+ All Categories
Home > Documents > The new phenomenology of carrying forward

The new phenomenology of carrying forward

Date post: 03-Jun-2018
Category:
Upload: archecinema
View: 215 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend

of 25

Transcript
  • 8/12/2019 The new phenomenology of carrying forward

    1/25

    Continental Philosophy Review37:127151, 2004.C 2004Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands.

    The new phenomenology of carrying forward

    E.T. GENDLINDepartment of Psychology, University of Chicago, 5801 South Ellis Avenue, Chicago, IL

    60637, USA (e-mail: [email protected])

    In this paper I show a new approach to what phenomenologists call phenom-

    ena, a deliberate way to think and speak withwhat is more than categories

    (concepts,theories, assumptions, distinctions. . .

    ). Some categories are alwaysimplicit in language, and language is always implicit in any human experi-

    encing. So what I just called the more cannot be separated from implicit

    categories and language. This is well known. What is little known is that expe-

    riencing always goes freshly beyond the categories and the common phrases.

    I have been establishing a deliberate way to think with more. This is crucially

    needed in philosophy, but it has seemed impossible. We can reformulate the

    problems it involves.

    Most philosophers gave up on phenomenology long ago, because it was

    recognized that neutral description is impossible. Description involves cat-

    egories. Sartres dialectical categories differed from Merleau-Pontys func-

    tional approach. Therefore their descriptions differed from each other and

    from Husserls. It was soon said that phenomenology finds no phenomena

    at all, only the same philosophical issues that have always been contested.

    The phenomena seemed to depend entirely on the categories (through history,

    culture, and common language forms). Philosophers were tempted, like Hei-

    degger in the years afterBeing and Time, to deal with categories apart from

    phenomenology, from the top down. Everyone can now see that working with

    the categories alone is not at all hopeful. None are ultimate and their use al-

    ways involves an excess which fits neither within categories nor can it be

    had separately. This impasse has led to the dead-end aspect of postmodernism.

    It frees us from any privileged set of categories, but leaves us only with an

    aporia, still only on the level of concepts. But if one recognizes that language

    is inherently metaphorical and not controlled by concepts, then there need beno dead end.

    It is now evident that philosophy needs to employ more than conceptu-

    ality, but the current return to phenomenology need not be a retreat from

    postmodernism. Phenomenology need not back away from the problem of

    the relativity of descriptive categories and approaches. We have ways to think

    with the so-called excess. I have shown that it is much more than a texture of

  • 8/12/2019 The new phenomenology of carrying forward

    2/25

    128 E.T. GENDLIN

    old concepts. What I call experiencing is not separable from concepts, but

    it plays crucial, directly demonstrable roles in ongoing thinking. It performs

    functions that concepts cannot perform.

    The excess is our situated experiencing in the world, in situations with

    others. It does not utterly depend on categories. History and culture are insuf-

    ficient to handle even an ordinary day. The common phrases do not limit our

    next steps of action and thought. Applying different categories does indeed

    bring forth different phenomena, but the direct experiencing of whatever we

    study always responds very precisely, always just so and not otherwise, and

    always with more than what could follow just from our categories. Experi-

    encing is a responsive order, as I call it.1 This order is always unfinished

    in regard to further conceptual form, but always more finely organized thanany conceptual forms. If you are willing to think with the excess rather than

    leaving it behind, you can attend to it directly at any juncture of thinking. Then

    you can notice that it will not permit you to say most of the cogent things

    you can easily say. It will stay opaque, stuck and mum unless and until just

    certain sentences come to open it. Such freshly formed, often metaphorical

    sentences show that language is deeply rooted in experiencing and not con-

    trolled by extant concepts or categories. If we think from where these arise, we

    can examine and redirect some of the functions which implicit experiencing

    provides at that particular juncture of thought.

    I am summarizing what I call a reversal of the usual philosophical order

    in my philosophical work. Philosophies have long claimed a basis in experi-

    ence, but experience was always construed according to the concepts and

    categories of that philosophy. The concepts were always read into experience.

    This is still done today when the excess is understood as just a texture of

    old concepts. Only a phenomenology can employ the functions of experienc-

    ing beyond the variety of concepts. In works I summarize here, one can find

    a philosophical way to show and directly employ some of its functions in

    thinking and speaking.

    We find neither objectivism nor indeterminacy. Where others see indetermi-

    nacy, we find intricacy an always unfinishedorder that cannot be represented,

    but has to be taken along as we think. It is a much finer, more organic order

    that always provides implicit functions, whether we attend to them or not. I

    will try to show some of these functions in the first part of my paper.To speak with and from what is more than the categories, we employ the

    capacity of language for new sentences. This capacity of language is rooted in

    the human body as reflexively sensed from inside. The reflexivity is currently

    being missed, because attention is understood along the lines of perception, as

    if a neutral and unexamined person over here directs a neutral beam at some

    already separate object over there. If we attend to experiencing directly we find

  • 8/12/2019 The new phenomenology of carrying forward

    3/25

    THE NEW PHENOMENOLOGY OF CARRYING FORWARD 129

    that we live with situational bodies which always sense themselves in sensing

    anything else. So the first half of my paper concerns the functions of what

    is more than categories, especially the inherent interrelations of language,

    situations, and the human body. The second half of my paper concerns the

    reflexivity of attention, self-consciousness and first-person process.

    1.

    Phenomenology as I understand it, determines its own use of language. It

    can develop new categories of description. It can examine and direct the use

    of logic and theory. Phenomenology for me is not the small phenomenologywhich understands itself as only describing conscious experiences cut off

    from the universe, from other persons, and from the unconscious depths

    of person and body. I will touch on these topics to show that they are not

    beyond phenomenology as I have always understood it. Phenomenology is

    small when it accepts a small corner within the world-picture of the reductive

    sciences.

    A philosophy that can think with more does not assume the science picture.

    It does not assume, in Russells words, that logic is the furniture of the

    world. We want to derive and understand the great power of logic and science,

    and grasp how these are embedded in more than themselves. We badly need

    to add a new and different kind of science to augment that world-picture.

    Husserls refusal to assume the reductive ontology was sound, and we can go

    much further in the direction he opened. We can derive this and also other

    ontologies in and from phenomenology.

    In use, all concepts involve more than their clean logical patterns. But if

    we do not pay more attention to this, then we seem to have nothing left, when

    the concepts fail. There is no new road, only arbitrariness where the concepts

    break. We find ourselves in a welter of conceptual possibilities, a mix of all

    the concepts and theories we have read and thought. We can move in all sorts

    of possible directions, old and new. Many analytic distinctions can always

    be made, and need not be foolish. In this plethora what we choose to say is

    arbitrary.

    Where I wish to point is a little further. The welter of old concepts is here,but they do not alone determine what we find. Let me ask you: When no

    concept seems to work, what more do you find here? I think you find that

    youare still here, of course, in midst of your situation, and you can still find

    your hope for something from your foray into the topic. Perhaps you were

    pursuing an unclear lead, the sense of something promising. In that case this

    is also still here. Along with this you feel implicitly all you ever learned and

  • 8/12/2019 The new phenomenology of carrying forward

    4/25

    130 E.T. GENDLIN

    thought, but not as a welter, rather as it relates in a focal way to what you are

    tracking. None of this goes away.

