+ All Categories
Home > Documents > Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd....

Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd....

Date post: 05-Feb-2018
Category:
Upload: lamnhan
View: 213 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend
58
Rethinking Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American Constitutionalism and War-Making Ryan Fried For Presentation at the 2012 Millennium Conference London School of Economics and Political Science 21 October 2012 This paper is a draft. Please do not quote, cite, or disseminate without the author’s expressed permission.
Transcript
Page 1: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Rethinking Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons,

American Constitutionalism and War-Making

Ryan FriedFor Presentation at the 2012 Millennium Conference

London School of Economics and Political Science21 October 2012

This paper is a draft. Please do not quote, cite, or disseminate without the author’s expressed permission.

In his recent work, Bounding Power,1 Daniel Deudney analyzes across the relationship

between material contexts and republican political arrangements in the forms of limited

1 Deudney, Daniel. Bounding Power: Republican Security Theory from the Polis to the Global Village. Princeton University Press (2007).

Page 2: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 2

government constitutions. Exploring these linkages within the nuclear era, Deudney argues that

nuclear weapons produced strong imperatives for concentrations of authority within the

executive. This tendency has also been noted by constitutional legal scholars who have gone so

far as to characterize this concentration as despotism.2 Of course, strengthening of the national

security state and presidential executive during the Cold War in response to external threats is

widely recognized by theorists of international relations and American politics.3 Given this, this

paper analyzes these claims about concentrations of power stimulated by material contextual

developments in the overall context of US state strengthening during the Cold War. In effect,

nuclear weapons amplify a tendency that is pronounced and already recognized. This paper asks

and seeks to answer if we can discern discrete effects of material context that are not effects that

stem from anarchic dynamics of the international system, which is generally assumed to lead to

the same outcome. The preliminary conclusion is in the affirmative. While executive

concentrations are over determined, I aim to show that this concentration was greater and took a

particular form because of the specific features of the material context itself.

The argument is presented in two parts across five sections. The first part is a brief

discussion of a larger project at work of which the focus on control of nuclear weapons is a part,

followed by a summation of assumed international effects of anarchy on domestic state

strengthening, emphasizing speed of use, and deference to military control of security functions.

In addition, I explore the added contours of an underlying nuclear material context that would

produce divergent results from expectations of anarchic system effects, most closely related to

structural realism. The second and most expansive portion, offers evidence in the American

2See Ayers, Russell W. “Policing Plutonium: The Civil Liberties Fallout.” Harvard Civil Rights-Civil Liberties Law Review. 10(2), 1975, pp. 369-343 and Cox, H. Bartholomew. “Raison d’état and World Survival: Who Constitutionally Makes Nuclear War?” The George Washington Law Review. 57 (1988-1989), pp.1614-1635.3 For example, see Higgs, Robert. Crises and Leviathan: Critical Episodes and the Growth of American Government. New York: Oxford University Press, (1987), and Porter, Bruce. War and the Rise of the State. New York: Simon and Schuster, (1994).

Page 3: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 3

case, using the Baruch Plan, both the 1946 and 1954 Atomic Energy Acts, and the decision to

install Permissive Action Links on nuclear weapons. I argue that the failure of international arms

control has resulted in a novel form of power concentration in which the concentration of power

centers on the civilian executive, rather than the professionalism of the military in an attempt to

reduce the risk of instigating nuclear conflict. This is because material contextual exigencies of

speed and scope of destruction render traditional modes of security practice ineffective.

American Constitutionalism and War-Making

A foundational premise of this project is that interstate anarchy is hostile to limited

government constitutions because of various power concentrations necessary for state survival.

While the American Union created by the 1787 Constitution accounted for this in various ways

by ending the balance of power in the western hemisphere, a second important feature of the

founding period, geographical isolation from Europe ended with the industrial revolution and the

advent of planes, intercontinental ballistic missiles and nuclear weapons.  This necessitated a

program of domestic state building and an attempt at deep international arms control to abridge

anarchy and save the limited governing constitution.  These new security arrangements are the

subject of most attention in this project. In this particular paper, I address new arrangements

related to the nuclear domain in the domestic apparatus as well as the United States’ foreign

policy. The incompleteness of the international agenda has resulted in power’s ultimate

concentration within the political system.

This study is the outgrowth of an attempt to recover historical efforts by the United States

to take strong action to preserve its limited government constitution. In eras prior to the industrial

age, the US pursued a policy of global isolation and regional hegemony rather than balancing as

a viable means of protecting its domestic institutions and from erosive centralization common to

Page 4: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 4

the balance of power. However, at the turn of the 20th century, changes in the material context

reduced effective distance between great powers making the existing US security practice non-

viable. This forced the United States to either become a centralized hierarchical state, due to

pressures related to the balance of power, or fundamentally change the character of systemic

anarchy and the units comprising it. Hence American security practice in the global industrial

and nuclear eras is measured not by relative power to other states, but rather as Deudney states,

the United States’ ability to mitigate international anarchy in a system of republican states.4 The

following section presents a theoretical framework for analyzing American interaction with the

international system under particular material contexts.

Geopolitics, Systemic Anarchy and Domestic Modes of Security Practice

This section discusses changes in the international system taking into account the change

in material context, and how the new context presented by the existence of nuclear weapons

enables states to drive toward executive concentrations of power. While nuclear weapons have

amplified centralizing tendencies in the hands of the executive in the United States, it is a

byproduct of systemic change in the international system. In short, nuclear weapons have

changed the constraints and inducements of unit level actors in the international system. As to

how they have done so, nuclear weapons lessen the costs of mobilization in the traditional

balance of power, their destructiveness holds the potential for decelerating arms races, and they

necessitate civilian executive custody because of the exponentially increased costs of war.

For structural realism, systemic anarchy is a threat to sovereign states.5 Because of this

international state of war, certain forms of domestic organization are more viable within the

4 Deudney (2007), p. 1865 Gourevitch, Peter. “The Second Image Reversed.” International Organization. (32)4, (1978), pp.881-912, p. 896.

Page 5: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 5

system than others. Given this, as Samuel Huntington has written, there is a certain tension

between state demands for security from violence and individual liberty.6

In instances of acute security threats, states traditionally are more likely to centralize their

power, with the formation of large standing armies under autonomous control of the executive

power of the state.7 The existence of large military bodies, particularly, land based military units

then serve the primary function of external defense, and in turn a possible foil for internal

repression in the name of state survival. That is, the domestic effect of large garrisons in

response to acute and immediate security concerns yields the specter of the garrison state. As

Gourevitch writes, “Defense of the realm was quintessentially that function which required a

single sovereign. It required speed, authoritativeness, secrecy, comprehensiveness.”8 These

qualities themselves are regarded as antithetical to deliberative, representative bodies.9

In such a situation, republican democracies, premised upon division, balance and mixture

– as a means of dispersing, slowing and demobilizing violence by creating co-binding internally

and internationally through mutual restraint10 – are ill suited for the balancing necessary to avoid

interstate hierarchy. As Deudney notes, “elaborate systems of internal check and balance power

restraints and the absence of centralized unitary decision making impede effective balancing

against outside threats.”11 Therefore, increased unit interaction in a pre-nuclear world of anarchy

6 Huntington, Samuel. The Soldier and the State. New York: Vintage Books, (1964).7 For more on the effects of war on centralization and state making, see Bruce D. Porter, War and theRise of the State: The Military Foundations of Modern Politics (New York: Free Press, 1994); and CharlesTilly, Coercion, Capital, and European States, AD 990–1990 (Oxford: Blackwell, 1992). For a discussionof crisis and state growth in the United States, see Robert Higgs, Crisis and Leviathan: Critical EpisodesIn the Growth of American Government (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987).8 Gourevitch, p. 899.9 Dahl, Robert A. “Atomic Energy and the Democratic Process.” Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science. 290 (1953).10Deudney, Daniel “Political Fission.” On Security. Editor Ronnie D. Lipshcutz. New York: Columbia University Press, (1995).11Deudney, Daniel. “Geopolitics as Theory” in the European Journal of International Relations. 6:1, (2000), pp. 77-107, p. 98.

