+ All Categories
Home > Technology > The science of impossibility

The science of impossibility

Date post: 24-May-2015
Category:
Upload: rajesh-aluru
View: 267 times
Download: 2 times
Share this document with a friend
Popular Tags:
14
PARADOXES
Transcript
Page 1: The science of impossibility

PARADOXES

Page 2: The science of impossibility

CONTENTS

Abstract

Introduction-Paradoxes

Visual paradox

Linguistic Paradox

Zeno‘s Paradoxes

Physical Paradoxes

Page 3: The science of impossibility

ABSTRACT

In this paper we have done a brief survey of the fabric and woof of paradoxes. The paper

starts mapping out the various types of paradoxes like visual, linguistic and logical with lucid

pictures. Amongst the large varieties of logical paradoxes, physical paradoxes are discussed

in detail with certain examples. This paper also illustrates briefly the works of Escher. The

famous Zeno‘s paradox is also briefly described.

“God is not all-powerful as he cannot build a wall he cannot jump.”

By

RAJESH A

Page 4: The science of impossibility

Paradox A paradox is truth standing on its head to attract attention.

The word ‗paradox‘ is a synthesis two Greek words, Para, beyond, and doxos, belief. It has

come to have a variety of meanings: something which appears contradictory but which is, in

fact, true; something which appears true but which is, in fact, contradictory; or a harmless

chain of deductions from a self- evident starting point which leads to a contradiction. A

paradox is a situation which gives one answer when analyzed one way, and a different answer

when analyzed another way, so that we are left in somewhat of a quandary as to actually what

should happen.

Philosophers love paradox. Indeed, Bertrand Russell once remarked that the mark of good

philosophy is to begin with a statement that is regarded as too obvious to be of interest and

from it deduce a conclusion that no one will believe.

Some philosophers have argued that the existence of certain paradoxes show that the

world in itself is contradictory - and no solution could therefore be given to these

paradoxes. Some paradoxes have, however, been given solutions - for instance, zeno's

paradoxes (see below), and Galilee‘s paradox about the discovery that there are as

many natural numbers as there are square numbers, which had its solution with

Cantor's development of set theory.

To give a solution to a paradox you can either:

(1) show that the contradiction was only an apparent one, or

(2) show that the paradox rests on invalid or unreasonable grounds.

While some paradoxes may be trivial, others reflect profound problems about our

ways of thinking and challenge us to re-evaluate them or so seek out unsuspected

inconsistencies in the beliefs that we held to be self-evidently true. Anatol Rapoport,

an international authority on strategic analysis—an arena where paradoxical results

often result from innocuous beginnings—draws attention to the stimulating role that

the recognition of paradox has played in many areas of human thinking:

Paradoxes have played a dramatic role in intellectual history, often foreshadowing revolutionary developments in science, mathematics, and logic. Whenever, in any discipline, we discover a problem that cannot be solved within the conceptual framework that supposedly should apply, we experience shock. The shock may compel us to discard the old framework and adopt a new one. It is to this process of intellectual molting that we owe the birth of many of the major ideas in mathematics and science. Zeno’s paradox of Achilles and the tortoise gave birth to the idea of convergent infinite series. Antinomies (internal contradictions in mathematical logic) eventually blossomed into Gödel’s theorem. The paradoxical result of the Michelson—Morley experiment on the speed of light set the stage for the theory of relativity. The discovery of wave—particle duality of light forced a reexamination of deterministic causality, the very foundation of scientific philosophy, and led to quantum mechanics. The paradox of Maxwell’s demon, which Leo Szilard first found a way to resolve in 1929, gave impetus more recently to the profound insight that the seemingly disparate concepts of information and entropy are intimately linked to each other.

Page 5: The science of impossibility

Visual paradox You arrive at the truth by telling a pack of lies if you are writing fiction, as

opposed to trying to arrive at a pack of lies by telling the truth if you are a

journalist.

