+ All Categories
Home > Documents > The Legacy of Luhmann

The Legacy of Luhmann

Date post: 02-Jun-2018
Category:
Upload: cjmaura
View: 223 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend

of 10

Transcript
  • 8/11/2019 The Legacy of Luhmann

    1/10

    r o f i l e

    T H E L E G C Y O F N IK L S

    L U H M N N

    G o t t h a r d e c h m a n n a n d N i c o S t eh r

    'n some of the many and extensive obituaries

    .published in European newspapers and maga-

    zines in 1999, Niklas Luhmann is remembered as

    the most i mportant social theorist of the 2 0th cen-

    tury.Yet in much of the Anglo-Saxon world he is

    vir tually unk now n among professional social sci-

    entists. Luhm ann was b orn into a middle-class fam-

    ily in Liineburg, Germany on December 8, 1927.

    Fol lowing ear ly graduat ion f rom high school

    Notabitur) , he was conscripted briefly in 1944

    and taken prisoner of war b y the American Forces.

    From 1946 to 1949, he studied law in Freiburg,

    entered public administration and worked for ten

    years as an administrative lawyer in Hanover. In

    1962 he received a scholarship to Harvard and

    spen t a year withT alcot t Parsons. In 1968, he was

    appoi nted professor of sociolo gy at the newly

    estab lishe d University of Bielefeld, wh ere he

    worked until his retirement. Shortly before his

    appointment he was asked on what subject he

    wish ed to work at university. His reply was: The

    theor y of mod ern society. Duration 30 years; no

    costs. He cons eque ntly realised exactly this theo-

    retical program . At the time of his dea th in De-

    cember 1998, at the age of 70, he had published

    an oeuvre of over 14,000 print ed pages.

    Luhmann's journey toward a theory of mod-

    ern societ y has taken a dual appr oach : first, in the

    form of essays since the end of the 1960s; and

    second, in the form of mono graph s since the

    1980s, dealing with the individual function sys-

    tems of society, such as law, science and art .

    Luhmann's intellectual evolution culminated in

    1997 with the publication of his magnum opus

    The Society of Society. Anyone suspec ting redun-

    dancy and repetition here might feel at first glance

    that their scepticism is confirmed.This two-vol-

    ume work contains no new subjects, let alone any

    previously unpublished approach.To this extent

    it is more a completion, a recapitulation, than an

    advance into new terri tory. However, a second,

    reassuring look reveals much that had not been

    said bef or e- -o r at least n ot in this way. In contrast

    to the essays, which are sometimes experimental

    and even playful in tone, and which occasionally

    close on a question mark, the b ook format requires

    a more systematic presentation. The Society of

    Society is the final stone to his theoreti cal cathe-

    dral and provides a map for, and a guide to, the

    understanding of modern systems theory.

    Around this principal work are clustered ear-

    lier, individ ual analyse s: The Scie nce o f Society,

    The Econ om ics of Society, The Art of Society,

    The Law of Society and the two pos thum ousl y

    published bo oks: The Politics of Society and The

    Religion of Society. The introduction to this se-

    ries of analyses took the form of a 674-page book

    bearing th e title Social Sy stems:The Outline o f a

    General Theory. This wor k is still the mos t con-

    centrated, abstract , and-- if one takes the trouble

    to work through it--also most rewarding presen-

    tation of the theoretical core.

    We now have a first overall picture at our dis-

    posal. If one wis hes to do Luh mann justice, one

    has to find one's bearings within the architecture

    of his general approach .Apart fro m these systemic

    studies, Luhmann also published a slightly less

    voluminou s series of sociological and historical-

    seman tic analyses. They c onsist of the fou r vol-

    umes of Societal Structure and Semantics and

    the six volumes of Sociological Enlightenment.

    These studies show Luhmann as a universal

    scholar, wh o loc ates his theo ry within the histori-

    cal contex t of enlightenmen t and Europ ean phi-

    losophy.Apart from this far-reaching research, he

    also pro duc ed a range o f political and social analy-

    ses of modern society, commenting on pressing

    public problems.We men tion only his books So-

    ciology of Risk, Ecological Communicati on, The

    Reality of the Mass Media and The Political

    THE LEGACY OF NIKLAS LUHMANN 67

  • 8/11/2019 The Legacy of Luhmann

    2/10

    Theory of the Welfare State." In all, his work con-

    sists of some 700 publica tions an d countless trans-

    lations into English, French, Italian,Japanese, Rus-

    sian and Chinese.

