+ All Categories
Home > Documents > The Emotional Power of Music DRAFT Introduction Section

The Emotional Power of Music DRAFT Introduction Section

Date post: 07-Jul-2018
Category:
Upload: irinamares
View: 218 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend

of 22

Transcript
  • 8/18/2019 The Emotional Power of Music DRAFT Introduction Section

    1/22

     

    The Emotional Power of Music: Multidisciplinary Perspectives on Musical

     Arousal, Expression and Social Control

    (2013, Oxford UP) 

    Review Essay (unpublished draft, 2014)

     by Dylan van der Schyff, Simon Fraser University 

    Introduction

    The power of music has been a topic of fascination for thousands of years; there is perhaps no

    human activity that so fully spans the range of human experience and potentials. Music exercises

    our cognitive abilities for pattern recognition and structure and thus affords some of the most

    exquisite formal phenomena we are capable of experiencing. Beginning early in life, musicality

    also plays a central role in developing the corporeal and social bonds that allow us to form

    interpersonal relationships, a sense of identity, belonging and community. As a result, music has

    traditionally provided an important public ÔspaceÕ where we come together to participate in

    culture. Musical experiences do move us physically, intellectually, socially and spiritually; and

    the transformative musical phenomena associated with ritual, ceremony, therapeutic contexts and

    everyday life are shared features of human existence around the world. But while it appears to be

    largely agreed that musicÕs ability to do what it does must be related to the way it engages our

    emotional faculties, explaining just how this is so is extremely difficult.For most of the last century, this project was dominated by a focus on the relationship

     between structure and expressivity in Western classical musicÐÐuntil relatively recently the

     putative superiority and autonomous status of the Classical canon went largely unquestioned and

    the locus of musical expressivity was often thought to be found in (or 'possessedÕ by) the formal

    structural relationships of the Ômusic itselfÕ. From this so-called ÔexpressionistÕ perspective, the

    subjective experiences of listeners and performers are largely irrelevant; it is only necessary that

    they are in possession of the appropriate cognitive apparatus to perceive, represent and correctly 

    appraise the supposedly objective formal relationships encoded into the score by the composer

    (Bohlman, P, 1999; D. Clark, 2012; Small, 1999; Davies, 2002).

    This perspective has developed hand-in-hand with the dominant information-processing

    model of the mind. By this light, cognition is understood to occur through a hierarchical input-

    output process, where representations of a 'world out there' are computed through abstract symbol

     processing at non-conscious levels in the brainÑi.e. Ôthe mind as computer metaphorÕ (Pinker,

  • 8/18/2019 The Emotional Power of Music DRAFT Introduction Section

    2/22

    2009; Varela  et al ., 1993). Thus research and theory has been dominated by a strangely

    disembodied, detached and decontextualized focus on the cognitive appraisal (i.e. processing) of

    musical stimuli in terms of ÔbasicÕ or Ôgarden variety emotionsÕ (such as joy, fear, anger and so

    on) according to rule-based processesÐÐwhere socio-cultural environments, human development,

    and personal agency receive little attention.Eric Clarke has argued that this so-called ÔcognitivistÕ orientation reduces musical

    cognition to an "abstract reasoning or problem solving process" where Òperception is treated as a

    kind of disinterested contemplation with no connection to actionÐÐwhich bears little relationship

    to the essentially exploratory function of perception in the life of an organism" (2005:15). Indeed,

    recent decades have seen a shift in our understanding of how the mind functions, as well as a

    much richer conception of what music and meaning-making entails. The notion of innate ÔbasicÕ

    emotions has come under growing scrutiny (see Colombetti, 2014); and an increasingly

    influential ecological-embodied paradigm has emerged that suggests more plastic, adaptive, and

    interactive (or ÔenactiveÕ) conceptions of the mind-brain and organism-environment relationships

    (Doidge, 2007; Gallagher, 2005; Johnson, 2007, Ramachadran, 2011). These new insights offer us

    a deeper perspective on the affective power of musicÐÐone that goes to the core of our embodied

    existence to consider how, beginning in infancy, our involvement with music originates in an

    embodied emotional-aesthetic context that is based in movement, cross modal perceptions, and

     pre-linguistic recognitions of embodied affective states (Johnson, 2007; Trevarthen, 2002).

    That we engage with music at this primordial biological level is evident in clinical settings

    (music therapy), developmental contexts, and in everyday life (DeNora, 2000; van der Schyff,

    2013). Along these lines, a range of researchers are exploring the affective power of music at the

    levels of culture and direct lived experience, revealing that even within rather codified cultural

    contexts individuals do  enact unique relationships with music that are central to their sense of

    identity, embodiment and self. As DeNora writes, music is Òa device for ordering the selfÓ; Òa

    resource for meaning and world makingÓ (2000; 2011). In brief, a greater emphasis is being

     placed on understanding how people become involved with music in terms of enacting individual

    and social-cultural economies, not as passive listeners-consumers but rather as active and

    embodied participants in the construction of musical meaning.

    This is all to say that it is indeed a very exciting and productive time for the study of

    musical emotion. A more nuanced story is beginning to be toldÐÐone where the factors that give

    rise to emotional-affective musical experiences span ecological-embodied interactions, primary

     bodily processes and social contexts, as well as cognitive appraisals and abstract cultural and

    individual meanings. Not surprisingly, the complexity associated with these richer conceptions of

    2

  • 8/18/2019 The Emotional Power of Music DRAFT Introduction Section

    3/22

    music, emotion and meaning is too much for one discipline to accommodate and recent decades

    have seen a surge in cooperative research across diverse fields of inquiry. Much of the knowledge

    generated by this interdisciplinary work has been presented in excellent edited anthologies (e.g.

    Juslin & Sloboda, 2010). The most recent contribution is The Emotional Power of Music:

     Multidisciplinary Perspectives on Musical Arousal, Expression, and Social Control (Cochrane,Fantini & Scherer, 2013), which will be the subject of the review that follows.

    Review: The Emotional Power of Music 

    Like its predecessors, The Emotional Power of Music is organized around broad themes. Three

    sectionsÐÐrespectively entitled ÔMusical expressivenessÕ, ÔEmotion elicitationÕ and ÔThe powers

    of musicÕÐÐprovide the general categories by which a diverse range of ideas and approaches are

     presented and discussed. Each section receives an introduction by one of the editors where

    constituent chapters are outlined and placed in context. These introductions offer useful

     background information for readers who may be new to this area of research. Likewise they allow

    more experienced readers to better orient the research offered by each author within the field at

    large. The writing is generally clear and well referenced; key terms and concepts receive adequate

    explanation. As a result, the book should be accessible to anyone interested in the topic while

    remaining a valuable reference for professional musicologists. For the most part, the ÔmusicÕ and

    musical practices discussed are restricted to Western art music and this will certainly frustrate

    some readers. This notwithstanding, the book offers critical perspectives, as well as welcome

    enhancements to traditional approaches, with many of the authors embracing important current

    concerns associated with embodiment. The focus of this review is on areas associated with

     philosophical and psychological musicology, which comprises the majority of the volumeÐР

    chapters dealing with historical issues are considered only briefly.

