+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Staal - On Being Reactionary

Staal - On Being Reactionary

Date post: 21-Nov-2015
Category:
Upload: alfricsmith
View: 18 times
Download: 1 times
Share this document with a friend
Description:
Politics
Popular Tags:
15
VIEWPOINT I1 On Being Reactionary Rein Staal CONTEMPORARY CONSERVATISM stands in danger of being the conservatism of nothing. Too much conservative en- ergy pours into negotiations over the pace and method of what are pre- sented as social changes and the policies designed to address them. Many on the Right appear content to represent the voice of prudence in a liberal world. When it falls victim to this mood, conservative thought fails to focus on the true nature of our cultural and political predicament. We must recognize that we face a great contest. At stake is the under- standing of personal identity that supplies moorings for the conserva- tive virtues and lies at the root of any distinctively Western tradition. That understanding is being crushed in the tentacular grasp of the techno- bureaucratic order, its idioms, and its methods. Such a predicament calls for the conservatism of conservatism, a recourse to first principles. No po- litical disposition, no set of policies, will suffice. Our situation calls for a frankly reactionary posture. We must return to the metaphysical founda- tions of Western culture, even and especially if these are denied or dis- torted in the prevailing matrices of power. At the heart of that return lies a renewed appreciation of the personal nature of our world and of ultimate reality. The drama of society mirrors the drama of the soul. Our world and its history, indeed all our stories, de- rive their meaning from personal ini- tiatives. I want to suggest that our most pressing political dilemmas raise the question whether God, man, and world are ultimately personal or im- personal realities. The Western tradi- tion rests at its core on the experience of personal identity. It rests also on the appreciation of ontological het- erogeneity, of the plural and many- leveled character of ultimate reality. Most criticism of the tradition reflects an antipathy to distinct and irreduc- ible personal existence. That antipa- thy comes from viewing multiple cen- ters of agency and responsibility as an illusion and as an affront to the constitution of being. The tragic story of the Left, obscured by its egalitarian formula, amounts to the generation of tyranny out of monism. I propose to sketch the fundamen- tals of a principled reactionary stance through the development of several converging themes. An initial con- trast between the personal and the impersonal suggests the twin themes of political thinking and political lan- guage. We face the rapid spread of I28 Winter 1996
Transcript
  • VIEWPOINT I1

    On Being Reactionary Rein Staal

    CONTEMPORARY CONSERVATISM stands in danger of being the conservatism of nothing. Too much conservative en- ergy pours into negotiations over the pace and method of what are pre- sented as social changes and the policies designed to address them. Many on the Right appear content to represent the voice of prudence in a liberal world. When it falls victim to this mood, conservative thought fails to focus on the true nature of our cultural and political predicament. We must recognize that we face a great contest. At stake is the under- standing of personal identity that supplies moorings for the conserva- tive virtues and lies at the root of any distinctively Western tradition. That understanding is being crushed in the tentacular grasp of the techno- bureaucratic order, its idioms, and its methods. Such a predicament calls for the conservatism of conservatism, a recourse to first principles. No po- litical disposition, no set of policies, will suffice. Our situation calls for a frankly reactionary posture. We must return to the metaphysical founda- tions of Western culture, even and especially if these are denied or dis- torted in the prevailing matrices of power.

    At the heart of that return lies a

    renewed appreciation of the personal nature of our world and of ultimate reality. The drama of society mirrors the drama of the soul. Our world and its history, indeed all our stories, de- rive their meaning from personal ini- tiatives. I want to suggest that our most pressing political dilemmas raise the question whether God, man, and world are ultimately personal or im- personal realities. The Western tradi- tion rests at its core on the experience of personal identity. It rests also on the appreciation of ontological het- erogeneity, of the plural and many- leveled character of ultimate reality. Most criticism of the tradition reflects an antipathy to distinct and irreduc- ible personal existence. That antipa- thy comes from viewing multiple cen- ters of agency and responsibility as an illusion and as an affront to the constitution of being. The tragic story of the Left, obscured by its egalitarian formula, amounts to the generation of tyranny out of monism.

    I propose to sketch the fundamen- tals of a principled reactionary stance through the development of several converging themes. An initial con- trast between the personal and the impersonal suggests the twin themes of political thinking and political lan- guage. We face the rapid spread of

    I28 Winter 1996

    LICENSED TO UNZ.ORGELECTRONIC REPRODUCTION PROHIBITED

  • theories and idioms that, to the ex- tent we take them seriously, reduce human beings to the pliable material of irresponsible power. The question of personality in turn suggests our responsibility to transform the given elements of life. These transforma- tions include that of time into dura- tion, the lived, human time that one can remember and relate as a story, and that of space into location, the place for fellowship and loyalty. (Re- actionaries tend t o b e storytellers and localists rather than theoreti- cians and cosmopolitans.) The dis- cussion of reactionary principles will conclude by considering authority, the crux of the mystery of personal existence. One of the reactionarys first obligations is to illuminate the significance of authority as a bulwark

    foundation of humane living. Todays political controversies re-

    volve around the embattled ideals of personal loyalty and personal respon- sibility. Put another way, those con- troversies imply the alternative of personal dependence or impersonal dependence. Progressive political thought has attacked the former and abet ted t h e la t ter , reflecting Rousseaus insistence that depen- dence on things is less corrupting and degrading than dependence on persons. Human associations con- stituted by mutual personal loyal- ties-notably family, friendship, and locality-confront an intensifying theoretical as well as practical on- slaught. Other spheres of human ac- tivity, such as school and workplace, likewise feature the rise of bureau- cracy and regimentation at the ex- pense of spontaneity and personal loyalty. From the rationalists per- spective, the relationships of family members, friends, and neighbors arise by chance and carry unfathomable

    I against social engineering and as a

    and unwanted dangers. Therefore, we are told, we need plans and programs, staffed by credentialed experts, to undo the damage wrought by us, the amateurs of life, hapless sleepwalk- ers whose first need is to be disabused of the illusion of free agency.