    In almost all of his work, Luhmann makes ref-

    erence to the operative logic of George Spencer

    Brown and radical constructi vism.These are treated

    in summary fashion in order to sketch the layout

    and the c once ptua l structure of his super-social sys-

    tems theory, endo wed with a range of method ologi-

    cal inst rumen ts wo n in this way. The t heo ry of

    politics, sociol ogy of religion, sociology of art, and

    moral sociology are de veloped subsequently.

    In our br ief in tel lectual por t rai t of Niklas

    Luhmann, we first deliberately focus on the sub-

    stance of his social theory, especially the ideas

    found in his last publication; and we refrain from

    advancing a sociology of knowle dge p erspectiv e

    that a t tempts to come to gr ips wi th- - for ex-

    am pl e- th e reluctance of Anglo-Saxon social sci-

    ence to engage Luhmann's notions as vigorously

    and promine ntly as has been the case not only in

    his ow n country , but also in Italy, France, and man y

    othe r non-English-speaking societies. This is a

    story, and a challenge, that must be left op en at

    this time. Second, onc e we have outl ined the ma-

    jor features of Luhmann's novel system-theoreti-

    cal approach, we offer various critical observa-

    tions and reflections.

    The Characteristics of Moder n Society

    For Luhmann, social differentiation and system

    formation are the basic characterist ics of modern

    society.This also means that systems theory and

    the the ory of society are mutually dependen t. In

    these terms, a socie ty is not the sum of all current

    interactions, but rather a system of a higher order,

    of a different type, determined by the differentia-

    t ion between system and environment; and i t is

    exactly this distinction which is the subject of

    Luhmann's two-volume The Society of Society

    Luh man n's key messa ge is this: soci ology is ulti-

    mately a theory of society, or it is not a science. If

    we look back at the his tory of sociology, this is by

    no means self-evident. On the contrary, at the start

    of the last century--and particularly after 1945

    in Germany and elsewher e--sociol ogy derived i ts

    identity by conceal ing its relationship with society.

    It was mainly a theory of social entities, with such

    categorie s as roles, interaction, inten tion and social

    action forming the basic co ncep tual framew ork for

    a sociol ogy whi ch was increasi ngly empirical and

    theoretica lly inclined to follow the m odel of the

    natural sciences, with their emphasis on causality

    and the discovery of laws.

    The c onc ept of society, however, retained i ts

    holistic claim; emphatically defended, for example,

    by cr i t ical theo ry and dev elo ped by J/ .i rgen

    Habermas into a theor y of communicative reason.

    This claim clashed with the unde rstand ing of so-

    ciology as a universal and inde pend ent theo ry of

    social entit ies.Would the mainstream per spectiv e

    within sociology turn society into a social system

    like any other, but at the same time an all-embrac-

    ing and fundamental system? Sociology has bee n

    unable to escape from this paradox, whi ch it has

    count ered by repression and historicisation: Social

    theory, and particularly critical social theory, has

    largely been left to the disciplinary concerns of

    philosophy , whi ch is believed to have the special-

    ists in holistic claims for the ultimate, fundamen-

    tal structures of thought and relationships with the

    world. If social scientists dealt with the theory of

    society, then they did so typically through exegesis

    of the classics, as if the history of their own disci-

    pline had the ability to preserve and recall claims.

    Today the exclusion of society from socio logy

    seems to be e xacti ng its revenge. Like Max Weber 's

    repressed worl d of the gods who celebrate their

    return to the mod ern world in the form of inces-

    sant conflicts of values, the con cep t of society is

    returning today in a wide diversity of terms, such

    as "post-industrial society" (Bell),"society of risk"

    (Beck)," socie ty of kn owle dge" (Stehr), and "post-

    mod er n society" (Lyotard); as if one aspe ct of so-

    ciety is capable of standing in for the wh ole. Such

    ad hoc fabrication of terminolo gy reveals what is

    being suppressed: namely, the claim to compre-

    hend socie ty in its totality.

