+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Two Lessons From Psychopathy Doc

Two Lessons From Psychopathy Doc

Date post: 04-Apr-2015
Category:
Upload: loipkujmnhhyg
View: 92 times
Download: 1 times
Share this document with a friend
37
Submitted by: Dr A E Denham, St Anne’s College, Oxford University, 0X26HSWord Count: DRAFT FORM ONLY 5279 excl. notes. NB: DRAFT ONLY - submission to be completed and abbreviated Reading Distress: Selective Egocentrism Psychopathy ABTRACT In the past decade, few experimental studies have provoked greater interest among moral theorists than James Blair’s remarkable investigations of psychopathy and autism. Blair was among the first to ask what we might learn from a comparative examination of the morally salient characteristics of subjects affected by these two disorders. His studies addressed, inter alia, the question of what role, if any, ‘mindreading (theory of mind) deficits play in the genesis of the morally deviant conduct associated with psychopathy. The question was an inspired one, and moral philosophers have been quick – perhaps at times too quick – to interpret his findings as offering empirical vindication for their favoured views of moral agency and judgment. In the first part of this paper I will set out how two theorists – Shaun Nichols and Jeanette Kennett – have interpreted Blair’s findings. Their resulting accounts of the nature of psychopathic disorder are not only different but incompatible. Nonetheless, Nichols and Kennett rely on a common and central interpretive thesis: both take Blair’s comparative results to show that a subject’s competence in moral judgment is in general independent of his proficiency as a mindreader. This interpretive thesis is the focus of my discussion in Part II. I there re-consider two empirical claims that serve as premises supporting it. The first premiss is that Blair’s autistic subjects suffer mindreading deficits in ways that sustain the needed contrast with the mindreading skills of psychopaths, namely in their ability to respond discriminately to states of distress in others. The second premiss is that Blair’s psychopathic population (or more precisely, Factor 1 psychopathic individuals generally) are not subject to morally salient mindreading and 1
Transcript
Page 1: Two Lessons From Psychopathy Doc

Submitted by: Dr A E Denham, St Anne’s College, Oxford University, 0X26HSWord Count: DRAFT FORM ONLY 5279 excl. notes. NB: DRAFT ONLY - submission to be completed and abbreviated

Reading Distress: Selective Egocentrism Psychopathy

ABTRACT

In the past decade, few experimental studies have provoked greater interest among moral theorists than James Blair’s remarkable investigations of psychopathy and autism. Blair was among the first to ask what we might learn from a comparative examination of the morally salient characteristics of subjects affected by these two disorders. His studies addressed, inter alia, the question of what role, if any, ‘mindreading (theory of mind) deficits play in the genesis of the morally deviant conduct associated with psychopathy. The question was an inspired one, and moral philosophers have been quick – perhaps at times too quick – to interpret his findings as offering empirical vindication for their favoured views of moral agency and judgment. In the first part of this paper I will set out how two theorists – Shaun Nichols and Jeanette Kennett – have interpreted Blair’s findings. Their resulting accounts of the nature of psychopathic disorder are not only different but incompatible. Nonetheless, Nichols and Kennett rely on a common and central interpretive thesis: both take Blair’s comparative results to show that a subject’s competence in moral judgment is in general independent of his proficiency as a mindreader. This interpretive thesis is the focus of my discussion in Part II. I there re-consider two empirical claims that serve as premises supporting it. The first premiss is that Blair’s autistic subjects suffer mindreading deficits in ways that sustain the needed contrast with the mindreading skills of psychopaths, namely in their ability to respond discriminately to states of distress in others. The second premiss is that Blair’s psychopathic population (or more precisely, Factor 1 psychopathic individuals generally) are not subject to morally salient mindreading and TOM-related cognitive deficits. I argue that these premises are not supported either by Blair’s studies or independent data, and that the former therefore provide additional warrant for either Nichols’s or Kennett’s conclusions. In Part III I sketch an alternative hypothesis: psychopaths are selective ‘mindreading egocentrics’, subtly impaired in their ability to detect and internally represent phenomenologically characteristised states of distress (especially pain, fear and sadness) in others and even in their own past and present selves.

1

Page 2: Two Lessons From Psychopathy Doc

Introduction

In the past decade, few experimental studies have provoked greater interest among moral theorists than

James Blair’s remarkable investigations of psychopathy and autism. Blair was among the first to ask

what we might learn from a comparative examination of the morally salient characteristics of subjects

affected by these two disorders. His studies addressed, inter alia, the question of what role, if any,

‘mindreading (theory of mind) deficits play in the genesis of the morally deviant conduct associated

with psychopathy. The question was an inspired one, and moral philosophers have been quick –

perhaps at times too quick – to interpret his findings as offering empirical vindication for their favoured

views of moral agency and judgment. In the first part of this paper I will set out how two theorists –

Shaun Nichols and Jeanette Kennett – have interpreted Blair’s findings. Their resulting accounts of the

nature of psychopathic disorder are not only different but incompatible. Nonetheless, Nichols and

Kennett rely on a common and central interpretive thesis: both take Blair’s comparative results to show

that a subject’s competence in moral judgment is in general independent of his proficiency as a

mindreader. This interpretive thesis is the focus of my discussion in Part II. I there re-consider two

empirical claims that serve as premises supporting it. The first premiss is that Blair’s autistic subjects

suffer mindreading deficits in ways that sustain the needed contrast with the mindreading skills of

psychopaths, namely in their ability to respond discriminately to states of distress in others. The second

premiss is that Blair’s psychopathic population (or more precisely, Factor 1 psychopathic individuals

generally) are not subject to morally salient mindreading and TOM-related cognitive deficits. I argue

that these premises are not supported either by Blair’s studies or independent data, and that the former

therefore provide additional warrant for either Nichols’s or Kennett’s conclusions. In Part III I sketch

2

Page 3: Two Lessons From Psychopathy Doc

an alternative hypothesis: psychopaths are selective ‘mindreading egocentrics’, subtly impaired in their

ability to detect and internally represent phenomenologically characteristised states of distress

(especially pain, fear and sadness) in others and even in their own past and present selves.