    Depending on the rhetorical cir- cumstance, our progressive savants remark the growth of the impersonal sphere either with the cool detach- ment of the impartial spectator or with the enthusiasm of a co-conspira- tor in the historical process. The reactionarys scandalous vocation consists in the refusal to abet such historical forces or t o accept their inevitability. The inner meaning of reaction is captured in Paul Elmer Mores elegant phrase: to oppose to the welter of circumstance the force of discrimination and selection. This determination must contend with a canard that should be exposed right away, namely the invocation of social change. It is in the name of this slogan that our pundits invoke the famed clock that cannot be turned back, the quintessential technocratic golem. The change in question is clearly not pure change, change as such. Change as such brings to mind the unpredictable, the novel, even the arbitrary. Change a s such has no predetermined content or direction. Social change has been tamed and mastered by t h e theoreticians of progress; it is change that has been filled, mapped out, predicted and pre- destined, a change to end all change. Progressive politics figures as the in- strument through which time sub- mits to theory.

    Since he knows that history has many other avenues besides the crude dichotomy of backwards and for- wards, the reactionary poses indeli- cate questions about the content and direction of change. (Not When will

    Modem Age 129

    LICENSED TO UNZ.ORGELECTRONIC REPRODUCTION PROHIBITED

  • we get there ? but Where are we going ?) A s the pathbreaking reac- tionary G.K. Chesterton put it, whats wrong with t h e world is that not enough people in it ask whats right. The unwillingness to pose that ques- tion explains the veiled, subversive character of the moral orientation behind relativistic and deterministic modes of thought.

    The key challenge facing our think- ing about politics is whether we ought to resist the spiraling augmentation of the impersonal at the expense of the personal. (To pose the question in terms of whether that development is capable of being arrested or reversed is t o substitute an insoluble pseudo- problem for a fundamental question of spiritual orientation.) The nature of our predicament has been expressed with consummate clarity by Romano Guardini as the divorce of power from person. This condition leaves power increasingly autonomous and intan- gible, while persons come increas- ingly t o see themselves as the para- lyzed playthings of forces outside their control. Thus divorced, both power and person are, strictly speaking, ir- responsible. The new world order has as its foundations two pillars, the impersonal constitution of power and the decomposition, one is tempted to say the deconstruction, of the person and of his experience of moral respon- sibility. The recognition that techno- crats and intellectuals, despite their professed disdain for each other, ac- tually operate hand in hand, supplies the key impetus to reactionary think- ing.

    Not for the first time, intellectuals have succumbed t o the lyricism of power. Today, popular social science and the machinery of opinion forma- tion have infused that murky passion deep into the public mind. Art, moral- ity, love, and learning, all the forms of

    judgment and affection, have been recast as matters of power relations. In a way, there is nothing new here. Since the first parents raised the first infant, human beings have known that relations of power figure in the most tender of human experiences. What is destructive in the current teaching is the identification of power with ultimate reality. Todays devo- tees of power eagerly embrace the Nietzschean view that the world of quality is a rhetorical gloss on the world of quantity; there is neither good nor bad, only more and less (power). In this view, all discrimina- tion between can be nothing other than discrimination against. Lacking the poetic integrity of Nietzsches ty- rannical vision, our power-worship- ping contemporaries seek shelter be- hind a patina of egalitarian politics. That retreat does not a t all detract from the lasting legacy of this intellec- tual movement, namely the metaphys- ics of tyranny. According to this view, ultimate reality consists of units of force acting on each other in relations of domination and subjection. On the existential plane, more and more people accept the claim that misery, despair, and lethargy can only be cured by empowerment . Empower men t commonly turns out to mean recruit- ment into the offices and doctrines of the techno-bureaucratic order. (One thinks of the sinister evolution of the once honorable word workshop.)

    Against the metaphysics of tyranny, the reactionary upholds a religious view of ultimate reality. (In this con- text religion is meant in an etymo- logical sense distinct from its applica- tion to specific institutions or to the specific content of Revelation. My dis- cussion draws on the treatment of personal fidelity and disposability by Gabriel Marcel and tha t of religation by Xavier Zubiri.) Accord-

    130 Winter 1996

    LICENSED TO UNZ.ORGELECTRONIC REPRODUCTION PROHIBITED

  • ing to this view, reality owes its coher- ence and its articulation to obliga- tion; or binding, between persons. Human beings are bound both verti- cally, to the source of their existence, and horizontally, to each other. These relationships occur in specifically personal forms such as love or loyalty, or, for that matter, other personal forms such as hate o r resentment. This holds with respect both to the Somebody to Whom we owe our exist- ence and with respect to the others with whom we share the given world. Our understanding of other human beings mirrors the image we have of the source of our existence. Even those who see God and man as things, or as nothings, are themselves bound as persons to an ultimate reality and to other human beings. Either their views are merely speculative and they nev- ertheless live according to a religion of personal fidelity, or they learn to prac- tice the religion of their philosophy and enact the story of personal ex- tinction. To be a person means to be open to the different forms of personal relation, and to find oneself in a field of obligations and loyalties. We can attempt to alter the particulars, or modify the scope, but obligation itself is inescapable, The idiot, the closed soul, lives on t h e spiritual capital accumulated by others.

