+ All Categories
Home > Documents > “Palaeo-Philosophy: Archaic ideas about knowledge in Homeric Greek, Ancient Near Eastern and...

“Palaeo-Philosophy: Archaic ideas about knowledge in Homeric Greek, Ancient Near Eastern and...

Date post: 23-Jan-2023
Category:
Upload: murdoch
View: 0 times
Download: 0 times
Share this document with a friend
36
Palaeo-philosophy: Archaic ideas about knowledge in Homeric Greek, Ancient Near Eastern, and Ancient Egyptian texts Paul S. MacDonald Murdoch University Plato is generally thought to be the first thinker to systematically consider the nature and scope of knowledge. Although there had been some speculation by the Presocratics about what it meant to know some thing, Plato analyzed the components “parts” of knowledge and attempted to give a theoretical account of the very concept of knowledge (epistemē). Plato argues that belief or opinion alone could hardly count as knowledge, unless the belief was true. But even a true belief could be held by chance, that is, where it is only by chance or accident that a belief one holds is true, say, a lucky guess. What “elevates” true belief to knowledge is that one holds the belief to be true on the basis of some ground, and hence that the true belief is justified. Hence, a claim to know some thing must meet three necessary conditions for it to genuine knowledge; in other words, one knows some thing only if: (a) one believes it, (b) it is true, and (c) one’s belief in it is justified. 1 The focus of Plato’s efforts and many others since his time has been on the concept of justification, since this condition does much of the work. Justification has different sources and different means, depending on the kinds of thing one is said to know. Knowledge claims have a wide temporal scope: one can claim to know about the present (through sense perception), the past (through memory 1 There is an enormous literature on Plato’s theory of knowledge; see amongst others Paul Woodruff, “Plato’s early theory of knowledge” and Gail Fine, “Knowledge and belief in Republic V-VII”, in Everson 1990 pp. 60-84, 85-115; and the lengthy bibliography on pp. 256-61. 1
Transcript

Palaeo-philosophy: Archaic ideas about knowledge in

Homeric Greek, Ancient Near Eastern, and Ancient Egyptian

texts

Paul S. MacDonald

Murdoch University

Plato is generally thought to be the first thinker to

systematically consider the nature and scope of knowledge. Although

there had been some speculation by the Presocratics about what it meant

to know some thing, Plato analyzed the components “parts” of knowledge

and attempted to give a theoretical account of the very concept of

knowledge (epistemē). Plato argues that belief or opinion alone could

hardly count as knowledge, unless the belief was true. But even a true

belief could be held by chance, that is, where it is only by chance or

accident that a belief one holds is true, say, a lucky guess. What

“elevates” true belief to knowledge is that one holds the belief to be

true on the basis of some ground, and hence that the true belief is

justified. Hence, a claim to know some thing must meet three necessary

conditions for it to genuine knowledge; in other words, one knows some

thing only if: (a) one believes it, (b) it is true, and (c) one’s belief

in it is justified.1 The focus of Plato’s efforts and many others since

his time has been on the concept of justification, since this condition

does much of the work. Justification has different sources and different

means, depending on the kinds of thing one is said to know.

Knowledge claims have a wide temporal scope: one can claim to know

about the present (through sense perception), the past (through memory

1 There is an enormous literature on Plato’s theory of knowledge; see amongst others Paul Woodruff, “Plato’s early theory of knowledge” and Gail Fine, “Knowledge and belief in Republic V-VII”, in Everson 1990 pp. 60-84, 85-115; and the lengthy bibliography on pp. 256-61.

1

and records), and the future (through prediction). So the source of

one’s justification for knowledge claims about sensible objects in one’s

proximate environs is those objects’ having those properties and the

means is a reliable sensory apparatus; the source of one’s knowledge

claims about one’s own past would (most likely) be one’s own memory; and

so forth. Moreover, knowledge claims can be about particular things or

events, as well as about things in general, e.g. one can claim to know

that all pieces of iron rust in water, such that what one claims to know

about this piece of iron is water is by way of knowing the general

natural law that iron rusts in water. Instead of considering what counts

as justification in rendering true beliefs knowledge, one can also

address the question of what sorts of things one can claim to have

knowledge about. Without going through the details, one can claim to

have knowledge of the following: (1) physical objects and events in

one’s proximate environs via sense perception, (2) past state-of-affairs

via direct or indirect memory, (3) future states-of-affairs via

prediction, (4) a skill or an art, e.g. carpentry, piano-playing,

language, (5) universal truths about mathematics and natural laws, (6)

one’s own cognitive, intentional and affective states, (7) intentional

states of others through their behavior, and (8) unobserved objects and

events via reliable testimony.

However, there is sufficient evidence from an “archaic” period

(loosely so called), predating the Greek Classical period by 300-1000

years (Homer, the Pentateuch, Gilgamesh, the Mari Letters, etc.), which

show upon close examination that their concepts in general, as well as

knowledge in particular, do not map directly onto our modern, post-

Kantian concept of knowledge. This is in large part due to significant

differences in their respective understanding of the conditions that

subjects and objects must meet in order to have knowledge of or be an

object of knowledge. The available textual evidence shows that their

writers were working, not with concepts, but with complexes which have

four salient features: (1) that it does not arise above its elements as

2

a concept does; it merges with the concrete objects that compose it; a

fusion of the general and the particular, of the complex and its

elements, a psychic amalgam; (2) that its abstracted traits are unstable

and easily surrender their temporary dominance to other traits; (3) that

the basic level of complex formation may be the most inclusive level at

which it is possible to form a mental image which is isomorphic to an

average member of the class, and thus, the most abstract level at which

it is possible to have a relatively concrete image; (4) that it has an

over-abundance of properties, an over-production of connections, and

weakness in abstraction.2

2 For more details see MacDonald 2005.

3

I. Knowledge in Homer’s Iliad and Odyssey

4

Our current view of what counts as knowledge via justified true

belief and what sorts of things one can claim to know about is not the

only view; it has its origins in distinctively philosophical,

theoretical reflection on the concept of knowledge. In a ground-breaking

article, Edward Hussey (1990) pushed back the historical frontiers of

research into the concept of knowledge through an analysis of the words

for knowing used in Homer and Hesiod, centuries before Plato’s

investigations into this theme. Hussey opens his study with the insight

that “Homer’s and Hesiod’s remarks about human knowledge are incidental,

unsystematic and, of course, pre-philosophical. Still, the ways of

thinking they reveal may be of philosophical interest in themselves and

have demonstrable relevance to the history of philosophy.”3 Hussey

begins by distinguishing between knowledge the gods are said to have, in

contrast with human knowledge: “Homer speaks of both gods and human

beings as knowing things, though there is a great difference in the

quantity and scope of the knowledge available to the two groups.

Moreover, the gods frequently and successfully deceive human beings

(though they keep this within strict limits).” On the other hand, “the

gods also supply reliable information to the human race through the

medium of dreams, omens, portents and oracles, and through favored

people, the prophets, seers and singers. Some men can interpret signs

from the gods; some have direct communication with them; and some seem

by divine favor to have a kind of direct access to knowledge of

otherwise hidden things.” Hussey argues that the possibility of humans’

deception by the gods is obviously discouraging; it stimulates some of

the Homeric characters not to take all appearances at face value, that

many things cannot be known for certain. Although it’s prudent to be

skeptical about some particular claims to knowledge there is no

skepticism about the general structure of the world. “Homer and his

characters take the structural and determining features of the world to

be absolutely beyond doubt; in particular, the existence of the gods,3 Hussey 1990 p. 11.

5

their separate individualities and powers, and their general

relationship to human beings.”4

Humans are disqualified from knowledge about the remote past (i.e.

the past beyond their own memory) not just because they lack personal

experience of past events. Aeneas says to Achilles (IL 20.203) that “we

know each other’s lineage and parents, hearing the words of mortal men

which have been handed on successively by word of mouth; but you have

never seen my parents with your eyes, nor I yours with mine.” And later

in the same speech: “But, should you wish to learn this also, so that

you have a good knowledge of our lineage, it is one that many men know.”