Part I

There are certain moral dispositions such that anyone lacking them could have no duty to acquire them. These are moral feeling, love of one’s neighbor, and reverence for oneself (self-esteem). There is no obligation to have these, because they lie at the basis of morality….All of them are natural dispositions of the mind (praedispositio) to be affected by concepts of duty – antecedent dispositions on the side of feeling. To have them is not a duty: every man has them and it is by virtue of them that he can be obligated’. Kant, Doctrine of Virtue, Sec. 59

1.1 Varieties of Egoism: Shaun Nichols The psychopath arguably provides moral theory with its

best empirical example of amoral agency, combining intellectual and rational competence with a

profound indifference to the claims of morality, acting without regard for moral norms and unburdened

by the reactive emotions of remorse, regret and shame. He has been aptly described as one who ‘knows

the words of morality but does not hear its music’. 1 Our ordinary sense of ourselves as moral agents

depends, as Kant observed, on certain familiar features of our psychologies. For example, an ordinary

moral agent will not be utterly ruthless or blithely indifferent to the difference between right and wrong:

he will be subject to moral emotions such as shame, guilt and remorse. He will also not be wholly

devoid of attachment to others: he will not be loveless. Finally, he will be aware that he, like others,

possesses value: as a person, he too is deserving of respect. The psychopath, by contrast, is arguably

1 J.H. Johns & H.C. Quay, ‘The effect of social reward on verbal conditioning in psychopathic and neurotic military offenders’, Journal of Consulting Psychology, 26 (1962), 207-220

3

Page 4: Two Lessons From Psychopathy Doc

deficient in all three of these qualities, and some have argued that he does not possess them at all. 2 As

Robert Hare has commented, psychopaths are ‘social predators who charm, manipulate, and ruthlessly

plow their way through life, leaving a broad trail of broken hearts, shattered expectations, and empty

wallets. Completely lacking in conscience and empathy, they selfishly take what they want and do as

they please, violating social norms and expectations without the slightest sense of guilt or regret” 3. It is

widely recognized that psychopaths have a good command of the moral vocabulary and appear to grasp

the norms that others in his community typically endorse: he can ‘talk the talk’ of morality well enough.

In his actions, however, this ‘moral talk’ does not appear to be appropriately related to an awareness of

others’ ends – of their concerns and interests. His conduct is systematically insensitive to other-

regarding moral norms (moralo-r norms) and to harm-based norms in particular.4

What explains the disparity between the psychopath’s theoretical and practical mastery of moral o-r

norms? One natural explanation is that his facile talk masks a deeper theoretical deficit, namely, a

defect in his understanding of the psychological states salient to those norms – a failure to be properly

aware of their fears, wishes, sorrows and the rest. But what constitutes a ‘proper awareness’ of others’

morally salient psychological states? This question has a long and sophisticated philosophical history,

but I will consider just two simple answers here that immediately suggest themselves. The first answer

– call it the externalist view - says that a cognitive grasp of others’ morally salient experiential states

consists just in an ability to reliably detect and individuate them and to embed them in action

explanations, and entails no consequences for practical motivation: for instance a subject may judge

others’s states of suffering correctly, even proficiently, and remain unmoved by them. The internalist,

by contrast, will say that a genuine understanding of such states cannot but move us, at least to some

2 See Appendix 1: What is psychopathy? 3 R.D. Hare, Without Conscience:The disturbing world of the psychopaths among us, (New York:Pocket Books, 1993)

4

4

Page 5: Two Lessons From Psychopathy Doc

extent and in at least most cases. Framing the issue in this way, it is easy to see why psychopathy

counts as an important test case for theories of moral motivation. The externalist (as here described) has

no difficulty explaining how a psychopath can understand moralo-r beliefs while being unmoved by

them: the psychopath is systematically unresponsive to the action-guiding significance of these beliefs

precisely because he is motivationally indifferent to the concerns, interests, needs etc. of other people.

He perceives others’s salient psychological states as well as the rest of us do, but he lacks the additional

desires that, in the normal case, prompt us to respond to them in action. On this view, mere beliefs

about others never constitute a reason to do anything, he will say: desires alone can motivate. And the

desires that drive the rest of usto think of others’ ends as reasons for action are desires the psychopath

does not have. The externalist view implies, therefore, that the psychopath is a desiderative egoist: 5

Desiderative Egocentrism: A subject is a desiderative egoist just if none or few of his desires concerning others are directed at satisfying others’ morally salient ends – satisfying their needs, relieving their suffering, etc. The desiderative egoist’s desires are always or almost always driven by his own purposes: he aims to maximize satisfaction of his interests only. Others’ ends only or almost only concern the desiderative egoist insofar as he believes that addressing them will instrumentally serve some end of his own.

The internalist will of course reject this analysis of psychopathy. He will claim that that the psychopath is

unresponsive to the moral significance of others’ morally salient states because he does not properly understand

the states themselves. The internalist view implies, that is, that the psychopath is a kind of mindreading

egoist:6

5 A similar, but not precisely parallel, distinction is drawn by Shaun Nichols. See his ‘Mindreading and the Cognitive Architecture underlying Altruistic Motivation’, Mind and Language, 16 (2001): 425-4556 Some theorists ( so-called ‘theory theorists’) have argued that ‘mind-reading’ or ‘mentalising’ – the ability to discern others’ mental states – issues from a process of theory acquisition: the theory is an inductively acquired set of general principles or laws which relate mental states to one another and to external stimuli as input, and to speech and action as output. Others (the ‘simulation theorists’) have argued that the ability to mentalise is less a matter of possessing a theory than it is a matter of possessing an ability – the ability to imaginatively simulate others’ circumstances and psychologies, and by doing so to play out in our own minds the processes to which they are subject and the resulting mental states. I will not enter directly into this debate here, but in due course it will be clear to the reader that I hold with simulationists with respect to affectively and motivationally characterized psychological and psychophysical states such as grief, joy, anxiety, fatigue, nausea etc. Many propositional attitudes such as believing, intending and even desiring need not exhibit any occurrant phenomenology, however, and I am content to leave these to the theory theorists.

5

Page 6: Two Lessons From Psychopathy Doc

Mindreading egocentrism: A subject is a mindreading egoist with respect to some psychological (or psychophysical) state or states just if he is unable to (a) reliably detect and individuate those states and (b) to embed them appropriately in explanations and predictions of actions.

Which of these two ‘diagnoses’ best describes the psychopath? Is he simply unmoved by others’ inner lives, or

is he somehow defective in his ability to correctly understand them?

Shaun Nichols has argued that mindreading egoism cannot explain psychopathic disorder, because the

psychopath exhibits no noteworthy mindreading dysfunctions.7 In support of this thesis Nichols relies on

Blair’s studies of criminal psychopaths. He interprets Blair’s studies as showing, inter alia, that psychopaths

exhibit no significant cognitive defects with respect to their abilities to represent others’ mental states and do

not differ significantly from normal controls in respect of their ‘theory of mind’ (TOM) abilities. 8 As Blair

himself described his results, psychopaths appear to be able to infer the ‘fullrange of mental states (beliefs,

desire, intentions, imagination, emotions, etc.) that cause action: the psychopath is as able as a normal subject to

reflect on the contents of his own and other’s minds’. 9 At the same time, Blair’s studies (and many others)

indicate that psychopaths are dysfunctional in their emotional and motivational responses to others.