    Section 1 Ð Musical expressiveness

    Following Tom CochraneÕs introduction, Section 1 opens with Michael SpitzerÕs analysis of

    ÒTrocken BlumenÓ from SchubertÕs song cycle  Die Schšne MŸllerin. Spitzer begins with a

    traditional musicological approach, initially looking for emotional meaning within the melodic

    and harmonic structure of the work. The chief focus here is on understanding how the composer

    constructs the pieceÐÐand, as Spitzer suggests, the whole cycleÐÐaround a Òmelodic apexÓ (the

    highest sung note) that coincides with the emotional peak of the composition. What makes

    SpitzerÕs approach so interesting, however, is the way he develops a more explicitly biological

    and movement-based conception of musical emotion than one usually finds in traditional score

    3

  • 8/18/2019 The Emotional Power of Music DRAFT Introduction Section

    4/22

     based analysisÐÐsee, for example, his discussion of the subconscious physiological-emotional

     power of the ÔcryÕ, as well as the metaphor of ÔgrowthÕ and ÔblossomingÕ. Indeed, Spitzer argues

    that Òmost analytical approaches to musical emotion are staticÓ and he suggests that we would do

     better to consider music in terms of its Òaffective trajectory.Ó This perspective allows Spitzer to

    analyze Òthe core affectÓÐÐin this case sadnessÐÐas a Òcomplex package of entailmentsÓ; or as agroup of Ògoal drivenÓ processes.

    This approach is not necessarily at odds with attribution, expressionist or persona models

    of musical expressivity. However, it does tend to radicalize such possibilities with the listener by

    highlighting the fundamental transformative aspects of musical experience; and by recognizing

    that emotions are not simply Òexpressive modes,Ó but rather Òstates of mind or beingÓ that involve

    Òaction tendencies.Ó Thus, for Spitzer, our affective involvement with music is grounded, first and

    foremost, in empathic experiences of movement, the body and social interactions (e.g. separation

    anxiety). According to him, these primal responses and associations are what allow Òemotional

    contagionÓ to occur in the first placeÐÐwhich, in turn, allows us to ÔaestheticizeÕ the feelings we

    refer to with terms such as sadness, joy and so on.

    Some readers will recognize the influence of theories developed in affective neuroscience

    and may wish that this connection be developed more fully. The work of Panksepp, for example,

    is discussed only briefly. Mark JohnsonÕs (2007) work in embodied aesthetics is also relevant to

    SpitzerÕs Òaffective trajectoryÓ approach; the inclusion of such research would lend further

    support from the fields of neuroscience, human development and philosophy of mind.

     Nevertheless, the chapter provides a welcome ÔembodiedÕ extension to traditional musicology that

    may point the way towards enhanced forms of analysis.

    Following SpitzerÕs analytical approach, Chapter 3 offers an interesting change of focus.

    Here Tom Cochrane interviews three very different composers in order to discover how they

    understand and employ the expressive powers of music in their practice. Cochrane begins each

    interview with essentially the same question, ÒDo you believe music arouses emotions in

    listeners?Ó This allows each composer to move off in his own direction, with Cochrane providing

    further questions that do an excellent job of clarifying and advancing the ideas at hand. The first

    interview is with electro-acoustic composer, Jean-Claude Risset. Risset works outside the context

    of traditional tonal harmony and is therefore able to offer a unique perspective on the relationship

     between sound and feelingÐÐone developed over many years of creative practice and research

    composing with sound and composing sound itself. The composer discusses our affective

    relationship with sound on a number of levels (bodily states, environmental context, survival and

    evolution) and he considers how music and sound may be used to manipulate listeners, for better

    4

  • 8/18/2019 The Emotional Power of Music DRAFT Introduction Section

    5/22

    and for worse. Along these lines, Risset shares some of the fascinating discoveries and

    experiences he and his colleagues have encountered in their practice, as well as reflections on

    how post-tonal and non-tonal music is received and experienced emotionally in different contexts

    (e.g. film, theatre, acousmatic listening environments and so on). In all it is a fascinating

    discussion, underpinned by RissetÕs quasi-ethical position that the generation of emotion in musicshould be an interactive process, Òperformed by the active and attentive listener, rather than as a

    result of systematic processes intended to make the music emotional by using tricks of the trade

     producing direct psychological effectsÓ (p.26).

    This is followed by a brief conversation with Brian Ferneyhough that examines concerns

    associated with the relationship between emotion and the Òcultural milieu,Ó as well as the

    composerÕs understanding of his relationship with the performers of his works. FerneyhoughÕs

    recognition of the fundamentally embodied status of the performer and listener (and thus the

    music itself) is revealing. Also interesting is the embrace of ambiguity and Òmulti-layeredÓ

    contextual interpretation in his understanding of composer-performer-listener relationships. As

    Ferneyhough puts it, ÒÔsincerityÕ [is] not interchangeable with the abandonment of ambiguityÓ (p.

    31).

    An insightful discussion with film composer Carter Burwell concludes the chapter. Among

    other things, Burwell reveals the central role music plays in highlighting the subtext of a

    cinematic narrativeÐÐhow music conveys emotional context when the visual imagery might

    otherwise be neutral or ambiguous: Òlike Psycho where the music is telling you to be tense, even

    when youÕre just watching someone in a hotel room doing nothingÓ (p.36). Of course, the way

    this is done varies drastically from film to film. As Burwell discusses, cinematic music may be

    employed both rhetorically and ironically to underscore more nuanced aspects of character

    development, plot, and style. See, for example, his entertaining discussion of musical

    exaggeration in the Cohen BrotherÕs film,  Fargo ÐÐwhere the fact that the music ÒcanÕt see the

    comedy is itself funny. ItÕs like the music is the straight man who has no idea that anything funny

    is going onÓ (p.39). In all, the chapter provides fascinating insights into how these three

    composers understand the emotional power of music and develop it in their work: BurwellÕs

    approach is overtly manipulative in order to support (or sometimes even drive) the narrative of

    the film; Ferneyhough plays with ambiguity and interpretation; and similarly, Risset highlights

    the active agency of the listener for enacting the emotional meaning of the work.