Hussey comments that “in both passages there is a (socially

intelligible) emphasis on the public availability of the facts. Their

truth can be ascertained by asking ‘almost anybody’, without recourse to

one special source. The illustrious families have impinged causally on

the world around them over a long period in many ways. Hence, any claims

about their history can be checked from many memories in many ways.

Collectively, the memory of mankind in the heroic age has a complete

grasp of the history of the house of Dardanus…. Homer is perhaps a

remote and unconscious predecessor of modern philosophers who require

that knowledge should ‘track the truth’.” In the note he says that “the

essential point about unverifiability is well brought out in Pindar’s

development of the topos (Paean 6.50-3): ‘these things it is possible

for wise men to take on trust from gods, but it is impossible for

mortals to find out [for themselves].’ Also Sophocles (Oedipus Tyr 499-

501): ‘there is no real way of deciding’ on the claims of seers.5

The implications of this passage are thus, “first, that there is a

realm of direct personal experience, within which general scepticism

would be out of place (though deception may occur occasionally). To

ordinary mortals, such experience comes by ordinary sense-perception,

while to seers and gods it may also be conveyed in ‘supernatural’ kinds

4 Hussey 1990 pp. 11-12.5 Hussey 1990 p. 15; next quote p. 16.

6

of direct perception. In a second stage, from a mass of mutually

overlapping and confirming experiences of human beings, there is

constructed a collective experience, which again admits no room for

scepticism, about part of the present and the immediate past, and about

the general structure of the world. Whatever falls within the range of

collective human experience is in principle knowable by a human being.

The necessary conditions for knowledge include not merely justified true

belief, but verifiability by means of the appeal to personal or

collective experience.”

“Where scepticism gets a serious foothold in Homer is where the

subject-matter lies beyond the boundaries of personal or collective

human verifiability. This means, above all, (1) the remote past,

including, for Homer and his contemporaries, the heroic age; (2) the

distant future; (3) the secrets of Fate and the plans of the gods…. Good

info is available [about the heroic age] but it comes from a non-human

source, the Muses. The bare possibility of deception by the Muses is

allowed to disqualify claims to knowledge. The cardinal role of the bare

possibility is characteristic of sceptical thinking.” However, there

appears to be an unresolved tension between two of Hussey’s claims: on

one hand he says, “the memory of mankind in the heroic age has a

complete grasp of the history of the house of Dardanus”; but somewhat

later he says, “where scepticism gets a serious foothold in Homer

[concerns]… the remote past, including… the heroic age”. In other words,

is it humans’ memory during the heroic age that has “a complete grasp” of

its own noble houses’ histories, or is it due to these houses’ “causally

impinging” on the social world in later ages that permits “Homer’s

contemporaries” to check on their stories about their heroic ancestors?

Further, would Homer then check on their descendants’ memories of these

events (which are open to skeptical doubt) or would he check on their

“complete grasp” of their own noble houses’ histories? The point is that

the later would bring with it a derivative kind of certainty, one that

relies on the surety that at one time in the past their ancestors had

7

certain knowledge by way of direct memories of those remote events;

whereas the former would bring with it little certainty at all.

In contrast with Hussey, J. H. Lesher has argued that the Iliad and

the Odyssey show different attitudes toward what their characters can be

said to know, and that this hinges on the gap between perceiving and

knowing. In the Iliad, Lesher says, things are really as they appear to

be; even when the gods assume mortal form they are correctly perceived

as the mortals they have become. But in the Odyssey this whole situation

changes; Aristotle himself described the theme of this work as disguise

and recognition (Poetics 1459b); related to this are the factors of

trickery, illusion, and deception. The dramatic power of Odysseus’ story

resides in the possibility of deceptive appearance and misunderstood

intentions. The story recounts a succession of encounters between gods

and humans who see things but consistently fail to properly identify,

name and recognize one another. This theme is also one of Odysseus’ own

characteristics: “the mastery of appearance and the use of deception is

a hallmark of Odysseus’ mētis or cunning. Recognition of the true nature

of the situation is a sign, perhaps the preeminent sign of his noos

[intellect].” The suitors’ failure to recognize his true identity when

he returns to Ithaca is the sign of their stupidity and leads to their

undoing. “It is therefore a mistake to attribute to Homer an uncritical

identification of sense perception with recognition and realization. The

Odyssey shows that Homer was aware of the contrast, and that it was a

distinction of importance for his story.”6

This distinction also applies to the use of speech in the Iliad and

the Odyssey; in the former, when one speaks and another hears,

understanding follows immediately, and the person reacts accordingly.

Speakers’ words are instances of the quality the word designates; when

one’s words convey wisdom, shame, harshness, folly, and so forth, the

words are themselves wise, shameful, harsh, foolish, and so forth. But,

in sharp contrast, many of the most important elements of the Odyssey are6 Lesher 1981 pp. 14-15.

8

built on the possibility of failing to understand the meaning of what has

been said, or even of deliberately misspeaking one’s mind, giving the

wrong intention. The wonderful story about Odysseus tricking the Cyclops

is one of the most famous ancient verbal tricks. Lesher says that this

“clever stratagem contains an element of linguistic subtlety and

possibility that leaves the more primitive mechanistic view of language

far behind.”7 In the later work, language is shown to be a powerful

weapon for deceit; it takes intelligence and ingenuity to use words this

way, as well as to “see through them”. Lesher concludes by stating that

cunning and intellect play a central role in the Odyssey and not in the

Iliad. When coupled with the other features of words for knowledge in the

text they reflect an interest in perception, knowledge, and intelligence

absent from the earlier work.8 In this paper we plan to extend the sort

of work done by Hussey and Lesher to other sets of “archaic” documents

from approximately the same period around the Mediterranean basin.

II. The scope of knowledge in general in the Ancient Near East.

The Epic of Gilgamesh is the longest and most famous ANE narrative; it

is the episodic story of a heroic quest for fame and immortality.

Gilgamesh is a hero with “an enormous capacity for friendship, for

endurance and adventure, for joy and sorrow, a man of strength and

weakness, who loses a unique opportunity through a moment’s

carelessness.”9 The historical Gilgamesh probably lived about 2800-2500

BCE, but the earliest Sumerian group of tales about him date from

c.2150. Old Babylonian tablets, written in Akkadian c.1800, diverge

widely in some places from the Sumerian versions, but in other places

are the same. During a state-sponsored surge of literary collection and

invention in the Kassite period (c.1500) many widely scattered tablets

were sorted and inventoried. The longest, most complete version of the

7 Lesher 1981 p. 17.8 Lesher 1981 p. 19.9 Dalley 1989 p. 39; Foster 1987 pp. 21-23.

9

epic dates from the reign of Assurbanipal in the seventh century and was

found at Nineveh.10 Various texts in Gilgamesh provide valuable clues for

an understanding of the meaning and scope of words for “knowledge” in

the ANE in the second millennium. According to Elena Cassin’s study 11

of Gilgamesh, in the episode about Enkidu’s encounter with the harlot,

Enkidu is a hybrid being, he comes from the union of two beasts who

express savage nature; it seems that he is a type of perfect savage. It

is in the desert that he becomes a hunter. His appearance is alarming: a

strange being, half-human half-beast creature, who befriends savage

beasts which he then captures and kills. A village prostitute seduces

Enkidu and they copulate for six days and seven nights. The first stage

of his passage from lullû state (living being) to awīlum (city-dweller) is

thus overcome. Afterwards, he “sets his face” toward the gazelles who

then run away; he loses his hairiness as well as his ability to run

fast. He has acquired knowledge and become wise; the prostitute says

that, in gaining knowledge, “he has become like a god.”12 The second

stage of his passage occurs when he accepts the prostitute’s invitation

to come to the village. Having entered their houses, he eats bread and

drinks beer. Tasting these two foods allows him to take part in

sedentary civilization, i.e. bread and beer are synonymous with

cerealist culture. After this he sings and his features brighten: the

song, in contrast with noise, is discourse according to norms. By

successive stages Enkidu definitely leaves the somber zone where he used

to live. He is no more a creature of nocturnal silence, and has become a

creature of song and light, like Gilgamesh.