Psychopaths exhibit vivid deficits in their autonomic responses to others’ mental states, and specifically to

others’ states of psychological and psycho-physical distress, e.g. fear, sorrow and pain; psychopaths show

significantly reduced physiological indications of affective responses (tested by skin-conductance, heart-rate

variations) to images, narratives and speech representing others in threatening, painful and otherwise

distressing circumstances. (In controls, these same autonomic responses are strongly correlated with self-reports

7 Shaun Nichols, Sentimental Rules, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004, Chapters 1 and 2, passim. See also Kennett, J, ‘Autism, Empathy and Moral Agency’, Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 52, No 208, July 2002, 340-3578 Subjects were prisoners at Broadmoor and Ashwood Special Hospitals. The selection criterion was a score of 30 or higher on Hare’s PCL-R, and was not sensitive to the distinction between Factor 1 and Factor 2 criteria. All subjects (both psychopathic and non-psychopathic controls) were incarcerated for life, all had been incarcerated for at least eighteen months. and all save one were incarcerated for either murder or manslaughter. (Life sentences in the UK are mandatory for murder; for manslaughter they are discretionary and are typically given when there are no mitigating reasons for the act). All were male and white. Subjects were matched for average IQ (90’s range), average age (early to mid 30’s) and social class (D/E). Some studies have used as few as 10 subjects in each category (psychopath and normal control) and some used as many as thirty. 9 R.J.R. Blair, C. Sellars., I. Strickland, F. Clark., A. Williams, M. Smith and L. Jones, ‘Theory of mind in the psychopath’, The Journal of Forensic Psychiatry, 7, 15-25 (1996)

6

Page 7: Two Lessons From Psychopathy Doc

and other evidence of emotional-affective engagement.10 ) This combination of cognitive competence and

affective deviance seems to provide good evidence that the psychopath is a desiderative egoist. That is, in any

event, how Nichols (and, initially Blair himself) interpreted them.11 Nichols’s diagnosis of the psychopath

characterizes him as an able enough mind-reader burdened by a dysfunctional motivational system. He argues

further that this diagnosis gives us reason to favour an externalist account of non-pathological moralo-r

judgments quite generally, for it suggests that the cognitive grasp of others’ concerns and interests underpinning

them can float free of their affective-motivational force. Moral belief and moral feeling are ‘really distinct’ in

Descartes’ sense of that phrase: each is capable of existing independently of the other.

1.2 The Moral/Conventional Distinction: Autism and Psychopathy

10 R.J.R. Blair, L. Jones., F. Clark and M. Smith, ‘The psychopathic individual: a lack of responsiveness to distress cues? Psychophysiology, 34 (1997), 192-8; Blair, R.J.R., and Mitchell, D.G.V., Richell, R.A., Kelly, S., Leonard, A., Newman, C. and Scott, S.K., ‘Turning a Deaf Ear to Fear: Impaired Recognition of Vocal Affect in Psychopathic Individuals’. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 111 (2002, 682–686; R.J.R. Blair, R.J.R., Colledge, E., Murray, L., & Mitchell, D.G., ‘A selective impairment in the processing of sad and fearful expressions in children with psychopathic tendencies’, Journal of Abnormal Child Psychology, 29 (2001) 491–498

11 Blair at one time proposed that the psychopath’s defects in empathy and in his moralo-r beliefs are owed to the failure of a dedicated ‘violence inhibition mechanism’ – VIM – which plays a solely motivational role, inhibiting aggression against conspecifics. See Blair, R.J.R. ‘A Cognitive developmental approach to morality: Investigating the psychopath’, Cognition, 57, 1-29 (1995) The notion of VIM was inspired by the ethologist Konrad Lorenz’s observation that in many species (for instances wolves and lions) an aggressing animal will withdraw his attack if a con-specific victim displays submission-behaviour. A submitting wolf, for instance, may ‘collapse his posture’, tuck his tale between his legs, and slowly retreat; a lion will sometimes lie on its back and bare its throat. Blair hypothesized that the aggressor’s withdrawal is activated by a VIM mechanism, which causes an aversive response in him. Extending this idea to humans, Blair proposed that VIM causes normal subjects to experience distress when confronted with others’ negative-affect states – i.e., states of either physical and emotional suffering such as pain or fear. He then appeals to VIM to argue that normal subjects’ grasp of the distinction between moral and conventional norms occurs by way of a four-stage process: (1) Perception of a distress cue in another person; (2) Aversion/withdrawal response; (3) a stage (somewhat obscure) of ‘meaning-analysis’ whereby one correlates one’s aversion to the other’s distress with characteristic causes of that aversion (e.g., our aversion to another’s physical pain is correlated with the assaulting actions which caused it); (4) We identify the characteristic causes as distinctively moral transgressions, our prohibitions against which are justified post-facto by appeal to others’ welfare; transgressions of other kinds are conventional ones. Philosophers will be familiar with Hume’s very similar account of the ‘natural’ vs. the ‘artificial’ virtues in his Treatise on Human Nature. In Hume, of course, the mechanism of ‘sympathetic resonance’ takes the role Blair assigns to VIM, and differs from VIM too in causing in the subject an ‘echo’ of the same or a similar kind of distress as he has perceived in the other. . See also Shaun Nichols’ criticisms of the VIM hypothesis in his , ‘Norms with feeling: Towards a psychological account of moral judgment’, Cognition, 84 (2002) 221-236.

7

Page 8: Two Lessons From Psychopathy Doc

Nichols argues that the externalist thesis finds further support from Blair’s studies of high-functioning

autistics. One pervasive image of the autistic depicts him as unresponsive to socio-affective cues of others,

lacking emotional warmth and incapable of empathy. The image is not without some justification, and there is

ample evidence that autistics suffer from TOM defects: most have great difficulty representing others’ beliefs

and intentions, certainly. Even quite high-functioning autistics characteristically fail very simple false-belief

tests and other tests of an ability to ‘mentalise’. 12 Autism clearly carries with it an impaired ability to deploy

psychological concepts both in identifying certain propositional attitude states (particularly beliefs, desires and

intentions) and in generating the predictions and explanations of others actions that render their speech and

behaviour intelligible. Whatever the right explanation of this deficiency, all sides are agreed in their diagnosis

of the autistic as in some respects an impoverished mindreader.13 Now, if the autistic is impaired in that way,

we might expect that he will also be impaired in his capacity to form accurate beliefs about others’ interests and

welfare. As Kennett remarks, ‘[I]f we do not have an adequate pathway to other people’s minds we shall be

unable to think in terms of their interests, or to understand whay their interests matter. The ability to think in

this way seems fundamental to the development of moral agency, so a defect here is a very grave mora

disability’. For these reasons, we should expect the autistic to be poorly placed to form moralo-r judgments.