    What you find is not disorder, not limbo, not just flow, not some concept

    together with the opposite of that concept. Rather, you find an intricacy, preg-

    nant, implicitly ordered, perhaps partly opaque. From this intricacy you may

    at times be unable to go on, at least for a while. This implicit intricacy is quite

    different than the welter of analytic concepts and possibilities.

    There are phenomenological variables at this edge. Sometimes the sense

    of such an edge is already there, calling for our attention, but usually we need

    a quiet minute of attending to where it can come. And when it has come, if we

    leave it even for a moment, then we only remember it. We need another quiet

    minute to find it again. When it comes, it may be open to be spoken-from. Or,it may be closed and opaque, requiring us to return repeatedly before it opens.

    It may be a diffuse sense from which many strands can be articulated. Or,

    there may be one single focal implying like a felt lead or an insistent sense of

    something. InExperiencing and the Creation of Meaning, I found interesting

    relations among these variables.2 Much work has since been done on this kind

    of datum.

    I have been speaking about concepts breaking down, but even when they

    work well, we canalways go to the implicit intricacy. It is a more organic order,

    a morepreciseand more demanding kindof order, a very finely determined

    order, very differentfrom logic, yet responsive to logic. It contains a great

    many implicit distinctions and entities, but you can easily assure yourself that

    it has much more order than these, and an order of a different kind.

    Now I must point to the mode of language I have already used here. Can I

    really use words such as organic, order, precise, kind, determined,

    and different, to speak of more than conceptual distinctions? These words

    seem to mean certain conceptual distinctions. Does not order always consist

    of discrete entities and patterns? Does not organic refer to certain defined

    entities? But in my sentences the words have not remained within their old

    meanings. When we speak from the intricacy, the sentences can add to the

    meanings of the words. We notice this especially when we have trouble finding

    words. Then we can sense the physical strain as the implicit words rearrange

    themselves in our bodies, so that when they come, they arrive newly arranged.

    Words can acquire more meaning when they come in sentences that comefreshly at the edge of the implicit intricacy.

    You need not be a philosopher to find yourself at such an edge. You might

    be tracking a half-formed new observation in any field. Or, you might be in

    midst of writing a poem. Or, you might find yourself in a troubling situation

    which no obvious action can resolve. With the usual view of the body as a

    machine, it may seem surprising that the body can feel a situation, and what

  • 8/12/2019 The new phenomenology of carrying forward

    5/25

    THE NEW PHENOMENOLOGY OF CARRYING FORWARD 131

    is more, can imply and demand a next step of speech or action that has never

    been seen before. But we are familiar with this bodily knowledge from

    many practical situations. We know that we cannot base our actions just on

    what we can conceptualize. We have to use our implicit bodily sense of the

    whole situation. We may find a way that resolves our bodily unease, or not. We

    decide when we must, but perhaps a large discomfort remains hanging there.

    This bodily discomfort knows some of the intricacy which the decision did

    not take account of. But when a decision does sit right in our bodies, how well

    we sleep that night!

    Right now, for example, where do you sense your reaction to what I am

    saying? If you have not stopped to articulate it, then it is still only a physical

    sense of implicit meaning, perhaps excitement, perhaps discomfort, at anyrate a bodily sense which only a philosophical body could create. It is not an

    emotion, not a mere feelingaboutthis discussion, but an implicit intricacy, a

    cluster of implicit philosophical thoughts.

    But I am getting too far ahead. Let me choose one example and go into

    some detail. I hope the example will let me point to the close relation between

    language and the body. In my example you will note the physicalcoming

    of words. The example should also show how we can find where the implicit

    intricacy opens. Thirdly it should show how we recognize when we did not

    speak from the implicit intricacy, and when we did.

    Say you are writing a poem. You have six or eight lines but the poem is

    not finished. It wants to go on. In an implicit way you feel (sense, have, live,

    are. . .

    ) what should be said next, but you do not know what to say. The phrases

    that come do not precisely say it. You reject one phrase after another. How

    are you able to do this? You do not know what to say, but you recognize that

    these phrases do not say it. Something implicit is functioning in your rejection

    of them. Lovely phrases come. Some are so good, you save them for another

    poem. But THIS demanding implicit sense still hangs there.

    You may be distracted for a moment. Now the demanding sense is gone.

    You quietly re-read the poem so far, and there, at the end of what you have,

    there it is again! And you still cannot say it.

    What or where is that, which is there again? It is so stubborn and precise.

    Your body understands the phrases that come. It knows the language and

    demands I say implies something more precise.Your hand rotates in midair your body knows what needs to be said and

    has never as yet been said in the history of the world (if it is a good poem).

    Eventually the right phrasescome!

    What does the word come say here? How do words come to us? This

    coming needs to be studied. How do the right phrases come and how are

    they recognized?

  • 8/12/2019 The new phenomenology of carrying forward

    6/25

    132 E.T. GENDLIN

    As a poet you need not worry over these questions. Poets work in what

    Husserl called the natural attitude. But as philosophers and phenomenol-

    ogists we want to think with, from, and into this unclear but more precise

    demanding edge, and think into this coming of words. When we then speak

    from there, these three words language, concept, and body will have

    acquired more meanings.

    As philosopher observing yourself as poet, you find that THIS, which

    needs to be said, is more precise than the common phrases. How or where do

    you have this? Your rotating hand almost says it. Your whole body demands

    (implies) THIS. But now the word body speaks from your body as sensed

    from inside, not only your externally observable body.

    The implicit meaning does not exist before or without language. In animalsthe inwardly sensed body exists before language. But the human body is never

    before language. But the implied meaning is not the result onlyof language.

    The relation of language to the body is more intricate than just with or without.

    Your body understands well the language and the phrases it rejects. But it can

    generate a bodily implying that goes beyond what the already-shared common

    meanings could imply. The body knows the language, and is always moves

    on freshly again, beyond the already existing meanings.

    The body physically rearranges the same old words, so that they come to

    us already arranged in new phrases and sentences. This is so in all ordinary

    speech, not only in fresh thinking. We do not look up single words and paste

    them together. If we hear ourselves saying the wrong thing, we can only stop,

    regain the implicit sense of what we were about to say, and wait for another

    set of words to come.

    The coming of words is bodily, like the coming of tears, sleep, orgasm,

    improvisation, and how the muse comes. But here we have to be careful. The

    higher animals also sleep and have orgasms, and very complex lives even

    without language. But language is implicit in the whole human body (not

    only in our brains). Language is implicit in our muscular movements and in

    every organ. It is implicit in what rouses or spoils our appetites, and in what

    disturbs our sleep. The language is part of culture and history, but the body is

    always freshly here again, and can say no, even when culture and reason say

    yes. If you enter there, you find a finely ordered cluster of strands, far more

    intricate than culture. The body can insist on some new and more sophisticatedway that has never as yet been found, and may never be found. We often need

    to find our way beyond the cultural forms. Similarly, improvisation and the

    muse come in a bodily way beyond the already existing forms.