    So wha t exa ctly does this mean for sociology,

    Luhmann asks, if we wish to avoid the trap o f naive

    objectivism, which views society as a given ob-

    ject that effectively pre ced es all scientific obser-

    vation? The implication of the objective poin t of

    view would be that we have to observe society

    from a point outside of society.There is no such

    point. Science and society are both an expressio n

    of social reality.This is precisely the point where

    classical soci ology of knowledge, for example , has

    broken down. I t was forced to delegate the ob-

    servation of knowledge to a hypothetical , free-

    floating intell igence that was not subject to any

    distortion of perc epti on due to interests or ide-

    ologies. More recently, a number of perspecti ves

    have come to accept the idea that the act of cog-

    nition is always itself a moment in the totality of

    68 SOC IETY 9 JANUARY FEBRUARY 2002

  • 8/11/2019 The Legacy of Luhmann

    3/10

    cognition. Luhmann shares this app roa ch- -an d at

    the same time pushes beyond it by arguing that

    there cannot be an object society accessible to

    independent observation.

    As soon as we cease to regard societ y as merely

    another sociological object of research and in-

    stead focus on its operational significance as a

    condition for the possibil i ty of sociological cog-

    nit ion i tself , then sociology beco mes a subject

    dealing with itself in exactly the sense in which

    the subject matter of philosoph y speaks of reflec-

    tion. Luhma nn transfers the struc ture of the self-

    referential mo de of operation by the subject to

    the theory of social systems.At the same time, he

    answers the question: How it is possible to prac-

    tice sociology as a theory of society that does not

    prematurely screen out the conne ct ion between

    theory and subject? This, accordi ng to Luhmann,

    requires a radical rejection of epistemolo gical

    posit ions based on the di chot omy of the subject-

    object paradigm. Sociology is conf ront ed with

    society as a subject. Luhmann therefore argues

    that this requires research into characterist ics that

    it has always generated itself. Luhmann consis-

    tently posits a radically anti-humanist, non-onto-

    logical and radical-constructivist idea of society.

    The most radical assumpt i on of Luhmann's

    mature theoretical approach is his emphasis on

    differences, more precisely on distinctions that

    are no longer seen as objective differences but as

    constru ctions. The substitution of the subject con-

    cept and the transfer of the subject /object differ-

    entiation into the distinction between system and

    environment take Luhmann to a post-ontological

    theo ry of society, deve lope d on a naturalistic and

    empirical basis as a the ory o f observation.This fun-

    damental questioning of the modern philosoph y of

    the subject and the resulting distinction betwe en

    the natural sciences and the humanities ( together

    with the associated rejection of a humanistic-an-

    thropocentric concept for defining society) have

    attracted a great deal of criticism, and even more

    incomprehension, of Luhmann's approach.

    T h e G e n e a l o g y o f L u h m a n n s S ys t e m T h e o r y

    The c once pt of the system is Luhmann's essen-

    tial starting point. In this respect he is exceptional

    in German sociology, whi ch at least since Max

    Weber has mainly been ac tion theory. Luhmann's

    proposal to describe social phenomena like in-

    teractions, organization s or societies as systems,

    possibly marks this categorical break most em-

    phatically.To think in terms of systems first ira-

    plies that we are no longer speaking of objects,

    but of differences and furth ermo re that differ-

    ences are not conceived as existing facts (distinc-

    tions), going back instead to an imperative to ex-

    ecu te them, s ince one cou ld o therwi se g ive

    nothing a name, thus having nothing to observe

    and would thus also not be able to continue any-

    thing (Luhmann, 1997:60).

    The text of the social (like all oth er texts) is

    neither self-explanatory nor is it deposited in dis-

    crete writ ing. And it does not posses s any consis-

    tent meaning which is identical with i tself , and

    which one could trace back to any specific in-

    stanc e of its creation. Sociology has to labo r with-

    out con ceivi ng its domain of objects as a conglom-

    erate of things, analogous to facts possessing a

    fixed shape--whose inter-relationship, moreover,

    is ensured in an uniform principle (be i t nature,

    divine will, morals or a transcendental subject).