Interestingly, Blair’s studies of autistics indicate that in some respects they are as morally responsive as normal

subjects, revealing that autistic children (already evaluated as TOM-defective/No- TOM subjects) performed

well with respect to two critical indicators of competent moral judgment. The first indicator is the ability to

distinguish between transgressions of ‘moral’ versus ‘conventional’ requirements. 14 (The moral-conventional 12 S. Baron-Cohen, Leslie, A.M. & U. Frith, ‘Does the Autistic Child Have a “Theory of Mind”?’, Cognition, 21, 37-4613 See Baron-Cohen, S. Mindblindness, (Cambridge, MA: Mit Press, Bradford Books, 1995)

14 Roughly speaking, a moral requirement is one which is directly justified by considerations of others’ welfare – their pains, pleasures, desire, fears and so on – and transgressions of moral requirements are distinguished by the presence of a ‘victim’ or victims. A conventional requirement is not so justified (or at least not directly), but rather serves to maintain social conformity and order. The requirement that we refrain from causing gratuitous physical pain is hence a moral requirement, whereas the prohibition against wearing a clown suit to an academic seminar is a conventional one. By the same token, moral requirements do not depend on the say-so of any authority: they hold (more or less) no matter what, and their normative force cannot be rescinded by the dictates of some

8

Page 9: Two Lessons From Psychopathy Doc

distinction, although ambiguous and unstable, is now a commonplace in experimental moral psychology.15)

Blair found that autistic children show a sensitivity on par with normal children to the distinction between moral

and conventional transgressions in response to narratives detailing acts of both kinds. 16 In a second set of

studies, Blair tested the same group of autistics for their autonomic responses to visual images of others in

various states of suffering or distress (e.g., pain, fear and sadness). The test procedures paralleled those he (and

others) had run on psychopathic subjects, recording electrodermal skin-conductance and heart-rate variations

while viewing the images. His results again suggested that autistic’s TOM deficits did not render them

insensitive to considerations of others’ suffering. Specifically, Blair found that autistics’ psycho-physiological

responsiveness to images of human distress are not deficient relative to those of normal subjects; autistics who

clearly tested as TOM-defective exhibited almost-standard physiological responses to visual distress cues,

individual or community. Conventional requirements, by contrast, are ‘authority-dependent’ – they are relative to some individual or social authority, without which they would carry no normative force. Certain rules of etiquette are often conceived in this way: if one is a guest in a community in which it is usual to eat with one’s hands, the requirement to use a knife and fork lapses. Likewise, certain institutional rules, e.g., not laughing aloud in a place of worship, are also conventional: if special circumstances obtain (say, the Rabbi tells a good joke or the priest announces that laughing is in order) the requirement lapses. Transgressions of moral requirements are, for obvious reasons, typically viewed as more serious and less permissible than conventional ones. The distinction is clearly a quite rough and ready one, and it does not survive well under pressure or in marginal cases: many seemingly conventional rules (when in England, drive on the left) find their ultimate justification in moral ones (respect the lives and well-being of other drivers). Conversely, it can happen that merely conventional rules come to be regarded as carrying independent moral force: consider the almost-moral indignation with which some react to infractions of institutional protocol (e.g., failing to follow proper procedure in a committee meeting, or to respect the norms of ‘impersonal’ conversation at a College dinner). None the less, there are enough clear and central cases to make the distinction a useful one, and it is fairly easy to determine whether a subject is or is not sensitive to it.

15 The population from which Blair’s subjects were selected adds procedural difficulties to the conceptual ones: all had been incarcerated within a highly punitive institutional setting for many years (Broadmoor Special Hospital and Wormwood Srubs Prison, on high-security wards), subjecte to a highly regimented daily routine in which, for example, the ‘light-out’ curfew and the dress code are as strictly enforced as the requirement to refrain from violent physical assaults on staff. It is easy to see how such a setting might lead one to consrue context-dependent conventional rules as on par with context-independent ones. This kind of setting positively discourages independent thought about the rationale for behavioural requirements. (I owe this observation to Terry O’Shaughnessy.) On the other hand, the ‘normal’ controls were drawn from the same population and setting and matched to the psychopathic subjects for gender, age, IQ and social class. 16 R.J.R. Blair, ‘Psychophysiological Responsiveness to the Distress of Others in Children with Autism’, Personality & Individual Differences’, 26 (1999) 477-485 Moral transgressions were represented by acst the consequences of which directly affected the welfare or rights of others (e.g. hitting a child or stealing valued property), and conventional transgressions threatened the social order (e.g., a boy wearing a dress or a child talking during ‘quiet-time’).

9

Page 10: Two Lessons From Psychopathy Doc

although they were unable either to describe or initiate appropriate actions in response to them. 17 The fact that

the (apparently) pre-cognitive responsiveness of autistics to others’ distress appears to be intact helps to make

sense of their good performance on the tests for the moral/conventional distinction. 18 These observations

combined with the autistic’s robust sensitivity to the moral/conventional distinction suggests that ‘responding’

to others in the ways that matter to morality might well be a job allocated to a discrete, affective-motivational

system or mechanism, just as Nichols claims.

Even worse news awaits the internalist when we turn to Blair’s studies of the psychopath’s grasp of the

moral/conventional distinction. In this series of studies, both psychopathic and control subjects were presented

with brief narratives involving transgressions of both kinds of requirements, further dividing moral

requirements into ‘positive act’/helping requirements (e.g., sharing some new possession or assisting with a

task) and ‘negative act’/harming prohibitions (e.g., refraining from hitting a child). 19 Blair subjected the

resulting data to a range of ANOVAs, exploring his subjects’ sensitivity to the moral/conventional distinction

across three dimensions: the relative permissibility of a transgression, its relative seriousness, and whether or

not the transgressed rule is authority-dependent (its modifiability).20 Finally, Blair analysed the subjects’

17 Ibid. In interpreting these results, Blair cites Mandler’s suggestion that an emotion state can be broken down in two components: ‘the autonomic nervous system response and the cognitive appraisal, where the cognitive appraisal of the autonomic response gives rise to the experienced emotion’. From a philosopher’s point of view, this yields a fairly crude view of what it is to experience an emotion, and yet there is no doubt some truth in it.18 Both sets of results should be surprising, for at least two reasons. First, it was long believed that autistics simply did not recognize their common humanity with other persons in any way at all: as Kanner described them in 1943, ‘people figure [for the autistic] in about the same manner as does the desk, the bookshelf, or the filing cabinet’.? As recently as 1994, Sigman found that autistic children were behaviourally unresponsive to adults showing distress, fear and discomfort in semi-naturalistic settings.? Secondly, as Gillberg observes, ‘if you do not even understand that other people have, as it were, inner worlds, how can you be expected to show compassion or empathy?’Gillberg, C. ‘Outcome in autism and autistic-like conditions’, Journal of the American Academy of Child and Adolesent Psychiatry, 30 (1991), 375-38219 R.J.R. Blair, L. Jones, F. Clark and M. Smith, ‘Is the Psychopath ‘Morally Insane?’, Personality and Individual differences, 19 (1995), 741-75220 The dimensions were tested by putting the following questions:

Questions: (1) Was it OK for X to do Y? (permissibility) (2) Was it bad for X to [the transgression]? And On a scale of one to ten, how bad was it for X to do [the transfression]? (seriousness) (3) Why was it bad for X to do [the t]? (justification categories) (4) Would it be OK for X to Y if the teacher\librarian\policeman says X can? (authority jurisdiction).