    Having considered the perspective of the analyst and the composer(s) in chapters 2 and 3,

    the following three chapters take up themes related to performance. In Chapter 4, Daniel Leech-

    Wilkinson begins with a look at the Òanxiety about the ontology of musical works.Ó The author

    5

  • 8/18/2019 The Emotional Power of Music DRAFT Introduction Section

    6/22

  • 8/18/2019 The Emotional Power of Music DRAFT Introduction Section

    7/22

    useful in analyzing how performers actually convey emotion in practice. What is needed, he

    claims, is a more nuanced middle ground approach. To this end, Scherer offers some interesting

     possibilities for analysis such as his Òpush-pullÓ model, which considers how the performative

    aspects of emotional expression in the theatre may be understood as extensions of those

    experienced in everyday lifeÐÐi.e. the distinction between largely involuntary ÔinternalÕ physiological factors that ÒpushÓ emotional expression in certain ways, and those external socio-

    cultural conventions that ÒpullÓ the expression to take on certain forms rather than others. As

    Scherer writes, Ò[É] we all constantly play emotion theatre. Thus the distance from real life to

     professional acting is not nearly as clear-cut as it is usually made out to beÓ (p.66).

    Some readers may wonder if such a clear Òpush-pullÓ distinction may actually be tenable

    outside of isolated cases. Scherer responds to this concern by suggesting that Òpush and pull

    factors occur only very rarely in isolationÓ and that both Òexpression determinants interact with

    each otherÓ (p.66). Thus it is implied that this distinction provides, at the very least, a useful

    starting point for the comparative analysis of how emotions are ÔperformedÕ both in the theatre

    and in everyday life. Finally, although the focus of this chapter is on operatic performance,

     performers from other genres may find much that is relevant here. Indeed, all musicians must

    learn to inhabit the emotional world of the music they are creating as fully as possible while

    maintaining a clear and present connection to the technical (physical and psychological)

    requirements necessary to enact that musical world in the first placeÐÐSchererÕs approach stands

    to be greatly extended through research with performers working in other musical environments.

    Chapter 6 takes up the issue of Òthe resistance of the instrument.Ó Here philosopher Tom

    Cochrane moves from a discussion of the nature of artistic expression to how the resistance of the

    instrument contributes to the creative act of the performer. Although some very interesting points

    are raised on the latter subject, a very generalizing romantic view of Ôthe artistÕ and ÔexpressionÕ is

     put forward in the opening pages of the chapter. Cochrane relies heavily on the thought of

    Collingwood (1938). And as a result, he seems to expect readers to simply accept certain

    assumptions, such as the notion that artistic expression begins with a vague and oppressive

    impulse from which Ôthe artistÕ extricates herself through the clarifying act of creative

    expressionÐÐÒthe business of art ÔproperÕ is to express the emotional state of the artistÓ (p. 75).

    Indeed, while the act of communication with the wider community is central to CollingwoodÕs

    theory, It has been argued that this approach overly identifies the artwork with the inner

    experience of the artist himselfÐÐa view Cochrane seems to have no qualms with when he argues

    that if the audience Òcannot re-create the artistÕs emotional state by engagement with the work,

    then the artist cannot be sure that he or she has had a genuine aesthetic experienceÓ (p. 76). By

    7

  • 8/18/2019 The Emotional Power of Music DRAFT Introduction Section

    8/22

    this light, the idea that the audience should have any role to play in interpreting the work is

    effectively rendered nonsensicalÐÐtheir role is reduced to reconstituting the intentions of the

    artist; a view that has received considerable criticism over the last century.

    Furthermore, the Collingwood-Cochrane position also demands a clear separation between

    the contrivances and conventions associated with some notion of Òmere craftÓ and the rarified, putatively original and wholly uncontrived activity of the artist. Keeping in mind here that Ôthe

    artistÕ Cochrane is discussing is the musical performer, we may reasonably question if all

     performances worthy of the status of art should (or could) adhere to the ideal criteria Cochrane

    lays out. Are we to exclude from ÔartÕ any music where the musician comes to the performance

     prepared with certain emotional and technical objectives in mind? It seems possible that most

     performers would (as a point of necessity) arrive with at least a tentative intellectual and

    Ôemotional trajectory.Õ Are listeners indeed simply passive re-creators of the artistsÕ emotional

    states? Are there some musical performers who are clearly not artists and are some performance

    genres and contexts not artistic? Where exactly do we draw that line? In brief, a somewhat

    outmoded and long-criticized idealist-expressionist conception of music and emotion is

    uncritically assumed; and readers, especially those who are performing artists and critical-

    aesthetic philosophers, may find much that is problematic here. Unfortunately, Cochrane does

    little to address potential objections or the question of who such ideal Collingwoodian performers

    might be. However, he does comment that:

    If the performer is engaging in a Collingwoodian act of creative  self-expression ÐÐthe kind

    of immediate creative articulation found not just in improvisation but any creative

    interpretation of a scoreÐÐthe physical interaction with the instrument will also shape that

    mental state expressed by the performer in the musical event. In these circumstances, then,

    we should recognize that the instrument is not merely a means to the end of realizing some

     pre-existing expressive sentiment, but a vital part of shaping expressive content from the

     beginning.

    This is a compelling statement (Collingwodian concerns aside) as it draws attention to the

    essential psycho-physical engagement with the musical instrumentÐÐboth directly for the

     performer and indirectly or empathically for the listener. Cochrane expands on this in interesting

    ways, notably drawing on Toru TakemitsuÕs discussion of the Japanese biwaÐÐa notoriously

    difficult one string instrument intentionally made to embrace imperfections and ÔnoiseÕ. In brief,

    it is argued that exploring and negotiating the Ôresistance of the instrumentÕ is a central to musical

    8

  • 8/18/2019 The Emotional Power of Music DRAFT Introduction Section

    9/22

    creativity; and that a sense of such physical engagements with instruments is crucial for

    emotional affect to be convincingly expressed and perceived in musical performances. Cochrane

    highlights this by considering how computer musicians deliberately simulate such interactions

    (ÔimperfectionsÕ: variations, or irregularities in timing, dynamics, tunings and attack) in order to

    make their music more expressive. Following this, Cochrane discusses a recent trend in musicinstrument technology that aims to reduce  instrumental resistanceÐÐincluding his own Ômood

    organ,Õ which employs physiological sensors to collect signals that are then used to Òmanipulate

    musical variables.Ó

    Cochrane also makes some interesting comparisons with the historical move towards

    standardization in instrument technology, and discusses how this may enable musical meanings to

     be conveyed more consistently. Some readers may find referencing to relevant literature to be

    somewhat limited. For example, the important recent work of Marc Leman (2008) is not

    discussed, which is surprising given CochraneÕs strong interest in interfacing or mediating

    technologies. In all, however, the chapter is very interesting and informative, although some

    readers will find the initial discussion of Collingwoodian aesthetics problematic and unnecessary.