Page 6: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 6

benefits the powers of the security functions of state to the detriment of republican-democratic

governance.

This existing mode, which Deudney calls real-statism, while challenged by nascent

democracy expansion, remains the dominant mode of protection today. It is a form of arms

control in which centralization and concentration of authority produces monopolization of the

use of violence within a given territorial space as a means of avoiding state-of-nature anarchy.12

As this is done, the citizenry is routinely disarmed. Hierarchal structures are put into being as a

means of both controlling the population under its jurisdiction, and preventing international

hierarchy by balancing against other real-states.13

However, in the pre-nuclear age, not all states by virtue of their geographical position

needed to adjust their domestic security practices in this way. Geography plays a tremendous

role in eras prior to the nuclear age, in which distance from the threatening states, enable limited

standing armies, and limited mobilization of material resources to sustain it. Distance also slows

the requisite speed with which decisions regarding security are made, allowing for deliberation.

Lack of proximate threats allows for the development of liberal political cultures and institutions

of restraint conducive to democracy. A removed security environment then enables a

development of a republican-liberal limited constitutional political order.

Nevertheless, as Deudney and others have shown, geographic distance is mitigated by

the advancement of technology used for destructive purposes. The broadening scope of

destruction and speed of delivery presented first by the advent of the airplane and most

12 Ibid, p. 9213 Deudney identifies five interrelated features of the real-state mode of protection being “the monopoly of violence capability within a particular territorial space, the concentration of control over that violence capability in the hands of a distinct organization, the relative autonomy of the organizational apparatus wielding this capability, the tendency to employ the capability at its disposal and thus to couple capability to outcomes, and the public acceptance or legitimacy of state authority as a consequence of the state’s ability to provide for security” in Deudney, Daniel “Political Fission.” On Security. Editor Ronnie D. Lipshcutz. New York: Columbia University Press, (1995), p. 93.

Page 7: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 7

importantly second, by the advent of nuclear weapons and intercontinental ballistic missiles

renders effective geographic distance all but irrelevant and national borders porous. In the

present age, the front line is no longer itself limited to the peripheries of state borders, but rather

makes vulnerable the whole territory of the state.

Often overlooked in works released at the birth of the atomic age is William Liscum

Borden’s There Will Be No Time, whose writing reflects much of what has since become. He

argues that the novelties of speed and scope of destruction that comes with the nuclear age

renders even industrial age wartime weapons, emphasizing full mobilization of citizens, obsolete.

The importance in preparing for nuclear war, Borden writes lies in preparation accomplished

“before the fighting begins.”14 Victory then, if there is such a thing, is accomplished not by the

destruction of cities, or citizens, but through destroying the opponents’ nuclear stockpiles in

being, before they destroy yours. Contrary to structural realist expectations, readiness to fight

wars in the current technological age then, no longer requires complete social integration of the

whole population toward a military ethic, but rather in the readiness to rapidly launch its nuclear

weapons before they themselves are destroyed in similar fashion. Similarly, because of the

intense speed element involved in nuclear weapons decision making, and particularly the

increased costs of war, the ability to launch nuclear weapons has concentrated itself into one

individual, the chief executive, who is fundamentally unaccountable.

This material contextual dynamic is also illustrated by a novel shift in civil military

relations in which the professionalism of the military cannot be relied upon, and rather, the

executive must be active and assertive in controlling the very weapons the military would

traditionally be entrusted to use. This Assertive Civil-Military Control as defined by Feaver,

using Huntington as a foil, is a method that does not presuppose that the military will conform to

14 Borden, William Liscum. There Will Be No Time. Macmillan: New York, (1946), p. 218.

Page 8: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 8

the values and more importantly the orders of civilian society or that the officer corps will

understand civilian leadership.15 Nor does it place its trust in military professionalism to restrain

itself. As it relates to control over nuclear weapons, assertive civilian nuclear control is a means

by which the military is restrained in its ability to use the nuclear weapons in its possession, by

keeping custody of the ability for launch out of their control. It is an emphasis on the ‘never’ end

of the always/never problematique, a means by which the weapons will not be fired unless given

the order by the civilian command. While in possession of the military, the weapons themselves

cannot be armed or used because of the method of positive control.

The need for the control of such weapons outside the bounds of what Huntington called

military professionalism, is a corollary of the increased costs of war and a heightened fear of

military accidents or unauthorized uses. In the aftermath of a major nuclear exchange, in as little

as 500 detonations, the planet becomes uninhabitable.16 As argued by the astrophysicist Carl

Sagan, global nuclear war would not only bring about the physical destruction of the countries

launching such weapons, but would very likely end life on earth as we know it. As he writes it,

“cold, dark, radioactivity, pyrotoxins and ultraviolet light following a nuclear war…would

imperil every survivor on the planet.”17 Sagan raises the specter that even a massive disarming

first strike by either superpower at the time might be sufficient to wipe out all life.

Therefore, the increasing speed of delivery in conjunction with the rapidly expanding

scope of nuclear destruction necessitates further positive control measures to prevent the military

from unauthorized use. This in turn reinforces the unchecked power of the president, for it

would be only he who can give the order to strike.

15 Feaver, Peter. Guarding the Guardians: Civilian Control of Nuclear Weapons in the United States. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, (1992), pp.3-254.16 Sagan, Carl. Nuclear War and Climatic Catastrophe. Foreign Affairs. (1983/1984), pp. 257-292.17 Sagan (1983/1984) p. 292-293.

Page 9: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 9

Paradoxically, while this hyper concentration has led to absolute presidential authority in

the nuclear domain, the rest of the political system has been largely unaffected. While the US has

compensated for its historical dearth in institutional capacity to internally balance against real-

states by expanding the national security state, it has done so in such a way as to preserve a

modicum of democratic practices. Given this claim to existing hierarchy within security serving

apparatuses of state, the United States regime has highly competitive free elections, oversight,

formal checks balances, and a robust free press. Even over the course of the Cold War, many US

freedoms and guarantees expanded.

The existence of nuclear weapons then, also serves the purpose of limiting the extent to

which states need to strain to balance against others within the international system in light of

external threat. The United States’ historical declaratory policy of first use of nuclear weapons,

particularly with reference to the defense of Europe from Soviet encroachment illustrates this.