10

Page 11: Two Lessons From Psychopathy Doc

perceptions of why a given transgression was impermissible (the justification category). The results again

appeared to support the idea that psychopaths suffer from some kind of desiderative egoism. Blair’s control

group (non-psychopathic, convicted criminals) revealed a clear tendency to respect a distinction between the

two categories for both positive and negative requirements in all dimensions. The control subjects’ responses to

narratives clearly indicated that they view some requirements (e.g., do not wear a clown suit to court) as wholly

authority dependent, and others (e.g., do not humiliate a disabled person) as authority independent. Moreover,

transgressions of moral requirements were judged correctly to be less permissible/more serious and were

specifically justified by considerations of victims’ welfare.

By contrast, the psychopathic subjects scored poorly in two ways. First, they showed a marked propensity to

treat all requirements as moral ones on the modifiability dimension; that is, they often regarded conventional

requirements as if they were authority independent ones, transgressions of which were as un-modifiable and

impermissible as moral ones.21 Secondly, on the justification dimension of the distinction psychopathic subjects

were significantly less likely to recognize that the rationale for the negative-act/harming requirements had to do

with the distress of others, and they were very significantly less likely to cite others’ welfare as a justification

when doing so required them to recognize and respond to negative states in others. They tended instead to

justify harm-based moral prohibitions in quite inappropriate ‘conventional’ terms, often appealing to seemingly

arbitrary norms (e.g., ‘that is just not the done thing’, or ‘no one is allowed to do that’) and social disorder

(‘doing that would disrupt the class’ or ‘doing that would cause too much trouble’).

The results of Blair’s different studies of psychopaths and autistics, taken together, seem to deliver an

empirical argument that spells doom for the friend of internalism. The argument runs as follows: Psychopaths

possess an intact TOM, but they are deficient in their pre-cognitive/autonomic responses to others’ distress.

21 One sometimes reads that the psychopathic subjects in these experiments treated moral requirements as if they were conventional. This is misleading. The converse is true in respect of three categories; only in respect of the justification category was this case – an interesting reversal of their more pervasive error.

11

Page 12: Two Lessons From Psychopathy Doc

Psychopaths are also defective with respect to the moral/conventional distinction and to the justificatory role of

other’s interests.22 Therefore, an intact TOM is not a sufficient condition of moral competence. Moral

motivation requires an independent desiderative mechanism which psychopaths lack: they are desiderative

egoists. Autistics, by contrast, lack an adequate TOM. They nonetheless have a good command of the

moral/conventional distinction and their responsiveness to distress (on autonomic measures) is near-normal.

Therefore an intact TOM is not a necessary condition of moral responsiveness. Conclusion: Since the ablilty

to reliably detect and understand others’ mental states is neither a necessary nor a sufficient condition of moral

motivation, moral motivation must depend upon some independent affective or desiderative mechanism that is

independent of our understanding of others’ inner lives. The psychopath, again, comes out as a desiderative

egoist: his understanding of others’ inner lives is intact, but his affective nature fails to subserve the appropriate

other-regarding desires motivating conformity with moralo-r norms.

Nichols argues that, just as it is one thing to understand other people and another to care about them, so

it is one thing to understand moralo-r norms and another to be moved by them. Hence a ‘second level’ of

externalism follows from the first – now externalism about moral motivation. At this level the externalist

denies that it that ‘judging something to be wrong carries with it a motivation to refrain from doing that thing’.23

Motivational internalism, by contrast, holds that ‘it is an empirical fact that when one judges that X is morally

wrong, one is motivated not to do X’.24 Hence Nichols concludes

…[T]he real empirical findings on on psychopaths pose a problem for empirical internalism about harm norms. The problem is that psychopaths seem to be well aware of the harm norms, but at the same time, they seem to lack the appropriate motivation to refrain from harming others….Psychopaths know that one is not supposed to harm others. On the moral/conventional task, they consistently maintain that the moral violations are indeed wrong…But psychopaths also, notoriously, lack the normal emotional and motivational response to harm violations….Despite the fact that psychopaths know the harm-norms and know that the norms apply to them, knowing that it is wrong to hurt others does not motivate them the

22 For a different interpretation of the data see my Metaphor and Moral Experience [M&ME], 150-180, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 200023 Nichols, 11024 ibid

12

Page 13: Two Lessons From Psychopathy Doc

way it motivates the rest of us. Rather their motivation for following harm norms seems to be largely external.25

This result is of course congenial to Nichols’s ‘sentimentalist’ account of the constitutive nature of moral

judgment which holds with the Humean conception of belief and sentiment as ‘distinct existences’ which can,

and sometimes do, operate independently of one another. As Nichols has interpreted Blair’s studies, then, they

support his view that ordinary, non-pathological moral judgment is constituted by the collaboration of ‘ an

affective mechanism and an internally represented set of rules, a normative theory’ and that ‘[t]he normative

theory and the affective system are independent mechanisms’.26 Psychopaths behave as they do because they

are desiderative egoists, and egoism of this kind is compatible with versatility in ‘moral talk’ precisely because

tour understanding of moral norms (our grasp of a ‘normative theory’) floats free of the mechanism which

moves us to be guided by those norms in our conduct.

1.2 Psychopathy, Empathy and Rationalist Ethics: Jeanette Kennett

The psychopath is commonly described as lacking in empathy: indeed, this is one of the principal markers of

psychopathic disorder on all versions of Hare’s PCL-R. Nichols’s interpretation of Blair’s findings easily

accommodates this feature, at least if by ‘empathy’ we mean a capacity not only to identify others’ affectively

characterized states (e.g., joy or pain) but to respond to them with other-regarding desires and other motivating

attitudes. Blair himself has proposed that we should distinguish three potentially independent modes of

empathy – cognitive, affective and motor empathy – and notes that the evidence suggests that the psychopath’s

impairment principally affects only the second of these.27 Against this proposal, Jeannette Kennett has argued

that that empathy (or its absence) has little or nothing to do with psychopathic disorder. Psychopathy, she

claims, is instead to be explained as a failing of rationality.