    The last two chapters in Section 1 offer interesting historical perspectives on how

     performance and emotion were understood in the early baroque and Renaissance periods

    respectively. In Chapter 7, Christine Jeanneret discusses the gender ambiguity inherent in

     performance practice and musical texts in 17th century Italy (i.e. the idea of the female performer

    and the role of castrati). And in Chapter 8, Claude Victor Palisca explores the ethos of musical

    modes that emerged and disappeared in the second half of the 16 th century, offering comparisons

    and contrasts with Ancient Greek perspectives. Because these chapters deal with concerns more

    closely associated with historical musicology I do not discuss them at length here.

    Section 2 Ð Emotion elicitation

    Section 2 turns the focus towards the question of emotion elicitation. This topic is one of the most

    interesting and contentious in the field, largely because the nature of musical emotions remains so

    frustratingly vague. For example, although studies have suggested that musical experiences may

    elicit psycho-physiological responses that are similar to those produced by ÔbasicÕ or Ôgarden

    varietyÕ emotionsÐÐand that often appear to correlate with certain structural aspects of music

    (rapid changes in dynamics, unexpected cadences, changes in tempo and so on)ÐÐit has also been

    shown that emotional-physiological changes associated with music do not always Òclearly map

    onto those found in studies of non-musical emotionsÓ (Krumhansl, 1997: 351). Indeed, there

    exists a large amount of evidence to suggest that specific emotions may be consistently attributed  

    9

  • 8/18/2019 The Emotional Power of Music DRAFT Introduction Section

    10/22

    to given musical passages by appropriately encultured listeners, but it has nevertheless proven

    difficult to demonstrate convincingly that music actually  produces  such emotions in listeners

    (Scherer & Zentner, 2001; Gabrielsson, 2001-2002). This, along with philosophical problems

    associated with musical intentionality (i.e. the ÔobjectÕ of musical emotions), has contributed to

    the problematic suspicion that affective musical experiences may be emotionally ÔcueimpoverishedÕ; that they are merely representative of, diminished versions of, or somehow

    different from, other types of emotions.

    Such ambiguities have prompted many researchers and theorists to develop more complex

    approaches based on richer conceptions of what the word ÔmusicÕ implies as well as more

    nuanced multi-factorial, embodied-ecological, developmental and action-based conceptions of

    what emotional-affective response entails. Thus, as Scherer points out in his introduction (Ch.9),

    underlying concerns in this section involve developing new perspectives on the nature of musical

    emotions, how they are created and represented, and what the meaning of such processes might

     be for human bio-cognitive development at ontogenetic and evolutionary levels.

    In Chapter 10, Scherer and Eduardo Coutinho draw out a Òmulti-factorialÓ approach that

    takes into consideration a wide range of interacting elements including structural, performance,

    listener, and contextual features. Five possible ÔmechanismsÕ or ÔroutesÕ that afford Òthe

     production of emotions in listenersÓ are discussedÐÐappraisal, memory, entrainment, emotional

    contagion, and empathyÐÐand the complex inner workings of each are considered at cognitive

    and pre-cognitive levels. Again, these routes are thought to function interactively and useful

    diagrams are provided to help clarify how this might be understood.

    While Scherer and Coutinho acknowledge that musical experiences involve many different

    types of affective states, their analysis is restricted to what they refer to as Òproperly emotional

    reactions to music as based on convergent definitions in the current literature and using SchererÕs

    [Component Processing Model] of emotion as a guideÓ (p.139). The CPM offers a way of

    discussing the emotional appraisal of an event though a set of criteriaÐÐphysiological symptoms,

    motor expression, action tendencies, and cognitive appraisal. These components are understood to

     be integrated multi-modally and continuously updated through largely non-conscious processing.

    This results in representations, Òparts of which may then become conscious and subject to

    assignment to fuzzy emotion categories which may then lead to labelling with emotion words,

    expressions, or metaphorsÓ (p.123). The CPM thus allows the authors to differentiate affective

     phenomena into a number of classes that are not separated by sharp boundaries and where Òthe

    meaning of emotion words for the respective classes may be difficult to define and are multiply

    interrelatedÓ (p. 128).

    10

  • 8/18/2019 The Emotional Power of Music DRAFT Introduction Section

    11/22

    Put simply, Scherer and CoutinhoÕs approach offers a more nuanced view of musical

    emotions, as well as a richer base of criteria and components for empirical research, than is

    afforded by attempts to align musical psycho-physiological responses with so called ÔbasicÕ or

    Ôgarden variety emotionsÕ (e.g. Juslin & VŠstfjŠll, 2008). This said, some readers may take issue

    with a number of assumptions. Of the eight affective classes suggested, the authors single outthree as properly emotional and thus relevant to music: the utilitarian, aesthetic, and epistemic. It

    is argued that immediate personal relevance is necessary for the production of utilitarian

    emotions. Thus special emphasis is given to so-called aesthetic or epistemic emotions because, as

    the authors claim, they correspond to the lack of personal relevance associated with most musical

    experiencesÐÐwhich, they argue, explains the ambiguity found in traditional attempts to align

    musical and non-musical physiological-emotional responses.

    In brief, the authors assume an essentially Kantian (aesthetic) stance with regard to musical

    emotions that, for many critics, tends to reduce music to a kind of detached perceptual process

    (Clarke, 2005; Johnson, 2007). Indeed the whole chapter, explores how Òmusic creates emotion

    in listeners.Ó And despite references to context and culture, the overriding assumption here is that

    musical emotions are caused by ÔexternalÕ structural antecedents ÔintrinsicÕ to the music acting on

    specific ÔinternalÕ processing mechanisms. Some will object that this plays down the fact that

    listeners are not passive receivers, but rather come to musical experiences primed for action,

    ready to enact the musical worlds they participate inÐÐi.e. that musical experiences are personally

    relevant. Along these lines, readers may find it useful to contrast Scherer and CoutinoÕs

    orientation with empirical research and theory associated with dynamic systems and enactive

    models of emotion and the mind (Freeman, 2000; Colombetti, 2014; Lewis, 2005; OÕRegan &

     Noe, 2001; Noe, 2004; Varela et al. 1993; Johnson, 2007). These perspectives offers a compelling

    alternative to the traditional reliance on 18th century aesthetic axioms (see Johnson, 2007; Elliott,

    1995) and the cognitivist/information-processing approach to cognition.