    Our world receives its articulation from the light cast by personal en- gagements and loyalties. This is as true of the fields of, for instance, eco- nomic and scientific experience, as it is of the personal or religious spheres as understood in the stunted sense current in social criticism. Truth of any sort builds on the fundamental sense of personal faithfulness. When mutual obligations weaken and per- sons begin to live like closed, imper- meable units, the world grows dim. As Guardini and others have noted, Franz

    Modern Age

    Kafka stands as the premier story- teller of a world succumbing to imper- sonality and bureaucracy. Reaction, if you will, is the self-conscious aware- ness of the fundamental reality of personal obligation, or binding. This awareness accompanies a spiritual orientation that sees historical devel- opments toward impersonality as the shadow, not the substance, of our lives. Disregarding the cynicism of those who regard history as the the- ater of necessity, the reactionary bases his outlook on the personal engage- ment of hope.

    At the level of political thinking, the distinction between the impersonal and the personal recalls a major argu- ment put forward by opponents of the French Revolution and of its legacy. That argument centered on a pen- etrating critique of what was seen as the spirit of philosophy. For the statesmen and thinkers of the party of order, the Enlightenment rationalism that claimed the mantle of philosophy stripped all customs and traditional institutions of their authority in order to substitute for them the illegitimate power of the revolutionary State. Jo- seph de Maistre lamented that phi- losophy having corroded the cement binding man t o man, there are no longer any moral ties. The endan- gered alternative was understood as the spirit of religion. In a powerful formulation, Juan Donoso CortCs con- trasted the internal control supplied by religion with the external control supplied by politics, warning that when the religious barometer falls, the political barometer, that is politi- cal control and tyranny, rises. Nor ought we to forget Edmund Burkes eloquent portrayals of the theoreti- cians who proposed to strangle Eu- rope in the grip of abstract schemes that would replace the contingency of tradition with social arrangements

    131

    LICENSED TO UNZ.ORGELECTRONIC REPRODUCTION PROHIBITED

  • flowing from logical necessity. In our day, the spirit of philoso-

    phy and the reactionary resistance contend over what is discussed in fashionable quarters as the equation of the personal and the political. From such quarters issues the demand that the lives of individuals and families be analyzed in terms of power politics. Even more ominous is the almost inevitable corollary that those lives succumb to the same techniques that the State and allied power syndicates have perfected on a larger scale. (As but one example, note the techno- feminist reduction of human beings to human resources valued accord- ing to their economic function, a de- velopment foreseen by Chesterton.) The reactionary stands the fashion- able equation of the personal and the political on its head. lnstead of fur- thering the spread of politicization, reactionary political thinking encour- ages personalization, the reconstitu- tion of power on the basis of personal responsibility. This emphasis replaces the bureaucratic formula of adminis- trative consolidation and spiritual fragmentation with the combination of spiritual integration and adminis- trative decentralization.

    Cries of irrationalism and anti- intellectualism hardly explain tradi- tional opposition to rationalist politi- cal experiments. Such charges side- step the central question of whether political thinking is participant or abstract. Conservatives spurn ratio- nalism because they sense that new meanings are best built up through organic growth within a tradition. At the living heart of tradition lies the experience of participation, of being a part of an order that endows words and deeds with meaning. The occa- sion for being reactionary in turn arises when one becomes conscious of that experience and that order,

    characteristically when they are en- dangered; reactionary hope emerges out of conservative despair. Reac- tionary thinking rests on the experi- ence of self-consciousness and the aspiration to participation. Drawing on ways of thinking deeply embedded in the Western tradition, the reac- tionary strives to order the social and political world in the light of the per- sonal and participant character of ultimate reality. (My understanding of participation draws especially on the treatment of that theme by Marcel and by Michael Polanyi, as well as on the work of Owen Barfield and John Lukacs. In his recent autobiography, Lukacs explains how he has come to think of himself as a reactionary; in one of his many masterful insights, he notes that reactionaries are made, not born. An insistence on the cen- trality of participation also lies at the root of Allen Tates essays setting out his reactionary ideas on literature and culture.)

    Participation is meant here in an ontological sense that goes much deeper than the immediate, often political, sense in which the word is generally used. Participation charac- terizes all human existence, think- ing, and utterance. To live, think, and talk as a human being means to be a part of the order of being and to be linked to the other parts of that order. Any purposive action, like any at- tempt at being understood, affirms that participation. Although we might seek to flee from it, whether frivo- lously or painstakingly, the experi- ence of personal self-consciousness belies those philosophies and politi- cal theories that insist on the imper- sonal or objective character of our human predicaments and their so- lutions. Being as such is irreducibly personal and irreducibly diverse. Abstraction is a fugitive occupation;

    132 Winter 1996 LICENSED TO UNZ.ORG

    ELECTRONIC REPRODUCTION PROHIBITED

  • one always returns to the experience of being a person with obligations. No argument from mechanical causation or logical necessity can explain either the experience or the obligations. It can only explain them away.