    Although what we called you does not control what comes, the implying

    is not an otherness(not an alterity), notanother self, not unreachable. Rather,

    what comesin this way feels more deeply and uncensoredly from yourself,

  • 8/12/2019 The new phenomenology of carrying forward

    7/25

  • 8/12/2019 The new phenomenology of carrying forward

    8/25

    134 E.T. GENDLIN

    not in is more complex than representation. We are speaking from it; we are

    taking it along.

    Does the implying become explicit? No, not at all! The implying does not

    become words, even after the newly-phrased words arrive. The implying never

    turns into something explicit, as if now it is no longer there. If the implying

    were no longer there, the poet would not know to prefer just these words.

    Rather, these words carry the implying along with it. They bring it. They carry

    it forward. They take it along. They bring this implying with them, which is

    how the poet knows to keep just this line.

    At last the poet knows what the implying was, but is this quite the same

    implying that was there before? We cannot say yes because the poet didnt

    quite know what was implied. We cannot say no because then there wouldbe no connection and no reason to keep these lines. Here again the old con-

    cepts break, and again I point to the more intricate pattern we find, and to

    the power of fresh language to speak from it. We can do much more than

    deny that the implying is the same or different. As philosophers we recog-

    nize the same and different as the arch principles of the logical use of

    concepts.

    In commenting on my philosophy, Mohanty wanted to divide carrying

    forward. He wanted to know which part was there before and which part is

    new and different. Instead, let us speak from the pattern that we do find here. 4

    The fresh language of no longer hanging there and carried forward now

    becomes a new concept, but also an instance of a new way to use concepts.

    Fresh language leads to a new concept when there is a pattern, something we

    can see also in many other places. I think you will find yourself using the

    concept of carrying forward at many junctures. There has been no way to

    speak from this relation between implying and words, but now there is .

    As a concept, carrying forward does also have the usual kind of pattern,

    a structure, a kind of diagram in empty space. It contains the spatial pattern

    of forward (and backward), and also the pattern of carrying, i.e., something

    taken and moved by something else. But this alone says very little. The concept

    means our use of it at this juncture, where words (it could be actions) let a

    precise implying no longer hang there, but take it along. Without taking this

    juncture along, the concept does not say much. So it does not substitute for the

    role which the implicit intricacy plays here. We do not substitute the conceptfor the intricacy; rather we take the intricacy along so that the concept can

    speak-fromthis intricate juncture.

    But is not something a concept only because its pattern goes free from

    the juncture at which it first arises, so that it is applicable elsewhere? But the

    pattern of this concept is not only a separable spatial diagram. The pattern

    is also its relation to the carried-forward intricacy. When we apply carrying

  • 8/12/2019 The new phenomenology of carrying forward

    9/25

    THE NEW PHENOMENOLOGY OF CARRYING FORWARD 135

    forward elsewhere, we apply this juncture. Let me explain how such a concept

    is applicable at other junctures.

    Concepts that carry their implicit junctures with them are much more pre-

    cise. They mean what they do at that juncture in that situation. When applied

    elsewhere they bring their first implicit juncture intothe new implicit junc-

    ture. So they do not have the same effect there, nor just a different effect, but

    again more than same or different. Can language say what we do find? The

    concepts first implicit juncture crosses with the new juncture, to produce

    just this next change at this new juncture. We can enter into its effect. Then

    we find that crossing opens every concept so that it can do more than be-

    fore. We also find that it opens each new juncture so that there is more there

    than before. The crossing of two junctures does not bring the lowest com-mon denominator but rather a great deal that is new to both of the two that

    cross.

    In a logical order every additional meaning is a further limitation of the

    result. It decreases the degrees of freedom. But intricacy has the responsive

    order in which, the more requirements have been formulated, the more further

    possibilities are thereby opened. I was able to show this in Experiencing and

    the Creation of Meaning.

    When two patterns function only logically, they do limit each other down to

    their lowest commonality. Our capacity for logical patterns is an enormously

    valuable human power, but we do not lose it if we also use the kind of pattern

    which happens with intricacy. Carrying forward and crossing are two

    more-than-logical concepts I have introduced. In the crossing of two intrica-

    cies, each becomes implicit in the other insofar as it can. This is an extremely

    precise implicit process. When we enter into this implicit effect, we find that

    the new possibilities are much more precisely differentiated than what we had

    before.

    (See C&D for this philosophy of language and word-use.)

    Forexample, earlier I distinguished experiencing from the arbitrary analytic

    plethora. This distinction has its meaning just at that juncture, in order to find

    both. I said only: If you go further; what do you find you have there? Other

    than for the sake of finding them, I did not distinguish them. Even so I had to

    say that the analytic one is already implicit in the experiential one. So this was

    not the separable pattern of two. When we apply this odd diad elsewhere, wecan expect it to do more there, than can follow from it here. But concepts really

    always bring their intricacy along. When we apply any concept elsewhere, we

    can enter the intricacy to find what effect it has had there.

    Things do not come separately with external relations between already-

    cut units. Experiencing precedes units. We create units. We fashion them

    retroactively, and thereby gain the powers of logical inference. We can create

  • 8/12/2019 The new phenomenology of carrying forward

    10/25

    136 E.T. GENDLIN

    logical theory without assuming a reality that consists of logical units. And,

    we can always re-enter the intricacy after any logical inference.

    It has long been known that concepts bring their implicit junctures and are

    not the same in different contexts, but this was always considered a terrible

    limitation which has to be ignored if we want to make sense. Concepts were

    therefore said to drop out all their intricacy, as if the actual intricacy con-

    sisted only of particulars subsumed under them. But concepts do not drop

    out their intricacy, and the intricacy does not consist only of subsumed detail.

    When concepts are treated as empty patterns, they seem to close the intricacy

    which is always there and can always be entered. Although this closing is vital

    for logic, it has given concepts a bad reputation as if they must always close

    us to more. This is not so.In contrast to spatial patterns which have no inherent value-direction, we

    find that experiential implying has a life-enhancing, forward-moving charac-

    ter. The implied new steps (of language or action) are in a life-forwarding

    direction. What we usually call the direction is defined by some external

    aim or mark. The externally-defined direction can change at each step, but

    in its implicit intricate meaning we say, looking back, that the surprising steps

    of carrying forward were in the same direction all along. The bodys organic

    direction is prior to the externally defined direction. As a society we must

    be careful that the great progress of the logically reductive sciences does not

    lead us to lose this little-understood characteristic of body process.

    We see that language, body, and situational interaction are a single system

    together. Every situation consists of hundreds of possibilities for actions and

    speech-acts. Those are culturally given routines, but an individual body can

    sense not only the routine patterns, but also new life-enhancing steps beyond

    the forms and routines.

    Experiencing is always a sequence. If we apply carrying forward to a

    whole sequence, the concept has a new effect. We can think of the sequence

    as a constant carrying forward of implying into new implying which is in

    turn carried forward into still newer implying. This process is a zig-zag

    between what is implied on the one hand, and statements or actions on the

    other. Implying and occurring respond to each other.