    In Chapter 11, Luca Zoppelli looks at Òfear-arousing mechanisms in VerdiÕs  Messa

     Requiem.Ó Zoppelli distinguishes three main ÒmechanismsÓ of musical communicationÐÐA)

    emotional coding, B) intrinsic meaning, and C) extrinsic symbolization. In doing so he extends

    the traditional focus on the formal and referential elements of musical works by bringing

     biological and developmental concerns to bear on the production of musical meaning. This allows

    him to pose some interesting questions and to make some tentative suggestions with regard to the

    various ways by which the constituent characteristics of A, B, and C might interact in differing

    works, contexts and with different listeners. Zoppelli then applies his approach to  Messa

     Requiem ÐÐthe juxtaposition of primordial embodied responses with symbolic imagery, traditional

    11

  • 8/18/2019 The Emotional Power of Music DRAFT Introduction Section

    12/22

    structural harmonic and melodic analysis, as well as a consideration of historical context, makes

    for a rich analysis that demonstrates how the musical experience of fear in the piece occurs

    through a complex and ÒmultilayeredÓ process. In all, ZoppelliÕs approach is refreshing and, like

    SpitzerÕs (Ch.2), it offers a welcome extension to traditional musicological methods.

    In Chapter 12 Jenefer Robinson offers a review of three well-known theories of emotionthat often underpin discussions of musical arousalÐÐi.e. cognitive appraisal theories, and the

    thought of Frijda and James respectively. The author claims that while all three approaches offer

    important insights, each is incomplete on its own. Following the pluralistic view of musical

    emotions developed throughout the book, and especially in the preceding two chapters, Robinson

    argues persuasively that each approach may be understood as attending to a different mechanism

    in a multi-stage process that involves, among other things, appraisal, action readiness, and

    feeling. Thus she suggests that these perspectives might inform each other, thereby allowing more

    comprehensive views on musical emotion than is possible through strict adherence to any one of

    them. There is little here that will be new to experienced readers in music psychology and

    musical aesthetics. Nevertheless, Robinson does a good job of outlining the complex concerns

    associated with the theories at hand. As a result, the chapter serves as a useful introduction to

    some important themes and figures in the field.

    In Chapter 13 philosopher Stephen Davies introduces his theory of Ôemotional contagionÕ,

    which he has been developing since the early eighties in order to deal with a central problem

    related to how music induces emotions in listenersÐÐnamely, the question of intentionality, or

    how best to understand the emotional object of musical experience. Initially (and traditionally) it

    seems the obvious place to turn to is the music itself, to its formal expressive characteristics and

    the listenerÕs appraisals of it. As Davies points out, however, the music itself cannot be the

    emotional object of the response Òbecause the listener does not believe of the music what would

    make it the intentional object of a sad response, namely, that the music is unfortunate, suffering or

    regrettableÓ (p.170). He then discusses contagion theory as a possible explanation.

    Davies argues for what he refers to as an Òattentional mirroringÓ response, which does not

    rely on beliefs about the music itself, but rather on the idea that we experience music as

    Òpresenting the kind of carriage, gait or demeanour that can be symptomatic of states such as

    happiness, sadness, sassy sexuality, and so onÓ (p.171). This, Davies suggests, allows for the

    communication of emotion from music to listener as emotional ÔcontagionÕ or ÔinfectionÕ, through

     physiological mimicking behaviour in the listener. The approach is interesting in that it draws less

    on representational syntactic-linguistic aspects of musical communication and more on movement

    and body related characteristics. However, the support offered for the theoryÐÐat least in this

    12

  • 8/18/2019 The Emotional Power of Music DRAFT Introduction Section

    13/22

    documentÐÐis sparse and speculative. Indeed, the chapter seems somewhat abbreviated and some

    readers may wonder why Davies does not draw on the growing body of research and theory in

    ecological-embodied music cognition, embodied aesthetics, cross-modal perception and

    developmental studies (but perhaps this is because such issues are taken up in subsequent

    chapters). Such an extended view might allow Davies the freedom to orient his work in a broaderand more supportive theoretical context; at present he sees contagion theory as an ÒexceptionÓ to

    more orthodox cognitive appraisal theories and he contrasts it with ÔpersonaÕ models.

    In Chapter 14 Joel Kruger offers, as Scherer points out in the section introduction, Òa much

    appreciated developmental perspective.Ó As I discussed in the introduction, research and theory in

    music and emotion has traditionally focused on examining the verbal and physiological

    responses, the brains and behaviours, of adult Westerners within the rather codified and

     prescriptive cultural environment of academic Classical music listeningÐÐgenerally assuming a

    disembodied information-processing conception of mind, where cognition occurs through

    representational recovery of an objective Ôworld out thereÕ (i.e. the mind as the mirror of nature;

    Rorty,; Varela, Thompson & Rosch, 1993). Therefore, it is not surprising that music and emotion

    research has traditionally emphasized more explicitly componential and iterative cognitive

     processes such as representation, appraisal and production rules. However, as Kreuger points out,

    the uncritical acceptance of these views has led to what Sloboda (2005) refers to as the

    Òpharmaceutical model,Ó where musical listening is understood to be an essentially passive

    experience. Given this prevalence of this view, it is also not surprising that many have argued that

    music has little or no biological relevance for human well being, that it is merely ÔparasiticÕ on

    cognitive processing (modules) that evolved to support proper adaptations (i.e. language, see

    Pinker, 2009; Patel, 2010). In response to all of this, Kreuger offers an excellent review of

    research and theory that focuses on infant musical development and neonatal therapeutic contexts

    (see DeNora, 2000). Here he explores themes of empathy and intimacy through a discussion of

    ÔmusickingÕ (Small, 1999) as form joint-sense making. This allows him to demonstrate the

     primordial necessity of musicality for embodied and pre-linguistic emotional-aesthetic forms of

    understanding and communicationÐÐincluding the Òprimary intersubjectivityÓ (Trevarthen, 2002)

    so necessary for developing social bonds. These embodied forms of knowing are understood as

    central to our ability to enact the physical and socio-cultural environments we inhabit as infants;

    and, as Kreuger argues, we continue to draw on them even as we grow up and begin to develop

    language and propositional ways of thinking (see also Benson, 2001; Johnson, 2007).