    The experience of participation re- flects what Marcel calls the ontologi- cal mystery, which he in turn ex- plains in terms of embodiment, or incarnate being, a theme that affirms the profoundest symbols of the West- ern philosophical and religious tradi- tion. Our personal identity consists in a mysterious reciprocal relation between our selves and our bodies; we are irreducible to our bodies, yet inexplicable without them. I t would be inaccurate to say either that we are our bodies or that we have them as possessions. We cannot step outside that relation, in order for instance to see if its exact workings function along either of the lines suggested above, without abstracting through our in- quiries the very personal identity whose nature we are trying to ob- serve. (Lukacs has illustrated how the realizations of modern science, of physics in particular, confirm this facet of participant thinking.) In this sense personal identity is a mystery that we live within, rather than a problem we can stand outside of in order to solve. The same abstract rea- son that yields such ample dividends in the solution of logical or technical problems, figures in personal life ei- ther as an irrelevance or as a fountain of distortions and simplifications. The usage of mystery as a synonym for meaninglessness or unintelligibility presumes that the only form of reason is the impersonal one that approaches its objects in the spirit of abstraction. Reactionary thinking aims instead to salvage and redeem the meaning won through personal, participant reason. It seeks out hard-won glimpses of

    inner realities rather than command of external, manipulable realities.

    An awareness of participation has clear consequences for political think- ing. Relativist and reductionist for- mulas traduce the conditions of per- sonal existence and ultimately im- pugn the grounds for their own valid- ity. The widespread propagation of such formulas compounds their in- herent deficiencies. Reductionism, for example, has traversed the path from scientific detachment spoken in the third person (Social forces cause ...), to disdainful invective spoken in the second person (Youre only saying that because ...), to the proud asser- tion of irresponsibility spoken in the first person (I, too, am a victim ...). Increasingly, official thought invites us to become the spectators and theo- rists of our own conduct. Yet in the conduct of life, as Burke explained in his critique of revolutionary rhetoric, it is disingenuous to argue from ne- cessity. Necessity needs no help, in- deed brooks no help. What is more important, any argument itself testi- fies to the presence of personal intel- ligence tha t t ranscends t h e mute workings of necessity. Participant political thinking affirms the central- ity of persuasion and deliberation among rational, responsible beings; it is teleological, not causal, because our actions derive their deepest mean- ing from their ends; and it admits that political explanation carries a spiri- tual valence that helps to shape the world it describes, and therefore shares in responsibility for that world.

    Consider the notorious oxymoron at the heart of deterministic thought. Whatever factors may figure as terms of explanation, any theory with a pre- tense of meaningfulness exempts it- self from the scope of the reduction it imposes on the world at large. This is, if anything, most poignantly true of

    Modem Age 133 LICENSED TO UNZ.ORG

    ELECTRONIC REPRODUCTION PROHIBITED

  • those theories, recurringly popular among the intelligentsia, that would deflect criticism by denying the real- ity of reason and of reasonable dis- course. Abstraction from the field of rational meaning operates much like abstraction from the field of personal obligation. The operation can be per- formed, but only so long as those involved nourish themselves on the spiritual resources of a wider world constituted by precisely those two fields. (In a striking analogy, Miguel de Unamuno compared gnostic intel- lectualswho deny the reality of per- sonal identity t o intestinal parasites who might take it upon themselves to deny the reality of sight or hearing.)

    Our political language suffers from a similar corruption effected by the spirit of abstraction. Consider the prevalence of the type of expression described by C.S. Lewis as the meth- odological idiom. Language of this sort plays on the transference of mean- ing between phenomena and the study or treatment of those phenomena. Li- able to occur in any established trade, it is particularly overweening in the language of academics. (One could easily, for example, hear someone re- ferred to as an important figure in German history only to realize that the speaker is referring, not t o Bis- marck or Adenauer, but to a professor at an American university.) Method- ological idiom supplies the pathway through which a host of noxious ne- ologisms have invaded our political discourse and, within the space of remarkably few years, begun to crowd out traditional moral and spiritual categories. Foremost among these invaders are expressions and formu- las such as social problems and social forces. Through such expres- sions the mindset of mechanical ex- planation has come to color our un- derstanding of ourselves as a commu-

    nity. In a development that comes as no surprise to a reactionary, the so- cial engineers who set out to harness those forces and solve those problems come back repeatedly asking for more time and more money, more pro- grams. The iatrogenic character of our social problems has become in- creasingly apparent t o sensible ob- servers. The interior, spiritual dimen- sion of personal existence exacts its revenge upon attempts t o manage human affairs as if people were closed units or carriers of impersonal forces. Undeterred, our managers have the temerity to identify the resultant an- ger and despair, not as the spiritual distresses they are, but as yet more problems requiring additional pro- grams.

    The connection between method- ology and bureaucracy is far from accidental. Over half a century ago Zubiri diagnosed the bureaucratiza- tion of the intellect, the reduction of the republic of letters to an amalgam of self-referential disciplines with a gentlemans agreement not to intrude on each others turf as each refined its terminology and amplified its tech- niques. The expansion of bureaucratic power requires a constant replenish- ing of the technical vocabulary pre- sumed to explain our social and po- litical life. The findings of social sci- ence likewise figure among the arcana of the techno-bureaucratic order. The impersonal they receives its para- digmatic use in the expression they did a study, which characteristically introduces the conclusion of some eager researchers that yet another facet of everyday life should be reorga- nized in order to benefit from profes- sional expertise. Sophists are the rain- makers of tyranny.

    Trend-setting theoreticians have pursued the bureaucratization of the intellect to its finale, suggesting that

    134 Winter 1996

    LICENSED TO UNZ.ORGELECTRONIC REPRODUCTION PROHIBITED

  • discourse may not be capable of refer- ring to anything but itself. Leaving aside the oxymoron, note that this approach elevates academic oppor- tunism to a theory of knowledge. When Jose Ortega y Gasset wrote that love is a text, he meant that it is a dramatic and creative engagement through which we enact our lives. When todays scholar argues that love is a text, he is likely to mean that its significance lies in being a subject for journal articles. Consider the effects of propagating such methodolatry. The danger is not so much that language will cease to be a medium for the transmission of meaning; not even the new theoreti- cians seriously envision such a fu- ture. The danger lies more in the weak- ening of our capacity t o hold the wielders of power accountable through intelligent public discourse. Some- one who has lost faith in the ability of language to illuminate reality is ready prey for any tyrannical design.