Lacking conventional military parody with the Soviet Union in Europe, the United States relied

upon the speed and destructive potential of theater nuclear weapons to right the imbalance. In

the event of a conventional war, the United States planned to use its nuclear weapons first in the

defense of Europe, the timing of which within the conflict was subject to revision. The

Eisenhower administration’s policy of Massive Retaliation – relying upon nuclear weapons

while cutting the defense budget, effectively more ‘bang’ and less ‘buck’ foresaw using nuclear

weapons early in the event of a conflict. The policy of flexible response spawned by the

Kennedy Administration, foresaw using nuclear weapons selectively after a series of escalatory

conventional exchanges. While the issue of presidential control of the first use of nuclear

weapons did not become politically salient until the 1970s, Congressional testimony offered by

then the Director of the US Arms Control and Disarmament Agency, Fred Ikle expresses the

Page 10: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 10

very essence of the centrality of the first use of nuclear weapons to the defense of Western

Europe:

…many non-nuclear weapon states depend of the nuclear deterrence of present security arrangements. A nonuse pledge could undercut such arrangements and thereby increase the incentives of such allies to acquire their own independent nuclear weapons…We are now faced with superior conventional strength in areas we have important commitments: I refer in particular to NATOs central front. In this context, it must be remembered that our principal goal is the deterrence of war altogether, and that NATO’s doctrine of potential first use can enhance this deterrence.18

Because nuclear weapons are so efficiently destructive, collective mobilization for war need not

be extreme, as the destructiveness of nuclear weapons renders large conventional buildups

unnecessary for security through deterrence.

This observation about changing patterns of great power warfare is not without historical

precedent. Changing destructive technologies have historically shifted the ways in which wars

are fought, and the implements with which they are fought. Like the dreadnaught after the

advent of the submarine, the need for large scale standing militaries to deter great power

revisionism has become effectively obsolete, which in effect has had the side benefit of lessening

a historical threat to liberty – the existence of large standing armies.

Lastly, the scope of destructive potential granted by the existence of nuclear weapons has

induced particularly early in the atomic age, efforts at international control by abridging anarchy

and seeking to avoid the balance of power politics so characteristic of the Westphalian state

system. Often ignored in looking back to America’s atomic monopoly was the strong emphasis

placed on the need to internationalize the control of atomic energy. Even the 1946 Atomic

Energy Act was designed specifically with this understanding in mind. In his report from the

Special Committee on Atomic Energy, Senator McMahan writes, “…since the only real solution

to the whole problem lies in continued world peace, legislation should be directed in specific

18 Ikle, Fred C. “Statement of Hon. Fred C. Ikle, Director, US Arms Control and Disarmament Agency.” Testimony in the House of Representatives Committee on International Relations, Subcommittee on International Security and Scientific Affairs. Washington D.C., March 25, 1976, 153.

Page 11: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 11

terms toward that end and should contain a practical expression of our desire for international

cooperation.”19 In essence, the 1946 Act was originally a placeholder, and would be subject to

significant revision once an agreement, like the Baruch plan, would be reached on international

control. As will be argued below in the case study, the 1954 Atoms for Peace proposal was a

further effort aimed particularly at slowing the arms race. That these efforts were not successful

placed further impetus on centralizing tendencies deemed necessary to survive within anarchy.

This phenomenon of multilateral arms control is a corollary of the increased costs of

using nuclear weapons. A prevailing debate of international relations literature centers upon

whether states act based on relative or absolute gains. According to the structural realist tradition,

any state that improves its position in the balance of power does so at the expense of other states,

which lose relative power. This is a zero sum world in which states cannot improve its own

prospects of survival without threatening the survival of other states. Other states then, take

actions to secure or improve its own position within the system, setting off a cycle of

competition that goes in perpetuity. While this may have been the case in eras prior to the

nuclear age, the prospects of state survival in a violence rich material context under balance of

power conditions are truly bleak. The incredible absolute costs of even a limited nuclear war are

so great that states have continually sought a comprehensive and binding international arms

control agreement to limit the costs of war. In the ill fated Baruch Plan and Atoms for Peace

initiative, a nuclear great power sought cooperation rather than great power balancing to restrain

institutionally and normatively the ability of states to employ nuclear weapons.

Accounting for the change in material context, brought about by the existence of nuclear

weapons, reveals a story of American Political Development that diverges widely from

19 Senator McMahan. “Committee Report No.1251 on the Atomic Energy Act of 1946” Congressional Record. 79th Congress (April 19, 1946), p.S6.

Page 12: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 12

conventional understandings of recessed capacities,20 civilian control,21 popular military

participation,22 and institutional restraint.23 However, it also diverges from structural realist

assumptions of the requisites of collective mobilization and requisite efficiencies in speed

required to use weapons at its disposal. In the nuclear age, the apparatuses of national security

have loosened the constraints on the government in the name of existential necessity out of fear

of sudden annihilation. Seemingly paradoxical, the contours of the contemporary material

context allows for formal democratic practices continue outside the realm of national security, as

the existence of nuclear weapons and their distinctiveness from everyday life,24 no longer

requires large standing armies.

What follows is a case study from the United States, analyzing a particular concentration

of power I argue that is unique to this particular material context due to the failure of

international control of nuclear weapons. In analyzing the Baruch Plan and Atoms for Peace, we

can see that the speed and destructiveness of nuclear weapons themselves leads to the tendency

of states to seek an abridgement of anarchy and balance of power politics, attempting to limit the

arms race. That these efforts ultimately failed exacerbated centralizing tendencies in the

American executive branch. By looking at the construction of the 1946 Atomic Energy Act, we

can see the formative structure of nuclear custody, in which the president and civilians within the

executive branch and congress is entrusted with the maintenance, custody, and oversight of the

20 Katznelson, Ira. “Flexible Capacity: The Military and Early American State Building.” Shaped By War and Trade. Ira Katznelson and Martin Shefter, Editors. Princeton: Princeton University Press, (2002).21 Hogan, Michael J. A Cross of Iron: Harry S. Truman and the Origins of the National Security State. New York: Cambridge University Press, (1998).22 See Skocpol et al.’s work in Shaped by War and Trade. Ira Katznelson and Martin Shefter, Editors. Princeton: Princeton University Press, (2002).23 Friedberg, Aaron. “Why Didn’t the United States Become a Garrison State?” International Security. 16:4 (1992), pp. 109-142.24 Nuclear weapons are ‘distinctive’ in the sense that outside of energy use and medical applications, the public has little to do with existing nuclear technology. In the current nuclear age, the material context is abundant in violence potential, and so balancing against hierarchy in the interstate system is relatively easy. This is because a quantitative imbalance in weaponry does not lead to qualitative difference in the means of violence wielded by states.

Page 13: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 13

nuclear stockpile, rather than the military. This tendency was further manifested by the decision

to employ permissive action links further solidifying civilian executive control over the custody

of nuclear weapons while permitting their possession to the military given Cold War exigencies.

International Nuclear Cooperation to Abridge Nuclear Anarchy

A hallmark of realism is the idea that interstate cooperation under anarchy is difficult and

ultimately impossible because of the existence of relative gains. In essence, the transaction costs

are too great to risk the effort. For structural realists, this dynamic is intractable, because even

when both parties share interests, and would even gain from cooperating, the relative gains of

one state over another that might result would be employed at the lesser party’s expense.