    In all, this developmental view offers a much broader conception of what ÔmusicÕ entails; it

    demonstrates the deep biological significance of Òcommunicative musicalityÓ for human

    13

  • 8/18/2019 The Emotional Power of Music DRAFT Introduction Section

    14/22

  • 8/18/2019 The Emotional Power of Music DRAFT Introduction Section

    15/22

    faculties by representing music as motor commands: depending on the listener, movement is

    ÔextractedÕ at different levels of the motor system; emotional intentions are thought to be inferred

    directly from this motor-activity, whether actual or simulated.

    Colling and Thompson attempt to refine this view by arguing that the Òaction plans

    generated by mirror neurons function for perceptual  predictionÓ (p.205). The authors then placethis in the context of musical expectancy theory, as discussed by Huron (2006), in order to

    develop a Òfeedback-controlled synchronization modelÓ that they claim unifies action-based

    models of emotions with anticipation-based models of musical emotions. This model further is

    supported by the work of Carver and Scheier (2009), which sees emotions as the Ònatural

    outcomes of the attainment of or failure to attain goalsÓ (p. 207)ÐÐwhere  feedback from this is

    then sent to a behaviour control system that regulates or modifies future action responses. As the

    authors explain in detail, this occurs though a complex process that operates over multiple

    timescales and across bodily, environmental and abstract contextsÐÐÒthe results of more

    immediate expectancies may interact with higher-order expectancies in order to create a

    multilayered emotional experienceÓ (p.209).

    To summarize, Colling and Thompson comment that by their model Òwe infer emotions

    from the motor activations that result from the actions we take to be responsible for producing the

    musicÓ; that ÒoneÕs emotional valence is due to oneÕs success or failure at predicting the musical

    actionÓ; and that thus ÒIt is possible then for one to have a positive emotional experience in

    response to predicting musical action that is perceived as emotionally negativeÓ (p. 209-210). The

    authors rely heavily on the relationship between expectation and emotion elicitation; other

     possibilities are not discussed in detail. Within this context, however, the chapter offers an

    excellent enhancement to established anticipation theories (e.g. Meyer, 1956; Huron, 2006)ÐÐone

    that is very well researched and richly referenced and that will no doubt be of great interest to

    newcomers and established musicologists alike. As with Scherer (Ch. 10), readers may find it

    interesting to contrast this approach with more explicitly dynamic and enactive sensorimotor

    approaches to emotion and aesthetics (for an overview see Colombetti, 2014; see also Johnson,

    2007).

    Chapter 16, by Wiebke Trost and Patrik Vuilleumier, takes up the topic of ÒRhythmic

    entrainment as a mechanism for emotion induction by music.Ó As the authors remark, ÒBy nature,

    emotions are regarded as transient processes emerging and transforming themselves in time. In

    this respect music shares an important characteristic, as they both fluctuate in timeÓ (p.213). With

    this in mind, the authors consider how musical experiences influence the perception of time and

    how such temporal properties are associated with emotional experiences; this is developed from a

    15

  • 8/18/2019 The Emotional Power of Music DRAFT Introduction Section

    16/22

    neurological and physiological point of view. After brief discussions of selected literature

    concerning Òmusic perception and emotions,Ó the Òmechanisms of emotion induction,Ó and the

    Òphysiological reactions to musicÓ (i.e. respiration and cardiac activity), the authors go on to

    discuss various forms of musical entrainmentÐÐperceptual, motor, physiological, social; and their

    relevance for emotion induction. They suggest that a distinction should be made between familiarand non-familiar music; and they briefly discuss why this is so, pointing to how: on one hand,

    entrainment with familiar music may rely on established pathways through various Òinduction

    mechanismsÓ like Ôevaluative conditioningÕ, Ôemotional contagionÕ, or Ôepisodic memoryÕ; while,

    on the other hand, unfamiliar music must be analyzed Òalong multi-step auditory pathways

    according to general acoustic features [É]Ó (p.221). Along these lines, Trost and Vuilleumier

    consider interesting possibilities for future research, especially with regard to how familiarity

    might heighten entrainment responses and how entrainment might be understood in terms of a

    cyclic or feedback processÐÐi.e. entrainment induces emotion, which in turn strengthens

    entrainment. The chapter offers a useful introduction to the subject, although reference to relevant

    literature in social cognition and developmental studies is strangely absent.

    Chapter 17 concludes Section Three with Stefan KoelschÕs fascinating examination of the

    Òneurophysiological correlates of music-evoked positive emotions.Ó Koelsh argues against those

    who assert that music does not elicit ÔrealÕ emotions; that musical emotions have little material

    (i.e. biological) effect on the listeners; that music does not involve goal-oriented responses; and

    that thus music is not directly relevant to human well-being. He begins by outlining the deep

    social significance of musical activity, drawing out seven interrelated functions that assert the

    central role of musicality for empathy (or co-pathy), communication, group cohesion and social

    cognition. Drawing on a range of relevant literature, Koelsh presents a convincing argument that

    music is in fact goal directed as it helps fulfill social needsÐÐÒmusic-evoked emotions are related

    to survival functions and to functions that are of vital importance to the individualÓ (p. 232;

    contrast with Scherer and Couthino above). Koelsh also takes a somewhat cautious stance

    towards the standard ÔmechanisticÕ and ÔinductiveÕ approach to musical emotions. Although he

    does sometimes use this vocabulary, he wants to avoid the assumption that musical emotions are

    necessarily determined by specific musical antecedents (see Kreuger, above). Thus he goes on to

    discuss some underlying principles of how emotions may be evoked  by musicÐÐas opposed to

    focusing on pre-given mechanisms and formal induction processes. These include appraisal,

    contagion, memory, expectancy, imagination understanding; but special attention is given to how

    these relate to the interactive social functions of musical activity. Koelsch concludes with a

    16

  • 8/18/2019 The Emotional Power of Music DRAFT Introduction Section

    17/22

    detailed look at the neural substrates of how ÒpositiveÓ emotions are evoked in musical

    experience leading to attachment and forms of social bonding.

    Section Three Ð The powers of music

    Like chapters 6 and 7, Section Three deals largely with historically related material. As a result, Ioffer only a brief overview of each chapter. This has nothing to do with the quality of the research

     presented, which is excellent, but rather reflects the focus of this review on current trends in

     philosophical and psychological musicology. This said, it should be noted that such historical

     perspectives are crucial for understanding the ways we have come to think and talk about

    musicÐÐthe metaphors we use and the personal and cultural significance we ascribe to it. As

    Fantini points out in the section introduction,

    Historical analyses provide a sense of how musical activities have been socially embedded,

     particularly as such activities reflect alternative conceptions of the nature and power of

    music, but also interpret the [current] models based on the concepts, beliefs, and metaphors

     present in a given culture.