    The spread of methodological lan- guage calls for a redoubled insistence on the use of participant, ontological language. Reliance on such language is an important aspec t of t h e reactionarys scandalous vocation. Ontological language rests on t h e awareness that meaningful thought and speech imply our openness to, and our participation in, realities other and larger than ourselves. Having passed through the crucible of per- sonal self-consciousness, such lan- guage, instead of implying a notional return to the participant language of those ensconced in an unproblematic tradition, represents a subsequent victory over the spirit of abstraction. (Barfield describes this victory as fi- nal participation, as distinguished from the original participation en- joyed before the rise of science and self-conscious theory.) In the case of moral and political language, such a

    recognition is especially pressing. In this sphere, we would do well to rely on an insight tha t goes back t o Socratess critique of sophistry. The debunking of a term such as justice would make no sense unless that term described a real quality that can be traduced or denied within political life. The reduction of moral and politi- cal language to symbols referring only to the relations of power among their users confuses the corruption with the substance. However much we may subvert its purposes, language re- mains the medium of our link with reality and with each other.

    Here reactionary thinking draws close to the spirit evoked by Thomas i Kempis when he warned against the temptation of being an inquisitive philosopher who, considering the con- stellations of heaven, willfully forgets himself, and told his readers that he would rather feel compunction in his heart for his sins than know the defi- nition of compunction. True knowl- edge is personal knowledge, charac- terized by the inward appropriation of ideas. Opposing this insight stands the regnant emphasis on how our language reveals our position on things. This emphasis rewards the repetition of approved formulas (what Lukacs calls the substitution of vo- cabulary for thought). This empha- sis finds its existential form in those ideologists convinced that their intel- lectual baggage enjoys diplomatic immunity. Consider the humanitar- ians who hold actual flesh-and-blood people in contempt, or the egalitarians who devote their own lives t o craven status-mongering. Under the influence of this spiritual pathology, the avarice of ideas, virtue and distinction lie in the accumulation of fashionable opinions. When the reactionary challenges those opinions he does so not so much for the undeniable amusement it brings as for

    Modern Age 135 LICENSED TO UNZ.ORG

    ELECTRONIC REPRODUCTION PROHIBITED

  • the sake of rehabilitating our public dis- course, crippled as it is by slogans gener- ated and disseminated through the bu- reaucracy of ideas.

    The methodological cast of bureau- cratic language reflects a rejection of metaphor in favor of the infinite re- gress of neologism. In the hands of skilled practitioners, neologism serves as a technology of ideas, the equiva- lent of techniques of advertising and planned obsolescence. In large part, the phenomena discussed under the label political correctness indicate attempts by bureaucrats and intellec- tuals to keep abreast of the stream of neologisms. For those susceptible to such techniques, proper moral and political terminology changes at a pace akin on the one hand to that of devel- opments in mass consumption, and akin on the other hand to that of methodological innovation in an aca- demic discipline. As in those other areas of endeavor, status rests on being at the cutting edge. One would not dare be seen sporting yesterdays paradigms. Each new accession of an issue leads to the demand that we demonstrate our commitment. Not coincidentally, the desired commit- ment invariably involves swelling the bureaucratic class and its power over our lives.

    The spirit of neologism is perhaps best illustrated when it fastens on a word in common use. Note the recent career of the word diversity. This term denotes a key conservative theme. As is pointed out by Erik von Kuehnelt-Leddihn in writings includ- ing his classic Leflism (1974), a devo- tion t o diversity arguably distin- guishes the Right from the Left. The elements of this devotion are many; consider, for example, respect for re- gional traditions, the insistence that human beings are not interchange- able, the tendency to think in terms of

    distinct persons rather than large classes of people, support for various institutions that shield individuals from the State, as well as the related belief in decentralization. We are now expected to restrict the term to one explicit, technical meaning, one that refers to a specific demographic dis- tribution. Not surprisingly, the new usage is explained and enforced by a phalanx of experts. Note also that, in a characteristic tour de force, the term is now compatible, not only with in- tellectual conformism, but also with the pursuit of economic and political integration on a global scale.

    The spirit of neologism also ac- counts for the notorious opacity of methodological language. Technical terms carry literal, stipulated mean- ings anchored in the presuppositions of the science or ideology that makes use of them. The opacity of technical terms lies not in their difficulty, but in the fact that one cannot, as it were, see through such terms to call on the kind of associations and implications that characterize t h e vernacular lan- guage. Steeped as they are in idiom- atic tradition, populists and tradi- tionalists are often perplexed by the strident insistence of issue activists that the population undergo educa- tion as the answer to social prob- lems, even when it does not seem that formal instruction could add much t o common sense about/ the matter in question. We must remem- ber that such programs of education are designed, not primarily as addi- tions to our stock of knowledge, but as initiations into the premises and terminology of social engineering. (As one listens to the way in which activ- ists intone the word education, it becomes apparent that this once noble word has itself undergone a contrac- tion even more egregious than the one that limits it to institutionalized, cer-

    136 Winter 1996

    LICENSED TO UNZ.ORGELECTRONIC REPRODUCTION PROHIBITED

  • tified schooling.) Taken seriously enough, such new idioms entirely cut off their users from inherited wisdom and reflection.