Neoliberals differ arguing that the fear of relatively greater gains does not always inhibit

cooperation. States can be motivated to cooperate to achieve absolute gains if their concerns of

future intentions can be alleviated. For neoliberals, barriers to cooperation thus are

surmountable.

While this debate has illuminated IR theorizing for the past 30 years, it has left out

another cause for interstate cooperation, the existence of absolute losses presented by destructive

technology, ecological degradation, and extra territorial threats from space. This phenomenon

identified by Deudney in Bounding Power and “Regrounding Realism” increasingly causes

states to bind together in comprehensive arms control agreements when states are no longer

secure from violence. Stated a different way, states in anarchy in anticipation of its effects can

exit anarchy without creating hierarchy. The effort by limited government constitutional states to

create international institutions then is truly a conservative project. For the act of exiting anarchy

both prevents the tragic costs of war and thus ensures state survival without security state

Page 14: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 14

building imperiling limited government constitutions. The failed Baruch Plan and Atoms for

Peace illuminate this under theorized concept in international relations.

Central to the issue of atomic weapons in the aftermath of the War, was the agreed upon

urgency of constituting some form of international arms control agreement. However, the nature

and scope of that agreement, including the necessity of even having one diverged widely in the

halls of government. The first position, readily dismissed by the Truman administration, was to

have limited to no arms control. The atomic monopoly would be the provision only of the United

States as a trusteeship – a guarantor of world peace. Moreover, the Russians could not be trusted.

Advanced most notably by Secretary of the Navy, John Forrestal, he concluded regarding

international negotiations, “We tried that once with Hitler. There are no returns on

appeasement.”25 Admiral Nimitz argued that the United States was in a dominant position in the

international system with sole possession of the bomb, and should exploit this advantage in order

to secure an international agreement on American terms.26 General Carl Spaatz of the Air Corps

argued that the United States’ military strength had been degraded significantly since the end of

World War II, and so had to retain its monopoly to enforce stability and peace. This position was

also held by Secretary of the Treasury Fred Vinson, Secretary of Agriculture Clinton Anderson,

and Attorney General Tom Clark among others, who generally felt that Soviet power would

stand to gain greatly in the arms control effort by effectively giving their geopolitical rival the

technics and knowhow to construct a bomb.

That the United States could survive as a republic in the international system given the

context of nuclear weapons figured heavily in the argument for doing something to abridge

international anarchy. Spearheaded by James B. Conant, chair of the National Defense Research

25 Forrestal quoted in Bernstein, Barton J. “The Quest for Security: American Foreign Policy and International Control of Atomic Energy, 1942-1946.” The Journal of American History. Vol. 60(4), (March 1974), p. 101926 Ibid, p. 1019

Page 15: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 15

Committee and Vannevar Bush, director of the Office of Scientific Research and Development,

as well as numerous Manhattan project scientists, the approach suggested called for a

comprehensive system of deep arms control, and information sharing to mitigate the possibilities

for nuclear arms races. A policy of secrecy and monopoly would only lead to a temporary

advantage at the cost of damaging long-term relations with the Soviet Union – making an

eventual deal less likely.

Calls for international control of atomic energy became more pronounced in the

immediate postwar world. The melodramatic “We are here to make a choice between the quick

and the dead,” accurately described the scope of international attention placed upon the first

attempt at international atomic control.27 President Truman had appointed Bernard Baruch to the

United Nations’ Atomic Energy Commission, to negotiate a comprehensive and binding

agreement. What became known as the Baruch plan entailed a ban on all atomic weapons and the

creation of an Atomic Development Authority to police all stages of development and research

of atomic energy. The United States would dismantle its existing weapons after an adequate

control system was in place. Furthermore, a declaration of violation and sanctions against

transgressors would not be subject to veto by the permanent members of the UN Security

Council.

This plan was challenged by the Gromyko plan of the Soviet Union, in which a

convention was called for that would prohibit the manufacture and use of atomic weapons. All

atomic weapons would be destroyed within three months of the convention’s effective date.

There would also be full information sharing of atomic energy, without binding onsite inspection

regimes called for in the Baruch proposal. In effect, the Soviet Union was asking for the United

27Baruch quoted in McDougal, Walter. The Heavens and the Earth: A Political History of the Space Age. New York: Basic Books, (1985), p. 85

Page 16: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 16

States to disarm unilaterally and divulge atomic information in return for an unenforceable

promise not to take advantage. Soviet resistance over the removal of veto power, and concern

over opening its closed political system to onsite inspections effectively sank the best chance at

international control of atomic energy.

This is not to say that this attempt was utopian or idealistic. Whatever the deficiencies of

the Baruch plan, it was an unprecedented offer of disarmament by a great power with material

interests befitting its position within the system. However, while the prospects of absolute costs

suggested international arms control, both the Soviet Union and the United States chose instead

to play according to the balance of power, unwilling to take the first step or relinquish an

advantage.

Regardless, an important distinction between the two plans is necessary. American

opinion strongly favored international control. Scientists and politicians, detailed in works such

as A Cross of Iron, began to sense the damage to the constitutional structure that a peacetime

arms race might cause. While the Truman administration was not as trusting as it could have

been in waiting to relinquish its atomic weapons only after a comprehensive system of binding

inspections were placed into being and after the Soviets would have shown to be keepers of their

word, the Soviet plan lacking any enforcement measures only promised an eventual Soviet

monopoly. As McDougal writes, “That Truman’s demarche was cautious is understandable; that

it was sincere was beyond question.”28 Still, any ban on nuclear weapons would strengthen the

Soviet position in Eastern Europe given their conventional superiority and yet, the United States

in earnest pursued this policy. That it failed surely contributed to the United States spending a

greater proportion of its gross national product on defense related research, development, and

state building. However, this would not be the last effort of some kind of international control.

28 McDougal, p. 87

Page 17: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 17

While the 1946 Atomic Energy Act aimed at centralizing and classifying the secrets of all

atomic application, it became apparent in 1949 that America’s atomic monopoly would not keep.

The running illusion that the original Manhattan project was purely an American cartel ignored

the international efforts given by Canada and the UK along with the elaborate Soviet infiltration

of these efforts. 29 As such, the US effort to embargo atomic information did little to prevent rival

and friendly states alike from acquiring atomic and later nuclear, capability. With the growing

concern that over 20 states had begun some rudimentary form of nuclear program, the

Eisenhower administration sought to share nuclear technology, as a means of preventing the very

arms races that traditional balance of power stemming from systemic anarchy might predict.

Furthermore, there was great concern of the potential for surprise Soviet attacks on

American cities, once the Soviet Union achieved parity or primacy in the number of nuclear

weapons in its possession. This stimulated the newly elected Eisenhower administration to have

a small group of top officials to deliver a series of speeches on the nuclear crisis, and Eisenhower

would soon propose mutual military fissile material reductions to the Soviets. This latter idea

never went far. However, the public information campaign outlining the nuclear danger, dubbed

Operation Candor continued through the Soviet testing of their first hydrogen bomb, of which

estimates indicated could destroy all of New York City.

Dismayed at the events, Eisenhower redoubled his efforts at Operation Candor now seen

as critical to bringing the nuclear arms crisis to peaceful resolution. In doing so, not only would

he be able to explain the situation publically, but the United States would also be able to judge

Soviet intentions by their reaction. If the Soviets still would not agree to international arms

29 Reed & Stillman. The Nuclear Express: A Political History of the Bomb and its Proliferation. Minneapolis: Zenith Press, (2009), p. 18.