More extensive insight into variety of uses of ANE words for

knowledge is provided in the comprehensive lexical entries in the Chicago

Assyrian Dictionary: the Akkadian idû/edû, “to know” is very common in

Akkadian from the Old Babylonian (OB) to the New Babylonian (NB) period.10 Dalley 1989 pp. 41-47.11 Cassin 1987 pp. 37-40; Tigay 1982 pp. 205-13; see also Bottero 1992 pp. 193-4.12

10

The forms of wadû are obviously back-formations based on the D stem; the

G stem “know” forms an adjective edû, “well-known, famous”, and an

irregular participle mudû, “wise, knowledgeable, well-informed”, found

also in the meaning “familiar”. We also find the nouns mūdûtu,

“knowledge” (OB), “wisdom” (NB), *idūtu, “knowledge” and mūdânūtu,

negated in the meaning “ignorance”. The D stem (w)uddû means “inform,

reveal”; the S stem šudû, “announce, make known”, is similar. From the

latter are formed the nouns mušēdû, “reporter”, and šudûtu,

“announcement” (both only LB). The št stem šutedû means “acquire

knowledge”. The few occurrences of the N stem have passive meaning. As

in Hebrew, the semantic field of “knowledge” and “wisdom” is highly

developed; the terminology usually builds on concrete perception.13 In

parallel with “know” we find amāru, “see, recognize”; ahāzu, “grasp,

learn”; hātu, “see grasp, learn”; lamādu, “experience, know (both

intellectually and sexually)”; sabāru, “grasp, understand”; šamu, “hear,

perceive”. Equally concrete is the expression pīt uzni, “wise” (literally

“having open ears”).14

The verb idû/edû denotes: (1) secular “acquaintance” (with persons,

their age, where they are staying, circumstances, facts, the right time,

etc.)15; (2) “experience” (in craftsmanship, military strategy,

geography)16; (3) then “knowledge” of a specific sort (when to harvest,

what roads and canals are blocked, a disaster); and finally (4)

specialized “expertise” (in astronomy, liturgy, warfare, irrigation,

treatment of diseases).17 From the Sultantepe Tablet, “The Tale of the

Poor Man of Nippur”: a poor man disguised as a medical doctor plays13 This claim is supported by Bottero’s detailed investigations of knowledge claims made by means of ANE divination practices – see below.14 idu in CAD vol. VII (1960) pp. 20-34; von Soden vol. I (1958) pp. 187-95.15 The instances cited correspond more or less to some of the pseudo-categories – see below.16 These instances are similar to an Aristotelian competence, i.e. inthe sense of unactualized capacity.17 On the last type of medical knowledge see the discussion by Bottero1992 pp. 173-7.

11

three pranks on the mayor. In the first episode, he presents himself at

the mayor’s house with this announcement: “I am a doctor, a native of

the town of Isin, one who knows…” presumably how to treat diseases. The

hymn to the goddess Gula opens with the words, “I am a physician, I know

how to heal, I carry with me all the herbs.” And further, “I am provided

with a bag full of effective conjurations. I carry texts for healing, I

effect cures for all.”

People are characterized socially by what they know (idû).

Highlanders and murderers do not “know” good manners, and the wicked “do

not know” how to keep an oath. Sages (eršu), however, know moderation;

they can understand how the deities are disposed toward them, but even

they are ignorant of how the gods punish. For the most part, however,

the “old human self-estimate holds”: people are “dull” (sukkudu), for

they know nothing. Akkadian epistolary literature understands idû

primarily in the sense of “be informed” (about the plans of others, the

commands of the king, imminent dangers, military positions); cf. The

stereotyped informatory formula: šarru bēlī ú-da, “know my lord the king

that…”. This usage indicates a view about things and persons in the El-

Amarna Letters in the phrase idû ana, “to be concerned with, to care

for”.18

In the realm of magic, gods “known and unknown” (idû u la idû) are

invoked. Felt to be especially dangerous were the machinations of demons

one might encounter unsuspectingly or curses of which one is unaware.

One has no power over a person whose name and location are unknown. One

may pray to the gods for help against demons because they are unknown

and their effect is therefore unpredictable. There were also prayers

against unknown diseases and people sought to protect themselves against

unwitting sins. Unless the name of the deity is known, there can be no

communication between a human being and a god. Generally, people have

only slight knowledge of the gods: their dwelling places and plans are

unknown, so that people are prevented from gaining insight into their18 Westermann TLOT vol. 2 p. 515.

12

own future. But this ignorance extends to the divine plane: the gods do

not know the plans of Tiamat, and therefore cannot prevent the deluge.

On the other hand, Šamaš is said to know the plans of other deities, and

Ea is versed in all things. Ea, Šamaš, and the Anunnaki [elder gods] are

therefore given the epithet mūdê kalāma, “knowing everything” (cf. also

the mother of Gilgamesh). Knowledge and wisdom are attributes of the

gods, Marduk, “who knows all wisdom” (mudû gimri usnu) knows the hearts

of the Igigi [young gods], and is therefore given the epithet dŠA-ZU (=

mudê libbi ilî); cf. the instructive parallelism here: soothe the hearts of

the gods, preserve righteousness, accomplish justice, etc.19

The forms uddû and šudu also function as terms for revelation. The

gods reveal themselves in the cosmos by “showing” the heavens their

course and “assigning” the moon to ornament the night. Marduk “makes

known” to the gods their various domains (mu’addî qirbēti ana ilî). The

domains of Sin and Šamaš can be found (utaddû) throughout the entire

cosmos. The gods can “make known” their will through signs and oracles,

above all by designating priests, kings, and governors; cf. Enlil’s

title “designator of governors” and Nabû’s title “designator of the

kingship”. The basis of all religious observance is laid by the deity’s

revelation of its name, which can then be “named” (zakāru). Even though

there is no extant Akkadian discourse on “revelation”, we see everywhere

how important the fact of revelation was felt to be. By means of oracles

and omens, people attempted to discover the will of the gods and learn

what human fate holds in store; it was considered a sign of impending

disaster when a desired omen was “not revealed” (ul utaddû). We return to

the topic of prophecy and revelation in the ANE and Old Testament below.

III. The scope of knowledge in general in Ancient Egypt

In Ancient Egyptian thought the second important physical aspect

of human being, after the body, was the heart, symbolized by the glyph

for a squat lidded jar. The heart was regarded by the Egyptians as the19 Botterweck TDOT vol. 5 pp. 457-8.

13

anatomical, emotional and intellectual center of the living human. In

the embalming and mummifying process the heart was removed and then

replaced in its proper setting within the chest cavity. As the emotional

center, it was in charge of and ruled over the positive and negative

feelings, as well as being the seat of the moral sentiment. As the

cognitive center, it was the locus of imagination and memory; in many

vignettes showing an individual’s posthumous judgment, the heart is the

witness of the measure of the person’s deeds. In amuletic magic, one of

the most important (and common) charms was a special type of scarab

which protected the deceased’s heart. Since the heart contained a record

of its owner’s deeds in its earthly life, a record that would be

examined by the gods to see whether its owner deserved eternal life, it

was crucial that the heart was protected against loss and damage. One of

the spells in the Book of Dead would guard against the heart revealing

potentially damning information to the judges, another to ensure that

the deceased retained his heart in the underworld, yet another against

theft, and so forth.

Meeks and Meeks’ recent study of the Egyptian gods offers a lucid

and concise description of the ancient Egyptian ‘picture’ of the gods’

knowledge, and by extension the more limited domain of human knowledge.