    Spurning neologism, participant language relies instead on metaphor. Metaphor requires initiation, not into a method, but into a culture and into a sense of idiomatic tradition. The ebb and flow of metaphors reflect the shap- ing force of what Barfield has dis- cussed as speakers meaning, which builds on but alters the literal, stipu- lated meaning of words. Speakers meaning is the source of nuance, of poetry, and of wit. Tradition allows and encourages a degree of personal inflection unacceptable to the tech- nocrats of ideas, who yearn for inter- changeable people holding inter- changeable opinions. For that rea- son, technocrats strive to replace tra- ditional usages with a vocabulary pre- sumed to express an unmediated ap- prehension of social reality. In this fashion, moral and political phenom- ena are redefined as technical prob- lems in fields ranging from medicine t o fiscal policy. Yet attempts to d o without metaphor mask their own poetic diction. Anyone who believes that a term such as codependency has a hard, literal meaning missing from a phrase like no man is an island, is truly lost in the mists of theory.

    The acceptance of technical terms as merely literal reflections of reality forecloses any consideration of the metaphysical postulates and political designs that have gone into the mak- ing of such terms. Consider the in- creasingly prevalent treatment of the concept equality as a literalism referring to an aggregate, demographi- cally proportioned distribution of po- litical power and of economic roles and rewards. (Here, the mathematical reduction seems to be a danger built

    into the concept itself, as von Kuehnelt-Leddihn and Marcel have argued and as Tocqueville warned so eloquently.) Again we confront a key term defined so as to foreclose consid- eration of the manner and quality of power and of economic roles. Taken seriously, technocratic politics con- jures up the Kafkaesque experience of the world as a place of outsides with no inside to them (Barfields descrip- tion of the mechanical worldview).

    Yet, to cite one of Chestertons clas- sic paradoxes, the inside is larger than the outside. Few propositions come closer to expressing the core of reactionary thinking. The spiritual dimension of life holds more signifi- cance, and ultimately more power, than those facets of life described from the outside in objective or me- chanical language. Hence the reac- tionary holds what one could call a sacramental attitude toward the given elements of life, which he sees as occasions for testifying to the obliga- tions of human agency. Foremost among those obligations are the re- demption of time through tradition and the transformation of space into place, or location. Both constitute per enn i a1 hum an engage men t s de- signed to cast the world in the form of an ethical community rather than that of a field for the workings of necessity. Deracination, the attempt to live out- side tradition and outside location, draws its inspiration from the desire to replace obligations with choices, yet it issues in submission to imper- sonal forces.

    Tradition anchors our experience of time in memory, and projects it into the future through hope. Its inner logic is dramatic rather than dialecti- cal, something explicated through narration rather than through dem- onstration or analysis. The principle of tradition seems backward and irra-

    Modern Age 137

    LICENSED TO UNZ.ORGELECTRONIC REPRODUCTION PROHIBITED

  • tional only from the imagined per- spective of impersonal, disembodied reason. The dramatic structure of his- tory, its character as a tableau of stories, reflects our existence as em- bodied spirits. We are unavoidably immersed in the succession of events yet also capable of, and given to, ab- stracting our self-consciousness, our thoughts, and our hopes, from that stream. Human beings experience neither the immersion nor the ab- straction to the exclusion of the other, which is why they experience life as a drama; personal life is self-conscious but not self-sufficient. Traditional is scarcely an appropriate term for static societies that have a diminished sense of time and of personal existence. As an active engagement, a sense sug- gested by its etymology, tradition im- plies a participant understanding of personal identity. The field of obliga- tion and the field of meaning extend into the past and into the future. The transmission of culture sustains our awareness of those relations.

    The propaganda of social change builds instead on an impersonal con- ception of time as mere succession. Such a conception reflects the deter- ministic errors so aptly pointed out by Henri Bergson. Progressivist time is dead; it consists of discrete moments that cannot react upon each other and instead run a necessary course visible to observers. This view in effect reduces time to space, and then ex- plains all movement (change) in terms of mechanical causation. In a world envisioned in this way, there is no room, for instance, for memory or hope, the human activities that allow past, present, and future t o shape and enrich each other. Tocqueville pointed out the political implications of this mechanical conception of time through his discussion of democratic historianship, a discussion amplified

    and updated in Lukacss writings. Once the doctrine of necessity takes hold of the public mind, the French- man warned, free citizens would be enervated into submission. Histori- ans of general causes teach men to obey. Aggregate movements are pre- sented as impersonal processes, only to wind up as idols, as hollow abstrac- tions presumed to govern our lives. In our day, we see a blatant manifesta- tion of this spirit in administrative boosterism, whose slogans are for- ever masking the march of bureau- cracy in florid asseverations of the need to adapt to exciting new histori- cal trends.

    Against the lure of historical neces- sity, the reactionary looks t o dura- tion, to lived, human time. From this perspective, progress is a spiritual phenomenon, in the s e n s e tha t Bunyan wrote of progress. Human time takes the form of a journey, a pilgrimage. The journey is shot through with contingency; the pil- grim may get lost, be misguided or delayed or ambushed, may even go backwards (at times because, having strayed or having neglected some- thing, h e ought to). We participate in our destiny through the media of hope and despair. Life has a plot that con- tinuously calls on us to assume re- sponsibility for our actions and for the spiritual orientation that supplies the shaping power of what we want to believe. The refusal to acknowledge human beings as pilgrims explains the hierarchical cast of most contem- porary egalitarian movements and ideologies. These generally embrace a historicized version of the rationalist distinction between the few and the vulgar. In this view, the many are weighted down by ostensibly tempo- rary forms of false consciousness. For the time being, the division persists between the few who recognize the

    138 Winter 1996

    LICENSED TO UNZ.ORGELECTRONIC REPRODUCTION PROHIBITED

  • workings of necessity and the many who suffer delusions of free agency. At some point in the future, after sufficient education and reconstruc- tion, the life of freedom and responsi- bility may commence. Meanwhile, we a r e put under t h e tutelage of a mandarinate licensed to tell us whats what. Reactionaries tend to believe, on the other hand, that the moral journey is now, that we should not wait for relief from our burdens. In opposing the proffered postponement of personal responsibility, reaction- ary thinking affirms one of the most powerful populist sentiments. Moral agency is not so much the goal as the way; our obligations would cease to have meaning if we could perform them without hindrance or temptation.