Page 18: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 18

control, then Americans would be able to assume hostile intentions. Under such circumstances,

it was not out of the realm of possibility for the United States to initiate hostilities.

In Eisenhower’s “Atoms for Peace,” later codified in the 1954 Atomic Energy Act, the

United States attempted to control international competition by sharing the secrets of the atom

for ‘peaceful’ purposes. The Eisenhower administration sought to use the ‘promise’ of peaceful

nuclear technological assistance to prevent its military applications.30 The 1954 Atomic Energy

Act provides for the growth of peaceful nuclear industries domestically, granting corporations

the right to receive licenses to construct civilian nuclear reactors for domestic energy

consumption. In doing so, the act grants the Atomic Energy Commission the ability to provide

private industry with data in assisting with the construction of these private reactors. Moreover,

the act allows for the dissemination of peaceful nuclear technical information and fissionable

material to any non-nuclear state seeking it.31

For our purposes, the Atoms for Peace plan, in accordance with the 1954 Atomic Energy

Act, would also call for the eventual establishment in 1957 of what today is the International

Atomic Energy Agency, with the United States contributing fissionable materials to it, of which

the IAEA would oversee. In conjunction with this, the United States gave strong support to the

creation of EURATOM, a consortium of France, Italy West Germany and the Benelux countries

in 1958. Similar to the fledgling European Coal and Steel community, EURATOM would foster

the development of an atomic energy industry. In this way, however naïve, the more fissionable

materials devoted to the use of peaceful nuclear energy, the less would remain for nuclear

weapons programs.

30 Hewlett, Richard G. and Jack M. Holl. Atoms for Peace and War 1953-1961: Eisenhower and the Atomic Energy Commission. Berkley: University of California Press, (1989), pp. 306-307.31 Hall, John A. “Atoms for Peace or War.” Foreign Affairs. 43(4), (1965), pp. 602-615.

Page 19: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 19

In doing so, the hope was that normalizing nuclear energy use would decrease the

incentive to use such technology as a weapon.32 Peaceful atomic use would foster advancements

in energy and medicine, and would lead to a more cooperative global climate. As a benefit, the

United States would tighten its alliances in Europe, forestalling other states from acquiring

nuclear capability, and allowing the United States to guard against further nuclear diffusion. In

this sense, Atoms for Peace would satisfy other states’ nuclear aspirations while discouraging

military nuclear programs.

In the end, Atoms for Peace was also a failure. It did little to slow the arms race and

nothing to scale it back. The notion that atomic research is peaceful rather than military in

application ignored what has since become known as the dual use problem. In fact, as Reed and

Stillman argue in The Nuclear Express, nuclear diffusion was enhanced rather than slowed by

this proposal. Eisenhower hoped that joint contributions of fissionable materials would be made

to the IAEA where the fissionable material would be allocated to peaceful uses in energy and

medicine. However, there was no method by which the IAEA could prevent the reactors and

related technologies shared with non-nuclear states from being used to produce nuclear useable

material.

In full, these actions do not comport neatly within standard assumptions of the effects of

anarchy upon domestic political development. Rather than seeking to maintain a fleeting

monopoly on nuclear material and control of information, the Truman and Eisenhower

administrations chose to create an effort of openness and candor about the military dangers and

civilian promise of nuclear technology to slow the arms race, rather than welcome it. Rather

32 Bundy, McGeorge. “Early Thoughts on Controlling the Arms Race: A Report to the Secretary of State, January 1953.” International Security. 7(2), (1982), pp. 3-27.

Page 20: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 20

than looking to international rivalry as a form of stability, Eisenhower and Truman sought

cooperation to ameliorate the apocalyptic specter of war if such anarchic practices persisted.

Concentrated Executive-Civilian Control of Atomic Energy

The failure of the international arms control agenda had significant effects on the

domestic control of atomic energy and the limited government constitution. While the domestic

arrangements made seem to conform to traditional notions of separations of power, civilian

authority would not be able to deny the military the weapons they needed to properly balance in

the anarchic international system, a concern to be addressed in the next section.

What follows first is a brief exploration of the initial public debates over the control of

atomic energy, in which the 1946 Atomic Energy Act was triumphed as a victory of civilian

control over the military and a bulwark against the looming garrison state. It is remarkable that

the research and design of ostensibly a military weapon, in the atomic bomb, was not granted to

the military but civil authorities in the aftermath of World War II. In the wake of the atomic

detonations, the public was saturated with both hope and dread for the atomic future.

Immediately, the vast majority of nuclear physicists who worked on the Manhattan project

lobbied opposing any plan that promoted secrecy at the expense of information sharing and

international cooperation.

As Walter McDougal writes, “by all accounts, atomic energy was a revolutionary

technology that justified abandonment of old patterns of research. But in favor of what?

Unprecedented control and secrecy or unprecedented cooperation and openness?”33 The novelties

of speed and volume of destruction made it such that the resolution of any atomic war would be

decided by the number of weapons already produced. Thus, emphasis on research and

development was vital in US security practice. However, it was also argued that these weapons

33 McDougal, p. 82

Page 21: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 21

were so destructive that they could not be entrusted into the military. Still the Army and its allies

in congress felt that atomic technology was very much within their traditional policy domain.

The army’s draft took the form of the Mays-Johnson bill in October of 1945. Initial

concerns centered upon whom was most capable of controlling the ‘secrets’ of atomic energy.34

On the one hand, the military and its vocal supporters in Congress felt that “the capacity of the

military to control atomic energy in peacetime was demonstrated beyond doubt by their victory

in war.”35 A further extension of this proposition, military control meant better readiness to fight

the Russians. As military control successfully kept secret the atomic bomb in wartime, any

civilian control would rely on atomic scientists, whose loyalties in the words of Representative

August Anderson were of questionable doubt:

There are many good Americans among them, probably all of them are good…but I also know some scientists in our country, in the United States, are as red as you can make them. If they were to get any information about atomic energy, I know that it would go outside the United States just as quickly as they could hand it to some agent who would be willing to pass it along.36

In this sense, the military was viewed as the most effective organization of keeping military

secrets. Others were simply frightened of the whole subject, and viewed the military by default

as best prepared to cope with this largely still undiscovered technology. Robert Rich of

Pennsylvania expressed this sentiment, “We should let the secrets remain in the hands of our

34 It should also be noted that the public debate premised upon civilian versus military control largely ignored the fact that both the May-Johnson bill (the original draft on domestic control of atomic energy) and the McMahan Bill largely agreed for some form of civilian control. Where the disagreement existed was the extent to which the military could influence policy on atomic energy. The Mays-Johnson Bill provided for a full-time administrator and deputy with a part-time commission, in which a member of the military could occupy either post. Furthermore, May-Johnson did not refer to peacetime usage of atomic energy. The McMahan bill on the other hand called for a fulltime five-member commission, in which active members of the military were barred from the commission and in which civilian and military control issues were provided. For more see Miller below and Hogan, pp. 234-252.

35 Miller, Byron S. “A Law is Passed – The Atomic Energy Act of 1946.” The University of Chicago Law Review. Vol. 15 Issue 4, (1948), p.801.36 Representative Anderson. “The Atomic Energy Act.” Congressional Record. 79th Congress (July 18, 1946), p. H9364.