    If we employ the zig-zag, we can monitor whether we are speaking from

    the implicit intricacy, or not. Suppose you have some half-formed new ideasfor a paper, and now you have a chance to talk about it with someone. You

    have a rich implicit sense of what you want to say, but nothing written. Talking

    about such an implicit sense may kill it. You seem to have had only two dull

    ideas. But we know that talking about it can also maximize and expand it.

    Then you are amazed to find so many strands, all still developing. What does

    this depend on?

  • 8/12/2019 The new phenomenology of carrying forward

    11/25

    THE NEW PHENOMENOLOGY OF CARRYING FORWARD 137

    My point here is: You need not wait till you get home, and either deplore

    speaking prematurely, or happily laud the power of dialogue. If you keep

    returning to the implicit, you can check step by step whether the implicit

    is being carried forward. If it shrivels, quickly discard the statement. Better

    words will come.

    This example will now help me to discuss a far-reaching conclusion:

    Whether you will say retroactively that you had a rich idea or a thin one

    depends not only on what you had, but also on whether it was carried forward

    or not. Carrying forward has two past times, both the recorded time behind

    it, and the retroactive past looking back from now. In the recorded past you

    might remember how it seemed before you began speaking. In the retroactive

    time you now say what the implying really was. Neither is invented. Bothare very precisely just what they are.

    The carrying-forward sequence gives us a new concept of time. For exam-

    ple, the new line lets the poet know what was really meant by the previous

    lines. Now they may need revising, but this will be a sharpening, not just a

    change. The process has reached back behind itself to carry forward what

    the previous lines meant. Retroactively one can now explain just what it

    was in the earlier lines that has led to this new one. There is not only the

    remembered past, but also a new past, a second past which is experienced

    from the present, back, but very precisely, not arbitrarily.5

    I call the carrying forward sequence nonlaplacian. Laplace said if he

    could know all the particles and their velocity at any one moment, he could

    tell us everything about the past and the future. The zig-zag stands in contrast

    to the Laplacian logic. We need both. Logical inference is indispensable and

    arrives where nothing else can. You might often want to pursue 39 purely

    logical steps in a row, but after that, or at any point, you can institute the

    zig-zag process in which each step can revise the whole.

    Action and speech-acts occur into implyingso that it becomes a next im-

    plying. The present is constantly also the going back behind itself to bring

    the past implying into the newly implied future. This pattern is more intricate

    than linear time. It is a time of internal relations, rather than the usual time

    which consists of perfectly present positions that are not related to each other

    unless an observer externally relates them.

    What I have presented are small samples, small bits from a philoso-phy. My intention is only to indicate a new way in which we can do phe-

    nomenology of language, phenomenology of the body, and phenomenology of

    concepts.

    To move to the second section of this paper, I must rely largely on references

    to the detailed philosophic work I have written elsewhere. I have to mention

    it and then skip it.

  • 8/12/2019 The new phenomenology of carrying forward

    12/25

    138 E.T. GENDLIN

    I could show only a little here. We have become able to employ and (by

    means of the employment also characterize) many of the ways in which the

    intricacy functions in thinking, in language, and in action, as well as in logic

    and science.

    Thereby the philosophy has also developed several practices which are

    being widely taught. I will mention them at the end.

    In addition to carrying forward and crossing we have developed other

    such more-than-logical concepts, for example implicit governing, and un-

    separated multiplicity.

    We have also found certain characteristics of more-than-logical processes.

    The one I mentioned is that more conditions increase the degrees of freedom.

    I have already mentioned theProcess Modelin which the carrying forwardprocess exhibits itself and develops concepts with which to understand itself.

    These non-Laplacian concepts are both internally and logically connected.

    They are inherently phenomenological, but also have the powers of logical

    inference. They consist partly of the implicit functions themselves, but they

    can also serve as purely logical concepts which can apply to the data of the

    reductive sciences. This makes it possible to augment the latter so that we can

    think also about living things and human beings.6

    This philosophy provides a new way to go on from where most philosophers

    stop. Of course they all employ the intricacy. Philosophy sharpens and usually

    repositions the main terms, which can happen only because terms work in the

    intricacy. Some philosophers also point to the intricacy. We can stand on their

    shoulders and go on from their work, both because we can enter the intricacy,

    and because we can let fresh language speak from it in new sentences and

    with new patterns. In this way we can employ a philosophers contribution

    more effectively. Also in this way we can go on from Husserl.

    2.

    Husserl discovered what I call the intricacy. And then he did not stop short

    of it, as so many others did. He entered it and classified a thousand or so

    facets, like Adam in Paradise naming all the animals.

    In his way, Husserl already found that the presentoccurs intothe previous

    implying and brings it forward as the new implying. He denied that timeconsists only of pure presents. He found that there is always also a protension

    of the not-yet. For example, as I now begin this very sentence, you are already

    . . . Yes. And, if I stop, you feel as if we had stopped in midst of a broad

    jump. Phrased in my terms, he found that the presenthappens intoa previous

    protension, and is also a new protention. If we enter further into the intricacy

    here, we find carrying forward.

  • 8/12/2019 The new phenomenology of carrying forward

    13/25

    THE NEW PHENOMENOLOGY OF CARRYING FORWARD 139

    Husserl also found that the intricacy cannot be exhausted. He says:

    dass jede noch so weitgespannte Erfahrungsmannigfaltigkeit noch nahereund neue Dingbestimmungen offen lasst, und so in infinitum.7

    that every manifold of experience, however far extended, leaves open stillcloser and new determinations of things and so ad infinitum.

    He says as I just did, that the application of a concept requires us to enter into

    the intricacy again, to find what the concept did there:

    Der Ausdruck ist nicht so etwas wie . . . ein darubergezogenes Kleid; er

    ist eine geistige Formung, die an der intentionalen Unterschicht neue in-tentionale Funktionen ubt, und von ihr korrelativ intentionale Funktionenerfahrt. Was dieses neue Bild wieder besagt, das muss an den Phanomenenselbst . . . studiert werden (IdeenI, para 124, p. 307).

    An expression is not as one might suppose . . . like a covering dress; it is apsychic formation which performs new functions at the intentional under-layer, and experiences correlative functions from it. The import of this newpicture must be . . . studied at the phenomena themselves.

    Husserl approached the intricacy with certain unquestioned categories, for

    example his top divisions between perceiving, feeling, and willing. He did

    not question linear time, geometric space, and mathematical logic, because it

    was his project to derive these from the intricacy. He saw that he could derivethe clear and stable forms. He considered that his project would be completed

    if he could find all that is involved in deriving these. And, he also assumes

    that the intricacy is finite in this regard:

    Der Ausdruck is vollstandig, wenn erallesynthetischen Formen und Ma-terien der Unterschicht begrifflich-bedeutungsmassig auspragt; (Ideen I,para 126, p. 309, my italics).

    An expression is complete when it conceptually and meaningfully expli-catesall synthetic forms and materials of the underlayer.