    The importance of such research is echoed by Ian Cross in scientific-philosophical context when

    he writes, Òwhat we know of music in neurobiological and neuroscientific terms is constrained by

    a conception of music that is narrowly shaped by historical and cultural notions of what

    constitutes ÔmusicÕ Ó (Cross, 2010: 2). Thus it is hoped that these chapters will receive the

    attention they deserve from reviewers better versed in historical musicology.

    In Chapter 19, Fantini offers a look at Òforms of thought between music and science.Ó This

    is taken up in a largely biological context to consider how two important Òmodels of lifeÓ played

    a fundamental role in the development of music theory in the 17 th and 18th centuries respectively.

    To begin, Fantini introduces the Ôtheory of fibersÕ developed in the Baroque period. In doing so,

    he demonstrates how the Ôpower of musicÕÐÐpreviously associated with abstract Pythagorean

    mathematical relationshipsÐÐcame to be understood in terms of vibration, movement and bodily

    resonances. This is followed by a discussion of the 18th century interest in elementary organisms,

    or ÔcellsÕÐÐagain, Fantini argues for an aesthetic parallel with how music was understood and

    constructed in the classical period (e.g. the focus on Ôsonata formÕ). In brief, it is shown how the

    appositional, interchangeable and sinuous approach of the Baroque biological-musical view is

    replaced with a cellular, hierarchical and autonomous (i.e. formal) perspective in the Classical

     period. The chapter convincingly demonstrates close ties between how we have historically

    17

  • 8/18/2019 The Emotional Power of Music DRAFT Introduction Section

    18/22

    understood musical and biological processes; and this may well inspire further cross-disciplinary

    work in uncovering new connections, such as those between music and more recent ÔautopoieticÕ

    and dynamic approaches to biological systems (Varela et al., 1993; Thompson, 2007).

    Moving backward in time, Chapter 20 looks at how the power of music was understood in

    the medieval and Renaissance periods respectively. Here Laurence Wuidar begins by consideringthe profound influence of Ancient Greek thought (Plato and Aristotle) as well as that of early

    Christian thinkers, with a special focus on St. Augustine. He then goes on to offer a wonderfully

    rich account that weaves together a wide array of figures, highlighting the various moral,

    religious, therapeutic, and socio-political dimensions of musical thought in these periods.

    Brenno Boccadoro remains in the Renaissance in Chapter 21, offering a look at Òthe

     psychotropic power of musicÓ in this era. Again, Greek antecedents are consideredÐÐwith special

    attention given to the ancient Hellenic connection between oenology, music and medicine; as well

    as the Pythagorean relationship between music, mathematical ratios, and psycho-physiological/

    spiritual states of being. It is then shown how Pythagorean concerns were reintroduced and

    developed in the RenaissanceÐÐvia the thought of Plato, Aristotle and their followers. Here

    Boccadoro provides a detailed introduction to the writings of Ficino and, in doing so, gives an

    excellent overview of the deep transformative, therapeutic, and bio-spiritual significance of music

    in the Renaissance.

    Chapter 22 moves the discussion into modernity. Focusing on the early Enlightenment

     period, Penelope Gouk discusses practice and theory related to Òmusic as a means of social

    control.Ó She begins with late 16th-century France, demonstrating how musical practice (psalm

    singing) played an important role in galvanizing the emerging protestant (Huguenot-Calvinist)

    religious identity. Such musical practice was encouraged by leaders of the new order; and was

    countered in turn by the Catholics through punitive anti-protestant musical legislation. Gouk then

    explains how the Catholic king, Charles the IX, attempted to establish a music education system,

    BaifÕs academy, based on a Platonic ideal that would lead to the production of musical works

    capable of regulating the social body. From here she moves forward some 200 years to the

    Scottish Enlightenment to consider the thought of Dr. John Gregory. Gregory also believed in the

     power of music to influence behaviour for better and for worse. Like Baif, he drew on the thought

    of the Ancients, albeit with a more medical-biological orientation; and he argued that a strictly

    controlled musical curriculum should be developed, not by musicians and poets, but rather by

     philosophers and medical doctors so that music could be employed to its full extent as a vehicle

    for Òself improvement and social integration.Ó In summary, the chapter draws out and contrasts

    two interesting perspectives on music and social control that, despite their differences, both attest

    18

  • 8/18/2019 The Emotional Power of Music DRAFT Introduction Section

    19/22

    to the power accorded to music over human development and socialization in the early modern

     period.

    Chapter 23, by Jackie Pigeaud, draws on a wide range of documents to explore how music

    was used to soothe ailments of the body and soul in the 18th centuryÐÐwith a special focus on the

    influence of the ancient tradition of music therapy found in Greek and Biblical texts. In Chapter24, Jean Starobinski discusses the theme of ÔnostalgiaÕ. He begins by pointing out that the naming

    of affective states may actually produce new emotions and new conceptions of the forces that

    influence how we live our lives, both individually and culturally. The word ÔnostalgiaÕ is

    interesting in this respect because its entrance Òinto the vocabulary of multiple languagesÓ can be

    traced to a specific time, place and documentÐÐnamely the work of the Swiss doctor, Johannes

    Hofer, who, in 1688, wrote a dissertation concerning what has also come to be termed

    ÔhomesicknessÕ. The development of ÔnostalgiaÕ is then discussed as a Ôsickness of memoryÕ

    through various historical documents; and a commentary on the ability of music to both relieve

    and exacerbate the symptoms of nostalgia is explored across the modern period.

    The final chapter of the volume turns from historical concerns to consider contemporary

     problems associated with copyright control. Here Ulrik Volgsten argues that the laws that govern

    the distribution and use of music are based on principles that run contrary to what music actually

    means for the Òdevelopment of human identity, both on an individual and a collective level.Ó

    Following Kreuger (Ch. 14), he draws on recent research that asserts the pivotal role musicality

     plays in human ontogenesis, socialization and the construction of culture; he argues that listeners

    are not simply as passive consumers; and that likewise, performers-composers should not be

    understood as detached ÔownersÕ of intellectual-aesthetic property. Rather both are seen as agentic

    interacting collaborators in the construction of musical cultures and meanings. In brief, Volgsten

    argues (like Leech-Wilkinson, Ch. 4) that our traditional ontologies of music are wrong-headed

    and in the end simply serve corporate interestsÐÐwhich over the years have come to narrowly

    dictate the aesthetic-emotional and economic parameters of the music that gets distributed. While

    this chapter, and the volume itself for that matter, is almost completely biased towards Western

    music, this last chapter hints at the somewhat ominous consequences of the global corporate

    culture that now touches the lives of everyone on the planet. Indeed, although this critical

     perspective is bound to generate controversy, it will be welcomed by many who fear that we may

     be risking losing an important part of who we are as our musical activities become more about the

     private consumption of musical commodities that are mass produced, possessing only superficial

    connections to actual cultures, locations, and individual expressions of life and meaning. 