    Localism, cultural as well as politi- cal, complements the understanding of time as a moral journey fraught with significance and contingency. Rationalist political thought and the social engineering it inspires feed on a hostility to what progressives see as the accidental, arbitrary constituents of a human life. Foremost among those constituents are the identities and loyalties generated by local attach- ments. Far more is at stake here than the admittedly important debate over federalism. Reactionary localism points to a first principle, the same theme of embodiment that underlies the dramatic structure of human his- tory. No embodied existence, not even that of the most abstracted theoreti- cian, can dispense with the categories of here and there. Even under the most dire conditions of cultural de- cline and confusion, much of a persons identity hinges on his loca- tion and on his ties to those he finds there. Local patriotism works to trans- form location from more of an exter- nal, spatial factor to something expe rienced as a source of meaning and

    significance. Viewed as human situa- tions, locations are no more inter- changeable than are persons or their biographies. The reactionary seeks to redeem the looming indifference of space through the building of homes and communities that mirror the ar- ticulated, obligation-laden character of ultimate reality.

    From the techno-bureaucratic per- spective, all the worlds places to- gether comprise one undifferentiated mass of space, flecked with recalci- trant spots pretending to distinct iden- tities. The inhabitants of this univer- sal space figure less as human beings than as human resources, inter- changeable units of labor ever more tightly girded in the mesh of national and international markets. Much of the sentiment derided as protection- ism expresses a dissent from this reduction of human nature, a dissent not stilled by discussions of the shifts and compensations effected by the macroeconomic mechanism. The managers of the mechanism do a deli- cate dance with their egalitarian part- ners, as the demand for an equal distribution of offices and rewards rubs against the bottom line. Neither wing of the new world order pays much attention to those mossbacks who would call into question their enterprise as a whole by insisting on the integrity of local communities and on the priority of personal ties over functional roles.

    Local loyalties run afoul of central- izing technocrats and leveling radi- cals for the same underlying reason. Both groups regard the various hu- man associations that arise organi- cally as impediments to the compre- hensive reconstitution of our lives. As students of tyranny have long recog- nized, such associations, when in- tact, endow persons with qualities that make them resistant to the or-

    Modern Age 139

    LICENSED TO UNZ.ORGELECTRONIC REPRODUCTION PROHIBITED

  • chestration of their lives. Confirming Richard Weavers apprehension, even the enjoyment of friendship has come under attack as arbitrary. We are in- creasingly encouraged to rely for sus- tenance o n support groups and mentoring conducted under profes- sional auspices. Reactionaries insist that such arrangements be debated on their merits, not on the basis of the social changes presumed to neces- sitate them. As to policies and institu- tions, the reactionary posture incor- porates suspicion, what the founding fathers would have called republican j ea1 o u s y . Reaction a r ie s a r e t h or- oughly skeptical of the bureaucratic claim that we have no alternative to centralization and regimentation. On the level of the spirit, t h e reactionary posture incorporates a scandalous hope. Perhaps we can turn back the clock; perhaps uprooting can be un- done; perhaps families, neighbor- hoods, friendships-the persons and places that matter-can rise from the ashes of dislocation and mistrust.

    As an alternative to the consolida- tion of impersonal power, the reac- tionary returns t o the principle of authority. Authority humanizes power and makes it personally meaningful and personally accountable. Much as tradition redeems time and location redeems space, authority redeems power. Power without authority works as a mechanical force. As Guardini argued, we who live at the end of modernity face the decisive challenge of curbing autonomous power and recasting it in the light of personal responsibility. Authority and respon- sibility intertwine inextricably; au- thority resides in persons or bodies of persons who can answer for their ac- tions. Power wielded in and by the techno-bureaucratic order functions precisely through its lack of author- ity. Its impersonality at once protects it

    from its subjects and justifies it in the eyes of its adherents. Tocqueville fore- saw the proliferation of this kind of power and, keenly aware of how its faceless and efficient character distinguished it from classical models of tyranny, termed it democratic despotism; in the twenti- eth century, James Burnham and later observers have charted,the course of managerial power and its method of handling persons as one might handle trained animals or other resources.

    Reactionaries tackle the crisis of authority on three levels, the per- sonal, the literary, and the political. In each case, bureaucratic institu- tions, private as well as public, do their best to shape a world in which authority gives way t o impersonal forces. At the same time, each case feeds on theories and idioms emerg- ing from the bureaucracy of ideas. A review of the three levels of the crisis will shed some light on the reaction- ary enterprise of reinvigorating au- thority.