Page 22: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 22

Army until we know more about it, and until the Army is willing to convey information to us as

to what the atomic bomb really is and what it will do.”37

These efforts to institutionalize military control of atomic energy failed popular opinion.

Newspapers denounced the haste of the Mays-Johnson Bill, indicating that it was a bid for

military control. Scientists denounced the bill as overemphasizing military uses of atomic

energy, to the detriment of other peaceful uses such as medicine, and industry. The bill provided

for too much secrecy and too burdensome security measures, providing insurmountable barriers

for scientists to freely participate in atomic research. As detailed by McDougal, Chicago

physicist Herbert Anderson led the cry of his colleagues that “the war is won. Let us be free

again.”38 There would need to be a greater degree of legislative oversight and presidential

control, along with fewer restrictions on research, and, to avoid militarism, fewer military

representatives on the board.39

Scientists and concerned citizens around the country formed independent citizens

committees to publicize the dangers of nuclear weapons and plea for global peace. “To many this

was a simple choice between war and peace,” wrote one article.40 As stated by Representative

Estes Kefauver of Tennessee:

Do we put our hopes for peace in atomic energy as a weapon and turn it over to the military here, thereby making certain the armament race already begun? Or do we leave the development of atomic energy in civilian hands…and proclaim to the world our faith in the future of civilization?41

Placing active members of the military on an otherwise civilian commission would be

ahistorical, concerning both traditional constraints of civilian control over military policy and the

37 Representative Rich. “The Atomic Energy Act.” Congressional Record. 79th Congress (July 20, 1946), p. H9546.38 McDougal, p. 8339 Hogan, p. 23640 Miller, p. 81741 Representative Kefauver. “The Atomic Energy Act.” Congressional Record. 79th Congress (July 18, 1946), p.H9348.

Page 23: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 23

interjection of military influence into domestic politics. The armed forces, “with their essentially

authoritarian training and discipline would not be adequately responsive to the public will.”42

Senator Brien McMahon introduced an alternative bill, calling for an Atomic Energy

Commission under control of five civilian commissioners appointed by the president, freedom of

information in basic science and a patent policy ensuring rewards for private investors. It

forbade any weapons R&D in violation of any existing international agreements and kept all

fissionable material under the control of the AEC. The bill was immediately supported by the

national press, and atomic scientists. Secretary Henry Wallace endorsed the McMahon Bill,

“stressing how important it was to adhere to the principle of civilian control, and to avoid any

possibility of military dictatorship.”43 It seemed that civilian supremacy under the guise of

openness and international cooperation was at hand.

Then, the Soviet spy ring in the Manhattan project was discovered in mid-February of

1946. Secretary of War Robert Patterson attacked the McMahon bill asking how the armed

services could be excluded from a policy area directly relevant to national security. Arthur

Vandenberg proposed his amendment providing a military liaison committee to consult on all

matters relevant to national security. However, McMahon maintained that such an amendment

would give the military a veto power over atomic policy and a “position of authority in our

national affairs unprecedented in our history.”44 Still skeptical Members of congress charged that

the AEC’s proposed powers would be considered unconstitutional, that the bill would give the

atomic secret away to (Red) foreign governments, or that the concept of any form of monopoly

was against capitalism and limited government. Despite fears over big government,

conservatives sought to give the military arm substantial authority, trusting them rather than

42 Miller, p. 818.43 Hogan, p. 23744 McDougal, p.83

Page 24: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 24

unreliable New Deal bureaucrats in light of the discovery of the Soviet spy ring. The Vandenberg

amendment was added, and more changes would be made in the House.

The McMahon bill came before the United States Senate in July of 1946, with the

Vandenberg amendment able to sway enough Senators for passage to the House where it faced

an uncertain future. Opponents of the bill sought amendments to virtually all sections of the bill.

The section granting the AEC the authority to educate the world of the danger and promise of

atomic energy was stripped, granting a measure of unprecedented secrecy to the scientific

enterprise. Provisions calling for the close monitoring of loyalties of all workers in the AEC

were put into place.

Almost a year to the day of the bombing of Hiroshima, President Truman signed into law

the Atomic Energy Act. As was written in the Washington Post the following day, “Army

domination of atomic energy development legally ended yesterday.”45 The final bill was in

essence, fully representative of a separation of powers agreement based upon division, balance

and mixture. Fully in civilian hands, control over atomic energy was to be divided between all

three branches of government. Congress was provided a Joint Committee on Atomic Energy to

provide funding and oversight for the new executive department, the Atomic Energy

Commission. As was written in the McMahan report, the development of atomic energy entailed

a such a commission with “broad powers to stimulate private [and military and industrial]

research…be required to own all materials from which an atomic bomb might be made, and to

operate all plants where these materials were manufactured.”46 These concepts as well as the

strict control of information deemed vital to the security of the United States were enshrined in

45 Associated Press. “President Signs Atomic Bill Terminating Army Domination. The Washington Post. (August 2, 1946), p. 9.46 McMahan, p. 6.

Page 25: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 25

the 1946 Atomic Energy Act. Any action stemming from either congress or the executive branch

would be subject to judicial review, a presidential veto, or a new law from Congress.

However, such a firm barrier between civilian and military control over atomic energy as

well as separation of power between the president and Congress would be severely undermined

in the absence of an international control agreement given the exigencies of anarchy. Domestic

practices related to realist oriented balancing would significantly degrade these power separation

arrangements because of exigencies of speed with the closing of effective distance. This is even

evident in the congressional debate showing a willingness to give large policy responsibility the

president because of the destructiveness of the technology. Jerry Voorhis of California expressed

this consensus, saying on the floor of the house that, “I believe all decisions with regard to what

is going on to be done under this bill should be made at the very highest level in our

Government, that is, the President of the United States.”47 In the absence of international arms

control, secrecy, surveillance, and presidential delegation for military use would be the result of

the Atomic Energy Act of 1946.

Regarding secrecy, the AEC was given wide authority to classify atomic ‘secrets’ not

subject to the purview of public debate rendering such checks and balances effectively moot.

Almost immediately, the establishment of the AEC drew complaints of secret administration

without adequate public consideration or oversight.48 More pernicious is language provided in

the bill requiring the surveillance of the loyalties of workers within the atomic energy industry

and granting the president expansive authority to “utilize the services of any government agency

to the extent he deems necessary or desirable”49 to protect against the dissemination of classified

47 Representative Voorhis. “The Atomic Energy Act.” Congressional Record.79th Congress (July 19, 1946), p. H9466.48 Marks, Herbert S. “The Atomic Energy Act: Public Administration without Public Debate.” The University of Chicago Law Review. 15:4 (1948), pp. 839-854.49 Italics mine, Atomic Energy Act, p. 14.

Page 26: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 26

data or materials. This authority granted the president also extends to the extensive surveillance

of Atomic Energy workers under this act. The bill requires that the FBI investigate “the

character, associations, and loyalty”50 of AEC workers, which the way the bill is written, does

not discount continual surveillance, given the president’s authority granted in section 10.