25 Nichols, 111-11226 Nichols, 2927

?

13

Page 14: Two Lessons From Psychopathy Doc

Kennett’s argument for this surprising claim is disarmingly simple. She first characterizes empathy in as a

species of mindreading (not implausibly), where the latter is characterized in ‘simulationist’ terms: ‘an

imaginative process of simulation with its resulting emotional contagion and reciprocal awareness’.28 How,

after all, can a subject empathize with others’s psychological states if he has no idea what those states are? She

then observes that by almost every standard measure of empathy, non-TOM autistics are empathically impaired

to an extreme. Yet, as we have seen, Blair’s studies suggest that they have no difficulty with the moral-

conventional distinction (a criterial measure of ‘moral competence’). They also do not share the psychopath’s

standard profile of being abusive and aggressive towards other persons. As Kennett comments, ‘The meaner

human dispositions, for example, jealousy, lying, cheating, vengefulness and Schadenfreude, are not part of the

autistic personality’.29

Kennett’s second move is to note that a lack of empathy cannot be ‘the complete explanation of the

psychopath’s moral failings, since another group of people, autistic people, who even more conspicuously lack

empathy….do in some cases seem capable of compensating for this deficit and becoming….moral agents’.30 ‘If

empathy is crucial to the development and exercise of moral agency’, she asks, ‘why is the autistic person not

worse off, morally speaking, than the psychopath?’ 31 She concludes that, pace Hume (and Blair), empathy

cannot be a necessary condition of moral agency, let alone a sufficient one. Instead, moral agency must be

understood as a capacity to be moved by rational considerations:

The case of autism shows that both selves and moral agents can be created in the absence of empathy, but further, the comparison with psychopathy shows something essential to the nature of such agency, and here, I have claimed, Kant’s emphasis on reason is right. Only individuals who are capable of being moved directly by the thought that some consideration constitutes a reason for action can be conscientious moral agents.32

28 Kennett, op cit 34529 Kennett, op cit 35030 31 32 Kennet, op cit 357

14

Page 15: Two Lessons From Psychopathy Doc

This view appears initially to rest on an interpretion of Blair’s data that is very different than that of Nichols.

After all, Kennett is claiming that psychopathy is precisely a failing of a rational, not a desiderative mechanism.

On closer inspection, however: their stories differ only at the very end, as it were, locating the source of

psychopathy in affect and reason respectively, and they converge on two key points. First, if we recast

Kennett’s view in terms of the framework of desiderative-versus-mindreading egoism, it is clear that she too

takes the psychopath to be a desiderative egoist: she just explains his egoism by appeal to a different etiology,

finding it to originate (somehow) in a failure of rationality. Second, both take Blair’s comparative findings on

autistism and psychopathy to show that the psychopath’s lack of moral motivation – whatever its origins – is

causally and conceptually independent of his understanding of others’ morally salient psychological states.

The next part of my paper will focus not on the differences between Nichols and Kennett, but on this last point

at which their interpretations converge – the claim that Blair’s data shows moral judgments must in some sense

float quite free of our proficiency as mindreaders able to reliably identify and individuate the contents of others’

inner lives. This claim seems to rest on two empirical premises. The first is that the mindreading abilities of

autistics are so radically impaired as to be absent altogether. The second premise is that the mindreading

abilities of psychopaths are not significantly impaired. Both Nichols and Kennett’s interpretations of Blair rely

entirely on these two premises. There is substantial evidence, however, that both are false.

Part II

2.1 Mindreading pathologies: a closer look The familiar classification of autistics as ‘No-TOM’ subjects

clearly overstates the case. Autistics are not in fact ‘mindreading egoists’, tout court. Many autistic children at

the same functional level as Blair’s subjects use a range of propositional-attitude terms appropriately –

15

Page 16: Two Lessons From Psychopathy Doc

particularly those relating to states of desire (‘want’, ‘need’).33 They also frequently master terms reporting

experiential states (‘see’, ‘hurt’, ‘good’ (as in a good taste), ‘sad’, ‘happy’) and appear capable of attributing

simple desires and emotions to others.34 Simon Baron-Cohen argues that most autistics even understand that

different people have different desires and can identify causal relations between desires and emotional states,

e.g. ‘that someone who gets what he wants will feel happy, and someone else who does not get what he wants

will feel sad’.35 If the capacity for attributing some intentional states – and particularly desires – is reasonably

well intact in most autistic children, then we have reason to doubt that their facility with the moral/conventional

distinction must be independent of a capacity for mindreading.

Moreover, there is evidence emerging that mindreading is not an ‘all or nothing’ ability, and that it is important

to distinguish different mindreading targets. In particular, the ability to attribute desires and emotions – so

important to the formation of other-regarding moral beliefs – appears to depend on different neurological

substrates from those underpinning the ability to attribute beliefs (an arena in which autistics are notably weak).

In fact, some research actually suggests that the only mindreading ability which is almost wholly absent in

autistics is the ability to attribute false beliefs. Therefore neither Nichols nor Kennett are entitled to conclude

that the ability to mark the moral/conventional distinction is independent of mindreading skills (or even

independent of all but the most ‘minimal’ mindreading skills, as Nichols puts it). They are only entitled to the

much less exciting claim that, in pathological cases, this ability is dissociable from the ability to attribute false

beliefs. Moreover, the claim that autistics exhibit normal autonomic responses to images of others in distress

tells us little about the relation of those responses to mindreading skills, unless one supposes that autistics are

‘mindblind’ to distress. But in fact there is good reason to insist that autism leaves intact a significant attentional

33 H. Tager-Flusberg ‘What language reveals about the understanding of minds in children with autism’, in S. Baron-Cohen, H. Tager-Flusberg & Donald Cohen (eds.) Understanding Other Minds: Perspectives from Autism (Cambridge University Press Cambridge: 1993)34 J. Tan, and P. Harris ‘Autistic children understand seeing and wanting’, Development and Psychopathology, 3 (1991) 163-17435 S. Baron-Cohen, Mindblindness, Cambridge (MA: MIT Press, Bradford Books 1995) 63

16

Page 17: Two Lessons From Psychopathy Doc

and behavioural sensitivity to others’ distress, discomfort and fear.36 If that is so, it should be no surprise that

autistics’ autonomic responses follow suit.