    Here I find in the margin my own note from when I first read this text many

    years ago. It says: Is there an all?Even in regard to any one concern, the intricacy can always lead further,

    and can enrich and complicate the earlier findings. But that never makes them

    wrong or useless. Unless one finds an error (which is something distinctly

    different, but this demands another intricate and unfinishable discussion), one

    retains the earlier steps, although the further intricacy becomes implicit in

    them.

  • 8/12/2019 The new phenomenology of carrying forward

    14/25

    140 E.T. GENDLIN

    Had Husserl not so often re-entered, he would have thought early on that he

    had completed the work and made everything clear that could be clear. But he

    was frustrated in his assumption that phenomenology reveals a singlerealm

    of permanent objects and relationships. Whenever he returned where he had

    found all his specific detail, he found that it had opened and developed further.

    Now he had to write a more differentiated description. Others build edifices

    he said, whereas I only dig further and further into the ground. In other

    words, he found carrying forward and the responsive order, but did not rec-

    ognize it as an inherent characteristic of experiencing and phenomenological

    speaking-from.

    If we enter the intricacy at any of the junctures Husserl opened, and if we

    are not bound by his logical concern and his categories, we can go further atany point. We cannot go further just with his concepts and essences alone, but

    we can, if we let them take the intricacy along, if we think not just with his

    concepts but rather with the intricacy and the concepts.

    With old habits we might wrongly assume that such a spot is entirely the

    result of his categories, so that it would disappear if we question them. But this

    is not so. AsExperiencing and the Creation of Meaningshows, the intricacy

    we find by means of concepts and categories is not controlled by the concepts

    and categories. In the intricacy they do not act as if they were logical premises

    which control what we will find. What we find with them does not need to

    remain consistent with them. What we directly find at any juncture where we

    apply concepts, can immediately require a further differentiation in the very

    concepts which led to it. The intricacy is not determined by any hierarchy

    of concepts. Even the smallest detail, seemingly subsumed under a lower

    concept, can lead to an experiential differentiation which reformulates the

    top categories. I showed this reversal inExperiencing and the Creation of

    Meaningand in a new procedure, thinking at the edge (TAE).8

    Husserl found the implicit too, but he thought of it as a halo around

    the edges of clear perceptions, like peripheral vision. He assumed that if he

    looked directly at anything implicit, there would be only clear perceptions

    there. We need not assume this. Husserl extended this perceptual model to all

    other reports from the reflective phenomenological level.

    The highest honor we can bestow on a philosophy is to make it fruitful

    and significant in the future, by thinking further with it, across its limitations.For Husserl the unclear halo is only at the edge of what we perceive. This

    is largely true for perception, although Merleau-Ponty showed that even a

    head-on perception can include much that is not clear. But with perception

    what is unclear is usually at the periphery. If instead of perception we con-

    sider language and meaning, we find, instead, that the halo is the center.

    To find what a statement means, we have to understand its implicit meaning.

  • 8/12/2019 The new phenomenology of carrying forward

    15/25

    THE NEW PHENOMENOLOGY OF CARRYING FORWARD 141

    This is the central meaning, not the edge. Words mean the change they make

    when they are said. The change happens implicitly in the situation. If we

    examine what it is that functionsas the statements meaning, what difference

    it makes to say it, what the point of it is, we discover that the implicit intri-

    cacy is what actually functions when a statement functions. When we say I

    understand it, the understanding is an implicit intricacy. When we do not un-

    derstand a statement, we can only repeat the statement. We repeat its form of

    words. But when we understand the statement, we can speak from it in many

    ways.

    For philosophy the model of clear perceptual objects found over there

    and capable of being formulated alone, utterly breaks down. We cannot use

    perception as the model for language or most everything else. An implicitintricacy functions centrally, and we have to study how speech, thought, and

    actionfunctionin relation to it. Philosophy cannotmodel itself on the reception

    of external perceptual objects. It has to study the process by which the

    external/internal distinction comes about (A Process Model, VIIB).

    The limitation of the model of perception is related to the problem about

    the categories of description. The two problems go together. With perception

    as the basic model, the categories of thinking, feeling, and willing seem apt.

    A percept seems to be a mere apprehension. It seems to split itself off from

    our affect about it, and our will to do something about it.

    Husserls work is phenomenological in that he always begins from the

    intricacy and finds much more there, than can follow from what he brought.

    But, by reentering one can follow how the intricacy differentiates itself further.

    Husserl knew not to attempt one logically coherent system from his many

    independent articulations from intricacy. Each of these provides access to

    reenter the intricacy. It is because Husserl enters the experienced intricacy

    that he can generate so many new terms and distinctions at points where there

    had been only a supposedly simple pattern before. But it is also for this reason

    that he does not make analytically desirable distinctions when he does not

    directly find them.

    For example, among the many questionsZahavivery justly raises, it seems

    true to me that Husserl does not make the following distinctions. Zahavi says:

    Ultimately Husserl tends to equate (1) the first-personal mode of givenness,(2) self-awareness, (3) a certain basic sense of ego-centricity, and (4) thevery life of consciousness.9

    The phrase tends to equate says a little too much, but I think Zahavi is right

    that Husserl does not make the distinction which would set apart how the egos

    self-awareness is a structural characteristic inherent in all experience. Zahavi

  • 8/12/2019 The new phenomenology of carrying forward

    16/25

    142 E.T. GENDLIN

    is also right to argue that this is Husserls view. Self-awareness is structurally

    inherent,not merelythe perceiving of,or thepresence to experiences.Zahavi

    is pursuing a cogent line of argument against Pothast, who seems to reduce

    Husserls account just to the Is perception and ownership of experiences.

    Zahavi writes:

    If the ego is conceived as something standing opposed to or above the expe-rience, it is difficult to understand whythe egos awareness of theexperienceshould count as a case ofself-awareness. [In] Husserls discussion . . . theego . . . is not [just] something standing apart from the stream of conscious-ness, but isa structural part of its givenness (my italics)

    I think Zahavi is right, that Husserl did not construe the I onlyas a pres-

    ence over against experiences. But given the juncture at which what Husserl

    describes what is directly experienced, and given Husserls logical categories,

    I think that Husserl is right not to make the distinctions which Zahavi makes

    in (1)(4) above. As Zahavi says, Husserl finds and says that self-experience

    is inherent in the very structure of any experience. There are many places

    where Husserl obviously speaks-from more than mere ownership. But I think

    one cannot distinguish the inherent self-consciousness with the language and

    kind of concepts Husserl had available.

    Let me first cite the evidence to support Zahavis reading, and then show

    what would be needed to provide phenomenologically the distinction which

    Zahavi proposes.Husserl includes (without making a distinction) not just the presence of

    experiences to the I, but also my what I do and suffer along with my

    consciousness.

    Husserl says:

    Auch mein Leib ist mir gegenuber als Korper, aber nicht als Leib; derStoss, der . . . meinen Leib trifft, trifft mich. (Beilage VI of Ideen II)

    Also my body is over against me as K orperbut not asLeib. The blow whichhits. . .my Leibhits me. A stab into my hand: I am stabbed.