More indicative of the power potential of the executive is the president’s granted

prerogative to “direct the commission to (1) deliver such quantities of fissionable materials or

weapons to the armed forces for such use as he deems necessary in the interest of national

defense.”51 This grant of authority has been used by presidents to assert a plenary nuclear war

power, as it enables the president launch nuclear weapons without deliberation or effective

restraint.

In light of real-state practices and changing material contexts, the United States’ adoption

of the Atomic Energy Act of 1946 represents a formative security structure, the outgrowth and

product of the real-state mode of protection given the failure of the Baruch Plan. The act was

made law with the benign intent of protecting the citizenry from foreign and domestic security

threats, at the expense of loosening the restraints of government given centripetal tendencies

from anarchy. The deference given to the executive branch in the form of surveillance, control

of information, and most damningly, the unilateral ability to launch the nuclear arsenal, would

overtime exceed constitutional arrangements. In full, the 1946 Atomic Energy Act has become

the cornerstone to what had been hoped to be avoided. A new form of hierarchy exists at the

very heart of the republic.

Still, this concentration of power in the hands of the chief executive contra the military

leadership is also inconsistent with expectations of military readiness to fight within the context

50 Ibid, p. 14.51 “Atomic Energy Act.” Legislative History of the Atomic Energy Act of 1946. Washington: US Atomic Energy Commission (1965), p 10.

Page 27: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 27

of acute external threats. Within the text of the act itself, the president effectively eschews the

reliance upon the professional military as proper stewards of the weapons themselves. This was

precisely the concern of the military and their largely conservative allies in Congress at the birth

of the new Atomic Energy Commission (AEC). Almost immediately following the passage of

the 1946 Atomic Energy Act, the military with congressional backing began stating wider claims

on Atomic responsibilities than were provided for in the original legislation, ultimately driving

the president to reassert his plenary authority in the atomic domain.

While the military lost the legislative fight to maintain possession of the bomb, they

continued to pressure the AEC to relinquish military control. Aided by conservative allies in

congress, members of the Military Liaison Committee (MLC) continued to pressure the AEC for

custody of atomic weapons, using the ambiguity of the MLC’s role to argue for more power than

had been intended. In the military’s view, the MLC would be serving “with and as part of the

[Atomic Energy] Commission.”52 The MLC would, or should, in this view, be consulted and

given time to consider any action to be taken by the AEC that would have anything to do with

national security or the interests of the Armed Services. In effect, the military viewed the MLC

having effective veto power over the AEC.

The AEC, directed at the time by David Lilienthal, argued that the atomic bomb was not

just another weapon of war, as was argued by the military, but rather it was an instrument of total

destruction.53 The scope of such destructive potential had broad diplomatic and military

implications, the importance of which only the president could resolve in a system of civilian

controlled constitutional government.

52 Hogan, p.243.53 Ibid, p. 248.

Page 28: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 28

The ongoing tension between military and civilian jurisdiction over the custody of the

atomic stockpile was temporarily resolved in a meeting with Truman in mid-July of 1948, in

which the representatives of the MLC did themselves no favors:

With all the bluster he could muster, which was considerable, Symington talked about how ‘our fellas’ thought they ‘ought to have the bomb. They feel they might get them when they need them and they might not work’. When Truman asked if they had failed to work so far, Symington had to say no, whereupon Royall made things worse by talking about the money that had been invested in atomic weapons. ‘Now if we aren’t going to use them’ he announced that ‘the investment doesn’t make any sense.’54

President Truman, perhaps, to only the surprise of the military, ruled in favor of civilian control.

However, the justification he used, speaks to the core of the specific concentration of power

under study. He commented on July 24, 1948 that because “a free society places the civil

authority above the military power, the control of atomic energy belongs in civilian hands.”55

While civil military cooperation is essential in controlling atomic energy, the power vested

within the president by the Congress through the 1946 Atomic Energy Act, privileges the

“president’s special responsibilities” and enables him to see “continued control of atomic energy

to be the proper function of civil authorities.”56

This decision, a further manifestation of the president’s independence from both the

Congress and the military concerning atomic energy and the nuclear stockpile, demonstrates the

dual nature of the executive concentration. The military in this instance cannot be trusted,

because it views the nuclear arsenal as simply another weapon system that can be used to fight

and win wars. In any acute crisis involving the Soviet Union, they would not hesitate to use

them. With the decision to leave the nuclear stockpile under civilian control, the president is

asserting his authority granted by the delegation of Congress, and buttressed by traditions of

American civil-military relations the capacity to control access to atomic energy. In making the

54 Ibid, p. 249.55 Truman, quoted in Hogan, p. 251.56 Ibid, p. 251.

Page 29: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 29

justification that civilian control of atomic weapons is the only method of ensuring the

maintenance of constitutional government, the president is subsuming the powers of nuclear war

making directly into the office of the presidency, symptomatic of broader material contextual

changes in the international system.

Assertive Civilian Control of Nuclear Weapons

The issue of civilian control of nuclear weapons took on a new complexity as the

stockpile grew in quantity and quality. While the physical possession of nuclear weapons

initially remained in the hands of the Atomic Energy Commission, the Cold War threatened to

become ‘hot’ throughout the ‘50s, and given the exigencies of the balance of power, their

possession gradually shifted to the military. However, concern over the custody of the weapon,

that is, the ability to use it, became a topic of considerable executive angst until the advent of the

Permissive Action Link (PAL), which would enable the continuance of assertive civilian

executive control over the military and military operations.

The first atomic weapons were “glorified physics experiments” rather than efficient

means of destruction.57 In the exigencies of the Second World War, weapons safety was of little

concern, with there being no demonstrated worry of unauthorized or accidental use. And indeed,

for the first years of the Atomic Energy Commission, atomic safeguarding would simply consist

of separating the plutonium core of the Fat Man implosion device from the weapon casing itself;

and only upon presidential order would the implosion capsule be wedded to the rest of the

weapon.58

While the 1946 Atomic Energy Act envisioned the ability to keep this strict physical

separation between the civilian controlled explosive device and the military’s delivery systems,

57 Reed and Stillman, p. 132.58 Ibid, p. 133.

Page 30: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 30

the international politics of the Cold War encouraged President Truman to deploy nuclear

capable bombers to forward locations in Europe. The major breach in civilian possession and

custody took place with the transfer of some nuclear capable core capsules to the US Air Force

in Guam at the outset of the Korean War. Furthermore, advancements in weapons designs, and

imperatives for speed of use resulted in the scrapping of the the removal process in the 1950s.

In place, the military installed various devices on the weapon system to prevent

inadvertent, accidental use. Environmental Sensing Devices, mechanical blocks inhibiting the

delivery of energy to arming switches and detonators and Enhanced Nuclear Detonation Systems

in which the weapon can only arm itself if it senses the “environment expected en route to the

intended target”59 were the methods of choice. While these precautions guarded against

accidental detonations in the event of a plane crash, they did not prevent unauthorized use. For

this concern, the US made use of a dual key system intended to prevent an illegal launch. The

two-man rule, a policy by which the transport, handling, maintenance and firing of the weapons

could not be done without at least two people, served as the only restraint against the

unauthorized firing of missiles, and the handling of ordinance.