The divergence of the artistic and scientific pictures of the world has been made most striking

by the focus of twentieth-century artists upon abstract images and distortions of the everyday

picture of the world. One of the most extraordinary consequences of human consciousness is

the ability it gives us to imagine things which are physically impossible. By this device we

can explore reality in a unique way, placing it in a context defined by impossible events. In

this way we are able to create resonances of meaning and juxtapositions of ideas which are

mind-stretching and stimulating. This we find appealing and novel. Some individuals devote

their lives to this activity, creating and appreciating these alternative realities in a host of

different media. The affinity that our minds possess for this activity is almost alarming. The

sudden appearance of sophisticated computer simulations of alternative realities and the ready

availability of computer games which are indistinguishable from direct human activities have

revealed how seductive such experiences are to young people. They offer a huge range of

vicarious experience without the need to leave the comfort of one‘s chair. Perhaps the appeal

of these virtual adventures is telling us something about the untapped potential within the

human mind which is so little used in the cosseted activities of everyday twentieth-century

life. We have, begun to use the computer interactively in education, but with little

imagination so far. I suspect there is a great opportunity here to teach many subjects—

especially science and mathematics—in an adventurous new way. Even a mundane

computer-based activity like word processing, has done more than make writing and editing

more efficient: it has altered the way in which writers think. Writers used to write because

they had something to say; now they write in order to discover if they have something to say.

The representation of the impossible has become a prominent part of the modern artistic

world. This takes several forms. The graphic style of Maurits Escher employs a form of

precise drawing which seeks to deceive the viewer into believing that he has entered a

possible world which, on closer scrutiny, turns out to be inconsistent with the nature of space

in which we live. Escher likes impossible objects which we could define as two-dimensional

images of apparent three-dimensional objects which cannot exist as we have interpreted

them: that is, they cannot be constructed in three-dimensional space.

The three-dimensional interpretation of these images is a different matter. The eye is led to

build up different local pictures which, ultimately, cannot be combined into a single

consistent visual scenario. In modern times impossible objects were drawn first by Oscar

Reutersvard. In 1934 he drew the first known example of an impossible tribar. Escher created

the first impossible cube in 1958.

Escher employed these in his famous drawings Waterfall (1961) and Ascending and

descending (1961). The strange loop is one of the most recurrent themes in Escher‘s work.

Comparing its six-step endlessly falling loop with the six-step endlessly rising loop of the

―Canon per Tonos‖, we see the remarkable similarity of vision.

Page 6: The science of impossibility

There are a number of curious older examples of this genre which have been recognized

retrospectively. Hogarth‘s engraving on copper False Perspective (1754) is a beautiful

example. It was drawn by Hogarth to exaggerate the mistakes of inept draughts men. He

labels the picture, ‗whoever makes a Design without the Knowledge of Perspective will be

liable to such Absurdities as are seen in this Frontispiece

Page 7: The science of impossibility

The tribar was rediscovered in 1961 by Lionel and Roger Penrose, who introduced the never-

ending staircase.

The famous Italian architect and engraver Giovanni Piranesi (1720—78) produced a sinister

collection of designs for a series of labyrinthine dungeons between 1745 and 1760. These

fantastic creations depicted impossible networks of rooms and stairways. His working

diagrams reveal that he deliberately set out to create impossible configurations.

Breughel‘s The Magpie on the Gallows (1568) deliberately makes use of an

impossible four-bar. Unintentional impossible objects can be found at very

early times. The oldest known example dates from the eleventh century.

These impossible figures reveal something more profound than the draughts- man‘s skill.

They tell us something about the nature of space and the workings of the brain‘s

programming for spatial analysis. Our brains have evolved to deal with the geometry of the

real world. They have defense mechanisms to guard against being deceived by false or

ambiguous perspective. In such a dilemma the brain changes the perspective adopted every

few seconds as an insurance against having made the wrong choice. A common example is

the Necker cube (fig 1.6), which seems to flit back and forth between two different

orientations.

Perhaps we like imaginary worlds that are impossible because their very impossibility

reinforces the appeal of artistic representations of strange environments and circumstances

which we can experience safely. They allow us to enter environments which are dangerous,

in the sense that they could not possible be part of our (or anyone‘s) experience, but without

real risk. Much has been made of the way in which geometrically distorted pictures began to appear at

a time when physicists first began to appreciate the physical relevance of geometries other

Page 8: The science of impossibility

than Euclid‘s. Pioneering cubists like Picasso always denied that scientific developments

motivated them in any direct way. Escher, on the other hand, seemed to appreciate the studies

that mathematicians made of other geometries. Indeed, his work may even have stimulated

some explorations of new tessellations of space.