The gods’ secret thoughts, they argues, was nothing more than the

intimate knowledge lodged in their viscera or ‘inner selves’, knowledge

which could not but be expressed in a creative manner. “The totality of

what could be conceived exactly coincided with the totality of what had

been set in motion by the gods; this totality was reflected, at least to

some extent, in the set of writings composed by [the god] Thoth.

Nevertheless, what could be known never coincided perfectly with what was

known. Between the one and the other, there remained a space open to the

kind of knowledge that could be progressively elaborated and subjected

to questioning. This type of knowledge was men’s portion and it set them

on an endless quest.” It was not the proper place or power of humans to

invent anything, but rather to limit their beliefs and actions to

14

appropriating a part of what was already known, provided that the gods

gave their consent and a suitable means. Unlike the creator god, who

knew everything, the other created gods could be ignorant of many

things, though they could learn much more than they began with. Each

created god knew certain things the other gods did not know; this inner

knowledge was concealed by each god from the other gods and ensured

their individual nature.20

The special faculty or power that enabled the gods to perceive an

event when it occurred was called sia, whose limit concept embraced all

the possible knowledge brought into being by the original act of world

creation. Meeks and Meeks claim that this cognitive capacity was “a

dormant kind of knowledge” that became active in the presence of the

event that brought it out; “it enabled the god to grasp, in the fullest

sense of the word, what was going on.” In other words, sia made it

possible for already extant knowledge to emerge at the conscious or

explicit level. Not to have sia of some thing was thus not an issue of

not knowing it, but rather of not being able, or no longer being able,

to recognize or identify it. This served to establish a conceptual

distinction between sia, which the authors call “synthetic knowledge”,

and rekh, which they call “technical or practical knowledge”. Along

these lines, “sia operated like an absolute intuition irreducible to

logical knowledge. Rekh implied a way of defining concepts that

necessarily entailed the use of speech, and later writing; they endowed

it with its specific character, that is, the capacity to be transmitted.

Only if filtered through the spoken and written word could sia become

accessible in the field of rekh.”21 The god Thoth was the intermediary

between the gods’ omniscience and humans’ limited acquisition of

knowledge. As the recorder and preserver of the gods’ knowledge, Thoth

had the power to diffuse information to whom he chose, and the vehicle

of his transmission was rekh. In this sense, Thoth (or Hermes) was both

20 Meeks & Meeks 1999 pp. 94-5.21 Meeks & Meeks 1999 pp. 95-6.

15

the teacher of humans, through his gift of speech and writing, and the

teacher of the practice of teaching itself, the means whereby humans

could acquire knowledge from others.22

IV. The scope of knowledge in general in the Old Testament

The Old Testament seems to draw important distinctions between

cognitive, intellectual knowledge and practical, embodied knowledge.23

Regarding the former group, external knowledge or recognition is often

paralleled by visual perception. (Nu 24:16; Dt. 11:2; 1 Sam 26:12; Neh.

4:5; Job 11:11; Ps. 138:6; Eccl. 6:5; Isa. 29:15; 41:20; 44:9; 58:3;

61:9; Jer. 2:23; 5:1; 12:3.) Visual perception often precedes knowledge

and makes it possible (Gen. 18:21; Ex. 2:25; Dt. 4:35; 1 Sam. 6:9;

18:28; Ps. 31:8; Isa. 5:19); there are also cases where it means

“behold”, “ gaze at”, “look at”, etc. An auditory process can also

precede knowledge (Ex. 3:7; Dt. 9:2; Neh. 6:16; Ps. 78:3; Isa. 33:13;

40:28; 48:7; Jer. 5:15) and where both factors are “constitutive of the

epistemic process”. About Yahweh, “then the lord said I have observed

the misery of my people who are in Egypt, I have heard their cry on

account of their taskmasters. Indeed I know their sufferings.” (Ex. 3:7)

“When any of you sin in that you have heard a public adjuration to

testify and, though able to testify as one who has seen or learned of

the matter, does not speak up, you are subject to punishment.” (Lev.

5:1) Moses said, “you have seen all that the lord did before your eyes

in the land of Egypt, to Pharaoh and all his servants and all his land,

the great trials that your eyes saw, the signs, and those great wonders.

But to this day the Lord has not given you a mind to understand, or eyes

to see, or ears to hear.” (Dt. 29:3) “From this time forward I make you

hear new things, hidden things that you have not known. They are created

now not long ago; before today you have never heard of them, so that you

22 See also Botterweck TDOT vol. 5 pp. 454-5.23 Botterweck TDOT vol. 5 pp. 461-2; Westermann TLOT vol. 2 pp. 511-12; Gaboriau 1968 pp. 18-20.

16

could not say I already knew them. You have never heard, you have never

known, from of old your ear has not been opened.” (Isa. 48:6).

Botterweck comments that, “the complexity of many epistemic

processes is expressed by an accumulation of various verbs belonging to

the semantic field of “knowing”, without distinguishable emphasis on the

various nuances of the individual meanings. “seeing, knowing,

considering, and understanding”… do not always point to a deliberate

distinction between sensory and intellectual apperception; more

generally the totality of human knowledge is addressed.”24 The knowing

subject must have the physical ability to apprehend: eyes are needed,

able to see, and thus not blind; eyes must be opened and uncovered. Ears

are needed and they must be opened and attentive; the heart is needed

and it must be discerning, not thick or rash. One must not be asleep or

drunk or blind; in his pain and suffering, Job does not see what happens

around him (Job 14:21).

The heart (lēb, lēbab) has many functions as the main organ or

perception and knowledge; it supports understanding and decision on the

basis of what is perceived. As the seat of memory the heart makes it

possible to incorporate particular perceptions into a larger realm of

experience, providing the basis for judgment and responsible action. In

the heart, the various objects of perception become concentrated to form

insight into the true nature of the world, on the basis of which persons

many consciously frame their lives. The vital physical nature of an

individual is concentrated in the heart; if one wants to continue

living, the heart must be refreshed and nourished, especially with bread

and wine. In terms of the earliest historical documents concerning the

concept of mind, the most important Hebrew usage of ‘heart’ is in

passages that clearly indicate intellectual, cognitive, and reflective

operations.25

24 Botterweck TDOT vol. 5 p. 462.25 Wolff 1974 pp. 40-58; Fabry, in TDOT vol. 7 pp. 419-25; Johnson 1964pp. 75-87.

17

While the sense organs engage in sense perception, it is within

the heart that thought, memory, understanding, attention, and reflection

take place. The heart’s cognitive activity is prior to seeing with the

eyes or hearing with the ears, since it initiates the sensory

operations. Following this internal activity, the heart internalizes and

preserves the content of sensory percepts for the purpose of making

judgments and decisions. The opposite of the heart’s cognitive action is

not sensory failure but lack of attention and confusion in making

judgments. Perceptive and cognitive operations are initially directed at

concrete, particular things, but then, as the main OT texts advance this

concept, the heart can be directed toward instructions, signs and

wonders. In prophetic contexts, the object may be an individual’s

vision, the word of God, or his grace and mercy. In the Wisdom

Literature, the heart knows wisdom, love, faith, and human fate. In

addition, the heart is the seat or storehouse of memory, used to recall

a previous situation in order to find a motive for a certain action.

Remembrance in the heart can be construed as internal advice, one’s own

rule of thumb, or the ethical ‘call’ of conscience, where the context

indicates moral precepts or rules. On the other hand, if the heart lacks

wisdom it is subject to a kind of folly which can show itself as

heedlessness, willfulness, and failure to see the larger picture. The

heart can be deluded by wine, sex, worldly goods, material gain,

temptations, idolatry, wicked words, and corruption. The boundary

between the cognitive functions of the heart and the activity of the

will is often blurred; perhaps this is due to a conceptual (and hence

semantic) oscillation between referents that are concrete and internal

and those that are abstract and internal. In any case, the heart

functions as the driving force behind an individual’s voluntary actions

and engages in conceiving and planning.26

It takes effort to gain specific knowledge hence it must be

26 Fabry in TDOT vol. 7 pp. 419-24; see also Wolff, 1974, p. 50-1; Johnson, 1964, pp. 77-8.

18

sought, searched out, or investigated until it is found. Knowledge is

the result of systematic searching or trying or effort or testing, all

verbs connected with the action taken to acquire knowledge. The object

of such knowledge must be fundamentally perceptible, i.e. it must be

within the grasp of the knowers: either ‘before’ them (Ps. 51:3; 69:20)

before their eyes (Isa. 59:12), immediately with them (Job 15:9; Ps.