    It is interesting here to compare Wittgenstein on the relation of person andpain in the body.10

    The blow to Husserls Leib which reaches what he calls mich clearly

    goes beyond what is presented over against his I. I might see my knees and

    feet over against me, but the stab reaches not just my hand but me. It opens the

    body directly to phenomenology, not just as a mere pre-condition, as Merleau-

    Ponty usually discusses it. And it supports my reading of his my what I

  • 8/12/2019 The new phenomenology of carrying forward

    17/25

    THE NEW PHENOMENOLOGY OF CARRYING FORWARD 143

    do and suffer which I quoted above. In reading Husserl we can definitely

    establish his finding of an I that goes beyond mere consciousness-of(mere

    presence to, ownership of), although one has to search for special spots. As

    Zahavi says, Husserl gives no distinctaccount of how the I is inherent in

    the very formation of experiencing rather than only present to experiences.

    Husserl puts his self-observations in quotation marks because he maintains

    the reflective stand of the pure phenomenological I, but what he finds within

    the quotes is his me which includes much more than this supposedly pure

    I. I dont agree that the reflective phenomenological reporter is a pure per-

    ceiving, but I can credit the report on the bodily I as much more than what

    is perceptually presented in front of us.

    Zahavi rightly seeks an account of the Ias a self-awarenessthat is inherentin every experience. But on what phenomenological grounds could we devise

    such an account? Of course we would not want just to invent one of many

    possible purely analytic theories. To go further we need to:

    (a) return to Husserls source, the implicit intricacy where he found what he

    wrote about,

    (b) enter further into the intricacy which opens at this edge,

    (c) let language form itself newly in relation to the intricacy, and

    (d) allow the language to speak-from nonlogical patterns which (by applying

    them) we can elevate to the role of new concepts.

    The intricacy will respond variously to various kinds of attention and dis-

    tinctions. If we come with the familiar distinctions and look for the familiar

    result, we can find the old familiar things once again. Of course one can find

    the familiar, already entitized packages such as memory, imagery, emotions,

    perception, feeling, and willing. So we can surely alsofind the way in which all

    experiences are inherently mine. Experiences are not things that exist alone.

    We easily find the I which issues our ray of attention. And as Husserl

    says, we can indeed shift this attentional viewing beam (Blickstrahl). We

    just did this by shifting our attention to the body from inside. But do we find

    these many experiences there? For example, take yesterday. Is yesterday

    an experience, or is an experience rather that moment yesterday when . . . ,

    or perhaps just only one of the many strands of relevances and consequenceswhich went into that moment? Now we can say that experiences are not

    waiting there, in advance of our attention. They are not pre-cut.

    Any way of attending toanexperience or experiencesis already a carrying

    forward from the implicit intricacy. What seemed to be one experience can

    become articulated into several, and each can be further articulated into many

    more directly experienced strands. The common philosophical language has

  • 8/12/2019 The new phenomenology of carrying forward

    18/25

    144 E.T. GENDLIN

    no way to speak of an implicit multiplicity, a multiplicity that is not already

    separated. If we speak from what we just found in new phrases, we can call

    experiencing an unseparated multiplicity. This is a third non-atomic concept

    we need.

    By shifting the relevance implicit in our attending, we can take the smallest

    most specific experience and find inside of it myriad strands which could

    each again be an experience. In this respect this moment or yesterday

    do not contain less than what we can come to notice in life or the human

    condition.

    Now we can say that there are no experiences as an already separated

    multiplicity like stamps in an album or marbles in a bag. Experiencing is

    variously and endlessly differentiable not only by speech and action, but alsoby attending to this, rather than to that. Mere attention is not mere. What

    attending lifts out is a product. Attention has the same power to lift something

    out, as any distinction in a phenomenological treatise does. Attention is an

    active symbolizing, but never arbitrary. The response to it can surprise us and

    force us to change our categories.

    What attention brings is not arbitrary because experiencing is always sym-

    bolized at least by the events that led up to this moment, and it almost al-

    waysimplies, demands, and pre-figures a next step. Attention, (consciousness,

    awareness, presence-to, . . .) is no merely neutral beam of light, although in

    some respects this can be said of it. It is always also a special kind offurther

    symbolizing and entitizing.

    Of course the categories and concerns we bring are not just arbitrary either.

    We respond within an ongoing continuity, or to an implicit demand. We can

    evaluate this by entering into the implicit sense of it.Or, if such a demand is not

    already there we attend with the project of letting such a demand form so that

    we might know what to do next. No attention operates alone. It always comes

    from and with a mesh of physically sensed relevance just as any other kind of

    symbolizing does, and it is therefore questionable, relative, and various, and

    yet also always in a precise and demanding relation to the implicit intricacy

    which motivates it.

    The attentional beam emerges from an intricate mesh of knowing, bod-

    ily feeling, and doing which are not separate departments. When this mesh

    changes, what attention can possibly bring, changes as well. We can enter thismesh at any time and carry forward some of what was functioning in it.

    We can study various kinds of attention. Rather than imposing some old

    classification, we can know that there will never be one final list of kinds.

    Instead, we can let newly relevant kinds emerge here, as I will do now.

    Rarely although very pleasantly, we attend just in a neutral way,just being

    and looking. We might manage such neutral attending for some time. Usually

  • 8/12/2019 The new phenomenology of carrying forward

    19/25

    THE NEW PHENOMENOLOGY OF CARRYING FORWARD 145

    we soon notice a distinct this or that. This is a second kind of attention.

    We feel our felt intricacy being carried forward into the constellation ofjust

    thisdetail. And as we attend to it, it may become insignificant, or grow and

    develop. This is a third kind of attention.

    More often our attention is not a peaceful neutral just being and looking.

    Rather, we attend in order to search for something or keep track of something.

    We attend only in a certain relevance, which is part of our situation and which

    we know and feel without going into it. Recall Sartre in a restaurant looking

    everywhere for the absent Pierre, thereby seeing none of the people who were

    there.

    We have already discussed the kind of attention which turns to a bodily

    sense of implicit intricacy. Sometimes we find that it is already there (as inmy poetry example). But usually a felt sense comes in the body only if we

    attend to its bodily coming before it comes. This is easy once one is familiar

    with this kind of attention, but when new it seems odd and difficult.

    A special kind which we have discussed, is attention to the sense of an un-

    resolved philosophical problem. A forward step, sometimes a whole series of

    such steps, may come if we just keep our attention on it. But if we enter what

    is happening at such times we find that fresh philosophical thinking involves

    an amazingly sophisticated type of attention. It involves making a bodily

    change in which we set ourselves in a certain way. Now we will reject the

    endless streams of distractions. We will constantly return to just this pregnant

    spot. Each time we check again: Have we returned? Do we indeed have back

    again that unresolved physical sense for the problem? We are very stubborn

    and deliberate about holding our attention there, and yet also very delicate and

    permissive to allow whatever comes to come, so long as it comes from it.