The second premise on which Nichols and Kennett rely – that psychopaths are able mindreaders and manifest

no TOM deficits – also tends to distort the wider evidence. Standard TOM tests typically present subjects with

scenarios for verbal interpretation, and pose questions which directly or indirectly required them to make

attributions of propositional attitudes.37 These tests target ‘cool’ mental states such as beliefs, intentions and

desires, rather than states such as grief, rage, joy, embarrassment, physical pain and fear – all of which both

feature a rich phenomenology and are high in motivational charge. Blair’s experiments vindicating the TOM

abilities of psychopathic subjects, for instance, principally tested solely for subject’s understanding of ‘cool’

propositional attitudes alone. The claim that psychopath’s are not TOM-impaired thus fails to reflect their

mindreading abilities with respect to the very experiential states which are most likely to be morally salient.

Moreover, the procedure of relying on verbal reports may mask a difference between psychopaths and normal

controls in their TOM ‘processing’. There are, after all, more ways than one to identify others’ mental states,

and the same verbal reports may mask two etiologically distinct kinds of judgments. This is more than a mere

possibility: several studies have shown that even where the verbal responses of psychopaths to a presented

image or other representation of distress mirror those of normal controls significant differences in their

36 See S. Nichols and S. Stitch, Mindreading (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004)37 Blair’s experimental procedures were not without their difficulties. In particular, his subject pools are limited in both size and scope: most experiments featured fewer than twenty-five subjects in each category (psychopathic/non-psychopathic controls), and all subjects – including the ‘normal’ controls – were drawn from a population of convicted male criminals incarcerated for a period of 18 months or more. Prolonged incarceration in a highly regimented and rule-sensitve environment may be expected to have some distorting effects on subject’s responses. In addition, there are arguably serious procedural difficulties in identifying and classifying subjects by the ‘file only’ method on which Blair often relies. The first worry is that the selection features sometimes overlap with the target features (i.e., subjects who are described in their files as possessing little empathy are tested and found to be wanting in empathy). A further cause for concern is the fact that files are created in part by a process of ‘inherited descriptions’. Particularly in the case of repeat offenders, files stand to be a history written by overworked and under-qualified penal officers whose views have been influenced by judges armchair assessments, whose views in turn have been swayed by penal psychiatric staff, whose views may be influenced by overworked and underqualified penal officers, and so on.

17

Page 18: Two Lessons From Psychopathy Doc

simultaneous autonomic responses belie the fact that the same words are masking quite different ‘global’

psycho-physical states. 38

These doubts about the ‘normal TOM’ diagnosis for psychopaths find positive support in the fact that in studies

specifically targeting their ability to ‘read’ the morally salient emotions psychopaths perform much less well

than controls. Psychopaths who rate high on an ‘emotional detachment’ scale in particular are very

significantly impaired in their attributions to others of the moral emotions of shame, guilt and remorse. This

might be explained away as an effect of their desiderative egoism, were it not for the fact that they also appear

to be defective in their ability to attribute a range of other negative emotions. 39 Several other studies by

Blair’s own research group show that many psychopaths have difficulty recognizing sad facial expressions and

sad vocal tones. Likewise, they appear to be sub-normal in their ability to detect fear, distress sadness in visual

and auditory representations (videos, pictures and voice recordings).40

Finally, it is noteworthy that psychopathic subjects underperformed most dramatically in their appreciation of

the moral nature of negative-act/harm prohibitions: it is principally with respect to transgressions of this kind

38 Repeated studies have shown that psychopaths exhibit markedly diminished physiological responses (skin-conductance and heart-rate variations) to pictorial representations of persons in motivationally-charged circumstances (e.g., a man cowering in terror before a gun, a child cornered by a snarling wolf). These diminished responses were not mirrored in the psychopathic subjects’ verbal judgments, however: like normal controls, they described the images as disturbing or frightening or distasteful. Psychopaths likewise exhibited diminished physiological responses to narrative representation of others’ ‘negative’ states (e.g., descriptions of grief, anxiety and pain), while again their was no discernible difference in their verbal judgments of the events described. What are we to make of these results? Of course there is much more to possessing normal empathic reactions to others than undergoing physiological responses. But these findings suggest that there is at least a stable correlation between the absence of such responses in psychopaths coinciding with an ability to linguistically evaluate the targets in much the same terms as do normal controls39 R.J.R. Blair, ‘A Cognitive Developmental Approach to Morality: Investigating the Psychopath’, Cognition, 57 (1995), 1-2940 R.J. R. Blair, D.G.V. Mitchell, E. Colledge, R. A. Leonard, J.H. Shine & L.K. Murray, et al. ‘Reduced sensitivity to other’s fearful expressions in psychopathic individuals’, Personality & Individual Differences (in presss- 2006); R.J. R. Blair, E. Colledge, L. Murray & D. G. Mitchell, ‘A selective impairment in the processing of sad and fearful expression in children with psychopathic tendencies’, Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 29, (2001) 491-498; R.J.R Blair, D. G. Mitchell, R. Richell, S. Kelly, A. Leonard, C. Newman, et al. ‘Turning a deaf ear to fear: Impaired recognition of vocal affect in psychopathic individuals’ , Journal of Abnormal Psychophysiology, 111 (2002) 682-686; R.J.R.. ‘Responsiveness to distress cues in the child with psychopathic tendencies’, Personality and Individual Differences’, 27 (1999), 135-145

18

Page 19: Two Lessons From Psychopathy Doc

(rather than transgressions of rules enjoying positive-act/helping behaviour) that psychopaths fail to recognize

the moral/conventional distinction and fail to appreciate that the rules in question are justified by others’

welfare. The psychopath’s judgement fails him most dramatically (and perhaps exclusively) with respect to

harmful actions – actions producing others’ pain, fear, grief and other states of distress: despite his superficial

facility with ‘moral talk’, it seems that he does not understand the rational implications and distinctive status of

moral norms justified by the intrinisic ‘badness’ of states of this kind. It should come as no surprise that his

conduct, too, violates one of the first principles of almost every culture’s morality, namely, the principal that

harming other persons is wrong.

2.2 Cognitive deficits in psychopathy If the causal basis of psychopathic disorder were solely attributable

to a dysfunction in some affective-motivational mechanism, we should not only expect the psychopath’s

mindreading abilities to remain intact, but his other cognitive capacities to be unaffected. However,

psychopaths do manifest several other, related cognitive aberrations. First, the psychopath shows impairments

related to his high risk tolerance and resistance to negative conditioning. He shows, for instance, a rationally

deviant preparedness to gamble in bad-odds situations, refusing to withdraw from the game even when

confronted with repeated negative outcomes. Moreover, psychopathic subjects show abnormal perserverence

behaviour in pursuit of rewards, and are irrationally motivated by the promise of small rewards disproportionate

to their likely cost. These results suggest impairments in abilities to calculate real probabilities or to introduce

those calculations into his exercises of practical reason.