    Every man is the author of his own actions. In that sense, each of us exercises what we could call personal authority. Personal responsibility hinges on personal authority; the former makes no sense without the latter. The current attack on the prin- ciple of authority is not directed at the overlords generally identified with authoritarianism. The attack begins closer to home, as more and more persons, inspired by the propaganda of determinism and sustained by the engines of therapy and pharmacol- ogy, disavow authorship of their own actions. Our culture displays an in- creasingly clear split between those who would extend the scope of per- sonal responsibility and those who would diminish it. The reactionary stands firm with those who would uphold the principleof personal respon- sibility. Reactionary thinking does not

    140 Winter 1996

    LICENSED TO UNZ.ORGELECTRONIC REPRODUCTION PROHIBITED

  • deny the reality of impersonal forces that may work on our bodies and on our minds. Instead, what is at stake is the existence of a nucleus of personal iden- tity and responsibility that is irreducible to those forces. Nor does the reactionary deny the crippling power of anger and despair, spiritual themes prominent in the stories of our lives. The line is drawn elsewhere, at the elevation of personal irresponsibility into a principle that one seeks to justify. Reactionary criticism is obliged to expose, and even lampoon, the spiritual oxymoron of reductionism voiced in the first person. Only those who acknowledge authority over their actions can work to curb irresponsible power.

    Note the controversy over literary authorship. At the most advanced fringes of academia the notion has got about that authors, strictly speaking, d o not exist; they have been deconstructed along with their texts. Once again, we see bureaucrats profi- teering in the void left by the eclipse of authority. The death of personal au- thority builds the business of treat- ment industries; the death of the au- thor builds the business of the critic, now presented with unlimited oppor- tunities for speculation. Books be- come matter for dissection, and for the virtuosity of artful manipulation; what suffers is their potential for trans- forming and enhancing the vision of the reader. The bureaucracy of ideas, here as elsewhere, repeats and incul- cates formulas that corrode the sense of personal identity and prepare the way for a more general consolidation of bureaucratic, managerial power. Deconstruction of personal identity effects the mining and sapping re- quired in order to supply ready mate- rial for projects of social engineering.

    The reactionary approach to politi- cal authority builds on the traditional conservative view of political power, a

    view simultaneously realistic and hopeful. Consider Burkes observa- tion: A certain quantum of power must always exist in the community, in some hands, and under some ap- pellation. Wise men will apply their remedies to vices, not to names; to the causes of evil which are permanent, not to the occasional organs by which they act, and the transitory modes in which they appear. Burke was well aware that the history of governments is a sad tale full of fraud and force. He also saw, as have most conservatives, that power is an enduring reality in political society and an enduring temp- tation to those who wield it. From this perspective, the government of men defies reduction to the administra- tion of things. The challenge posed by power is whether it can be experi- enced as authority and not as force, whether, in other words, it can be redeemed through personal obliga- tion.

    Progressive thought has suc- cumbed to different variants of a m e nistic view of power (reflecting what More discussed as the Demon of the Absolute). The revolutionary Left rested in the belief that in the future relations of power would be completely transcended. The story of Marxist re- gimes has made this position increas- ingly untenable, though the power of such nostrums to persist should never be underestimated. The main current of todays progressive thought pro- poses a cynicism as thoroughgoing in its way as the discredited utopianism. We are now asked to adjust ourselves to a world whose ultimate reality is inescapably constituted by relations of power, a world in which the joys and burdens of personal existence are reduced to manifestations of those relations. We are used to identifying this view with those who invoke the demonology of oppression, but it also

    Modern Age 141

    LICENSED TO UNZ.ORGELECTRONIC REPRODUCTION PROHIBITED

  • informs the theory that sees the end of history in a global technocratic re- gime. (Perhaps we could speak of Left Nietzscheans and Right Nietzsche- ans.) Against both variants of the metaphysics of power, the reaction- ary puts forward the principle of au- thority derived from the metaphys- ics of personal obligation. W e cannot escape relations of power, but they can and must b e transfigured by mutual loyalties and personal ac- countability. Authority marks the transmutation of necessity into obli- gation. To the extent that the reac- tionary can be distinguished from the traditional conservative, the difference may lie in the reactionary belief that the unbought grace of life did not die with the Old Regime, but instead rep- resents a perennial human possibil- ity. The counterrevolution cherishes personal loyalty and insists on per- sonal responsibility, though these spiritual values may conflict with ev- ery known institutional imperative; and it works t o replace unilateral, bureaucratic power with power of a personal scale and constitution, dis- regarding t h e cynicism of those pawned to the techno-bureaucratic order.

    The distinction between power and authority reflects the mystery of per- sonal identity. The prevalence of im- personal power indicates that funda- mental human realities have been problematized so that they appear

    to us as phenomena whose impersonal workings we can trace. The theoreti- cians and managers of impersonal forces will reply that they are simply dealing with observable realities that just hap- pen to be so, regardless of our wishes. Non ridere, non lugere, neque detestari, sed inteelligere. (Not to laugh, not to weep, neither to denounce, but to under- stand. Spinozas motto captures the dominant mood of technocratic politics.) Yet the reactionary knows that all hu- man phenomena reflect the mysterious quality at the heart of personal identity. The inside is larger than the outside. The reactionary also knows that those, small or great, who claim to be merely the pristine vessels of impersonal forces in fact harbor the souls of tyrants. We must recognize power exercised outside the field of mutual personal obligations as the usurpation that it is.

    Being reactionary entails care for the spiritual realities that integrate and illu- minate our common world. The integrity of language, the mutual obligation of personal ties, the cultivation of place, the insistence on personal responsibil- ity for power: all testify to the fundamen- tal reality of personal identity. The reac- tionary vocation lies in the reclamation of these projects, even and especially if the constitution of the social and politi- cal world threatens to make them obso- lete. Though the faith in recovery may seem a scandalous and quixotic dream, the reactionary knows the work is worth the effort.

    142 Winter 1996

    LICENSED TO UNZ.ORGELECTRONIC REPRODUCTION PROHIBITED


Recommended