    Under the metaphysica l conditions of the mod-

    ern, a meta-perspec tive that permits the recogni-

    t ion of somethi ng resembling the natural as the

    invariable ess ence or the totality of society is no

    longer available to the observer.

    According to Luhmann's system-theory ap-

    proach, the world (as the ho rizon of possible de-

    scriptions) is expressed by means of a network

    of contingent distinctions and labels that always

    have to be understood in context.That an observer

    may label this as this (and not as that) is due to a

    dist inct ion in which both mom ents, separated

    from each other, can only be understood in rela-

    t ion to each other; the distinctive units only pos-

    sessing their own identity in the difference to the

    other. To be able to chara cterise some thin g as

    something, one has to have already distinguished

    it from its distinctive other: what deserves to be

    called true, for example, is measured by the dif-

    ference from appearance; and to speak of the past

    makes sense only with referenc e to a present that

    can be distinguis hed (con stitutively) f rom it. Even

    if it is not explicitly raised as an issue, this other

    side of something termed as this or that is always

    presen t in every determination of spee ch or ges-

    ture we make. It is a pe rma ne nt horiz on. It is pos-

    sible to change sides at any time and to bring the

    dist inguished moment of form (appearance for

    truth, or the present for the past) into the focus

    of attention, making it the point of departur e for

    furth er deliberat ions. In the interest of a deliber-

    ate treatment of self and world, it is inevitable

    that we distinguish and label. Such operations are

    the start of all perce ption and recognition.

    THE LEGACY OF NIKLAS LUHMANN 69

  • 8/11/2019 The Legacy of Luhmann

    4/10

    Why distinctions and labels in different con-

    texts are made in a certain way and not in others

    is impossible to determine from the perspective

    of systems theory. Distinguishing always takes

    place in a medium of lack of foretho ught and pre-

    vious indeterminacy, endowing each form with

    the seal of indelible conti ngen cy: in principle one

    could have ma de c ompletely different distinctions.

    To speak o f systems t hus m eans to establish a dif-

    ference: that between system and environme nt.

    By system, Luhmann means a chain of events

    related to each other, or of operations. In the case

    of living creatures, for instance, these are physiologi-

    cal proces ses;f or psyc hic systems, ideas; and in rela-

    tion to social relationships, communic atio ns. Systems

    are formed by distinguishing themselves from an

    environment of such events and operations that

    cann ot be integrated into their internal structures.

    In contrast to his early mentorTalcott Parsons,

    who defined systems by means of the presence

    of collectively shared nor ms and value patterns,

    Luhmann proceeds from a system concept shaped

    in a strictly relational manner. His notion relies

    on the idea of a constitutive boundary that per-

    mits the distinction between inside and outside.

    Each operation of a system (in the case of social

    systems: each communi cati on) (re)p roduces this

    boundary by embedding i tself in a network of

    further operations, in which it at the same time

    gains its own unity/identity.Therefore, such a con-

    cept of boundary--above all in relation to psy-

    chic and social systems--is not to be understood

    spatially, but rather operatively: The boundary of

    the system is nothing but the type and concre-

    tion of its opera tions w hic h individualise the sys-

    tem. I t is the form of the system who se other side

    t h us b e c o m e s t h e e n v i r o n m e n t ( L u h m a n n ,

    1997:76-77.) . This operative unde rsta ndin g re-

    quires the insight that systems are unable to tran-

    scend their own boundaries.

    Such a research strategy is due to an elemen-

    tary conviction of the improbabili ty of the emer-

    gence of social order. Everything could in prin-

    ciple be different. From Luhmann's perspective,

    social structures have nothing self-evident to

    them: they require permanent new social con-

    struction from the view of their existence and of

    their determined shape. In contrast to the func-

    tionalism of the Parsonian persuasion, Luhmann

    is not c ommit ted to the pre servation of social

    systems. On the contrary, the cont inge ncy and

    compl exit y of the social is the starting po int of

    all of his theoreti cal efforts.