    In an experiment by Vermersch you are asked to do three things which

    require your attention at the same time.11 You find you cannot do it until

    you place them into a rhythm so that they really become one thing, one pattern

    of activity. You discover that the beam of attention is not loose. It cannot

    oscillate quickly. You discover why. The reason is yourself! The beam is YOU

    and you cannot bring yourself so quickly back and forth.

    Thefact that so much andespecially we ourselves are implicitly involved

    in the humble beam of attention can now come together with what I have

    said about experiencing as a carrying forward process, and about internaltime. We might miss the inherent togetherness of self-consciousness and the

    internal time of carrying forward, because we so accustomed to read the model

    of perception into everything, as if our consciousness were only a perceiver,

    added on to percepts. But here we have been pursuing a philosophical lead,

    the sense that self-consciousness is structurally inherent in the very making

    of experiencing, not just the perceiver of it.

  • 8/12/2019 The new phenomenology of carrying forward

    20/25

    146 E.T. GENDLIN

    Experiencing, I argue, is inherently a process of carrying forward,occurring

    into implying, reaching back behind itself in going forward. The carried-

    forward implying is also the present and also the next implying. The sequence

    generates itself by means of the carrying forward relation.

    Carrying forward is the continuous recognition that what is happening is

    what was implied. Experiencing involves theinherent re-reception of itself

    from moment to moment, a re-having of experiencing internal to the self-

    generating of experiencing.

    Now we can enter directly into our experiencing of what we call mere

    attention, to see if we have spoken from it, and if it responds with more.

    Is this intricacy carried forward if we say that attention is also a self-

    reception? Of course, I find myself saying, I always felt implicitly thatIwas meant by pay attention! If I was not paying attention, it meant that

    I myselfhad wandered away inside, and was not there with the event. So, of

    course.

    The concept of carrying forward lets us think how we differ from ma-

    chines. The process ofconstant re-recognition of the implying differs from

    mere reception considered as mere impact, for example on a film in a camera.

    The film does not know that it received anything. There is only impact. Of

    course there is impact also in experiencing, but the reaching behind itself in

    going forward constitutes are-reception, a reception of the fact of reception,

    which is also the further implying that brings the further occurring. In my

    model the feedback generates the next step so that awareness is inherent in

    the moment to moment genesis of behavior. There can be no division between

    awareness and events that could supposedly happen without it. In the animal

    world, even the lower animals, such event series do not exist. I have devel-

    oped a conceptual model in which the usual flat is and the separated of is

    replaced by a single implying-occurring pattern. We can build sophisticated

    concepts using this pattern which we actually find when we articulate expe-

    riencing. Phenomenology can develop its own concepts, and become able to

    think beyond the inanimate model of time-space-fillers.

    Without the continuous recognition inherent in carrying forwardwewould

    not be there. There would notbe consciousness or attention, only some hypoth-

    esized third-person events. Rather than a merely added light, consciousness

    isthe self-generating ofexperiencing.I must point out the sharp difference between this reflexive re-reception

    internal to experiencing, on the one hand, and what we call reflection on

    the other hand. The reflexive re-reception generates the process. It generates

    each next bit of process. A first-person process happens through this reflexive

    re-reception. On the other hand, when we reflect, we take a separate stand

    in relation to the past. The reflexivity of carrying forward is not the past,

  • 8/12/2019 The new phenomenology of carrying forward

    21/25

    THE NEW PHENOMENOLOGY OF CARRYING FORWARD 147

    not reflection. It is the self-generating of the present. Reflexivity is a more

    complex concept of the present.

    Now we must ask: Is that what a personis, a bodily-situational mesh gen-

    erating itself by its implying into occurring, its self-sensing? Is that you? Is

    that me? I go to see directly: The concept does indeed speak-from how I am

    always there again having already been there before. This is certainly enough

    reason to keep the concept and the intricacy it carries forward. It has powerful

    logical implications despite not consisting of logical units itself. I think you

    will find it a very useful concept. But of course it is only a thin little pattern,

    very far from carryingme forward in my myriad ways that I sense implicitly

    as me. So, of course, when we think about ourselves or self-consciousness,

    we think from THAT, and not just from this concept, or just from any concept.We think from the intricacy from which it speaks, which is always capable of

    much that cannot follow from the concept.

    Leibnitz said that each person is a differentmirror of the whole. Nobody

    else can replace you. You cannot define you. A person is anoematic. You

    cannot become an object of your knowledge. To think about what a person is,

    you have to think you.

    I want to conclude by touching on the topics I mentioned at the outset, to

    show that phenomenology can be basic to them and is certainly not excluded

    from them.

    Levinas said that another person is not just your other, not alive to fit you

    or to frustrate you by being other than you need. The other person is not your

    other. Another person is alive in different dimensions, another life with its

    own issues, and not the issues seem to you to be, not how they seem to be

    other-than yours. Levinas is right about this. But this does not mean that you

    are not connected. The other person is already inherent in your bodily carrying

    forward of your situation. How you are a self remains mysterious; how you

    are the other people and the things is obvious.

    The reality of the other person who keeps me company is not based on

    same or other. Implicit intricacy gets past the old notions. Another person

    keeps me the most company when we touch or look at each other silently and

    implicitly. Each of us is a thick implicit process. If we relate to each other

    from there, then we can be very close with very little content shared. Or, we

    can share a lot but the company is thick only if we relate from there. Of courseanother person may not choose to interact from the implicit level. Then we

    are at a distance. Even so I can relate to that implicit level, since it is there.

    Phenomenology has no problem going beyond a single persons private

    experiencing, because experiencing is inherently an interaction process in

    a situation with other people and things. What appears is neither internal

    nor external, neither just private nor just interactional. My situation is not

  • 8/12/2019 The new phenomenology of carrying forward

    22/25

    148 E.T. GENDLIN

    subjective since the others in it are more than I can experience, but neither

    is it objective since my situation does notexist apart from me.My situation is

    a function of me, although the other people and things in it are not a function

    of me. Again we find a pattern that is more complex than subjective or

    objective, or a combination of these artificial two. Rather, our interpersonal

    interactions are patterned so that we count on the ways in which the others

    have private experiencing, while the process of private experiencing is itself

    always the carrying forward of situations with the others. This is a more

    complex pattern that can be reduced to logical units. Yet it is totally familiar.

    Each is inherently implicit in what the other is.

    My body is a situational body environment interaction. Rather than just

    a structure in space and time, every organ of the human body is better thoughtof as a carrying forward. The body is situational, suffused by me and how

    I live in my situations.

    Phenomenology does not exclude the unconscious. A few steps into im-

    plicit intricacy reveal what wethensay was implicit. After many zig-zag

    steps we can look back and apply the phrase was unconscious, knowing of

    course that this is the retroactive past from here. About the earlier time we

    know that it was not there as it is now formed, but whatever was there could

    give rise to these steps through which it has now appeared.

