-theology." Post-Secular Philosophy. Ed. Phillip Blond. London: Routledge, 1998. 67-106. "L’ego et le Dasein, Heidegger et la ‘Destruction’ de Descartes dans Sein und Zeit." Revue de Metaphysique et de Morale 92 (1987): 25-53. “Emmanuel Levinas: Autrement que savoir.” Avec les études de Guy Petitdemande et

Jacques Rolland. Paris: Éditions Osiris, 1988. "Esquisse d'un concept phénoménologique du don." Archivo di Filosofia 62 (1994):

75-94. "The Essential Incoherence of Descartes' Definition of Divinity." Essays on Descartes’

Meditations. Ed. Amelie O. Rorty. Berkeley: University of California Press,1986. 297-338.

"La fin de la fin de la metaphysique." Laval Theologique et Philosophique 42 (1986):

22-33. / "The End of the End of Metaphysics." Trans. Bettina Bergo. Epoche 2 (1994): 1-22.

Page 103: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

103

"Generosity and Phenomenology: Remarks on Michel Henry’s Interpretation of the

Cartesian Cogito." Trans. and Ed. Stephen Voss. Essays on the Philosophy and Science of Rene’ Descartes. New York : Oxford University Press, 1993. 52-74.

"The Idea of God." The Cambridge History of Seventeenth-Century Philosophy. Ed.

Daniel Garber. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998. "L’idéologie, ou la violence sans ombre." Communio 6 (1980): 82-92. "L’idole et l’icône." Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 84 (1979): 433-45. "Is the Ontological Argument Ontological? The Argument According to Anselm and Its

Metaphysical Interpretation According to Kant." Journal of the History of Philosophy 2 (1992): 201-18.

"La modernité sans avenir." Le Débat. Histoire, Politique, Société 4 (1980): 54-60. "A Note Concerning the Ontological Indifference." Trans. Jeffery L. Kosky. Graduate

Faculty Philosophy Journal 20-21 (1998): 25-40. "Nothing and Nothing Else." The Ancients and the Moderns. Ed. Reginald Lilly.

Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1996. "On Descartes’ Constitution of Metaphysics." Graduate Faculty Philosophical Journal 11 (1986): 21-33. "The Other First Philosophy and the Question of Givenness." Trans. Jeffery L. Kosky.

Critical Inquiry 25 (1999). 785-800. "Le paradigme cartésien de la métaphysique." Laval théologique et philosophique 53

(1997): 785-91. "Metaphysics and Phenomenology: A Relief for Theology." Trans. Thomas A. Carlson.

Critical Inquiry 4 (1994): 572-91. "Présence et distance. Remarques sur l’implication réciproque de la contemplation

eucharistique et de la présence." Résurrection 43-44 (1974): 31-58. "Responses à quelques questions." Revue de métaphysique et de morale (1991) 65-76. "La rigueur de la louange." Confession de la foi chretienne. Ed. [Unavailable]. Paris:

Fayard, 1977. 261-76. "Saint Thomas d’Aquin et l’onto-théo-logie." Revue Thomiste 95 (1995): 31-66.

Page 104: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

104

"Splendeur de la contemplation eucharistique." La politique de la mystique hommage à Mgr Maxime Charles. Limoges: Criterion, 1984. 17-28

"La vanité de l'être et le nom de Dieu." Analogie et dialectique. Eds. P. Gisel and P.

Secretan. Geneva: Labor et Fides, 1982. "Le verbe et le texte." Résurrection 46 (1975): 63-80.

Select Secondary Sources Benoist, J. "Résponse de soi: pour Jean-Luc Marion." Philosophie 34 (1992): 37-44. Bracken, Joseph A. "Toward a New Philosophical Theology Based on Intersubjectivity."

Theological Studies 4 (1998): 703-19. Caputo, John D. "How to Avoid Speaking of God: The Violence of Natural Theology."

Prospects for Natural Theology. Ed. Eugene Thomas Long. Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press, 1990. 128-50. Carlson, Thomas A. Indiscretion: Finitude and the Naming of God. Chicago:

University of Chicago Press, 1999. Gabellieri, Emmanuel. "De la métaphysique à la phénoménologie: une 'relève'?" Revue

Philosophiques de Louvain 94 (1996): 625-45. Gagnon, Martin. "La phénoménologie à la limite." Eidos: The Canadian Graduate Journal of Philosophy 11 (1993): 111-130. Gilbert, Paul. "Substance et presence: Derrida et Marion critiques de Husserl."

Gregorianum 75 (1994): 95-133. Grondin, Jean. "La tension de la donation ultime et de la pensée herméneutique de

l’application chez Jean-Luc Marion." Dialogue 38 (1999): 547-59. Hemming, Laurence. "Reading Heidegger: Is God Without Being?" New Blackfriars 76

(1995): 343-50. Horner, Robyn. Rethinking God as Gift: Marion, Derrida, and the Limits of

Phenomenology. Perspectives in Continental Philosophy Ser. Vol. 19. Ed. John D. Caputo. New York: Fordham University Press, 2001.

Kerr, Fergus OP. "Aquinas after Marion." New Blackfriars 76 (1995): 354-64. Kosky, Jeffrey L. "The Disqualification of Intentionality: The Gift in Derrida, Levinas,

Page 105: Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis: A Phenomenological Approach to …rnorlander.weebly.com/uploads/2/3/4/5/23456640/norlander... · 2018-10-18 · Self, Alterity, Discourse, Praxis:

105

and Michel Henry." Philosophy Today 41 (1997) (Supp): 186-97. Martis, John. "Thomistic Esse – Idol or Icon? Jean-Luc Marion’s God Without Being."

Pacifica 9 (1996): 55-67. ---. "Only Theology Overcomes Metaphysics." New Blackfriars 76 (1995): 325-42. Overton, J. "See(k)ing God Through the Icon: A Semiotic Analysis of Marion's God

Without Being." Semiotica 110 (1996): 87-126. Smith, James K.A. "Between Predication and Silence: Augustine on How (Not) To Speak of God." Heythrop Journal 41 (2000): 66-86 ---. "Liberating Religion from Theology: Marion and Heidegger on the Possibility of a

Phenomenology of Religion." International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 1 (1999): 17-33.

---. "Respect and Donation: A Critique of Marion’s Critique of Husserl." American

Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 4 (1997): 523-538. Virgoulay, René. "Dieu ou L’Etre?: Relecture de Heidegger en marge de J.-L. Marion,

Dieu sans l’être." Recherches de science religieuse 72 (1984): 163-198. Ward, Graham. "The Theological Project of Jean-Luc Marion." Blond. 67-106. ---. "Introducing Jean Luc Marion." New Blackfriars 76 (1995): 317-24. Ziarek, Krzysztof. "The Language of Praise: Levinas and Marion." Religion and

Literature 22 (1990): 93-107.


Recommended