    The complexi ty of the design of Luhmann's

    theory expresses i tself not only through the di-

    versity of the sociological issues which he is able

    to tackle with the help of the syste m-theory ap-

    proach, but also in the way that the perspectives

    vary in their emphasis when eve r he presen ts his

    general theoretical approach. His Social Systems

    is writ te n primarily from the poin t of view of the

    dist inct ion between system and environment ,

    while The Science of Society takes the theory of

    observable systems as its starting point, leading

    to more epistemological debates about obse rving

    observation. If one had to choose such a central

    point of view for The Society of Society the focus

    would clearly be on the social system, in contrast

    to all social subsystems formed through social

    operations within society.

    T h e i f fe r e n c e o f i f f e r e n c e s

    Luhmann distances himself from what he calls

    the old Europea n ontolo gical theore tical tradi-

    t ion, hopelessly out mode d in i ts potential for cap-

    turing m ode rn society in all i ts complexity. In

    doing so, he is trying to overcome two thousand

    years of tradition that, in his view, have been tran-

    scend ed by the process of functional differentia-

    t ion. He descr ibes the old European style of

    thought as concerned with the identif ication of

    the unity unde rlyi ng diversity. Society, in the clas-

    sical view, consists of subjects of action whose

    fundamental unity is based on sharing a comm on

    understanding. Ontolo gy refers to a world exist-

    ing objectively in separation from the subjects

    aware of i t , capable of unambiguous l inguistic

    representation.

    Against this, Luhmann sets a view of a world

    that temporalizes, differentiates and decentralizes

    all identities. Identities are pro duc ts o f past ev ents.

    Unity is no longer the ult imate p oint of reference

    of the th eory. By relativizing even the o ntol ogica l

    scheme of existence/non-existence as but one of

    many observational schemata, Luhmann attacks

    the foundations of powerful tradit ions of thought.

    The paradox, according to Luhmann, is that the

    old European tradit ion em erged in a society that

    no lo nger exists today, either in terms of the sys-

    tem of communication or in terms of forms of

    differentiation. Even so, this tradition remains part

    and parcel of our historical heritage, and in this

    sense a part of the culture that is relevant for ori-

    entation. I t cannot disappear bec ause i t no longer

    fits; it is constantly negated, and has to be avail-

    able for this purpose.

    70 SOCIETY ~ JANUARY FEBRUARY 2002

  • 8/11/2019 The Legacy of Luhmann

    5/10

  • 8/11/2019 The Legacy of Luhmann

    6/10

  • 8/11/2019 The Legacy of Luhmann

    7/10

    T h e o r i e s o f T h e o r i e s

    But how can society document i tself without

    comi ng into contra dicti on with itself, and particu-

    larly with out recourse to transcend ental refer-

    ences outside itself?. In the last chapter of The

    Society of Society und er the title Self-descrip-

    tions, Luhma nn deals with the intrica te relation-

    ship betwee n theor y and subject. Can theo ry ex-

    plain i t s own locat ion wi thin the process of

    society? And if it can, does it not regard socie ty to

    a certain extent from without, al though this is

    possible within society in the capacity of com-

    munication? Here, we are reminded (not entirely

    inappropriately) of Escher's hand drawing itself,

    generating itself and its own image in the course

    of its own op eration . Luhma nn follows a similar

    line: Just like self-observations, self-descriptions

    (generation of texts) are individual oper ations of

    the system. In fact, descriptions and what is de-

    scribed are not two separate objects which are

    only externally l inked--with a self-description,

    what is desc ribed is always part of what it is de-

    scribing and it changes it simply by the fact that

    it appears and subjects itself to observation.