50:11), or near them (Isa. 5:19). Westermann argues that the primary

meaning of yāda for humans is the “sensory awareness of objects and

circumstances in one’s environment attained through involvement with

them and through the information of others”; he cites forty-one passages

where knowing is directly attendant on or conveyed by the verb for

“seeing”. The next most pregnant sense of yāda describes “the

recognition that results from the deliberate application of the senses,

from investigation and testing, from consideration and reflection.” And

third, it indicates “the knowledge that results from realization,

experience, and perception, and that one can learn and transmit” this

knowledge to others through instruction.27 Only Yahweh can know things

from afar (Ps. 138:6; 139:2). For ordinary humans, in order for some

thing to be known it must not be hidden, but must come forth; perception

cannot deal with things that are great, hidden, dark, deep or new, nor

is there any knowledge in the underworld. It is certainly a curious

feature of these meticulous studies of Hebrew usage that there are

virtually no instances where humans beings are said to know about the

distant past, or for that matter, the near past beyond their own

memories or witnesses’ memories.

In contrast with cognitive or intellectual knowledge, yāda also

conveys the sense of practical and/or embodied knowledge, under three

headings.28 (1) It can mean a competence or a skill, e.g. “skilful

hunter” (Gen 25:27), “skilful sailor”, “one who knows the sea” (1 Kgs

9:27; 2 Chr. 8:18); “skilled in writing” (Isa. 29:12), “skilled in lyre-

27 Westermann TLOT vol. 2 pp. 511-12; Gaboriau 1968 pp. 24-26.28 Westermann TLOT vol. 2 pp. 514-5; Botterweck TDOT vol. 5 pp. 464-5.

19

playing” (1 Sam. 16:16). Westermann comments that the Hebrew usage

corresponds with the Akkadian usage of “to know” in passages such as one

in Gilgamesh where the god Ea is said to know every craft. (2) It can

also mean emotional and/or sexual knowledge: a man is said to “know” a

woman or a woman to “know” a man when they have had sexual intercourse.

(Gen. 4:1,17,25; 38:26; Jgs. 19:25; 1 Sam. 1:19; 1 Kgs. 1:4) The same

connotation of experience through direct sexual acquaintance is found in

Akkadian when the wild man Enkidu is seduced by the harlot. (3) It can

also mean knowledge of good and evil. The early story of knowledge

gained from eating the tree of knowledge of good and evil (Gen. 2:9,17)

has been interpreted many ways, nicely summarised by Westermann.29

First, acquiring the capacity for good and evil in the moral sense;

second, the capacity to shape life based upon the freedom of autonomous

decision; third, sexual experience or an understanding of the normal and

abnormal manners of sexual expression; and fourth, comprehensive

knowledge and practical wisdom through which human culture was

initiated.

V. Knowledge from Divination and Prophecy

Two further sources of knowledge commonly cited in the archaic

period are divination, the expert reading of signs about hidden things,

and prophecy, the utterance of divinely inspired predictions by a

privileged person. Jean Bottero discusses these within the fundamental

parameters of the Mesopotamian system of thought: “They were convinced

that the world around them did not have a rasion d’être within itself. It

depended entirely on supreme forces that had created it and that

governed it primarily for their own advantage. The images of these gods

were based on a human model; they were greatly superior, however, by

their endless life, by their intelligence, and by their power that was

infinitely above our own. Every thing on earth, all objects and events,

came forth from the gods’ actions and their will, and fitted into some29 Westermann TLOT vol. 2 p. 513; see also Gaboriau 1968 pp. 34-6.

20

kind of general plan that they had in mind. The plan was impenetrable,

as such, to humans, who discovered its unfolding from day to day.

Nothing that we are ignorant of in the past, the present, and of course,

the future, escaped the gods’ knowledge and their decisions. But they

could report on it to mankind at their pleasure: this was the entire

meaning of divination.”30

Bottero argues that there were two ways in which such divine

reports or notices could be conveyed to humans, the direct way and the

indirect way. There are only one or two examples in Mesopotamian texts

of the gods’ revealing directly to humans what their plans were. In such

cases, the gods preferred to take a single intermediary (the medium) to

inform him of their secret, by ordering him to spread the word. It seems

that anyone could be chosen for receipt of this message, usually but not

always conveyed by both sound and sight. The message could pertain to

the past, present or future. The secret content was sometimes clear and

unambiguous, but it could also be obscure and hence in need of expert

exegesis. Bottero says that this kind of inspired divination was not

common in Mesopotamia, except in certain periods and milieus. The

indirect way, on the other hand, was more common and is attested in

large numbers of tablets devoted to deductive divination. This method

was based on the model of written discourse, instead of direct speech or

vision, and hence was encoded in graphic signs that had to be

interpreted.31

Bottero argues that the “objective foundation” of deductive

divination was the repeated observation of similar event-sequences. “One

event that drew attention because of its unnatural character preceded

the other which was equally accidental and unexpected. The first event

was imagined as the harbinger of the second, regardless of whether their

mutual bond was real or imaginary.” Once the general frame for this sort

of prediction had become entrenched - via Hume-like custom and habit –

30 Bottero 1992 p. 105; see also Rochberg 2004 pp. 44-48.31 Bottero 1992 p. 106; and see Rochberg 2004 pp. 49-55.

21

the diviners developed the process to an extraordinary degree. “Thus

they established a type of ‘code’ which was entirely parallel, even here

and there identical, to that of the script, from which the experts,

informed about the values of the ‘divine pictograms’ could decipher

exactly and univocally their message concerning the future…. They could

extract it from the divine pictograms, deduce it from them, hence the name

deductive divination. And as the entire universe was at the mercy of the

gods, who regulated its functioning and progress, the Mesopotamians

logically considered the sublunary world in its totality as the

supporter of their ‘script’ understood in this fashion, and also as the

bearer of their messages to be deciphered.”32

From the Royal Archive at Mari, Babylonian outpost (c.1800-1760

BCE), there is ample evidence of a phenomenon attested there and in the

Bible – intuitive prophecy, i.e. revelation without resort to mantic or

oracular devices or techniques.33 Ordinary divination was the province

of formal cult priests and sorcerers and generally served the royal

courts throughout the ANE. Unlike the ‘official’ diviners, “these

prophets were spontaneously imbued with a certain consciousness of

mission and of a divine initiative.” Also unlike the Biblical prophets

who pronounced on important social, ethical and religious matters, the

Mari prophets pronounced on all sorts of mundane matters, esp. with

regard to the king’s personal well-being. Records indicate that there

were two types of diviners who coexisted side-by-side in the Mari

precinct, and these show two patterns of predicting the future and

revealing the divine word.

On one hand, the professional was a specially trained expert;

their activities were usually confined to crucial matters e.g.

pertaining to the city’s security. On the other hand, there were

intuitive prophets, those who without special training claimed to have

acquired the divine word. These are the earliest such manifestations in

32 Bottero 1992 p. 107; and see Rochberg 2004 pp. 55-65.33 Malamat 1989 pp. 79-80; relevant texts in Nissinen 2003 pp. 13-77.

22

the ANE and are similar to those found in the OT.34 The essential nature

of this kind of prophecy has certain dominant characteristics, according

to Malamat: (1) spontaneous manifestations resulting from inspiration or

divine initiative, in contrast with to mechanical, inductive divination,

usually initiated at the king’s request for signs from god. Isaiah said,

“I was ready to be sought by those who did not ask for me; I was ready

to be found by those who did not seek me.” (Isa 65:1) (2) consciousness

of mission, where the prophets take a stand before the authorities to

present divinely inspired messages. (3) an ecstatic component, “a

somewhat problematic and complex characteristic”, which may include

auto-suggestion, an infused dream, though rarely extreme frenzy.