It would not be until the late ‘50s that the breakdown of Assertive Civilian Control

became apparent. As a means of assuaging European allies concerns regarding America’s

extended deterrence, the United States had been deploying significant numbers of nuclear

weapons to NATO member countries, while retaining nominal possession. Visiting a Thor

missile base in 1958 Britain, Congressman Charles Porter found a British missile control officer

possessing both his key, and the key of his American counterpart, abusing the two-man rule. As

is recounted:

59 Ibid, p. 135.

Page 31: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 31

We were scared stiff by what we saw…we wondered what would happen if, for some reason – two NATO states falling out, perhaps – the Turk [i.e. a non-US missile control officer] decided to overpower our man and take away his key. Why, the Turk would have himself a modern weapon, that’s what.60

This was not the last time, the potential for unauthorized use carried salience within policy

circles. The most famous instance is detailed in the 1960 report of the head of the Los Alamos

Weapons Division, Carl Agnew on joint military control of nuclear weapons at NATO

installations in Europe. When Agnew arrived at a German air base during the tour, he was

shocked to find four German aircraft with German pilots on five-minute alert fully armed with

atomic bombs under each aircraft.61 The only US control apparent at the time was a nineteen

year-old American GI with a rifle, sans instructions or radio in the event that any of the aircraft

took off. In the event of a rogue pilot, any of those planes could have successfully delivered

their ordinance, potentially starting a nuclear exchange.

Because of the unacceptable possibility of a rogue nuclear launch and the demonstrated

abuse of the two-man rule, the United States outfitted its nuclear weapons with Permissive

Action Links (PALs). It is not surprising, given the US military’s reticence in civilian control of

nuclear weapons, that the Armed Services were unenthusiastic about this reassertion of civilian

authority. For the military, PALs showed a lack of confidence in the military, with their concern

being that PALs hampered their readiness to fight when facing acute security crises.62

Nonetheless, the Kennedy Administration decided on PALs. Initially, the devices were

five digit electronic combination locks, which when given the correct code would arm the

weapon for detonation. That code could only come from the American president. Current PALs

require a 12-digit code into control panels on the nuclear weapon.63 There is a limited try 60 Caldwell, Dan. “Permissive Action Links: A Description and Proposal.” Survival. (29)3, (1987), pp. 224-238. See also, Larus, Joel. Nuclear Weapons Safety and the Common Defense. Columbus: Ohio State University Press, (1967), pp 1 – 165.

61 Ibid, p. 141.62 Reed and Stillman, p. 142.63 Ibid, p. 142.

Page 32: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 32

feature, which disables the weapon after repeated incorrect imputing. These 12 digit codes today

leave the military in possession of the weapon, but they are only useable if given the correct

code. Likewise, the weapons can only be used with the direct order of the president, or his

designated successors.

Permissive Action Links are a means of strengthening executive concentrations of power.

By inhibiting the military’s ability to use what they consider to be a weapon of war, the President

limits the national security state from performing what might otherwise be an automated

operation given the anarchic international system. Because the costs of nuclear war are so high,

the president can no longer trust the members of his own security apparatus to safely control the

weapons. Inadvertent or unauthorized launch augers a nuclear doomsday. The utility of PALs

then is to enable the president to overcome the nuclear dilemmas of custody and speed as the

president is able to place nuclear weapons in the possession of the military without giving

complete control.

Furthermore, with the decision to implement Permissive Action Links, the president is

asserting his sole authority to conduct nuclear war. In making the justification that civilian

control of atomic weapons is the only method of ensuring against nuclear accidents or

unauthorized launch, the president is subsuming the powers of war making directly into the

office of the presidency. In other words, in the president’s attempt to preserve civilian control

over the military, all nuclear war powers remain with and only within the powers of the chief

executive, again, hampering the military’s ability to fight and win wars. Power is still

concentrated within the executive, but the military’s ability to fight in war, is constrained. While

the military holds the bomb, the president holds the key.

Conclusion

Page 33: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 33

This paper has argued that the specific contours of the nuclear material context in the

absence of robust arms control enabled a particular form of concentration of power into the

hands of one individual, the president. It is an advancement of an argument that essentially, the

material context of any international system directly affects the interaction of the units and the

units’ internal structure. This shift toward executive power is a byproduct of larger changes in

the international system brought about by the advent of nuclear weapons. Nuclear weapons have

lessened the costs of mobilization in the traditional balance of power, they have the potential

because of their destructiveness to spark the deceleration of arms races and abridge anarchy, and

they have necessitated executive civilian custody because of the exponentially increased costs of

war.

Considering this material context, the Baruch Plan and Eisenhower’s Atoms for Peace

policy sought international restraint and binding arms control rather than primacy. Given the

destructiveness of the weapon, Truman and Eisenhower feared increased international nuclear

rivalry. In this sense, the Baruch Plan would eliminate atomic weapons by a robust international

organization mitigating or even ending the anarchic state system. Atoms for Peace would satisfy

other states’ nuclear aspirations while discouraging military nuclear programs, decreasing the

likelihood of catastrophic nuclear war. The benefit of the arms control agenda domestically

would be that the United States would not have to take on the centralizing security practices so

common to European Westphalian states. Through restraining itself through binding

international institutions and in the process abridging international anarchy, the United States

attempted to avoid the total transformation of its constitutional order into a centralized ‘garrison

state.’

Page 34: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 34

The inability to end international anarchy has resulted in domestic hierarchy in the

nuclear domain, potentially fatally compromising the limited governing constitution. Because of

the intense speed element involved in nuclear weapons decision-making, and the increased costs

of nuclear war making, the ability to launch nuclear weapons has concentrated itself into one

individual, the civilian chief executive. Concurrent with this, the existence of such

destructiveness renders the cost of intentional or accidental nuclear use to be so prohibitively

high that the military has been effectively disarmed in the nuclear domain. Because of the speed

of delivery, the weapons themselves are placed on high alert, ready to launch in as little as fifteen

minutes, but cannot be fired without the delivery of an arming code held at the ready by the

president. For perhaps the first time in history, the US military has possession of a weapon

without effective control of it.

What should be worth future consideration is the extent to which the structure of control

of nuclear weapons varies across states and regimes. A stronger claim to the independent effect

of material context upon domestic security practices could be made if it is demonstrated that the

same domestic executive concentrations occur in states with more authoritarian forms of

government. A cursory glance at the then Soviet Union’s security practices indicates roughly a

mirror image of the United States’ control over nuclear weapons, demonstrating that there is

nothing necessarily inherent in the United States’ constitutional political tradition that produces

this particular form of concentration. As described by Bruce Blair, the USSR developed the

same form of Permissive Action Links to prevent unauthorized use of nuclear weapons, and even

assigned intelligence officers loyal to the civilian government for equally the same purpose.64

64 Blair, Bruce. “Characteristic Behavior of the Soviet Command System.” The Accidental Logic of Nuclear War. Washington DC: Brookings Institution, 1993, pp. 59-115.

Page 35: Web viewRethinking . Civilian Control: Nuclear Weapons, American . Constitutionalism. a. nd. War-Making . Ryan Fried. For Presentation at the . 2012 . Millennium

Fried 35

This admittedly perfunctory evidence lends reasonable speculation that there is nothing

inherently ‘American’ about the form of concentration of power in the nuclear domain. Rather, I

postulate, that it is the material context itself, the existence of nuclear weapons, which presents

new inducements favoring the leadership of nuclear-armed states to the particular form of

executive control detailed here.


Recommended