    Sociology, then, is always the con str uct ion of

    the unity of the system within the sys tem itself,

    never reaching an end to this process.This insight

    prompts Luhmann to avoid any conclusions for

    his own theory.Although there is a particularly

    close relationship here with Hege l,who also gave

    the absol ute a self-referential chara cter by regard-

    ing the system as entirely self-referential--where

    nothing can be external because everything ex-

    ternal has be co me an aspect of its self-differen-

    tial--Luhmann leaves this tradition exactly at this

    point by translating i t into a cybernetic vocabu-

    lary and hence overcoming it . Nor is society a

    subject in the anthropological- interactive sense,

    as Adorn o still view ed it despite all his criticism

    of phil osop hy: Society is a coagu lated relation-

    ship betwe en people. Humani ty is not the ulti-

    mate elem ent in society, nor ca n soci ety still be

    described within the classical cognitive model of

    subject-object ; beca use the self-referentiality of

    society itself causes this duality to collapse, since

    cognition seeks intersubjective certainty on the

    part of the subject and presup poses stable objects.

    Society is in any case not such a stable object.

    Critical e f l e c t i o n s

    According to Luhmann's approach, only radi-

    cal constructive semantics provide sufficient dis-

    tance to prevent succumbing to the suggestions

    inherent in tradit ional terminology. Luhman n's

    terminology in the theoretically most demanding

    part of this wor ks is devoi d of classical associa-

    t i o n s a n d c o n n o t a t i o n s . I f t h e r e a d i n g o f

    Luhmann's studies is not be abandoned due to

    sheer resignation, frustration or even anger, then

    his terminology requires considerable tolerance

    from readers not familiar with the terminology

    of systems theory.

    Luhmann's strict, austere artificial language is

    not due to any affectation but rather to the strin-

    gency of his theoret ical p rogr am-- and this pro-

    gram has to keep its distance from the implica-

    tions of the seman tics of tradit ional Europea n

    social theory. In this respe ct one s hould take seri-

    ously the penultimate sente nce of the Society of

    Societies, accor ding to whi ch an adequat e mod-

    ern t heory of society requires the sacrif ice of the

    mere pleasure of recogniti on and the judging of

    theory construction on i ts own merits.

    This does not imply that reading Luhmann's

    theo ry is simply a struggle with nomi nal cons truc-

    tions and cascades of abstract terms; in betw een

    one finds analyses of traditional European seman-

    tics, in which Luhmann attempts to clarify why

    they are no longer adequate for the structural facts

    of mod er n society. Again and again ther e are

    pointed and paradoxical formulations, in which

    the fruits of the switch in theory formatio n from

    first-order observation to second-order observa-

    tion are bundled as under a magnifying glass.An

    example of this would be when Luhmann says of

    memo ry that i ts true function for society consists

    not of storage, but rather of forgett ing; or wh en

    he conceives of information as a product of de-

    cay that disappears by being updated.

    Such paradoxes are more than skilful plays on

    w o r d s : t h e y p r o v i d e e n t r y p o i n t s t o t h e

    constructivist co re of Luhmann's societal theory,

    which consists of the fact that all observation is

    based on paradox to the extent that i t relies on

    distinctions upon which i t cannot reflect as a

    uniform whole.The unity of the world as the unity

    of society, according to Luhmann, cannot be as-

    serted as a principle but simply as a paradox--

    this too is a consequence of the loss of meaning

    of traditional semantics.

    But is the loss of meaning of old European se-

    mantics truly compell ing in the face of the four

    volumes by Luhmann on the subject of structure

    of society and semantics ? Or, is it at least rein-

    forced wel l by methodology? One can doubt that

    this is so, since Luhm ann is forced to fall back on

    THE LEGACY OF NIKLAS LUHMANN 73

  • 8/11/2019 The Legacy of Luhmann

    8/10

    socio-structural developments to be able to es-

    tablish the loss of significance of socio-political

    semantics.This circularity is probably the weak

    point in Luhmann's theory of society. Of course,

    this did not escape Luhmann, but the solutions

    he suggested were not particularly consistent.

    They stretch from the admittance of circularity as

    an inevitable pre-requisite of theory formation--

    which traditional European semantics were only

    able to avoid by recourse to metaphysical construc-

    tions, such as God, nature or re aso n-- to the claim

    that semantic changes were subject to structural

    change at considerable distance, as a result of

    which semantics are suddenly again in the posi-

    tion of verbally depic tin g facts. But is it really true

    that social change precedes cognitive change, or

    are there also cases where the opposite is true?