Despite the external similarities between the diviner-prophets of

Mari and Israel there are discrepancies in the type of message content,

the function they played, and the status of the prophets within their

respective societies. In Israel the prophet seems to have enjoyed a more

or less central position (although some of them were peripheral),

whereas in Mari the prophets appear to have played only a marginal role.

The Mari prophecies are limited to material demands on the king, such as

building a city gate, the offering of funerary sacrifices, the dispatch

of valuable objects to temples, the request of property for a god, and

so forth. These sorts of messages are very distinct from Biblical

prophecy which often expresses “a full-fledged religious ideology, a

socio-ethical manifesto, and a national purpose.” Malamat points out

that this apparent discrepancy may simply reflect the limited scope of

the Mari tablets so far discovered, all of which have come from the

royal diplomatic archives. In addition, more than six hundred years

separate the Mari texts from the OT prophetic texts and the intervening

‘links’ in the development of prophetic knowledge have either not

survived or not yet been discovered.35

34 See esp. Jeremias TLOT vol. 2 pp. 697-9; and Müller TDOT vol. 9 pp. 129-31.35 Malamat 1989 pp. 80-82; and Malamat 1998 pp. 122-33.

23

Twenty-eight letters addressed to the king, containing reports on

prophecies and divine revelations have been published. The senders were

all high-ranking officials and bureaucrats from the Babylonian kingdom;

there are thirty-five prophecies in total. The diviner-prophets were of

two types: the professional or ‘accredited’ speakers, and the causal or

amateur type. There are five titles for expert, cult prophets: (1)

šangûm, a priest imbued with a warning dream, (2) assinnum, a

transvestite or eunuch or cult-prostitute, (3) one case of a female

qabbātum, from Akk. qabûm, “to speak or proclaim”, (4) mukhhûm, some

sort of ecstatic or frenetic, similar to the Hebrew mešugga, from a

root-word meaning “insane”, (5) āpilum, a title exclusive to the Mari

texts, meaning “answerer or respondent”. The two titles mukhhûm and

āpilum have counterparts in Biblical Hebrew, for the latter ‘ōneh,

“answerer”, and mešugga for the former.36

More than half the reports, however, deal with unaccredited,

amateur prophets, the majority of whom were women, mostly from the

court. Almost half of these reports contain accounts of the prophet’s

dreams. There are some features that distinguish the professionals from

the amateurs: first, only in the official cases is the actual message

preceded by the verb tebû, “to arise”, which seems to allude to

prophetic stimulation in the temple. Second, the medium of dream

prophecy is totally absent from the professionals, while it is prevalent

amongst the amateurs. The accredited prophets received their messages

while fully conscious. This is clearly paralleled in the Hebrew Bible

and shows that one can distinguish between message dreams, not intended

for the dreamer but for someone else, and revelatory dreams, intended

for anyone. (See Dt. 13:1; 1Sam 28:6; Jer 23:28; 27:9) The Mari letters

with dream reports have a regular structure: (1) the male or female

dreamer, (2) the opening formula, which uses “see”, (3) the dream

content, based on vision or hearing, (4) the communicator’s comments,

often including a piece of the dreamer’s hair or garment. 36 Malamat 1989 pp. 85-87; and Nissinen 2003 pp. 5-7, 13-17, 79-80.

24

This “unique and puzzling practice” is attested only at Mari and

seems to be related to establishing the reliability of the prophet and

his/her message. Malamat suggests that the lock of hair or fabric may

have functioned as an “identity card”, in other words, “it may have had

a legal significance, more than a magical-religious meaning”.37 They may

also have been sent to the king to “guarantee” the very existence of the

prophet, and not just the fabrication of the communicator. He quotes an

explicit codicil from one of the letters: “since this man was trusty, I

did not take any of his hair or the fringe of his garment.” Malamat

argues that “the credibility of prophetic revelation was obviously a

sensitive matter, not to be taken for granted. Thus it was often

verified and confirmed by the accepted mantic devices, considered more

reliable means than intuitive prophecy per se.” In such cases, the

communicator recommends carrying out precautions or reports that further

examinations were conducted. In contrast, in the Bible the words of the

prophets are never subjected to confirmation or corroboration by other

means, but are vindicated solely by their fulfillment in the future.

(Dt.18:21; Ez 33:33; Jer 28:8)

37 Malamat 1989 p. 95; and Huffmon 1968 pp. 101-24.

25

VI. Knowledge from dreams and their interpretation

According to Jean Bottero (again), in Mesopotamian thought ‘to

dream’ did not constitute a specific state or action; there is no verb

for ‘to dream’ in Sumerian or Akkadian. One is said ‘to see a dream’

(amâru and natâlu; also sometimes naplusu and šubrû), such that the dream

content is the object of sight, an internal spectacle. In Gilgamesh, the

God Ea wants to prevent the destruction of the entire human species and

thus reveals the impending disaster to the Babylonian Noah. “I have

revealed to Atrahasis a dream, and it is thus that he has learned the

secret of the gods.” The most archaic example (c.2450) comes from the

Vulture Stele, where the King of Lagash, engaged in battle with his

enemy Umma, reports how the god Ningirsu appeared to him in his sleep to

reassure him of the good outcome. The King Amiditana (1683-47) was

warned in a dream that he had to offer a statue of himself to the gods;

similar reports were made by Assurbanipal and Nabonidus. Since most of

the extant documents concern public affairs perhaps it is not too

surprising that such private dream revelations are exceptional.38

The ancient dreamers often felt the need for expert assistance in

dream exegesis; when Gilgamesh first dreams of Enkidu, who resembles “a

block from heaven”, he goes to his mother for interpretation. Bottero

says that such cases are instances of intuitive dream divination, and that

there is nothing technical or rigorous about this kind of dream

unpacking. But deductive divination from dreams is different. First, it

was valid for everybody. “There was no longer a question about

extraordinary dreams and explicitly supernatural messages, which were

perhaps more easily reserved for the great of this world (?), but of

ordinary, current, daily dreams… valuable for all. Whoever dreamed, and

whatever his dream was, that individual was the recipient of the message

that the dream bore. Only the message was ‘written’ and ‘coded’, and to

‘read’ it one needed a real technician, a specialist initiated in this38 Also discussed by Noegel in Bulkeley 2001, pp. 45-50.

26

‘writing’… an examiner, someone who looked closely at and studied the

‘pictograms’ incorporated in the dream, who deciphered them and

translated them for the interested party who came to consult.”39 Two

notes on this: first, Bottero seems to avoid the use of the word

‘divination’ in these passages and instead prefers ‘mancy’, ‘-mantia’;

perhaps since ‘divination’ implicitly refers to god-given, or god-

related, and that was not true for all dreams. Second, his reliance on

the notion of reading ‘pictograms’ reminds one of Freud’s ingenious

insight that some dream-content appears like a rebus and has to be

‘read’ in terms of ambiguous, polyvalent visual-graphic imagery.

The ancient Egyptian language had no verb for “to dream”, only a

noun “dream”. In their terms, one could see something “in a dream”, or

see “a dream”, as a mental ‘object’. In other words, a dream was the

object of a verb of perception – “it was something seen, not done”, as

Szpakowska says. “In a sense it was not an event arising from within the

dreamer or an activity performed by an individual; rather, it had an

objective existence outside the will of the passive dreamer. In

particular, the use of the phrase “seeing in a dream” also indicates

that the dream was considered as an alternate state or dimension in

which the waking barriers to perception were temporarily withdrawn.”40

The earliest known references to dreams in Ancient Egypt are found in

the so-called “Letters to the Dead” (c.2100 BCE) These letters were

written to a deceased relative or friend, usually requesting some sort

of favor on behalf of the living person, and then left in the tomb of

the addressee. “The dreams in these texts functioned as a sort of

liminal zone, a transparent area between the walls of two worlds that

allowed beings in separate spheres to see each other.” Szpakowska

speculates that this zone was like a two-way window, “allowing the

living to see the dead and the dead to watch the living. More

39 Bottero 1992 p. 113; and his analysis of the treatise “Oh, dream god”, pp. 114-16.40 Szpakowska in Bulkeley 2001 p. 31.