There is also a complementary literary style which trades on impossibility and paradox. The

greatest early exponent of this was probably the Victorian surrealist Lewis Carroll. We see

it‘s more eclectic and fantastic manifestations in the short stories of Jorge Luis Borges, and

others. The conjuring up of worlds that don‘t quite fit remains a strangely attractive creative

activity: the only way to be truly original.

The interesting feature of all these examples is the way in which they show our recognition of

the impossible. The impossible is not necessarily something that lies outside our mental

experience even if it falls outside our physical experience. We can create mental worlds

which are quite different from the one we experience. Indeed, some people clearly relish

these images of impossible worlds as much as any that could be made of this one

Page 9: The science of impossibility

Linguistic paradox The supreme triumph of reason is to cast doubt upon its own validity.

Impossible figures are examples of visual paradoxes, or perhaps we should say inverted

paradoxes. A paradox is usually something which, although seeming to be false, is in fact

true. Impossible figures are things which, despite seeming true, are in reality false. We might

have expected that our reaction to paradox would be one of confusion or aversion.

Paradoxically, it is apparently quite the opposite. We enjoy paradox: it lies at the heart of

many forms of humour, stories, pictures, and a host of well-appreciated quirks of human

character.

Paradoxes spun for amusement have a habit of subsequently proving deeply profound.

History is strewn with examples. Zeno‘s paradoxes have stimulated our understanding of the

infinite. Zeno was Greek philosopher of the fifth century BC who is best known for these

paradoxes, which appear to show that motion is impossible. His most famous example is that

of the race between Achilles and the tortoise. Suppose that the tortoise is given a 100-metre

start but Achilles runs a hundred times faster than the tortoise. While Achilles runs 100

metres, the tortoise covers 1 metre; while Achilles runs 1 metre, the tortoise covers 1

centimetre; and so on, for an infinite number of steps. As a result:

Achilles will never catch the tortoise! The problem can be resolved if we recognize that

although an infinite number of instants of time will have elapsed before Achilles catches the

tortoise, it is not necessarily true that an infinite number of instants of time must add up to

make an infinitely long time.

In modern science the term ‗paradox‘ is usually reserved for a counter- intuitive finding that

is believed to shed light upon something fundamental. Thus we have the ‗twin paradox‘ of

relativity, Schrödinger‘s ‗cat paradox‘, the ‗Einstein—Podolsky—Rosen (EPR) paradox‘, the

‗Klein paradox; of quantum field theory, and the paradox of ‗Wigner‘s Friend‘ in quantum

measurement. These ‗paradoxes‘ may be created by some incompleteness of our knowledge

of what is going on, either at the level of the theory supposed to describe it, or in the

specification of the state of affairs that is observed. Alternatively, they may appear

paradoxical only because our expectations are simply wrong and derive from very limited

experience of reality (as in the case of the ‗twin paradox‘). We can expect that further d of

our understanding will either resolve the apparent paradox or reveal that there is in fact no

paradox.

Linguistic and logical paradoxes are not like this at all. They are simple enough for everyone

to appreciate. They affect the very tools that we use to think about everything and are

therefore more deeply disturbing. Logic seems to be the final stop for human thinking. We

can reduce science to mathematics and mathematics to logic, but there seems to be nothing to

which we might reduce logic. The buck stops there.

Logical paradoxes have a long history. The most famous is repeated by St Paul in his Epistle

to Titus when he remarks that ‗all Cretans are liars, one of their own poets has said so.‘ This

is the Epimenides (or ‗Liar‘) Paradox. For centuries such paradoxes appeared to be little more

than isolated curiosities that could safely be ignored because they never seemed to arise in

situations of practical importance. But during the twentieth century their importance has

grown into something fundamental. They are consequences of logical structures which are

complex enough to permit self-reference but arise when we are insufficiently careful to

distinguish statements made in a particular language from those made in another language.

Far from confining the linguistic paradoxes to the world of triviality, this distinction ends up

Page 10: The science of impossibility

by giving them a central role in formal proofs of the logical incompleteness of logical

systems.

One of the most notable modern thinkers to be troubled by paradoxes was the philosopher

Bertrand Russell, who wrote about his discovery, in June 1901, that logic contains a

fundamental inconsistency. Subsequently, it became known as the ‗Russell Paradox‘

It seems to me that a class sometimes is, and sometimes is not, a member of itself.