    Luhmann analysed the change from traditional

    European society to modern society by using

    three dimensions, to each of whi ch he dedicates

    three main c hapters of his societal theory ("The

    Society of Society"): first, the social di mension ,

    which Luhmann conceives as that of communi-

    cation and media, consti tuted only by the distinc-

    tion be twe en Ego and Alter (deliberately avoid-

    ing the tradit ional European semantics of perso n

    and subject) ; second, the temporal dimension, in

    which past and future are separated, and which

    L u h m a n n t e r m s e v o l u t i o n - - d e f i n i t e l y n o t

    progress, since there is no guiding medi um am ong

    the various media and the functional differentia-

    tion of society has no guiding system; and third

    and finally, the factual dimens ion ,wh ich Luhman n

    comp rehe nds as functional differentiation, and in

    which we are concerned wi th determining the

    system and the environme nt.These are not, how-

    ever, stable distinctions, that which constitutes

    environment depending instead on the compo-

    n e n t s y s t e m c o n c e r n e d , o n s c i e n c e o r th e

    economy, law or education.And this also changes

    during the evolution of the co mpo ne nt systems.

    Decisive for Luhmann' s the ory of society is the

    assertion that there is no do minan ce of any com-

    pone nt system in the dimension of functional dif-

    ferentiation, for instance of politics; that in the di-

    mension of communication, no dominant med ium

    may be recognised; and furthermore, that the lack

    of guiding systems and dominan t media is the de-

    finitive characteristic of mode rn society.This is also

    the reason why traditional European semantics can

    no longer adequately describe a modern society.

    But is the loss of measure due to the c onver-

    sion of norms and values into forms of societal

    commun icati on, as describe d by Luhmann, really

    plausible? Unfortunately, Luhmann at no point

    makes reference to Michael Walzer's conc ept of

    spheres of just ice: Within th is conc ept , wha t

    Luhmann has described as the appropriate self-

    descripti on of mode rn societies is describ ed as

    thei r permanent ly- to-be-achieved norm, as the

    measure of justness that is perma nent ly threat-

    ened by the dominat ion of - - to use Luhmann's

    t e rm- - compon en t sys tems .

    This closes the circle for a major train of

    thought, so that what initially appeared a para-

    do x- na me ly , that the self is at the same time what

    is d i f ferent- -emerges as a complete theory of

    society that also includes reflection on i ts own

    location in society, and regards society in this

    sense as a unity capable of self-modification. If

    we take this strictly intra-social perspective seri-

    ously, accept ing that any commu nic atio n about

    society can only take place within society, then

    there is no location for critical reflection on soci-

    ety external to society, whe re socie ty can be re-

    garded as an object.This descripti on of society in

    society is no longer based on the con cep t of the

    subject or seen from the standpoint of transcen-

    dental rationality. It is the tautological operation

    of communication itself. Society is society's for-

    mula for the self-desc ription of social unity. An

    emphatic definition of sociology would here seek

    the unity of this difference in order to distinguish

    wha t is actual, wha t is essential.The unity of soci-

    ety would then be a society that has arrived at

    itself, corresponding to its ideal.Tradition has re-

    served the label "enlightenment" for this, and

    measured existing society against this claim. So-

    ciological explanat ion of enl ighte nment must

    abandon these claims, since this position can still

    be observed, even if only from the po int of view

    of second-order observat ion.The cont ingency of

    the world cannot be reversed in this sense, be-

    cause sociological theory belongs to the very

    thing that it is analysing, name ly society.

    The t rue meaning of sociology would hence

    be that it is set free to engage in this type of self-

    descripti on in order to modify the semantic lega-

    cies of tradit ion to the chang ed social structural

    relationships in the p rocess of "re-description."

    This bridges the second major distinction be-

    tween semantics and social structure. Modern

    society, throu gh functional differentiation, gener-

    ates the compulsion to self-observation and so

    changes all the themati c elements. This brings

    postmodernism to the point where the past be-

    74 SOCIETY 9 JANUARY FEBRUARY 2002

  • 8/11/2019 The Legacy of Luhmann

    9/10

  • 8/11/2019 The Legacy of Luhmann

    10/10


Recommended