    We can phenomenologically study how we use logic for examples in

    philosophical analysis, or in computing our bank account. We do it by holding

    the implicit intricacy aside, it is always there. We know why we are pursuing

    this logical chain just now, and what it means for our philosophy or our

    finances. We keep all this aside so as to follow only the logic. Without

    this implicit holding-aside, the logical thinking would not be possible. Logic

    brings out what nothing else can.12 Logic has remade the world so that it can

    support six billion people. But logical analysis must always be positioned by

    someone, and it can be repositioned. The results of the logical chain have their

    meaning within the context that is being kept aside. Logic does not control

    where it begins and ends. It also does not control the creation of the defined

    units it requires. One slight shift in the implicit meaning of any one unit can

    utterly undo a logical conclusion. By entering the implicit directly, we can

    generate a whole territory of distinctions and new entities, and then position

    the logical analysis where it is informed by the implicit intricacy. We can muchbetter use the great human power of logic when we can enter the implicit and

    consider where to position and re-position the logic, and how to create its

    units. We do not need the assumption that reality consists of defined units.

    Phenomenology does not exclude science; rather it derives the forms of

    science as well as alternatives to them. One of the major implications of my

    argument concerns what I call third-person science, especially the relation

  • 8/12/2019 The new phenomenology of carrying forward

    23/25

    THE NEW PHENOMENOLOGY OF CARRYING FORWARD 149

    of consciousness to neurology. I argue that third-person events supposedly

    just filling empty space and time constitute an obvious construction, a wild

    assumption, floating as they seem to do over there at separate points alone,

    requiring an idealized observer to interconnect them. This kind of science

    has made more progress than any other in human history, but we can surely add

    another kind of science which can also employ a more complex first-person

    model. We have developed such a model far enough to show its possibility.

    I have been arguing against the assumption that consciousness is a mere

    addition to events considered as if they could happen in the same way without

    consciousness. The reflexivity of the person is not a mere consciousness-

    of, not an addition to perceived things, as if percepts existed as mechanical

    events, leaving consciousness an empty of, which can seem unnecessary.The current concept of consciousness is the poor remainder that is left-over

    when reductive science defines the content as if it consisted of events that can

    occur alone. To split the things away makes us a mere of, of events in a third-

    person world without us. The third-person science needs to be augmented by

    a first-person science.13

    From this philosophy of the implicit have come two practices. Yes, phi-

    losophy now comes with practices, just as philosophy did in ancient times.

    What is now called Focusing consists of simple steps to attend in the body

    where the implying can come. We have a lot of phenomenology on how this is

    done. Focusing is useful in many ways, and has now generated a world-wide

    network of trained teachers and focusing partners. Focusing is often done

    alone, but is also practiced regularly with a listening partner. One need not

    understand the philosophy to do this practice. It enables one to find and enter

    the intricacy.

    A second practice has developed just in the last three years. It enables one

    to find that use of language which brings fresh phrasing, not caught within

    the old assumptions. It is called TAE. As in focusing, one takes turns with

    a listening partner. We find that most people have a deep response to the

    following question:

    In your professional field or in your life, what do you know and cannotyet say, that wants to be said?

    When we enter the implicit we find not just a plethora of unseparated strands,

    but also something known that seems in need of being said, something de-

    manding which could not be said something that was perhaps hanging there

    for many years. People find no words to say it. Each word that is attempted

    couldbring some vital strand, but of course the word means something else

    and would be misunderstood. By letting whole sentences come from what

  • 8/12/2019 The new phenomenology of carrying forward

    24/25

    150 E.T. GENDLIN

    they wish this old word could mean, people soon find fresh phrases coming

    from several strands of what had been one dark knot. These new sentences do

    not say something else. They cannot be misunderstood. If they make sense at

    all to someone, they say their new sense.

    If TAE is followed all the way, it leads to the formation of a theory, by

    which I mean a set of concepts that are implicitly-emergent and also logically

    interlinked. Most people do not come so far, but they find it exciting and

    politically empowering to become able to speak and think from what had

    been a mute knowing. The usual report after TAE is Ive been talking about

    it ever since!! Also, I love being able to think. I did not know I could think.

    For us as philosophers, the process develops concepts. Any topic that is

    articulated from the implicit will go much further into that topic.The directly sensed intricacy vastly exceeds the common generalities. In

    any field almost anything we wish to think about lies waiting with its much

    finer intricate order. If we make our home at the edge of the implicit intricacy,

    we can employ all formulations, all logic and mathematics, all measurements

    and third-person variables, and we can then also enter the implicit intricacy

    to which they have just led.

    Speaking-from implicit intricacy can revolutionize most any topic. One

    can transform any topic by thinking with, and also about how the implicit

    functions in that topic. Once you know how to let this datum come from the

    implicit, you can use it in anything you are investigating. You can find some of

    what was hidden in what seemed clear. You can find what needs to be said and

    has not been possible to say, a gift and a demand. Then your bodys language

    can rearrange its words to speak from it.

    Notes

    1. The Responsive Order: A New Empiricism,Man and World30/3 (1997): 383411.

    2. Experiencing and the Creation of Meaning(New York: Free Press, Macmillan, 1962); 2nd

    paperback edition (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1997).

    3. See www.focusing.org for an overview of the research. Twenty-seven successive studies

    have shown that higher levels on the Experiencing Scale (applied to the tape-recorded

    interviews) correlate with more successful outcome in therapy. The philosophy has led to

    wide applications in psychotherapy and other fields.

    4. Reply to Mohanty, in Language Beyond Postmodernism: Saying and Thinking inGendlins Philosophy, ed. David M. Levin (Evanston: Northwestern University Press,

    1997). See also Crossing and Dipping: Some Terms for Approaching the Interface Be-

    tween Natural Understanding and Logical Formation, Minds and Machines 5/4 (1995):

    547560; and Thinking Beyond Patterns: Body, Language and Situations, in The Pres-

    ence of Feeling in Thought, ed. B. den Ouden and M. Moen (New York: Peter Lang, 1992),

    pp. 25151, also at www.focusing.org.

    5. For the new time model, seeA Process Model, IV, V (available at www.focusing.org,

  • 8/12/2019 The new phenomenology of carrying forward

    25/25

    THE NEW PHENOMENOLOGY OF CARRYING FORWARD 151

    printed from Focusing Institute, 1997), here, IVB.

    6. Much of the philosophy is available at www.focusing.org, click philosophy.

    7. Edmund Husserl,IdeenI and II (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1950 and 1952), IdeenI,

    para 3.

    8. Introduction to Thinking At The Edge (TAE),The Focusing Folio, 2004.

    9. Dan Zahavi, Self-Awareness and Alterity (Evanston: Northwestern University Press,

    Evanston, 1999).

    10. If someone has a pain in his hand . . . one does not comfort the hand, but the sufferer:

    One looks into his face (Philosophical Investigations286). See also my What Happens

    When Wittgenstein Asks: What Happens When . . .? in Zur Sprache Kommen: Die

    Ordnung und das Offene nach Wittgenstein, [conference paper, University of Potsdam,

    1996]Philosophical Forum28/3 (1997), also at www.focusing.org.

    11. Pierre Vermersch,Carbondale Conference, Southern Illinois University, 2001.

    12. See the power of patterns, derived inA Process Model, VIIA.13. SeeFirst-Person Science, www.focusing.org.


Recommended