    19

  • 8/18/2019 The Emotional Power of Music DRAFT Introduction Section

    20/22

    Conclusion

    The volume closes with a very brief ÔCodaÕ that draws together key recurrent themes, reasserts

    the importance of multidisciplinary projects, and points the way to future research in historical,

    social and cross-cultural contexts. In all, The Emotional Power of Music  offers an impressive

    array of perspectives on music and emotion and can be highly recommend to anyone interested inthe subject. Like its predecessors, it opens up much needed discourse between diverse areas in

    musicologyÐÐand between music, science and philosophyÐÐthus affording more nuanced,

    embodied, and open-ended perspectives on the meaning of music for the human animal. While it

    is hoped that future efforts might offer broader cultural and critical perspectives, the authors and

    editors of The Emotional Power of Music are nevertheless to be congratulated for an excellent

    contributionÐÐone that will remain valuable and relevant for many years to come.

    References 

    Benson, C. (2001). The Cultural Psychology of Self: Place, Morality and Art in Human Worlds. 

    London: Routledge.

    Bohlman, P. (1999). Ontologies of Music. In N. Cook & M. Everist (Eds.) Rethinking Music (pp.

    17-34) Oxford: Oxford UP.

    Carver, C.S. & Scheier, M.F. (2009). Action, affect, and two-mode models of functioning. In E.

    Morsella, J.A. Bargh, and P.M. Gollwitzer (Eds.), Oxford Handbook of Human Action,  pp.

    298-327. Oxford: Oxford UP.

    Clarke, D. (2012). Musical Autonomy Revisited. M. Clayton, T. Herbert & R. Middleton (Eds.), 

    The Cultural Study of Music: A Critical Introduction (pp.172-83) Oxford: Oxford UP.

    Clarke, E.F. (2005). Ways of Listening: An Ecological Approach to the Perception of Musical

     Meaning. New York: Oxford UP.

    Cochrane, T., Fantini, B. & Scherer, K. (2013). The Emotional Power of Music: Multidisciplinary

     Perspectives on Musical Arousal, Expression, and Social Control. Oxford: Oxford UP.

    Collingwood, R.G. (1938). Principles of Art. Oxford: Oxford UP.

    Colombetti, G. (2014). The Feeling Brain: Affective Science Meets the Enactive Mind. Cambridge

    MA: MIT Press.

    Cross, I. (2010). The evolutionary basis of meaning in music: Some neurological and

    neuroscientific implications. In F. Clifford (Ed), The Neurology of Music (pp.1-15).

    London: Imperial College Press.

    DeNora, T. (2000). Music in Everyday Life. New York: Cambridge UP.

    Doidge, N. (2007). The Brain That Changes Itself: Stories of Personal Triumph From the

     Frontiers of Brain Science. New York: Penguin.

    20

  • 8/18/2019 The Emotional Power of Music DRAFT Introduction Section

    21/22

    Elliott, D. (1995). Music Matters: A New Philosophy of Music Education. Oxford: Oxford UP.

    Freeman, W.J. (2000). Emotion is essential to all intentional behaviour. In M.D. Lewis and I.

    Granic (Eds.),  Emotion, Development, and Self-Organization:Dynamic Systems

     Approaches to Emotional Development (pp. 209-235). Cambridge: Cambridge UP.

    Gabrielsson, A. (2001-2002) Perceived emotion and felt emotion: Same or different?  Musicae

    Scientiae, Special Issue: Current Trends in the Study of Music and Emotion, 123-148.

    Johnson, M. (2007). The Meaning of the Body: Aesthetics of Human Understanding. Chicago:

    University of Chicago Press.

    Gibson, J.J. (1966). The Senses Considered as Perceptual Systems. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

    Huron, D. (2006) Sweet Anticipation: Music and the Psychology of Expectation. Cambridge, MA:

    MIT Press.

    Juslin, P. & Sloboda, J. (2010). Handbook of Music and Emotion. Oxford: Oxford UP.

    Juslin, P. & VŠstfjŠll, D. (2008). All emotions are not created equal: reaching beyond traditional

    disputes. Behavioural and Brian Sciences, 31, 600-12.

    Krumhansl, C.L. (1997). An exploratory study of musical emotions and psychophysiology.

    Canadian Journal of Experimental Psychology ,51(4), 336-352.

    Lewis, M. D. 2005. Bridging emotion theory and neurobiology through dynamical systems

    modeling. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 28:169Ð245.

    Leman, M. (2008). Embodied Music Cognition and Mediation Technology. Cambridge, MA. MIT

    Press.

    Meyer, L. B. (1956). Emotion and Meaning in Music. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Molnar-Szakacs, I & Overy, K. (2006). Music and mirror neurons: from motion to ÔeÕmotion.

    Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience, 1(3), 235-41.

     Noe, A. (2004). Action in Perception. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.

    OÕRegan, J.K., and A. Noe. 2001. A sensorimotor approach to vision and visual consciousness.

    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24, 883Ð975.

    Patel, A. (2010). Music, Language and the Brain. Oxford: Oxford UP.

    Pinker, S. (2009). How the Mind Works. New York: Norton.

    Ramachandran, V.S. (2011). The Tell Tale Brain: A NeuroscientistÕs Quest for What Makes Us

     Human. New York: Norton.

    Rorty, R. (1979). The Mind as the Mirror of Nature. Princeton: Princeton UP. 

    21

  • 8/18/2019 The Emotional Power of Music DRAFT Introduction Section

    22/22

    Scherer, K.R. & Zentner, M.R. (2001) Emotional Effects of Music: Production Rules. In P.N.

    Juslin & J.A. Sloboda (Eds.),  Music and Emotion: Theory and Research  (pp.361-392).

    Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Small, C. (1998).  Musicking: The Meanings of Performing and Listening.  Middletown, CT:

    Wesleyan UP.

    Trevarthen, C. (2002). Origins of musical identity: Evidence from infancy for musical social

    awareness. In R. A. R. MacDonald, D. J. Hargreaves & D. Miell (Eds), Musical Identities 

    (pp. 21-38). Oxford: Oxford UP.

    van der Schyff, D. (2013). Emotion, Embodied Mind and the Therapeutic Aspects of Musical

    Experience in Everyday Life.  Approaches: Music Therapy and Special Music Education,

    5(1), 50-58.

    Varela, F., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1993). The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and

     Human Experience. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.

    22


Recommended