A second and related cognitive impairment is evidenced in the psychopath’s difficulties in forming

longer-term risk avoidance strategies in ordinary life. Some psychopaths are so reward-driven, and attend so

little to potential hazards, that one wonders whether their inability to imagine ‘suffering states’ applies not just

to others, but to their own future selves. This speculation is supported by a third cognitive distortion reported

19

Page 20: Two Lessons From Psychopathy Doc

by researchers, namely, the dramatic distortions in the psychopath’s (apparently) sincere recollections of

negative past experiences, such as childhood abuse. In some cases, remarked psychologist Barbara Kirwin, it

seems that the psychopath’s ability to accurately remember a painful event (either emotional or physical) is

negatively correlated with its actual intensity and importance.41 This kind of defect, of course, is one already

familiar to psychology in other contexts, e.g. Post-traumatic Stress Disorders, and it is a candidate for familiar

psychodynamic explanations. Be that as it may, it too is a further hybrid impairment in which past and present

affective-motivational states fail to integrate correctly with cognitive judgments.

A fourth kind of cognitive distortion to which the psychopath is subject concerns his ability to detect and

use affective information effectively and accurately. Recall that psychopaths perform poorly as a group at

recognizing manifestations of fear and sadness in both facial expressions and voices, and showed hyposensitive

autonomic responses to these states and other .42 This is a cognitive failure to correctly interpret perceptual

cues, and it leads to deficiencies in the ability to discriminate and predict others’ experiential states. Moreover,

psychopaths have difficulty making appropriate use of ‘secondary’ or contextually-cued information about

emotional states more generally – incidental, case-specific information that lies outside their focus of

attention.43 Their difficulty with secondary information is also reflected in linguistic abnormalities.

Psychopaths are significantly less likely to incorporate metaphor, affective tone and connotative (rather than

denotative) associations in their language, ‘despite having good explicit awareness [of word meanings] and

understanding on direct examination.’44 Hervey Cleckley described the discourse of psychopaths as a

‘mechanically correct artifact that masks a semantic disorder in which the formal, semantic and affective

components of language are dissociated from one another’,45 and recent studies show that psychopaths reveal

41 In personal conversation.42 The evidence on this point is rather mixed, but the best controlled studies support this claim. 43 Hiatt and Newman distinguish between primary, ‘top-down’ or voluntary goal-directed processing of information corresponding to a “dominmant set, primary task, or effortful attention”; Hiatt and Newman, ‘Understanding Psychopathy:The Cognitive Side’ in C. Patrick (ed.) Handbook of Psychopathy, New York: Guilford Press (2006) p. 346 44 Ibid45 Cleckley, paraphrased by Hare in Hiatt and Newman, op. cit., p. 339

20

Page 21: Two Lessons From Psychopathy Doc

consistent abnormalities in their ability to apply emotional metaphors correctly, despite having good literal

understanding of them. The researchers concluded that ‘psychopaths do not understand or make effective use

of the emotional content of language’. 46

End of Draft: Part III to follow

Word count for draft here at 5000+. If accepted, I will complete and revise the paper within the word

limit immediately after the end of my academic term (May 15) for advance submission.

46 Hiatt and Newman, op. cit., p. 340

21

Page 22: Two Lessons From Psychopathy Doc

Appendix: What is psychopathy?

The precise nature of psychopathic disorder has proven difficult to pin down with any precision, and clinical and research efforts continue to be hampered by definitional uncertainties. All are agreed that it should be characterized as a ‘construct’ or constellations of several co-existing features, but inconsistencies vitiate the way those features are identified and organized in the professional literature. First, there are terminological inconsistencies in the uses of the terms ‘psychopathic disorder’, ‘sociopathic disorder’ and ‘Anti-social personality disorder’ (APD). Secondly, there are substantive disagreements about the specific characteristics criterial of each (and particularly those criterial of psychopathy as opposed to APD). Finally, there are radically different diagnostic instruments in use to identify psychopathic subjects – instruments which can yield strikingly different diagnoses. This is all bad news for any theorist attempting meta-analyses of past research and clinical records. In the past decade R. D. Hare’s ‘Psychopathy Checklist’ (PCL), has become generally (but not unreservedly) accepted as a reliable measure. The PCL was first designed and tested by Hare in 1980 as a list of 22 items. It was revised in draft form in 1985 and, after scrupulous testing for inter-rater reliability and item-reliability, saw official publication in 1991 as a checklist of twenty items: the ‘Hare PCL-R’. The highest possible score is thus 40, and a subject is typically classified as psychopathic if he receives a scoring of 30 or above. Perhaps the most influentialsignificant achievement of the new PCL-R was that it introduced thean critical distinction between ‘Factor 1’ items correlated to interpersonal/affective/trait characteristics and ‘Factor 2’ items correlating to social deviance characteristics. The resulting checklist, including ‘Factor 1’ items (1-8) and ‘Factor 2’ items (9-20) is:

Glibness/superficial charm. 2. Grandiose sense of self-worth. 3. Need for stimulation/proneness to boredom. 4. Pathological lying. 5. Conning/manipulative. 6. Lack of remorse or guilt. 7. Shallow affect. 8. Callous/lack of empathy 9. Parasitic lifestyle. 10. Poor behavioral controls. 11. Promiscuous sexual behavior. 12. Early behavior problems. 13. Lack of realistic, long-term plans. 14. Impulsivity. 15. Irresponsibility. 16. Failure to accept responsibility for own actions. 17. Many short-term marital relationships. 18. Juvenile delinquency. 19. Revocation of conditional release. 20. Criminal versatility

The division between Factor 1 and Factor 2 has subsequently served (in practice) to mark the distinction between psychopathic disorder proper, and APD, where the latter is normally identified solely by behaviourally-manifested criteria indicative of ‘inadequate socialization’ – for instance repeated law-breaking, aggressiveness, irresponsibility (as evidenced, for instance by employment history) and impulsivity. ’. The label ‘APD’ thus serves better to reflect the anti-social, but not the interpersonal/emotional factors of the PCL. As it happens, however, almost all current research recognizes that there exist in fact two independent (if frequently co-morbid) disorders – the first, psychopathy, delineated roughly by the PCL-R, and the second delineated only by the DSM’s behavioural indicators of APD. The APD construct is not unrelated to the psychopathy, of course: most (but not all) subjects classified in accordance with the latter also satisfy the former. It is significant, however, that in forensic populations the

22

Page 23: Two Lessons From Psychopathy Doc

prevalence of APD is two or three times higher than the prevalence of psychopathy, as measured by the PCL-R. Most offenders with a high PCL-R score meet the criteria for APD, but the converse does not hold, for APD subjects often fail to manifest the PCL-R’s Factor 1 items.

23


Recommended