27

specifically, the dreams allowed people on earth to communicate with the

inhabitants of the Netherworld.” However, the author is not licensed to

make the claim that dreams allowed the living to see the dead, as

opposed to claiming that in their dreams they could see the dead; even

less so, is their any textual support for the assertion that dreams

allowed the dead to see the living.

Although Leo Oppenheim, in his highly influential work The

Interpretation of Dreams in the ANE (1956), said that Egyptian royal dreams were

typical of “message dreams” in the ANE, Szpakowska argues that these

dreams were not typical of the Egyptian literary tradition until the New

Kingdom, when they make their first rare appearance. With one exception,

the dreams usually cited to support this claim are Late Period and

Hellenistic descriptions attributed to earlier pharaohs, “which bear

little resemblance to the dream anecdotes recorded centuries earlier.”41

There is a single, very rare dream-book (Papyrus Chester Beatty III),

dated in the reign of Ramesses II; it is the only oneiromantic manual

that has been found in pre-Hellenistic Egypt. It records 227 dreams and

their interpretation, divided into three sections. The first is composed

of visual images and their interpretation; the second is a spell to

counter a bad dream; and the third offers a detailed description of the

characteristics of the “followers of Seth”, and then their dreams. This

dream-book has been the subject of a great deal of speculation but it is

still the only text for dream interpretation until the end of the Nubian

dynasty (650 years later). Szpakowska points out that “even this dream

book is suspect, for it is not clear that it was ever actually used. It

is possible that it was kept as a curiosity or as a literary exercise

and did not necessarily require a specialist to be used. For nearly the

first 2000 years of Egypt’s history, there is no extant evidence for the

mantic use of dreams nor for rituals designed to solicit dreams.”42

E. R. Dodds studied the ancient Greek notion of dreams and visions

41 Szpakowska in Bulkeley 2001 p. 32.42 Szpakowska in Bulkeley 2001 p. 34.

28

at great length in a number of important papers. Dodds argued that in

the Homeric texts all of the textual evidence points to the

understanding of dreams by the dreamer as objective facts, in which the

dreamer is a passive recipient of either a visit by a messenger or a

vision created by some other being.43 The crucial implication of Dodds’

findings for our present investigation is that, at least until six

centuries later (and then only in a few rare cases), a dream was not

thought to have its origin in the dreamer, that is, it was not thought

to be a product of the dreamer’s own mental states.44 Homer’s dream

stories follow a very strict pattern in four stages: the circumstance

before the dream; the dream image’s movement toward the sleeper and

location over his head; the dream image’s speech; and the dream’s

aftermath. An example: when the Iliad tells us that before the battle

Achilles dreamt that Athena came to him in a dream and gave him advice,

Achilles would not have thought that he was the source of the dream,

Athena was; the dream-setting was not within his own ‘mental space’, but

in some other place; and Athena’s words of advice were her own words,

not Achilles’ own ‘inner voice’. In Homer’s texts the principal function

of dream stories is to advance the narrative action, to provide the

audience with an ‘inner’ motive for the character’s decisions and

actions. In this sense, Homeric dream reports cannot be employed to

provide a complete picture of actual dream experience for the Archaic

Greeks.

In the background chapter to her book on Dreams in Late Antiquity,

Patricia Miller makes a number of important points pertinent to our

argument.45 In the Odyssey, “dreams were located spatially in an imaginal

43 W. V. Harris describes these as “epiphany dreams”; Greek and Roman dream accounts “often represent them as admonitory epiphanies, that is to say, the sleeper’s experience of a visitation by an individual, oftena divine being or messenger, but sometimes simply an authoritative person or a ghost, who brings instructions or important information”, Harris 2009 p. 24.44 Dodds 1951 pp. 104-06.45 Miller 1994 pp. 14-16.

29

landscape that was in close proximity to the dwelling place of the

dead”. Penelope’s slain suitors travel “from the concrete space of

empirical reality through a fantastic geography: ‘Hermes led them down

dank ways over grey Ocean tides, the snowy rock, past the village of

dreams [dēmos oneirōn] and narrows of the sunset.’” (OD 24.10-12) The

regions of Ocean “inscribe a boundary in cosmic space. Beyond that

boundary in a realm of images and ghosts, a space that [is] ‘the reverse

side of the cosmic order’ that mirrors its other in fantastic,

phantasmal ways.” In another incident, Penelope is described sleeping

sweetly between the gates of dream (OD 19.560-67): dreams which come

through the gate of ivory are dangerous to believe, for they bring

messages which will not issue in deeds; dreams which come through the

gate of horn have power in reality, whenever any mortal sees them.46

Miller agrees with Amory that the former gate signifies speech or

utterance and the latter signifies eyes and vision;, as such they made

fitting monuments for the village of dreams. Miller claims that as

figures, “dreams were autonomous; they were not conceptualized as

products of a personal sub- or unconscious but rather as visual images

that present themselves to the dreamer. Thus Homeric dreamers spoke of

seeing a dream, not of having one as modern dreamers do.” Other dream

incidents (e.g. OD 4.795-807) reveal another important point: dream-

figures are connected with divine beings, who either send an image or

appear as the figures themselves, though always in disguise. “Certainly

the connection with the gods serves to underscore the dream’s autonomy

and the authoritative quality of its message…. The dream appears to be a

kind of technique for overcoming epistemological uncertainty that nevertheless

participates in that very dynamic.”47

Studies in genetic psychology conducted by Jean Piaget and others

have confirmed that there are three distinct stages in the child’s

46 Amory 1966 pp. 3-57; Kessels 1978 pp. 100-103.47 Miller 1994 p. 19, emphasis added.

30

understanding of the nature of his own dreams.48 In the first stage, the

dream is regarded as coming from outside and remains an external event;

dreams occur where their dream-content is located, and the child dreamer

actually participates as himself in the dream-story. In the second

stage, the child admits to the subjective, internal origin of his dream,

but will not admit that the image is internal and distinct from what it

represents, i.e. the dream-content cannot be detached from physical

reality. In the third and final stage, both the dream-origin and the

dream-content are regarded as internal to the dreamer; just as thought

is regarded by the child as “a voice in the head”, so dreams are

regarded as “visions in the head”. This shows us that the skeptical

trope about waking and dreaming appeals to a level of cognition which

recognizes only the second stage of concept formation and disclaims any

intelligibility for a hypothetical third stage. For the Ancient Greek,

the claim that the source and the content of a dream are entirely

internal is itself an hypothesis, as strange as this may seem to us now.

Since they have ruled out any appeal to a higher cognitive level, there

is no evidence that can count to support such an hypothesis. It is open

to the same sorts of doubts as other hypotheses which cannot be

verified, such as, in the 4th C anyway, the claim that the earth is

actually a sphere moving around the sun.

VII. Conclusion

In conclusion, the textual evidence cited above from all languages

supports the general claim that the verb for “to know” is closely

related to the verb for “to see”: Akkadian îdu, Hebrew yādā, Sanskrit

veda, Greek ideo, and Latin video. The archaic concept of knowledge is

grounded or dependent on the archaic concept of direct perceptual

acquaintance; what one can be said to know is what one can see with

one’s own eyes or grasp with “the mind’s eye” (i.e. the intellect), and

48 Hallpike 1979 pp. 387-90.

31

this close connection is “rooted” in the basic link between the words.49

One salient difference with the “modern” concept of knowledge is the

wider field of suitable “objects” of seeing and grasping. Botterweck

comments on the various ANE words for knowledge that, “the semantic

field … is highly developed; the terminology usually builds on concrete

perception.” With regard to the Hebrew word yāda he states that

“external knowledge or recognition is often paralleled by visual sensory

perception”; that “the object of knowledge and perception must be

fundamentally perceptible, i.e. it must be within the grasp of the

knowers.”50

With regard to our modern post-Kantian concept of knowledge, the

following aspects of the archaic concept (or ‘complex’) of knowledge can

be adduced from the textual evidence cited above.