The class of teaspoons, for example, is not another teaspoon, but the class of things that are

not teaspoons, is one of the things that are not teaspoons. . . [Let me to consider the classes

that are not members of themselves; and these, it seemed, must form a class. I asked myself

whether this class is a member of itself or not. If it is a member of itself, it must possess the

defining properties of the class, which is to be not a member of it. If it is not a member of

itself, it must not possess the defining property of the class, and therefore must be a member

of itself. Thus each alternative leads to its opposite and there is a contradiction.

The most memorable formulation that Russell gave to this difficulty of the set of all sets that

are not members of themselves was to tell us of a town in which there is a barber who shaves

all those who do not shave themselves. Who shaves the barber? What worried Russell so

much about this paradox was its infiltration of logic itself. If any logical contradiction exists

it can be employed to deduce that anything is true. The entire edifice of human reasoning

would fall. Russell was deeply pessimistic of the outcome:

Every morning I would sit down before a blank sheet of paper. Throughout the day, with a

brief interval for lunch, I would stare at the blank sheet. Often when

Evening came it was still empty . . . it seemed quite likely that the whole of the rest of my life

might be consumed in looking at that blank sheet of paper. What m it more annoying was that

the contradictions were trivial, and that my time was spent in considering matters that

seemed unworthy of serious attention.

Later, we shall discover that these seemingly innocuous linguistic paradoxes revealed the

presence of profound problems for the whole of logic and mathematics, showing there to be a

trade-off between our ability to determine whether statements are true or false and our ability

to show that the system of reasoning we are employing is self-consistent. We can have one or

the other, but not both. We shall find that there are limits to what mathematics can do for us:

“Limits that are not merely consequences of human fallibility.”

Page 11: The science of impossibility

Zeno’s Paradoxes Zeno of Elea was an ancient Greek (born around 490 B.C.) who lived in what is now

southern Italy. He became a disciple of the philosopher Parmenides, a philosopher who

went around telling people that reality was an absolute, unchanging whole, and that

therefore many things we take for granted, such as motion and plurality, were simply

illusions. This kind of thing must no doubt have brought on ridicule from the more

common-sensical Eleatics, and so Zeno set out to defend his master‘s position by

inventing ingenious problems for the common-sense view. Ever since then, Zeno‘s

paradoxes have been debated by philosophers and mathematicians.

Space Paradox

―If there is such a thing as space, it will be in something, for all being is in something,

and that which is in something is in some space. So this space will be in a space, and so

on ad infinitum. Accordingly, there is no such thing as space.”

Aristotle analyzed four paradoxes of motion: the Racetrack (or Dichotomy), Achilles and the

Tortoise, the Arrow, and the Stadium (or Moving Rows).

The Racetrack (or Dichotomy)

One can never reach the end of a racecourse, for in order to do so one would first have to

reach the halfway mark, then the halfway mark of the remaining half, then the halfway mark

of the final fourth, then of the final eighth, and so on ad infinitum. Since this series of

fractions is infinite, one can never hope to get through the entire length of the track (at least

not in a finite time).

Start ____________________1/2__________3/4_____7/8__15/16... Finnish

But things get even worse than this. Just as one cannot reach the end of the racecourse, one

cannot even begin to run. For before one could reach the halfway point, one would have to

reach the 1/4 mark, and before that the 1/8 mark, etc. As there is no first point in this series,

one can never really get started (this is known as the Reverse Dichotomy).

Achilles and the Tortoise

Achilles and the tortoise is similar. Suppose that the swift Achilles is having a race with a

tortoise. Since the tortoise is much slower, she gets a head start. When the tortoise has

reached a given point a, Achilles starts. But by the time Achilles reaches a, the tortoise has

already moved beyond point a, to point b. And by the time Achilles reaches b the tortoise has

already moved a little bit farther along, to point c. Since this process goes on indefinitely,

Achilles can never catch up with the tortoise.

The Arrow

An arrow in flight is really at rest. For at every point in its flight, the arrow must occupy a

length of space exactly equal to its own length. After all, it cannot occupy a greater length,

nor a lesser one. But the arrow cannot move within this length it occupies. It would need

extra space in which to move, and it of course has none. So at every point in its flight, the

arrow is at rest. And if it is at rest at every moment in its flight, then it follows that it is at rest

during the entire flight.