1. Direct perception of concrete sensible objects is preeminent in

knowledge formation with respect to the perceptual grasp of some

thing, identification as that thing, and recognition of it in other

contexts.

2. Testimony is accorded greater epistemic weight for, inter alia, (a)

prophetic utterances, (b) unvisited places, (c) distant ancestors’

words and actions.

3. Although there are some rare cases where the ‘signs’ of prophets or

omens are ‘checked’, this is always very arbitrary, never rigorous or

methodical; there is no real idea of confirmation by supporting

evidence, nor of any ‘objective’ standard to establish justification.

4. Epistemic claims about dream contents have a more fluid scope with

respect to internal vs. external constraints on the acquisition of

beliefs; this is clearly manifest in ancient dreamers’ attitudes

toward the origin, setting, and meaning of dreams.

49 Thus our claim here goes against Hussey’s rebuttal (1990 p. 13 note 6) of the so-called Snell-Frankel thesis, advanced in the 1950s, that there are linguistic connections between words for seeing and knowing.50 Botterweck TDOT vol. 5 pp. 462-3; Westermann makes the same assertions, TLOT vol. 2 pp. 511-12.

32

5. There is a surfeit of divine knowledge, which means that “everything

that can be known is already known by the gods”; human knowledge is

always in deficit and incomplete with regard to the overall cosmic

order.

6. Knowledge of the name of some thing leads to power over the thing

named due to the cognitive ‘complex’ that amalgamates graphic sign

with natural thing; the sensible (=phonetic) properties of the

graphic sign are the same as the sensible (=qualitative) properties of

the signified.

7. Human knowledge can be gained by intimate acquaintance with some

thing, penetrating to the interior or inside of some thing, signaled

in Egypt and the ANE by the word for “heart” which also comprises

meanings associated with the interior of a building, an area, or a

person.

8. The lack of systematic knowledge (epistemē) of the natural world

through humans’ epistemic deficit does not lead to doubt or

disbelief, nor to a skeptical attitude about appearances. The rare

exceptions to this foundational credulism are those occasions when a

“crafty god” (like Hermes or Enki or Thoth) sets out to deliberately

deceive a character in one of the epic stories.

REFERENCES

Amory, Anne (1966) “The Gates of Horn and Ivory”, in Yale Classical Studies

vol. 20 pp. 3-57.

Bottero, Jean (1992) Mesopotamia: Writing, Reasoning, and the Gods. Trans by Z.

Bahrani & M. van der

Mieroop. University of Chicago Press.

Botterweck, G. J. (1980) “yāda” in Theological Dictionary of the Old Testament. G.

J. Botterweck &

H. Ringgren (Eds.) 10 vols. Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1974-90.

33

vol. 5 pp. 448-81.

Bulkeley, Kelly (Ed.) (2001) Dreams: A Reader on Religious, Cultural, and

Psychological Dimensions of

Dreaming. NY & London: Palgrave.

Cassin, Elena (1987) Le semblable et le différent: symbolismes du pouvoir dans le proche-

orient ancien.

Paris: La Découverte.

Cryer, F. H. (1994) Divination in Ancient Israel and its Near Eastern Environment.

Sheffield: JSOT.

Dalley, Stephanie (Ed.) (2000) Myths from Mesopotamia. Rev. Edn. Oxford

University Press.

Dodds, E. R. (1951) The Greeks and the Irrational. University of California

Press.

Fabry, H.-J. (1998) “leb, lebab”, in Theological Dictionary of the Old Testament. G.

J. Botterweck &

H. Ringgren (Eds.) 10 vols. Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1974-90.

vol. 7 pp. 399-437.

Foster, Benjamin (1987) “Gilgamesh: Sex, Love and the Ascent of

Knowledge”, in J. H. Marks & R. M.

Good (Eds.) Love and Death in the Ancient Near East. Guilford, CT: Four

Quarters, pp. 21-42.

Gaboriau, F. (1968) “Enquête sur la signification biblique de connaître”

in Angelicum vol. 45 pp. 3-43.

Goody, J. (1977) The Domestication of the Savage Mind. Cambridge University

Press.

Hallpike, C. R. (1979) The Foundations of Primitive Thought. Oxford University

Press.

Harris, W. V. (2009) Dreams and Experience in Classical Antiquity. Harvard

University Press.

34

Huffmon, H. R. (1968) “Prophecy in the Mari letters”, in Biblical Arch.

vol. 31 pp. 101-24.

Hussey, Edward (1990) “The beginnings of epistemology: from Homer to

Philolaus”, in Stephen Everson

(Ed.) Cambridge Companion to Ancient Thought: 1 Epistemology. Cambridge

University Press.

idû “to know” (1960) in Chicago Assyrian Dictionary, University of Chicago

Press, vol. VII, pp. 20-34

Jeremias, J. (1997) “nābî” in Theological Lexicon of the Old Testament. Ernst

Jenni & Claus

Westermann (Eds.) 3 vols. Peabody, MA: Hendrickson. vol. 2 pp. 697-

710.

Johnson, A. R. (1964) The Vitality of the Individual in the Thought of Ancient Israel. 2nd

Edn. Cardiff:

University of Wales Press.

Kessels, A. H. M. (1978) Studies on the Dream in Greek Literature. Utrecht: HES.

Lesher, J. H. (1981) “Perceiving and Knowing in the Iliad and Odyssey”, in

Phronesis vol.26 pp. 2-24.

MacDonald, Paul S. (2005) “Complex and Concept in Archaic Patterns of

Thought” in Cosmos and

History, vol. 1 no.2.

Malamat, Abraham (1989) Mari and the Early Israelite Experience. London: The

British Academy.

Malamat, Abraham (1998) Mari and the Bible. Leiden: E. J. Brill.

Meeks, D. & Meeks, C. F. (1999) Daily Life of the Egyptian Gods. Trans by G. M.

Goshgarian. London:

Pimlico Books.

Miller, Patricia Cox (1994) Dreams in Late Antiquity. Princeton University

Press.

Müller, H.-P. (1985) “nābî” in Theological Dictionary of the Old Testament. G. J.

Botterweck &

H. Ringgren (Eds.) 10 vols. Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1974-90.

35

vol. 9 pp. 129-50.

Nissinen, Martti (Ed.) (2000) Prophecy in its Ancient Near Eastern Context.

Atlanta: SBL.

Nissinen, Martti (2003) Prophets and Prophecy in the Ancient Near East. Atlanta:

SBL.

Oppenheim, Leo (1956) The Interpretation of Dreams in the Ancient Near East.

Philadelphia.

Rochberg, Francesca (2004) The Heavenly Writing: Divination, Horoscopy, and Astronomy

in

Mesopotamian Culture. Cambridge University Press.

Snell, Bruno (1953) The Discovery of the Mind. Trans. by T. G. Rosenmeyer.

Oxford: Blackwell.

Tigay, Jeffrey (1982) The Evolution of the Gilgamesh Epic. Philadelphia:

University of Pennsylvania Press.

Von Soden, W. (1958-81) Akkadisches Handwörterbuch. 3 vols. Wiesbaden.

Westermann, Claus (1997) “yāda”, in Theological Lexicon of the Old Testament.

Ernst Jenni & Claus

Westermann (Eds.) 3 vols. Peabody, MA: Hendrickson. vol. 2 pp. 510-

20.

Wolff, H. W. (1974) Anthropology of the Old Testament London: SCM Press.

36


Recommended