The Stadium

With reference to equal bodies moving in opposite directions past equal bodies in

the stadium with equal speed, some form the end of the stadium, others from the

middle, Zeno thinks half the time equal to twice the time.

Page 12: The science of impossibility

Physical Paradoxes In physics there are never any real paradoxes because there is only one correct answer; at

least we believe that the nature will act in only one way (that is the right way, naturally). So

in physics a paradox is only confusion in our own understanding.

Here is our paradox-1:

Imagine that we construct a device like that shown in the figure. There is a thin, circular

plastic disc supported on a concentric shaft with excellent bearings, so that it‘s quite free to

rotate. On the disc is a coil of wire in the form of a short solenoid concentric with the axis of

rotation. This solenoid carries a steady current I provided by small battery, also mounted on

the disc. Near the edge of the disc and spaced uniformly around its circumference are a

number of small metal spheres insulated from each other and from the solenoid by the plastic

material of the disc. Each of these small conducting spheres is charged with the same

electrostatic charge q. Everything is quite stationary, and the disc is at rest. Suppose now that

by some accident –or by prearrangement- the current in the solenoid is interrupted, without,

however, any intervention from the outside. So long as the current continued, there was a

magnetic flux through the solenoid more or less parallel to the axis of the disc. When the

current is interrupted, this flux must go to zero. There will, therefore, be an electric field

induced which will circulate around in circles centered at the axis. The charged spheres on

the perimeter of the disc will all experience an electric field tangential to the perimeter of the

disc. This electric force is in the same sense for all the charges and so will result in net torque

on the disc. From these arguments we would expect that as the current in the solenoid

disappears, the disc would begin to rotate. If we knew the moment of inertia of the disc, the

current in the solenoid, and charges on the small spheres, we could compute the resulting

angular velocity.

But we could also make a different argument. Using the principle of the conservation of

angular momentum, we could say that the angular momentum of the disc with all its

equipment is initially zero. There should be no rotation when the current is stopped. Which

argument is correct? Will the disc rotate or will it not? We will leave this question for you to

think about.

We should warn you that the correct answer does not depend on any non-essential feature,

such as asymmetric position of a battery, for example. In fact, you can imagine an ideal

situation such as the following: The solenoid is made of superconducting wire through which

there is a current. After the disc has been carefully placed at rest, the temperature of the

solenoid is allowed to rise slowly. When the temperature of the wire reaches the transition

temperature between superconductivity and normal conductivity, the current in the solenoid

will be brought to zero by the resistance of the wire. The flux will, as before, fall to zero, and

there will be an electric field around the axis. When you figure it out, you will have

discovered an important principle of electromagnetism.

Page 13: The science of impossibility

Paradox-2:

Attempts to construct perpetual motion machines still continue in our days, too. It is known

that in the absence of a dielectric field electrons moving in any conductor are in a state of

perpetual motion. The total randomness of the motion might lead to a situation in which the

upper part of a conductor contains amore electrons than the lower one. Here the question is

electron density fluctuations. These fluctuations will result in a potential difference across the

conductor ends which can be used to charge a capacitor. A detector will prevent the capacitor

from discharging when the potential difference across the conductor ends changes sign. The

charged capacitor can then be used as a source of ―gratuitous‖ energy. The power will of

coarse be low, but it is the principle that is important.

Paradox-3:

A device consuming 50w is connected through another resistor of 40 ohm to a power supply

of 120v.

Let us calculate the current through the device from these data.

To solve the problem, note that the voltage across the device and the voltage across the other

resistor must be equal to the sum of the network voltage, i.e.

Udev + Ures =Unet

By expressing the first term on the left hand side in terms of the power consumed by the

device divided by the current running through it and second term, as the product of the other

resistance and the same current , we obtain the following equation:

W/I + IR = Unet

All the quantities here except for the current are known. By substituting in the numerical

values we get

50/I + 40I = 120

If we solve this quadratic equation we obtain two values for the current, Viz. I1=0.5A and

I2=2.5 A

Page 14: The science of impossibility

Bibliography

Gödel, Escher, Bach: an Eternal Golden Braid by Douglas R. Hofstadter.

Physical Paradoxes and Sophisms by V.N Lange.

Lectures in Physics by Richard Feynman.

Impossibility-Limits of Science And Science of Limits by John D Barrow


Recommended